Religious belief Michael Lacewing enquiries@alevelphilosophy.co.uk © Michael Lacewing Belief-that • Standard analysis: content + attitude • Content: what the person believes, given by a proposition – E.g. ‘He believes that elephants are grey.’ • Belief-that aims at truth: – Beliefs are true or false (unlike desire) – To believe that p is to believe that p is true. – To say ‘I believe that p’ implies that you take p to be true. Other types of belief • ‘I believe him’ = – ‘I believe that what he says is true’ – ‘I believe that he is trustworthy/sincere’ • Belief-in – ‘I believe in God’ = ‘I believe that God exists’? – ‘I believe in love’ – Not belief-that (no truth claim), but faith, trust, commitment Religious belief • Does belief in God presuppose belief that God exists? – Yes: you can’t believe in a person if you think they don’t exist – No: you don’t have believe that love exists (literally) to believe in love • What is more basic in religious belief? Should belief-that be analysed as (really) belief-in or vice-versa? The religious ‘hypothesis’ • Is ‘God exists’ a factual hypothesis about reality? – Presupposes that the claim expresses a beliefthat • Empirical statements are capable of being false; the meaning of the statement is connected to this. – What circumstances or tests would lead us to atheism? Is the test correct? • A statement can be empirical without us knowing what experiences would show that it is false. • ‘God exists’ may help explain experience - it is tested not directly by experience but by philosophical argument. • But philosophy is not what gives ‘God exists’ its meaning. Does ‘God exist’ state a fact? • Not tested against empirical experience • Not purely intellectual • Theism not acquired by argument or evidence • Religious ‘belief’ is belief-in, an attitude or commitment, towards life, others, history, morality… a way of living. Objections • Different religions can prescribe similar ways of life while arguing for different beliefs about God – Orthodoxy (right belief) has been thought very important • What supports or justifies the attitude if not beliefs about how things are? • Perhaps religions distinguished by their stories – But stories don’t justify commitments • This approach makes religion too subjective Wittgenstein on meaning • To understand language, we must understand how it is used. • Compare uses of language to ‘games’ - rules that allow or disallow certain moves/meanings • Surface grammar v. depth grammar – ‘The bus passes the bus stop’ v. ‘The peace of the Lord passes all understanding’ – Asking your boss for a raise v. asking God for prosperity • Language is part of life, a ‘form’ of life Wittgenstein on religious belief • So religious language takes its meaning from religious life • Its surface grammar looks empirical, but its depth grammar is very different – God is not a ‘thing’ like any other – ‘a religious belief could only be something like a passionate commitment to a system of reference. Hence, although it’s a belief, it’s really a way of living, or a way of assessing life. It’s passionately seizing hold of this interpretation.’ (Culture and Value, §64) Implications • The ‘Last Judgment’ is not a future event • Prayer is not asking to be given good things • Talk of ‘God’ only makes sense in the context of religious belief - God does not ‘exist’ independent of belief in God • Religious belief cannot be criticized by facts and ‘evidence’, although it must make sense as part of human life Objection • This interpretation contradicts what most religious believers believe! • Suggestion: religious language is both factual and expressive