Life Goals and Health Decisions What will people live (or die) for? Alan Schwartz Gordon Hazen (NWU) Ariel Leifer Paul Heckerling Funded by grant SES-0451122 from the National Science Foundation (Decision, Risk, and Management Sciences) to Schwartz and Hazen, PIs. Mike Richards also assisted in data collection for this project. Overview What’s a QALY? How do we measure QALYs? What’s wrong with QALYs? How might knowing about life goals help? Which life goals really count? Now what? What’s a QALY? The most important method for evaluating health-related quality of life. Central to medical decision and costeffectiveness analyses. A common metric that weights quantity and quality of life. QALY defined Years(stat e) * Quality(st ate) QALY health states in remaining lifetime Quality() ranges from 0 (death) to 1 (perfect health) For example: •Two years of life in perfect health = 2 QALYs •Four years of life in health quality 0.5 = 2 QALYs How do we measure QALYs? Subjectively querying patients, physicians, or community members. Most common method: time-tradeoff utility assessment Time-Tradeoff Imagine your remaining life expectancy is 20 years Imagine you’re going to spend those 20 years in a single sub-perfect health state, like blindness Would you rather: Live for 20 years with blindness Live for 16 years in perfect health QALYs If your Quality(blindness) = 0.60, and you expect to live 20 more years (12 QALYs): A medical treatment that would cure your blindness would provide you with 8 additional QALYs And you should prefer that treatment over extending your (blind) life by 10 years (6 QALYs) What’s wrong with QALYs? Tsevat (2000) notes that numerous studies have demonstrated that: The correlation between one’s current health and the time-tradeoff utility for that health state is at best modest. Willingness to trade away time is often much less than the general public, health care professionals, and even family members believe. Unwillingness to trade off Miyamoto and Eraker (1988) found that subjects might: accept a tradeoff of life duration for improved health quality when remaining lifetime was long but decline all tradeoffs if remaining lifetime was short. Maximum endurable time (Sutherland, et al. 1982, and others) Sometimes, people indicate they can tolerate no more than a particular time in an undesirable health state, beyond which each additional increment of time decreases overall utility. Miyamoto et al. relate an instance of a patient who regarded his health state as almost intolerable, but who wanted to live at least 5 more years to see his son graduate from high school. Quality of What? In Robert Harling’s play Steel Magnolias, Shelby, a young diabetic woman chooses to put her health at risk by bearing a child, saying… Quality of What? Shelby illustrates a distinction pointed out by Tsevat (2000): a person’s willingness or unwillingness to trade away life years or accept a gamble involving life years is more a function of how the person values quality of life than quality of health. Quality of What? Several of the problems with QALYs can be explained – and even motivated – by noting that quality of life is more than quality of health What issues are potentially relevant to quality of life? Adding extrinsic goals to the QALY model Specifically, quality of life may also include attainment of relevant extrinsic goals extrinsic here meaning: goals achievable at a specific point in time E.g. Shelby’s goal of having a child For extrinsic goals, the level of goal achievement has importance that is unrelated to life duration. Shelby’s goal of bearing a child has value that is independent of her length of life – having borne a child has the same value to Shelby whether she lives 5 or 15 or 30 years. This value cannot be expressed in standard QALYs. Examples of extrinsic life goals Shelby wants to bear a child; an author wants to complete a book; an athlete wants to compete in the Olympics; an artist wants to complete a major work; an engineer or architect hopes to see a building raised; a politician wishes to achieve higher office; a celebrity plans to write their memoirs; political activists seek campaign reform legislation; individuals seek the financial and social welfare of their families. How do life goals help? Extrinsic goals might account for lack of willingness to trade away time or take a gamble that might shorten life Why should an author trade away or risk time she needs to complete an important work, for health quality improvements that do not affect her ability to write? Maximum endurable time is sensible if one’s worse-than-death health state is compensated for by the ability to attain a goal in the near future. Moreover, goal-related issues may impact the value structure appropriate for decision analyses. For instance, prophylactic oophorectomy is an option for women at high risk for ovarian cancer; but this course of action negatively impacts the extrinsic goal of bearing children. Our research program 1. 2. 3. 4. 5. 6. Studies of life goals: create a taxonomy Develop new utility models that can incorporate goal achievement, multiple goals Develop utility assessment procedures that are goal-sensitive Repeat or simulate decision analyses with goal-sensitive utilities Replicate unwillingness-to-trade studies and ask whether goal differences can explain results Explore implications for societal cost-effectiveness analyses Phone survey: Methods Fifty Chicago-area residents Contacted using random-digit dialing Interviewed by telephone, paid $25 Each respondent asked to generate: Three goals they hoped to achieve within the next five years One goal they hoped to achieve within the next ten years One goal they hoped to achieve during their remaining lifetime. Phone survey: Methods For each goal, the respondent was asked how long they thought the goal might take to achieve, in years; whether they would prefer a shorter lifetime with certain goal achievement to their full lifetime without goal achievement; whether they would prefer lower quality of health with certain goal achievement to their full health without goal achievement. Phone survey: Analysis Two investigators (AS and AL) independently reviewed the list of goals and developed taxonomic classifications. The classification systems were compared and each goal was reviewed by the two investigators jointly to resolve any disagreements. Goal categories were then analyzed to determine whether the categorization could predict goals for which respondents would be significantly more willing to trade off either life or health for goal achievement. Mixed logistic models were fitted with SAS PROC GENMOD to predict willingness to trade off from goal category; correlations in willingness to trade off within each subject were modeled assuming compound symmetry. Taxonomy of Goals Goals 232 Education 20 Health & Fitness 21 Family 50 Family Member 27 Self 28 Personal Fulfillment 17 Job 38 Professional 54 Retire 16 Travel 25 Wealth 59 Financial Personal Real Security Property Property 28 6 26 Results: Who will trade? Participants were willing to trade life years for goal achievement in 43% of goals, but were willing to trade health for goal achievement in only 29% of goals Trading life years Considerable correlation for goals within subject (r = 0.42, p<.05) Women were significantly more likely to trade off life years than men (OR = 2.49, 95% CI=[1.04, 2.95], p=0.04). No differences by age, race, or goal horizon (5 year, 10 year, life) Trading health Considerable correlation in willingness to trade health for goals within subject (r = 0.37, p<.05). No differences by gender, age, race, or goal horizon Results: Trade to achieve what? Goals categorized as family, wealth, professional, other. Controlling for goal category and interactions, women were still significantly more likely than men to be willing to trade off life years (OR = 3.69, 95% CI = [1.28, 10.62], p = 0.016). No difference for trading health Controlling for gender and interactions, respondents were significantly more likely to trade life years for family goals than any other type of goal (OR = 7.39, [2.42, 22.50], p < 0.001). Similar for trading health (OR = 5.11 [1.67, 15.61], p = 0.0042). However, men were 1.55 times more likely to trade life years for family goals than women (p = 0.0092) and 4.72 times more likely to trade health for family goals than women (p=0.001). Willingness to trade life years Odds ratio 10 1 Family Wealth Professional Other Male Female 0.1 Goal category Willingness to trade health Odds Ratio 10 1 Family Wealth Professional Other Male Female 0.1 Goal category Implications Potential systematic bias in utility assessment, and a caution to those who might seek to interpret preference-based utilities as measures of quality of health. Patients who are asked to assess their utilities for health states using a time-tradeoff method and who have salient family goals may express greater willingness to trade life years if they are likely to achieve their goals in the years remaining to them than patients with other salient goals. Implications As a result, patients with family goals, especially male patients, may generate significantly lower utilities for health states that threaten those goals than patients with other life goals, not because they necessarily consider the quality of those states to be worse, but because their quality of life would suffer so much from being denied their goal. Alternately, patients won’t want to trade off time to escape a health state that does not threaten a life goal, particularly if the life goal requires time for its achievement. The health state would thereby be overvalued, especially if patients refuse to trade off any time at all. Now what? 1. Studies of life goals: create a taxonomy 2. 3. 4. 5. 6. Second study: 100 inpatients at UIC and VA hospitals Develop new utility models that can incorporate goal achievement, multiple goals Develop utility assessment procedures that are goalsensitive Repeat or simulate decision analyses with goalsensitive utilities Replicate unwillingness-to-trade studies and ask whether goal differences can explain results Explore implications for societal cost-effectiveness analyses The Final Thought People facing medical decisions may – and should – consider not only: 1. How long they might live 2. In what state of health But also: 3. What they are living for (and, if we are to measure quality of life correctly) 4. What they would be willing to die (sooner) for.