Transnational Security and Human Rights: Bridging the Divide Ian Turner Lancashire Law School University of Central Lancashire idturner@uclan.ac.uk Overview of presentation • Attacks by Islamist terrorists • Counter-Terrorism and Security Act 2015 • A right to security • A ‘positive’ right to security Ian Turner Lancashire Law School University of Central Lancashire idturner@uclan.ac.uk • Theoretical justifications for a ‘positive’ right to security Attacks by Islamist terrorists • ‘9/11’ (2001) • ‘The Shoe-bomber’ (Richard Reid) (2001) • The ‘Ricin case’, a plot to spread the deadly poison ricin on the streets of Britain (2003) • Madrid train bombings (2004) Attacks by Islamist terrorists • The ‘7/7’ attacks on the London transport network (2005) • ‘21st July’ failed suicide bombings in London (2005) • ‘Airline Bomb Plot’, a plot to blow up planes flying with home-made liquids (2006) • Car Bomb attack in Glasgow (2007) • Failed suicide bombing in Exeter (2008) Attacks by Islamist terrorists • Failed attempt to blow up an airliner at Detroit airport on Christmas Day (2009) • Parcel bomb from Yemen found at East Midlands airport (2010) • Woolwich attacks (2013) • Shootings at the Jewish Museum in Brussels (2014) • Massacre at the offices of Charlie Hebdo in Paris (2015) ISIL – and the raising of the domestic terror threat level The Counter-Terrorism and Security Act 2015 “The shocking attacks in Paris last month, in which 17 people lost their lives, and the many plots that the police and security and intelligence agencies continually work to disrupt, are clear evidence of the threat we face from terrorism.” The Counter-Terrorism and Security Act 2015 • Section 1 – seizure of passports etc from persons suspected of involvement in terrorism • Section 2 – imposition of temporary exclusion orders from the United Kingdom • Section 16 – amendment of the TPIMs 2011 Act allowing for a residence specified by the Secretary of State, including at least 200 miles away from a suspect’s home A right to security: (1) ‘Negative individual security against the state’ The right to security of an individual is an example of a: i) ‘First Generation’ ii) ‘civil and political’ iii) ‘negative’ right iv) a ‘freedom from’ state intrusion. Article 5(1) of the European Convention on Human Rights (ECHR): ‘Everyone has a right to liberty and security of person.’ A right to security: (2) ‘Security as justification to limit human rights’ Many individual human rights are ‘qualified’, in that they can be infringed by the state only for legitimate purposes such as security. Article 8(1) of the ECHR is the right to privacy but is qualified by Article 8(2), in the interests of: i) national security ii) territorial integrity or public safety iii) for the prevention of disorder or crime etc A right to security: (3) ‘International, collective or human security’ The right to security is also a: i) ‘Third Generation’ ii) ‘collective’ right of peoples and groups of individuals. For example, Article 23(1) of the African Charter on Human and Peoples’ Rights (ACHPR) states: ‘All peoples shall have the right to national and international peace and security.’ A right to security: (3) ‘International, collective or human security’ The ‘responsibility to protect populations from genocide, war crimes, ethnic cleansing and crimes against humanity’ (‘R2P’) • This imposes obligations on states to protect their civilians (‘Pillar I’) and • the international community to help states meet those obligations (‘Pillar II’). A right to security: (3) ‘International, collective or human security’ If a state has ‘manifestly failed’ in its duty to protect, then ‘Pillar III’ is particularly relevant: ‘The international community…has the responsibility to use In this context, we are prepared to appropriate diplomatic, take collective action, in a timely humanitarian and other peaceful and decisive manner…on a casemeans…to help to protect by-case basis and in cooperation populations... with relevant regional organizations as appropriate, should peaceful means be inadequate…’ A right to security: (4) ‘Positive state obligation to offer security to individuals against other individuals’ The final security concept requires states to take ‘positive’ measures to prevent harms committed by non-state actors. In protecting individuals from violations of rights by third parties – killing, torture, enforced disappearance, slavery, for example – states are obliged to, say, criminalise such abuses and to investigate, prosecute, convict and adequately punish those found to be responsible A right to security: (5) ‘Positive state obligation to offer security to individuals against other individuals’ Regionally, the concept of ‘positive’ obligations seems to be most developed in the case law of the ECHR, such as: • Article 3, freedom from torture and inhuman and degrading treatment and punishment: MC v. Bulgaria (2005) 40 EHRR 20 In some instances ‘positive’ obligations can be drawn from the text of the right itself: • Article 2(1) states: ‘Everyone’s right to life shall be protected by law.’ A right to security: (5) ‘Positive state obligation to offer security to individuals against other individuals’ Individual protections aside, the ECHR also imposes a ‘positive’ duty on member states to respect human rights; indeed, the full title of the ECHR is the ‘Convention for the Protection of Human Rights and Fundamental Freedoms’. And of particular significance is Article 1 of the ECHR: ‘The High Contracting Parties shall secure to everyone within their jurisdiction the rights and freedoms defined in Section I of this Convention.’ Bridging the divide: a ‘positive’ right to security • A lawful killing? • A lawful torture? • Greater ‘controls’ over those suspected of terrorism? Theoretical justifications for a ‘positive’ right to security: ‘social contract’ (1) Thomas Hobbes (1588-1679) • Hobbes’ most famous work was Leviathan which was first published in 1651. • Hobbes lived during a very turbulent time in England’s history eg Civil War so was greatly concerned at the evil of state collapse. Hobbes sought, therefore, to effect a strong central authority that maintained peace and order. Theoretical justifications for a ‘positive’ right to security: ‘social contract’ (1) Thomas Hobbes (1588-1679) • If not, anarchy, which Hobbes described as a ‘state of nature’, would ensue – a place where only the strong would survive • Human life in the ‘state of nature’ would be: ‘solitary, poor, nasty, brutish, and short’. Theoretical justifications for a ‘positive’ right to security: ‘social contract’ (1) Thomas Hobbes (1588-1679) • Only when the state had failed to fulfil its bargain of protection had it exceeded its authority and the individual’s duties to honour the social contract were severed. Theoretical justifications a ‘positive’ right to security: ‘social contract’ (1) Thomas Hobbes (1588-1679) • In condoning an oppressive government – if it provides peace and order – this state ‘absolutism’ ignores the reason why we may be entertaining a right to security in the first place: • to protect the very principles of democracy we are seeking to defend. • Indeed, Hobbes also failed to appreciate how the state itself might pose a threat to security Theoretical justifications for a ‘positive’ right to security: ‘social contract’ (2) John Locke (1632-1704) • For Hobbes bad government was better than no government. Not so for John Locke who was writing a generation after Hobbes. • Locke’s principal work, Two Treatises of Government, which was published in 1690, was a reaction to the allegedly tyrannical government of James II. Theoretical justifications for a ‘positive’ right to security: ‘social contract’ (2) John Locke (1632-1704) • But Locke further believed that the individual’s obligation to obey the state, in return for security, ceased in circumstances less demanding than a breakdown of peace and order: ‘To tell people they may provide for themselves by erecting a new legislative, when, by oppression, artifice, or being delivered over to a foreign power, their old one is gone, is only to tell them they may expect relief when it is too late, and the evil is past cure. This is, in effect, no more than to bid them first be slaves…and men can never be secure from tyranny if there be no means to escape it till they are perfectly under it.’ Theoretical justifications for a ‘positive’ right to security: ‘social contract’ (2) John Locke (1632-1704) Furthermore, again in opposition to Hobbes, Locke viewed the ‘absolute’ power of the sovereign as a threat to the security of individuals. He therefore advocated a minimal state, whose power was limited to its preservation; and therefore one that guaranteed much more freedoms to the individual. ‘[The] legislative can have no more power than this. Their power in the utmost bounds of it is limited to the public good of the society. It is a power that hath no other end but preservation, and therefore can never have a right to destroy, enslave, or designedly to impoverish the subjects…’ Theoretical justifications for a ‘positive’ right to security: contemporary liberalism of John Rawls and Ronald Dworkin Theoretical justifications for a ‘positive’ right to security: ‘communitarianism’ The author’s theoretical justification for a right to security is a compromise between the social contract theories of Thomas Hobbes and John Locke: • Hobbesian ‘absolutism’ ignores, say, liberal concerns about the state being a threat to security but • liberals perhaps pay too much attention to individualism and too little attention to ‘community’. Theoretical justifications for a ‘positive’ right to security: ‘communitarianism’ Recent communitarian theorists are Amitai Etzioni and Mary Ann Glendon For them, an important communitarian principle is redressing the balance between individual rights and social responsibilities Theoretical justifications for a ‘positive’ right to security: ‘communitarianism’ Unless society begins to redress the balance between rights of the individual and a person’s obligations to the community: communitarians believe society is, and will continue to be, self-centred and driven by self-interests. Theoretical justifications for a ‘positive’ right to security: ‘communitarianism’ no society can survive if people only want rights and are unwilling to assume responsibilities ‘To take and not to give, to draw on the commonwealth, but to refuse to contribute, people demanding that the government, and above all taxes, be curtailed, while still seeking more government services from education to public health, from housing to protection from crime.’ Theoretical justifications for a ‘positive’ right to security: ‘communitarianism’ and security For Etzioni the right to security is more fundamental than any others. So much so, ‘it ought to be treated as a class unto itself’. The main reason that the right to security takes precedence over all others is that all the others are contingent on the protection of life – whereas the right to security is not similarly contingent on any other rights. Theoretical justifications for a ‘positive’ right to security: ‘communitarianism’ and security And in reference to, say, security measures post ‘9/11’, Etzioni believes that nations did not lose their liberty as a result of a small accumulation of increased safety measures: ‘they did so when they failed to respond to urgent public needs.’ ‘True patriots…realize that one must protect the nation from all enemies and the essence of what it means to be patriotic is to protect our Constitution and its Bill of Rights with all our might.’ Theoretical justifications for a ‘positive’ right to security: ‘communitarianism’ and security Article 17 of the ECHR: ‘Prohibition of Abuse of Rights’ • Nothing in this Convention may be interpreted as implying for any State, group or person • any right to engage in any activity or perform any act aimed at • the destruction of any of the rights and freedoms set forth herein or at their limitation to a greater extent than is provided for in the Convention. A ‘positive’ right to security, grounded in communitarianism Ian Turner Lancashire Law School The University of Central Lancashire idturner@uclan.ac.uk