In pursuit of wisdom: Ancient Chinese and Greek perspectives on cultivation International Conference at UNSW Australia (Sydney), 15-18 January 2016 New College, UNSW Elements, Sylvia Benitez, Oil on Birch Panel, 2008 Conference Organisers Professor Rick Benitez, Philosophy Department, The University of Sydney Dr Hyun Jin Kim, School of Historical and Philosophical Studies, The University of Melbourne A/Professor Karyn Lai, School of Humanities and Languages, University of New South Wales, Australia Conference Secretary Mr Andrew Koh, PhD Candidate, Philosophy, UNSW Conference Sponsors ARC Decra DE120101493: Dr Hyun Jin Kim (The Transfer of Global Hegemony: Geopolitical Revolutions in World History) Keynotes Professor Sophie-Grace Chappell Open University Beneficial actions and beautiful actions It is routinely assumed that the ancient Greeks were eudaimonists: they believed that the point of action is to bring about eudaimonia, a word which we usually (mis)translate as “happiness”. It might be roughly true of some of the views that Socrates presents to say that they are, in our sense, eudaemonist views, and there is of course plenty of material that can be used to support this reading in Aristotle. Nonetheless there are also deep mistakes in this view even of the “big three” ancient Greek philosophers; and eudaimonism is nowhere near the truth about the ethical views of many other Greek thinkers, in particular the tragedians Aeschylus and Sophocles. My project in this paper is to reappropriate, in particular from Sophocles and Aristotle, the ethical idea of beauty as a reason for action. I claim that our moral, and so our ethical, concepts, and the moral and ethical normativity that goes with them, are deeply aesthetically-coloured. The beautiful does indeed have a central place within our thinking about normativity; because it has a central place within our thinking about moral normativity. And the central place it has is this (or this is one of them): very often, it is a good answer to the question “Why should I do x?” to reply “Because x is the beautiful thing to do.” Bringing the idea of to kalon, the beautiful, to a central place in our ethical thinking and our understanding of the ancient Greeks’ ethical thinking is a somewhat unusual move; but it has great explanatory power when we are trying to understand them. It also casts surprising light on a number of other issues, including how to understand unhappiness ethically, and even the theological problem of evil. Professor Yahei Kanayama Nagoya University Everlasting Inquiry in Ancient Greek Philosophy: Socrates, Plato and the Sceptics Philosophia in Greek is different from its Chinese equivalent, 哲學, in its inclusion of philo (love). For Socrates and Plato philosophy was above all ‘love of sophia (哲, wisdom)’, consisting in consideration in quest of happiness. Greek skepsis, too, was different from its equivalent, 懷疑, in that skepsis was positive in meaning, representing ‘consideration’ in pursuit of wisdom, while 懷疑 is rather negative, with 疑 meaning ‘standing stock still, being unable to decide’. Later in Hellenistic philosophy skepsis approaches懷疑, when it comes to imply ‘doubt’ under the influence of the Sceptics. However, I maintain that their skepsis still kept its core meaning of ‘consideration’, without abandoning ‘pursuit of wisdom’. Their doubt was an outgrowth of their everlasting inquiry, and helped them to distance themselves from threatening appearances and disturbing suspicion, and to achieve tranquillity, or at least moderation of passion, so as to be able further to engage in pursuit of wisdom and cultivation of the mind. This is essentially the same as the attitude of Socratic awareness of ignorance, and I think in this sense the Sceptics were genuine followers of Socrates and Plato, sharing their attitude of emphasizing ‘pursuit’ more than ‘wisdom’. This emphasis is taken to be a distinctive character of Greek philosophy. 1 Keynotes Professor Mu-chou Poo Chinese University of Hong Kong Mortuary practice and the search for happiness in Han China The aim of personal cultivation, as implied by the theme of this conference, is in pursuit of wisdom. The reason to pursue wisdom, ultimately, is to find happiness. However, as demonstrated by generations of thinkers, happiness is a vague concept. It could be defined as a state of contentment, a kind of existence that has no want, yet what that contentment entails may vary throughout time and space and among different cultures. Yet scholars in pursuit of the pursuit of happiness found it fascinating how people in different cultures satisfied their urge to seek for happiness in life. It could even be argued that by looking at what happiness means and how happiness is supposed to be achieved in different cultures we could find a common denominator that is the converging point of similarities and differences of the meaning of human existence. In this paper, I propose to look at the problem not from a philosophical point of view, but by looking at the mortuary practices, in ancient China in particular. My view is that, since happiness is often elusive, and life is short, people resort to constructing an existence beyond this life on earth, based on their earthly experience, their aspirations and apprehensions, as well as their hopes for a rewarding life. The relationship between the concept of the netherworld, the belief system, and the social norms that formulated the idea of happiness, therefore, may provide researchers with insights into a particular cultural system. How people imagined the afterlife and make mortuary preparations to ensure that existence could reflect what people had in mind of an ideal existence, or happiness. If, as many may have assumed, this ideal existence was defined and confined by the conventional wisdom of the day, it was a demonstration of the collective value of the society as a whole, which may or may not be in accord with the elite ideologies in that society, or, for that matter, in other societies. Through comparison, therefore, we learn that such differences can be traced back to how people in different historical and cultural contexts managed to deal with universal human problems. Professor Lisa Raphals University of California, Riverside On Spontaneity Several modes of action or attitudes of mind have been proposed as skills or processes at the heart of good lives. Prominent among these are, in a Greek context, the devious but felicitous quality of mētis, and in a Chinese context the particular type(s?) of indirection characterized as wuwei 無為. Both, in different ways, are centrally concerned with spontaneity. In Reason and Spontaneity, A.C. Graham attempted to address Hume's famous lacuna between “is” and “ought.” He proposed a theory of value that grounds all values in the imperative to “be aware,” an approach explicitly derived from the Zhuangzi. I reconsider these arguments from three points if view: (1) Graham's account of inclination informed by awareness as the basis for agency and choices among ends; (2) recent research on the biology of agency; and (3) possible continua between humans and animals. I conclude with a few brief remarks on how Greek mētis and Chinese wuwei might fit into such an account of awareness and spontaneity. 2 Keynotes Professor Wang Keping Institute of Philosophy Chinese Academy of Social Sciences Two Ways of Pursuing the Good life: The Beauty Ladder and the Mind Excursion Being two ancient thinkers living in the axial period, both Plato (428-348 BC) from Hellas and Zhuangzi (369-286 BC) from China are preoccupied with the human condition in general, and engaged in the search of the good life in particular. They have offered many interesting alternatives among which two acknowledged ones turn out to be more appealing to my reconsideration: one is renowned as the beauty ladder and the other the mind excursion. As depicted in the Symposium by Plato, the beauty ladder is set to comprise seven levels of beauty (kallos), ranging from the beauty of one body, the beauty of two bodies, the beauty of all bodies, the beauty of souls, the beauty of observances and laws, the beauty of learning or sciences, up to the very essence of beauty in itself, the essence that makes all other kinds of beauty become what they are. Having climbed up to the top of the ladder, one is so delighted to encounter with the main ocean of the beautiful, and thereby he attains not merely a peak experience of intellectual and spiritual joy via due contemplation, but also a fundamental knowledge of the idea of the beautiful itself. Such joy is a special type owing to its profundity, duration, and higher values. It is stemmed from intelligent intuition apart from aesthetic perception, and identified with the supreme happiness that leads one to live a worthwhile life. Allegorically, the seven levels of the beauty ladder imply a process of getting to know the seven kinds of beauty. The process as such involves personal cultivation that can be seen as an epistemological progression from the phenomenal to the essential, and a moral pilgrimage from the carnal attraction to the spiritual exaltation. Its possible accomplishment is supposed to lie in the step-by-step enlightenment via aesthetic wisdom, moral wisdom, political wisdom and theoretical wisdom. Then, as noted in The Great Venerable Master (Da zong shi) by Zhuangzi, the mind excursion is claimed to have eight stages of meditation for absolute spiritual freedom and independent personality. The eight stages as a whole consist in a process of self-cultivation through approaching and exercising the Dao itself. Specifically they include the first stage of going beyond the world (wai tianxia) that means the freedom from social engagement in search of ambition and fame, the second stage of going beyond external things (wai wu) that symbolizes the freedom from material acquisition and fetishist desires, the third stage of going beyond life (wai sheng) that implies the freedom from bodily preservation, the fourth stage of morning enlightenment (zhao che), the fifth stage of seeing the unique (jian du), the sixth stage of non-distinguishing between the past and the present (wu gu jin), the seventh stage of living in the realm of neither death nor life (ru yu bu si bu sheng) that is approximate to the state of nirvana, and the last stage of attaining the Dao in serenity (ying ning). All this features a gradually deepened understanding of what it takes to live well in the light of the Dao itself. It thus ranges from the initial insight into the Dao up to the final attainment of it as is companied by a free play with it. 3 Paper and Panel Abstracts Anstey, Peter The University of Sydney Back, Youngsun City University of Hong Kong Benitez, Rick The University of Sydney Black, Martin Socrates as dikaios in Plato’s Crito This paper argues that the central theme of Plato’s Crito is what it is for a person to be dikaios. It claims that Socrates’ attitude both to his impending death and to Crito’s offer to help him escape from prison reveal him to be the exemplar of such a person. Confucian Heaven and the Good Life This paper examines the Confucian conception of tian, conventionally translated into English as “Heaven.” The secondary literature on tian has primarily focused on the question of what tian is: e.g., whether tian is an anthropomorphic deity or a naturalistic force, or whether tian is transcendent or immanent. Instead, in this paper, I locate tian with respect the ethical life of human beings and argue that tian directly involves a particular way of understanding the world. Accordingly, by investigating the Confucian conception of tian, we can figure out how early Confucians perceived the world, how they conceived of the way to flourish in such a world, and what kind of flourishing life they actually dreamed of. This paper will provide us with a more comprehensive understanding of the role of virtue and the status of non-moral goods in the early Confucian conception of the good life. Cultivation and Harmony in Plato and Confucius Plato once wrote that "rhythm and harmonious adjustment are essential to the whole of human life," while Confucius claimed that "of the things brought about by the rites, harmony is the most valuable." For both, harmony provides the framework within which a conception of cultivation for both individual and society can be worked out. This paper will focus on three 'levels' of harmony in Plato and Confucius. The first is the level of rectification, where harmonious adjustment to right ways is necessary to potential future happiness. The second is the level of understanding, where ordinary rectification is adjusted to the greater melody of insight. The third is the level of performance, where musical life enables the philosopher or sage to promote not only personal happiness, but the happiness of society. Both Plato and Confucius believe that musical life constitutes the highest level of harmony, and the greatest cultivation possible for a human being. Thus, the harmony advocated by both philosophers is the very essence of cultivation, not something merely instrumental to it. I conclude with some observations about the application of Platonic and Confucian harmony to 21st Century society. The Forgotten Teaching of Classical Philosophy: Cultivation is the Imitation of Nature The central thesis of the understanding of human affairs of classical Greek philosophy is that human cultivation is an imitation of nature. This view is well known, but I intend to suggest that its meaning has been forgotten. The power of the new conception of nature promulgated by the early modern philosophers has apparently been confirmed by the political and scientific success of their project. As their heirs we are tempted to understand human affairs either as derivative directly from sub-human natural processes or as “cultural,” i.e. non-natural constructions. The classical view freely acknowledges the constructed nature of human affairs: the poetry and laws give human beings their ways of life or forms their souls, and the arts and sciences that sustain their bodies, are all human invention. However, they argue that our language, standards, and forms of knowledge are more or less imperfect reflections of the natural principles of things. This thesis has the advantage that it is hard to argue for a coherent alternative on the basis of reason. However, it culminates in a tension between the virtues cultivated for the political good and those cultivated for the good of philosophizing itself, or between theory and practice. 4 Buckingham, Will Sichuan University / De Montfort University Coulson, Lee The University of Sydney Di Lauro, Frances The University of Sydney Writing in the Service of Life: Liu Xie and the Practice of Literature In this paper, I will look at the notion of shengqi, or ‘nurturing vitality’ in Liu Xie’s Wenxin Diaolong, or ‘Literary Mind and Carving of Dragons’ to propose a notion of the craft of writing as a form of cultivation in the service of life. The practice of writing in the Western traditions has sometimes been claimed to be a form of derangement or possession that, potentially at least, uses up the writer. Alternatively, it has been seen as a practice that can act as a form of therapy, a means towards curing the writer of the ills of existence. But for Liu, writing can serve life in a way that departs radically from ideas of writing as a form of exhaustion, whilst also going beyond notions of therapy. Instead, it is an activity that can contribute actively to the nurturing of the vitality, or the liveliness, of life itself. In this paper, I will draw on Greek and Chinese sources, and also on my own practice as a writer. Moving between first and third-person perspectives, I aim to explore the virtuous circle that is suggested by Liu Xie’s text, a circle in which writing can act to nourish life, and equally, life can act to nourish writing. Cultivating εὐήθεια: the wisdom of noble simplicity Etymologically understood εὐήθεια is a compound of εὖ+ἦθος, and thus has the semantic value of good disposition or character. Yet in ancient Greece, and indeed much Platonic scholarship, the term is largely pejorative and generally connotes foolish naïveté and simplemindedness. My paper argues that Plato's regeneration of εὐήθεια seeks to redress what Thucydides warns are the dire consequences of losing "the ancient simplicity (τὸ εὔηθες)" (Th. 3.83.1). That Plato's progressively positive use of the term in the so-called early and transitional dialogues culminates in Republic’s affirmation of εὐήθεια as "the truly good and fair disposition (εὖ τε καὶ καλῶς τὸ ἦθος) of the character and the mind" (R. 400e), a noble and virtuous disposition he personifies in Laws' Εὐηθέστεροι Virtue-Hero-Myth. Εὐήθεια in Plato thus inscribes a remarkable semantic arc from its largely pejorative use in early Greek literature to its personification as the exemplary Εὐηθέστεροι, who as δαιμόνιο may afford the deific function of a personal tutelage deity. For Plato, then, the cultivation of εὐήθεια is seemingly essential to satisfying the soul's affections for the virtue qualities of courage, temperance and righteousness. Indeed, εὐήθεια may be synonymous with the wisdom that nurtures virtue and develops self-knowledge. Hence in Plato, where rightly cultivated, the deific spirit of εὐήθεια might mimics divine intelligence and endow the apprehension of εὐδαιμονία as the wisdom of noble simplicity. Esoteric concepts of self and self-cultivation in early Daoist thought Confucian texts like the Doctrine of the Mean, espouse self-cultivation by adhering to communal norms, refining relationships between “monarch and subjects … the father and the son … the husband and the wife etc.” Three moral traits of “sagacity, charity and character” are attained through “studying”, “charity” and “doing good deeds”, and having “a sense of shame.” Early Daoist self-cultivation texts instead prescribe internalized practice to achieve individual transcendence. Abstract or esoteric concepts of self-cultivation are first discernible in the philosophical speculations of the “Warring States” or Zhanguo age, the period to which the emergence of the Daoism can be traced. The earliest of these, the Neiye (“inward training”) grounds psychology and self-cultivation in a physiological substratum, and prescribes techniques to induce self-transcendence, optimum health, and longevity. This paper will examine the concept of the emptiness in Chinese philosophical thought, outlining the development of abstract notions of the self and self-cultivation practices in the formative period of daojia (Daoist philosophy), and the mutation in meaning of the concept of wu wei, variously rendered “non contrived,” “non-artificial, “non striving,” and “taking no action contrary to nature,” in texts that precede the Wang Bi, after which it was read as “non action.” 5 Fech, Andrej South University of Science and Technology of China Hendrischke, Barbara University of Sydney Hooper, Anthony University of Sydney The role played by auditory and visual perception in moral cultivation as represented in early Confucian and Daoist texts When consulting the early Chinese texts on the topic of moral cultivation, we encounter a large number of passages dealing with the issue of auditory (wen 聞) and visual (jian 見) perception. Moreover, this topic seems to be of comparable importance to philosophical traditions that had a radically different understanding of the nature of moral cultivation such as Confucianism and Daoism. Therefore, in this presentation, I am going to talk about similarities and differences in concepts of sensory perception as represented in the texts associated with the two schools. Its leading question can be formulated as to how perceptive abilities came to be connected to the question of moral excellence and which contents of sensory perception were regarded by the two schools as beneficial to cultivation. The talk will be based on such texts as the Xunzi 荀子, Laozi 老子, Zhuangzi 莊子 as well as the newly excavated texts Wuxing 五行 (Mawangdui, Guodian), Wenzi 文子 (Dingxian) and Ting you wu huan 聽有五患 (Yinqueshan). Nurturing life in the Laozi as understood by Han Fei The term “nurturing life” does not occur in the Laozi. However, what the Laozi says on lengthening life had a big impact on the text’s enduring popularity. This paper starts with a brief introduction to Laozi 50. This section deals with the threat of death. More questions are raised than answered. The paper’s main topic is Han Fei’s (d. 233 BCE) engagement with Laozi’s advice to avoid the “terrain of death”. Han Fei applies the innovative concept of “dao’s patterns” (dao li 道理) to argue that personal survival relies on the accurate and comprehensive analysis of one’s own situation. My, How Death Becomes You! or Cultivation, Death, and Immortality in Plato’s Symposium Plato is a thinker who is centrally concerned with the cultivation of a virtuous character, and no small amount of ink has been expended to explicate the faculties, behaviours, habits, and perspectives that one must develop to live a eudaimon life. But Plato’s interests in cultivation extend beyond ensuring a happy life, as he also has an interest in ensuring that one may enjoy a state of death that is maximally productive of virtue. But here I refer not to Plato’s various comments regarding the post-mortem existence of the soul, but a subject on which insufficient ink has been spilled: the account of immortality that is offered to us in the Symposium. This presentation is idiosyncratic because it does not concern the post-mortem existence of the soul, but rather concerns the vicissitudes of remembrance people may enjoy in this world. In the voice of Diotima, Socrates here details how people win immortality by having the memory of their virtue inspire others towards the production of virtue long after one’s death. According to Socrates, the enterprise of winning immortality through memory necessitates various modes of cultivation. These include: i) a re-evaluation from seeing virtue as something that is valuable only when it is ‘one’s own’ to something worthy of production in its own right; ii) a shift in emphasis from the production of virtue exclusively in oneself, to a concern in bringing about virtue in others; and iii) a commitment to the idea that the development of one’s own wisdom concerning virtue constitutes merely one stage in an inter-subjective process of learning. Prima facie these particular modes of cultivation of character appear relevant only to winning immortality, however they more generally underlie the foundations of the development of philosophical communities in life. In this way, happiness in death flowers from the same soil as happiness in life. Time permitting, I also hope to comment on whether this account of cultivation has any parallels in Confucianism and Daoism. 6 Hui, Oceana University of New South Wales Kim, Hyun Jin The University of Melbourne King, RAH Berne University Machek, David Berne University PANEL: Virtues, virtue and roles in China and Greece (Organiser: R.A.H. King) The Zhuangzi’s Free and Easy Wandering: Equanimity through Metacognition and its Associated Processes The opening chapter of the Zhuangzi, titled "逍遙遊", has been translated several ways: "Free and Easy Wandering", "Enjoyment in Untroubled Ease" or "Going Rambling Without a Destination". These various iterations bring to mind ideas of a calm, relaxed existence that is free from sources of worry. Accordingly, one might expect such a chapter to advocate a quiet, reticent life. Counterintuitively, there are no such prescriptions therein. Instead, one finds that it is brimming with paradoxical anecdotes, dialogue, and witty criticisms. This paper adopts a literary analysis approach to examine how the narrative form of the text itself might trigger metacognition through the continual disruption of reader expectation. In doing so, it is suggested that achieving a state of equanimity involves the restructuring of both cognitive and affective dispositions. The ‘Good Life’ according to the sages: ‘Solon’ and ‘Confucius’ The ancient Greeks and the early Chinese both articulated the good life and also discussed what was good about it in their surviving works of literature. This paper examines the Greek perception of the good life as presented by 'Solon' in Book 1 of Herodotus. That perception is then compared with the 'Confucian' articulation of the good life as practiced by the Junzi. It is observed that the socio-political milieu of both traditions is critical to understanding the similarities and differences in the respective representations of the good life in Greece and China. Virtue and a swarm of virtues (King) In Plato’s Meno, Socrates famously argues against Meno’s view that there are lots of virtues – a swarm – for men, women, children, and he demands that meno give him a definition of virtue – that form because of which anything is virtue, if it is virtue (72C). Aristotle, as is well known argues against this view, but only in the Politics (I 13) – where he poses the question about whether there can be virtues for slaves and women and children. His view of politics is based on the family, and extends these roles to the operation of the city. In this paper, I present Socrates’s arguments, and suggest that Aristotle is right, both in having a general account of virtue in itself and in wanting to preserve the role centred virtues. In the absence of a general account of virtue in China the question arises of what serves as the core of virtue, and I scout some possibilities, above all wisdom. Because not all have wisdom, this view of virtue militates for forms of social dependence. It is also a central claim of the Socratic tradition. Being a tax-collector, a human, a wife: China Warring States views about self-cultivation in light of a role-defined self (Machek) Is studying philosophy or learning how to control one’s emotions more conducive to becoming a better person than learning to play the piano, or even learning to cook? Is development of some skills or habits more central for cultivating one’s self than of some others? The answer will depend largely on what we think this “person” or “self” actually is. Besides defining the self in terms of entity (e.g. soul, mind, character or body), we can also define the self in terms of its role: one can be a father, an officer, and/or simply a living being. One’s self can be defined by multiple roles (that may be in tension with each other), or by one fundamental role from which other roles are derived. What exactly the self defined by its role amounts to, and what are the implications for the appropriate self-cultivation curricula, was a much debated issue in Warring States thought. Three different accounts from different fourth century B.C.E. texts – Mengzi, Zhuangzi, as well as a Guodian text “Six excellences” – will be outlined in order to bring out the diversity of existing positions in this debate. 7 Lai, Karyn The University of New South Wales Lee, Yungwhan Inje University Ley, James University of Sydney Reliability as the linchpin of Confucian life In Analects 2.22, Confucius remarks on the implausibility—or impossibility—of a life lacking in xin 信, reliability (人而無信,不知其可也). In discussions of Confucian philosophy, this aspect of life is often eclipsed by greater emphasis on Confucian values such as ren 仁 (benevolence) and yi 義 (rightness). More attention is typically given to the Confucian value orientation, with less detail provided on the cultivation processes that underpin the successful realisation of values. My discussion addresses this imbalance by focusing on reliability, extending current debates in two ways. First, it proposes that the common translation of xin as ‘trustworthiness’—to denote coherence between a person’s words and deeds—is inadequate. The translation fails to capture the longer-term consistency in a person’s actions and behaviours in different circumstances across time, which is an irreducible dimension of xin. Second, I suggest that reliability is not only moral but also epistemic in nature. That is, in order to be able to proceed (行 xing; Analects 15.6) reliably, a person needs to know how best to act or respond in different circumstances. I focus especially on the processes involved in equipping oneself with this knowledge. Cultivation of reason and ethics as an invitation to philosophy Aristotle characterizes the good person as “heeding the reason/argument” (logoi peitharchein). While the masses, living according to passion, should be persuaded only with penalties, reason and teaching (logos kai didachê) cultivates the soul of the well brought up person to enjoy and hate proper things. Even though it is obvious that the reason takes the central place in Aristotle’s ethics, the reasonableness (capacity to heed the reason) of the good person, how it is cultivated and how the excellences of the character (not only the excellences of the intellect) are related with it, has not been given sufficient discussion. Nicomachean ethics will be the primary text I will discuss but I will also examine Plato’s Gorgias and the discussion of the power of logos in it also. I will suggest in the end that we read NE as protrepticus where Aristotle encourages students with good upbringing to listen to and appreciate (the power of) his arguments and be properly motivated to follow philosophers’ path in their lives. The cultivation of memory in Classical Greek Philosophy For both Plato and Aristotle living well involves acting in the right way in relation to the capacities of human memory. Both philosophers describe iterative practices that affect memory and determine whether we live well or badly. These practices concern both the acquisition and retrieval of memories and they have effects both upon our access to knowledge and our ability to live a good life. Plato’s recommendation that philosophers target the retrieval of long-held propositional memories is familiar to us as his ‘theory of recollection’. But he also carefully warns against the harmful acquisition of new memories in the Phaedo. In this paper I consider Plato’s separation of beneficial and harmful practices in relation to memory and Aristotle’s responses to it. 8 Liang, Yuhan Nanyang Technological University Lind, Per Lund University Liu, Linna Nanyang Technological University Thinking as a method to cultivate moral character For Mencius, moral cultivation is to nurture a moral character through long time practice and thinking (si思) is a main method to do it. However, if we scrutinize the whole text, some inconsistencies can be found. On the one hand, Mencius proposes people should think to be moral. On the other hand, he also seems to appreciate the moral actions that are carried out without thinking. In this paper, I try to provide a plausible explanation of this problem by deciphering the functions of thinking in moral practice. Despite that one can carry out moral actions occasionally, this kind of moral impulse is unstable. Thinking is crucial for moral fortitude because both the epistemological problem and motivation problem can be solved by thinking in practice. Firstly, thinking not only can reinforce incipient moral judgments in mindheart but also assist mind-heart to make proper decisions in moral dilemmas. Secondly, since thinking maintains a moral view, when one fails to do what ought to do, feeling of shame would be triggered and motivate one to try again and harder until he fulfills the goal. Thus thinking can assist one to adhere on the moral practice, until one nourishes virtuous character and performs moral will spontaneously and reliably in the most time. How to Learn from Fake Mistakes: Raising metaconceptual awareness the Pyrrhonist way The present paper proposes that the wisdom cultivation technique prescribed by the ancient Greek art-of-living school of Pyrrhonism sidesteps the central transformative issue of the Stoic and Epicurean systems, namely the molding of the practitioner’s cognitive outlook into accordance with school dogma. Instead, it is argued, the Pyrrhonean technique of deliberately seeding cognitive conflict (“fake mistakes”) in the mind of the practitioner aims to wake her up to the contingency, instrumentality and negotiability of the cognitive structures she already employs. Observing that in everyday experience, the presence of cognitive conflict (and its functional corollary perplexity) signals the occurrence of a mistake (in the form of cognitive failure and/or misjudgment) the basic developmental potential inherent to states of cognitive conflict and perplexity is undeniable. According to the proposed reading, the Pyrrhonean technique effectively harnesses the unique – and most likely hardwired – function of cognitive conflict in the human cognitive architecture to derail habitual and automated ways of conceiving the world so as to bring consciousness to bear more immediately on the conflicting structures of cognition, which otherwise tend to function outside the direct reach of volitional thought. In thus effectuating a shift from the cognition of reality to the cognition of cognition, cognitive conflict enables the owning up to of previously unacknowledged instances and levels of cognitive agency. Forgetting Emotions: Zhuangzi’s Pursuit of Peaceful Mind Zhuangzi advocates a peaceful mind free from the disturbance of emotions. However, his perspective towards emotions seems contradictory. Does he mean that sages will keep positive emotions like ordinary people, or should eliminate all influence of emotions? Evidences on both views can be found in the Inner Chapters. In this paper, I will firstly argue that both the opinions of “with emotions” and “without emotions” fail to explain some counter examples in the text. Secondly, I will raise the idea of “forgetting emotions” as a better approach to interpret Zhuangzi’s perspective, with which we are able to read the text of the Zhuangzi consistently. Thirdly, I will demonstrate how people can reach the state of “forgetting emotions”, and “fasting of mind” will be discussed as one of the most important approaches to deal with emotions. 9 Liu, Ni Shanghai Jiao Tong University Pfister, Lauren Hong Kong Baptist University Ciccotti, Jesse Hong Kong Baptist University (PANEL) Anger and Self-Cultivation in the Analects Yuet Keung Lo advocates the ability to manage one’s anger is a sign of one’s selfcultivation. He takes Yanhui as a good role model for the ability to master anger; Confucius praises Yanhui for “not taking his anger out on others (不迁怒)” in the Analects. However, in the Analects, Confucius also finds that anger (忿) can make one lose awareness of one’s safety and for his/her parents. The solution to this problem is to turn his/her thoughts to the consequences. Besides that, Confucius relates one’s safety to his/her piety (孝). In this way, how to manage one’s anger (忿) has a crucial role to play in one’s self-cultivation. In this paper I will discuss the two ways of managing one’s anger in the Analects as well as scholars’ interpretations of the relationship between anger and self-cultivation. Dislodging Mundane Wisdom: Counter-Cultural Alternatives for Transformative Forms of Cultivation in the Dialogic Teachings and Paradoxical Rhetoric of Master Zhuāng and Rabbi Yeshuah (Pfister) Practical wisdom is often dressed in rationalized garb, especially among the literati elite in ancient China and the philosophical teachings of major intellectuals in ancient Greece. They regularly presented a form of prudential wisdom couched within rationalized visions of life involving idealized rulers and their own sagely teachers. Nevertheless, counter points to these teachings were explicitly articulated in the more paradoxical dialogues of Master Zhuāng and Rabbi Yeshuah (or, as Witherington intones, the “Sage Jesus”). In order to dislodge more rationalized versions of wisdom in their own traditions, both employ “dislodging” paradoxes and parables with embedded critiques in order to reorient the development of a form of practical wisdom based upon transformative understandings of the nature of reality – including the human selves living within those realities. Based on revised reflections about the use of dialogic / pluralogic speech texts in selected portions of the Inner Chapters of the Zhuāngzǐ (following cues from Yearley and DeFoort) and the Four Gospels in the New Testament (with help from Witherington), I will seek to characterize and compare these two varying approaches to practical wisdom. Within this process, I will argue that transformative experience must precede the search for practical wisdom for both sages, leading subsequently to new expressions of inner peace, and fidelity to the Way. As already suggested, both Master Zhuāng and Rabbi Yeshuah initiate this transformative process by dislodging contemporary forms of “mundane wisdom” for the sake of recognizing and pursuing alternative and higher (and therefore therapeutically more satisfying) forms of sagacity. The Feelings of Kingship: Mèngzǐ and Marcus Aurelius on Regal Emotion (Ciccotti) Central to discussions of action and agency is the role of the emotions, and both Stoic and Ruist (Confucian) traditions make much of the role of emotions in the moral life in particular. While some general studies have been made to compare Greek and Chinese theories of emotion,1 specific studies that closely examine texts comparing Stoic and Ruist views of emotion and its relation to ruling have not yet been undertaken. My paper will seek to fill this gap by comparing the writings of the Roman Emperor Marcus Aurelius (AD 120180) and the Chinese philosopher Mèngzǐ (372-289 BC). In particular, I will be exploring the role(s) Aurelius and Mèngzǐ believes the emotions play in the activity of ruling, and what prescriptions for cultivating and exercising these emotions they advocate in order to assist the ruler in ruling well. I will argue that appropriate regulation and engagement with apposite emotions is a key resource that enables a ruler to perceive the needs of the people and respond fittingly. 1 E.g., G.E.R. Lloyd, “The Greeks and Chinese on the emotions and the problem of cross-cultural universals and cultural relativism,” in How Should One Live?, ed. R.A.H. King and D. Shilling (Berlin: de Gruyter, 2010), 241-258. 10 Pierdziwol, Annette The University of Notre Dame Australia Riegel, Jeffrey The University of Sydney Sharpe, Matthew Deakin University Sin, William Hong Kong Institute of Education Aristotle on role of habit in moral education This paper examines the role of habituation in Aristotle’s account of how the virtues are acquired. The first part of the paper surveys recent positions in the debate between non-cognitivist and cognitivist interpretations and considers their relation to the ‘paradox of moral development’ (the progression from habituated virtue to reflective virtue). Focussing on some of the more persuasive proposals from the cognitivist camp, and in view of the charge levelled against them that they lack any explicit textual warrant, the second part of the paper pursues a close reading of key passages where Aristotle discusses the role of habituation in virtue acquisition, and seeks to offer a clearer account of the concrete resources Aristotle can and cannot offer contemporary philosophers of education on this question. Emotion and Accumulation in the Xunzi Two key elements in the theory of moral cultivation found in the text of the Xunzi are qing 情 (emotion) and ji 積 (accumulation). Several passages in the text illustrate how emotional reactions to stimuli of various sorts disclose to a subject the boundaries of proper behavior while learning and other experiences one has accumulated guide a subject in transforming insightful feelings into a fuller understanding of what one ought to do. The meaning of some key passages that relate to these ideas of moral cultivation remains obscure and the passages themselves are perhaps corrupt. Part of the problem is that the old forms of the graphs 情 and 積 were sufficiently similar that they were easily confused by scribes. There is of course a wealth of philological research on these passages done mostly during the 17th and 18th centuries. This paper re-examines these passages and the relevant scholarship on them and then offers what the author takes to be the best readings. Cultivation in Seneca: Ilsetraut Hadot’s Spiritual Direction and Practice of Philosophy 2015 saw the translation of Ilsetraut Hadot’s magisterial study on Seneca: Spiritual Direction and Practice of Philosophy into the French language. In contrast to recent analytic treatments of his thought, the book argues that Seneca’s Stoicism and his philosophical writings should be conceived as belonging to a long Greek and Roman tradition of “spiritual direction”. This paper will critically reconstruct Hadot’s claims concerning the practice of philosophical cultivation in Seneca’s writings, paying particular attention to her defence of “the very idea” of such cultivation against analytic readings of the great Roman Stoic. Bruce Lee, Zhixing, and the Trolley Problem: Cultivating the Right Response in the Desperate Moment When an agent comes across a desperate situation, his ability to perform the right action is often not a mere matter of theoretical clarification, but practical deliverance. In the case of Trolley, for instance, even if it would be morally better for the agent to save five lives by diverting an out-of-control trolley onto an innocent victim, he might not have the strength and determination to perform the action. This point is echoed by the martial artist Bruce Lee in his book Tao of Jeet Kune Do. Lee says that in the case of street combat, unless the agent is prepared to die, and has complete devotion to deal with the difficulty which arises in the moment, he will not survive the challenge. In this paper, I will describe this ability with reference to the virtue of zhixing 直性; the literal meaning of zhixing involves a preparedness to respond to challenge in a straightforward manner and with complete determination. In addition to Lee’s elaboration, I will explain the virtue of zhixing with reference to the doctrines of Zen Buddhism and Confucianism respectively. 11 Suzuki, Yumi University of Hong Kong Tiquia, Rey University of Melbourne “Examining a life” in the ‘Teaching’ of Socrates and Confucius Both arête (ἀρετή/virtue) and ren (仁/humanity) are one of the most frequently discussed topics in Socratic and Confucian ‘teaching’. Socrates famously suggests that it is the greatest thing to discuss arete and to test himself and others on the issue because the unexamined life is not worth living (Apology 38a). He thinks that the discussion should come first, before the state of being virtuous, or any action whereby to practice virtue, because it is impossible for us to examine how to come to possess the virtue before knowing what it is (Meno 71b). On the other hand, Confucius often responds to the question of what ren, renzhe (仁者) is, or what it is to practice ren in various ways (4/1-7, 5/8, 19, 6/26, 7/30, 34, 12/2, 3, 22, 14/1, 4). Ren is developed through reading the Classics, learning traditions and rituals, whereby we reflect on ourselves in order to achieve ren (1/4, 4/17, 9/24,). This paper demonstrates that the two different paths to become a good person entail different modes of doing moral philosophy: the former focusses on developing hypothetical methods to approach the destination, while the latter on the pragmatic approaches to the process. The Wisdom of Developing the Habit of Cultivating and Aligning the Flow of Our Life Force (qi) With The Movement of the Season/Time For Good Health and Good Life In the prologue to his book On Their Own Terms Science in China, 1550-1900, Benjamin Elman observed that ‘like their classicist counterparts in sixteenth-century Europe, the Chinese authors of natural histories sought to identify and classify natural phenomena through correct use of language of words. For them, all phenomena originated from the stuff of the world (qi) formed through the spontaneous shaping of all things (zaohua) by some sort of ultimate shaping force (zaohua zhu) or internal power (zaowu zhu). They mediated efforts to make sense of the world of things through their prevailing social, political and cultural hierarchies.’ Therefore, qi acts. Qi translates. Qi defines. Qi flows. Qi gets stuck. Qi gets unstuck. When qi ‘assemble’ 聚 there is life. When qi disperses 散, there is death and a new form of life.” “The cosmic yin and yang qi of the ‘sky/heaven/ celestial sphere’ 天 and ‘earth/terrestrial sphere’ 地 ascend and descend and climatic weather conditions during the‘four seasons’ resonate with these changes. Humanity must harmonize and adapt to these changes as well. During spring and summer seasons, one must nurture the cosmic yang qi while during the autumn and winter seasons one must nurture the cosmic yin qi. In this way, unusual illnesses will not come about. According to Chinese medical theory, if one maintains a balance of heart and mind and a qi (yang) 氣 and blood (yin) 血 that flow in harmony with the world around them xin he qi ping 心和氣平, then there will be a presence of good health. And in accordance with the classical, modern, Eastern and Western senses, ‘good humour’ or good qi flow that is a natural effect of the alignment of emotions and seasons, which if absent should be restored. As Joseph Needham puts it: “When one feels naturally happy, and free from self-seeking and upsetting personal desires or greedy ambitions, then the salutary qi of necessity responds and follows. Vitality thus guarding from within, how can diseases originate.” 12