1NC OFF Aff must say what “US” and what “legalize nearly all” means—vote neg Fairness—legalize can include hundreds of regulations which radically alter the case neg we need- makes the aff a moving target and spikes out of our disads Topic education—confusion over what legalize means kills productive debate over sex work PEN, Prostitutes Education Network, Last Modified Sunday, August 10, 2008 2:40:54 PM “Prostitution Law Reform: Defining Terms” Definitions Legalisation and Decriminalisation according to Scarlet Alliance, Australia from PRINCIPLES FOR MODEL SEX INDUSTRY LEGISLATION Scarlet Alliance and the Australian Federation of AIDS Organisations, http://www.bayswan.org/defining.html ac 8-17 Many (or most) societies that allow prostitution do so by giving the state control over the lives and businesses of those who work as prostitutes. Legalization often includes special taxes for prostitutes, restricting prostitutes to working in brothels or in certain zones, licenses, registration of prostitutes and government records of individual prostitutes, and health checks which often means punitive quarantine. The term legalization does not necessarily have to refer to the above sorts of regulations. In fact, in one commonly accepted definition of legalization, legal can simply mean that prostitution is not against the law.¶ Legalization ¶ From sociological perspective, the term legalization usually refers to a system of criminal regulation and government control of prostitutes , wherein certain prostitutes are given licenses which permit them to work in specific and usually limited ways. Although legalization can also imply a decriminalized, autonomous system of prostitution, in reality, in most "legalized" systems the police are relegated the job of prostitution control through criminal codes. Laws regulate prostitutes businesses and lives, prescribing health checks and registration of health status (enforced by police and, often corrupt, medical agencies), telling prostitutes where they may or may not reside, prescribing full time employment for their lovers, etc. Prostitute activists use the term legalization to refer to systems of state control , which defines the term by the realities of the current situation, rather than by the broad implications of the term itself.¶ Because of the range of definitions of legalization , it is difficult to use the term in a discussion of reform. When the general public concerned with civil rights, privacy, etc., call for "legalization," they may not be aware implications of that term , or of the problems inherent in many legalized systems. OFF Prostitution includes the seller and the patron- they leave half of the laws against prostitution on the books Birckhead, 11 -- UNC Chapel Hill law professor [Tamar, "The 'Youngest Profession': Consent, Autonomy, and Prostituted Children,” 2011, Washington University Law Review, 88 Wash. U. L. Rev. 1055, l/n, accessed 6-21-14] n177. See, e.g., Alaska Stat. § 11.66.100 (2007) (defining the act of prostitution to include both the person who accepts a fee in exchange for sex as well as the person who makes the offer); Wis. Stat. Ann. § 944.30 (West 2005) (defining the act of prostitution as applying equally to sellers and buyers). Even the broadest possible interpretation of nearly all is 51% Miller, 98 – ABC correspondent [Judy Miller, ABC Correspondent, and Catherine Kenney, teacher, 8-3-1998, ABC News, "A Closer Look," l/n, accessed 2008] JUDY MULLER: (voice-over) But what does "nearly all" mean exactly? CATHERINE KENNEY: Our understanding at the meetings that we've had is that we can have a very broad interpretation of that. It could be 51 percent, you know, really kind of pushing it . Independently, Nordic model does not legalize Kennedy, 14-- Postmedia News staff [Mark, "Tory government’s new prostitution laws will likely target pimps, customers and sex-trade traffickers," National Post, 4-2714, news.nationalpost.com/2014/04/27/harper-governments-new-prostitution-laws-will-likely-target-pimps-customers-and-sex-tradetraffickers/, accessed 9-20-14] The federal government is poised to introduce legislation in the coming weeks that will overhaul Canada’s prostitution laws — possibly targeting the pimps and johns as criminals while leaving the prostitutes themselves free from criminal prosecution. Justice Minister Peter MacKay has been exploring various options since the Supreme Court of Canada struck down Canada’s prostitution laws last December, giving the government a year to come up with a new law. Among the alternatives being examined is a Canadian version of the “Nordic model” — an approach first used in Sweden which then spread to Norway and Iceland — in which police target prostitutes’ customers, pimps and sex-trade traffickers. Earlier this month, MacKay said his bill will be drafted to find the “right balance” to a “complex” issue. Two things have become apparent: the government will not decriminalize or legalize prostitution, as some other countries such as New Zealand and the Netherlands have done; and the governing Tories appear to be contemplating the Nordic model. Vote neg for precision and ground- these are two entirely different debates Miller, 4 -- Coughlin Stoia Geller Rudman & Robbins LLP [Coty, J.D., former Georgetown Journal of Gender and the Law senior editor, and Nuria Haltiwanger, ACS Infrastructure Development CEO, J.D., "Prostitution and The Legalization/Decriminalization Debate," The Georgetown Journal of Gender and the Law, 5 Geo. J. Gender & L. 207, Spring 2004, l/n, accessed 6-21-14] It is in these different ideas and policy initiatives where one sees the divergent goals and theories underlying groups such as WHISPER and COYOTE. Although WHISPER's two main legislative reform priorities, the creation of civil causes of action for individuals coerced into prostitution and the elimination of "mistake of age" defenses, are supported by most prostitutes' rights groups (including COYOTE), its other policy initiatives have sparked heated debate. n195 WHISPER, for example, applauds and lobbies for the imposition of harsher penalties against johns, while COYOTE fears that these penalties will unduly endanger prostitutes by only keeping criminally inclined customers on the streets. Similarly, WHISPER advocates stronger penalties for pimping, particularly laws making it a crime to live "off the earnings of prostitution." n196 COYOTE, on the other hand, argues that many women choose prostitution precisely because of the financial support it can give their children, parents, friends, etc. Although these laws are meant to protect against violent and coercive pimps, their broad wording can make children or parents (i.e. any person deriving financial benefit from the commercial sex transaction) a criminal. n197 OFF The exploitation of the sex worker lies in how surplus value can be extracted from her in a motion to further expel capitalism. Only by rereading class in the feminist debate on prostitution can we resolve the root of the problem. Beloso 12 (Brooke Meredith Beloso is Assistant Professor of Gender, Women and Sexuality Studies at Butler Univeristy. Her general areas of interest are gender, sexuality, information and communications technology, critical race theory, transnational feminisms, prefigurative politics, critical university studies, and neoliberalism. “Sex, Work, and the Feminist Erasure of Class”, Signs, Vol. 38, No. 1 (Autumn 2012), pp. 47-70, The University of Chicago Press, accessed via JSTOR ) Inviting class into the feminist debate on prostitution In the interest of beginning to reckon with what we have lost in the translation of class from a theory of privilege and oppression into an identity analogous to gender and sexuality, I want to perform a bit of a hermeneutic experiment: I want to see what comes into focus when we invite a Marxist theory of class into the feminist debate on prostitution. To this end, I take up Rosemary Hennessy’s (2006) articulation of cultural oppression as a “second skin” that capital uses against the worker in order to extract surplus value (profit) from him or her.12 Also to this end, I take up Crenshaw’s aforeme tioned concept of intersectionality as an important tool with which we may more accurately identify the myriad forms of cultural privilege and oppres- sion both before and beyond gender—the various second skins that laboring bodies freely (at least, in the formal sense) offer up to capital in the marketplace—upon which economic exploitation is predicated. In so doing we see that the rhetoric of, alternately (and for many interchangeably) prostitution as the measure of woman and woman as the measure of prostitution (e.g., Giobbe 1990) leaves largely unexamined not only the mode of production predicated upon the mass exploitation of labor in the interest of profit (capital accumulation) but also the participation of feminism itself in the “microphysics of power” (Foucault 1995, 139) that constitute the macropolitical oppression and exploitation of people in the sex industry. Parsing sex work as the metamorphosis of the commodity through an intersectional second skin, we see that the plight of the prostitute—when, in fact, there is a plight (more on this below)—often lies not in her womanliness, per se, but rather in the degree to which her impoverishment, her gender, her race, her sexuality, her age, her religion, her legal status, her looks, or her ability (mental and physical) can be used against her in the extraction of surplus value (profit) from her labor.13 And the question of whether these can be used against the sex worker has little to do with the presence or absence of formal freedom between any given sex worker and her clients. Rather, the exploitation of the sex worker hinges upon any number of structural second skins of cultural oppression (such as patriarchy, white supremacy, heterosexism, ageism, religious chauvinism, nationalism, looksism, ableism, and so on) that both allow capitalists to slap a particular wage on a particular service provided by a particular body and establish that wage and its working conditions not in accordance with the principle “from each according to his ability; to each according to his need” (Marx [1875] 2010, 347) but rather in relation to other forms of labor available for sale and purchase at a particular moment in time. Much like Chandra Talpade Mohanty’s Western feminist who misses the veil as a marker of agency when she wears only her imperialist, oppression- seeking glasses (1991, 346–67), the feminist who sees only victims everywhere she or he looks at prostitution misses entirely the ingenuity and agency of the human being who chooses to work in the sex industry rather than, say the sweatshop industry (or even, for that matter, the knowledge industry; see Anonymous, Ph.D. 1999), because the wages and working conditions are, to his or her mind, better. According to the prevalent feminist logic of prostitution as the measure of woman, Ashley Dupré is a better canary in the coal mine of gender inequality than Chun Yu Wang, and Eliot Spitzer is a better fit for the role of canary-killing cat than, say, Jack Abramoff.14 Hence, too, the often uncritical feminist embrace of a figure like New York Times columnist Nicholas Kristof, who rants and rages against the exploitation of female prostitutes halfway across the globe, even as he sings the praises of sweatshops. The faulty logic at work here—that closing sweat- shops forces people into prostitution—not only problematically relies upon Kristof’s own moralizing determination that the sex industry unilaterally offers comparatively worse wages and working conditions than the sweat- shop industry but also, incredibly, offers sweatshops as a solution to the problem of poverty driving many to work in any number of different capac- ities for very low wages in terrible conditions.15 Conversely, woman as the measure of prostitution misses entirely the exploitation that men can experience in the sex industry, not because they are women but because they are men, impoverished, gender nonconforming, of color, or gay, or young, or undocumented, or criminalized, non-English speaking, conventionally “ugly,” or living with physical or mental disabilities, and so on.16 Woman as the measure of prostitution misses, too, the exploitation that transpeople can experience in the sex industry, not because they are women but because they are trans, impoverished, of color, gay, young, undocumented or criminalized, nonEnglish speaking, conventionally “ugly,” living with physical or mental disabilities, and so on (see Ryan 2006). But lest the intersectionalization of some sex-working subjects’ oppression and exploitation inadvertently reinforce blanket stereotypes associated with the plight of the prostitute, I want to shift the focus of attention to the privilege—the agency— that also becomes visible when we invite class into the feminist debate on prostitution. For, once having grasped class as a theory of privilege and oppression, one begins to see that both within and beyond the sex industry some women are more equal than others (to paraphrase George Orwell). Taking seriously both privilege as the flip side of the coin of oppression and the complex intersections of these two along any number of axes of cultural privilege and oppression that Crenshaw privilege along one axis can mitigate oppression along another, even within the sex industry itself. As Siobhan Brooks (quoted in Soldano 2010) succinctly puts it, “Not everybody can sell their sex equally.”17 Taking seriously both privilege as a and others in her wake have theorized as constitutive of intersectionality, we see that mitigator of oppression and class as a dynamic, rather than reified, relation between labor and capital, we also see that the selfsame person may be today’s woman-as-laborer, selling sex as “the particular product of [her] individual labor,” and tomorrow’s woman-ascapitalist, buying and selling sex as “the particular product[s] of [other] individual[s’] labor”—and vice versa (Marx [1861–63] 1969, 509). One might think here of former nude model and stripper Danni Ashe, aka “the billion download woman,” who is now an Internet entrepreneur overseeing a “stable” of more than one hundred women and reportedly grossing more than $300,000 in monthly revenue (Russell 1998), and former stripper and “queen of porn” Jenna Jameson, who recently sold the highly profitable Internet pornography company she created in 2000 to Playboy Enterprises. Moreover, as Angela Davis (1983, 17) has observed, intimate labor of all sorts has throughout history served for many women as an exploitative means to a liberatory end.18 Last but not least, through the lens of class analysis one begins to see the mutually imbricated privilege and oppression structuring what Laura Agus- tín has recently theorized as “the rescue industry” (2007) and Jo Doezema describes as “Western feminists’ ‘wounded attachment’ to the ‘third world prostitute’” (2001), whereby a radical abolitionist feminist such as Donna Hughes makes an excellent living as an endowed women’s studies program chair with her research funded by the State Department, while the women and men employed in the massage parlors she helped shut down in Rhode Island (a state with one of the highest unemployment rates in the nation) endure forcible unemployment, detainment, deportation, and incarcera- tion.19 In this vein, and in one of the English language’s greater ironies, the “abolitionist” feminist seeking the aid of the police state (rather than, say, the welfare state) in his or her fight against prostitution is frequently if unwittingly at cross-purposes with the prison abolitionist feminist, who sees the criminalization of sex work as but one more poverty-to-prison pipeline and the police themselves as no small source of oppression for sex workers. 20 One begins to see here, too, the widely divergent relationships to labor and capital structuring the “will to empower” (Cruikshank 1999) of New York Times columnists Bob Herbert, who tried to rescue an unnamed young woman selling sex on Atlanta’s Metropolitan Parkway in 2006, and Kristof, who has in recent years tried to rescue women selling sex in Cambodia. Selling the stories of these women as “reality porn” (Debbie Nathan quoted in Broeske 2006), Herbert and Kristof participate in what Katha Pollitt recently described as “a long tradition of privileged men rescuing individual prostitutes as a kind of whirlwind adventure” (2004). In so doing, they earn wages for “the particular product of [their] individual labor” (Marx [1861– 63] 1969, 509–10) and a profit for the New York Times, but in the wake of these stories, the women they seek to rescue merely return to what are, to their minds, the best wages and working conditions available to them: sex work. Conclusion If we as feminists are to honor the central tenets of the feminist standpoint epistemology that gave rise to women’s studies as the academic arm of feminism—that knowledge production is never objective and must always be checked against dissenting perspectives—then we must check the feminist debate on prostitution against the dissenting perspectives of the sex- working subjects about whom so much has been and is being said. By taking sex workers’ choices and visions of liberation at least as seriously as our own choices, we stand to realize that the exploitation endemic to some sex work is not just something that happens to prostitutes; rather, it is part and parcel of everything that happens under the sign of capitalism. Radical-feminism- cum-abolitionist-feminism has too long masked its disavowal and dislocation of the economic exploitation endemic to capitalism as heteropatriarchy. Sex work has become one of neoliberal feminism’s favorite scapegoats, whereby many of us can deny the reality that under the current political economy, “what has been repressed, the idea of sin, is capital itself” (Ben- jamin [1921] 1996, 289). To seek to save one’s soul by saving prostitutes is thus to imagine that, under capitalism, all privilege is not purchased at the expense of another’s exploitation. It is to imagine that some of us are above the law of capital and that capitalism is not an adversarial, zero sum system. Feminist and queer theory that rolls right past or right over the intersectional, agentic subjectivity of sex workers is premised in the falsehood that atonement—rather than “guilt pervasive”—is possible under capitalism (Benjamin [1921] 1996, 289). To proclaim that prostitution harms all women, everywhere, is to cover over the harm that we all do every day, to varying degrees, as participants in our political economy. To overlook our own complicity, as producers and consumers, in the pricing of sexual services and the construction of cultural hierarchies that enable economic exploitation in every labor sector is to refuse to flip the intersectional coin. Inasmuch as sex work functions as feminist and queer theory’s imaginary outside, whoromyopia is in no small part a means of preserving the fantasy of an imaginary outside to capitalism—the fantasy that some of us living under capitalism have ingeniously managed to finagle a way of not selling out.21 It is to trade the farsighted feminist project of expanding the range of meaningful choices available to human beings for the shortsighted project of taking one choice away from them—whether by evacuating the choice to work in the sex industry of all meaning by dismissing it as false consciousness, or by so criminalizing this choice that to make it is to find oneself squashed beneath the iron heel of the prison industrial complex. Whoromyopia is thus also predicated upon the fantasy that some of us have somehow managed to get a special purchase on a true consciousness about sex work (miraculously uninflected by our own relations to the means of production), while others of us have, sadly, fallen prey to false consciousness about sex work. To correct for whoromyopia is to give the lie to the notion that equality—including but not limited to gender and sexual equality—is possible under capitalism. And if we truly want to be more than “merely cultural” (Butler 1997)—if we are to seize heteronormativity by the roots rather than by its offshoots—then we must challenge the political economy that has taken and continues to take advantage of anything it can, including feminism, in order to take advantage of millions. We must find a way to recontextualize the various second skins that, for so many of us, capital turns against us into instruments of our own exploitation. We must, instead, turn these second skins into instruments of solidarity with all workers under capitalism, including sex workers. Failing this, we may rest assured that capital will proceed unchecked in the appropriation of gender and sexual oppression—and any number of other forms of cultural oppression it can appropriate—to both further entrench and mask the direct correspondence between those who enjoy the freedom to choose their own relationship to the sexual body as a means of production and those who enjoy freedom from want (an infinitesimal percent of the global population at best) and to have us fall for the ruse that desire could somehow ever be autonomous from need. Together, we can do better than this. The time has come to radically reread class into the feminist debate on prostitution and to reckon with all that we— “whores, housewives, and others” (among others)—have lost in translation. Vote Negative to validate and adopt the method of historical materialism that is the 1NC Marxist method can solve the case but not vice versa Tumino (Prof. English @ Pitt) 01 [Stephen, “What is Orthodox Marxism and Why it Matters Now More than Ever”, Red Critiqu] Any effective political theory will have to do at least two things: it will have to offer an integrated understanding of social practices and, based on such an interrelated knowledge, offer a guideline for praxis. My main argument here is that among all contesting social theories now, only Orthodox Marxism has been able to produce an integrated knowledge of the existing social totality and provide lines of praxis that will lead to building a society free from necessity. But first I must clarify what I mean by Orthodox Marxism. Like all other modes and forms of political theory, the very theoretical identity of Orthodox Marxism is itself contested—not just from non-and anti-Marxists who question the very "real" (by which they mean the "practical" as under free-market criteria) existence of any kind of Marxism now but, perhaps more tellingly, from within the Marxist tradition itself. I will, therefore, first say what I regard to be the distinguishing marks of Orthodox Marxism and then outline a short polemical map of contestation over Orthodox Marxism within the Marxist theories now. I will end by arguing for its effectivity in bringing about a new society based not on human that to know contemporary society—and to be able to act on such knowledge—one has to first of all know what makes the existing social totality. I will argue that the dominant social totality is based on inequality—not just inequality of power but inequality of economic access (which then determines access to health care, education, housing, diet, transportation, . . . ). This systematic inequality cannot be explained by gender, race, sexuality, disability, ethnicity, or nationality. These are all secondary contradictions and are all determined by the fundamental contradiction of capitalism which is inscribed in the relation of capital and labor. All modes of Marxism now explain social inequalities primarily on the basis of these secondary contradictions and in doing so—and this is my main argument— legitimate capitalism. Why? Because such arguments authorize capitalism without gender, race, discrimination and thus accept economic inequality as an integral part of human societies. They accept a sunny capitalism—a capitalism beyond capitalism. Such a society, based on cultural equality but economic inequality, has always been the notso-hidden agenda of the bourgeois left—whether it has been called "new left," "postmarxism," or "radical rights but on freedom from necessity. I will argue democracy." This is, by the way, the main reason for its popularity in the culture industry—from the academy (Jameson, Harvey, Haraway, Butler,. . . ) to For all, capitalism is here to stay and the best that can be done is to make its cruelties more tolerable, more humane. This humanization (not daily politics (Michael Harrington, Ralph Nader, Jesse Jackson,. . . ) to. . . . eradication) of capitalism is the sole goal of ALL contemporary lefts (marxism, feminism, anti-racism, queeries, . . . ). Such an understanding of social inequality is based on the fundamental understanding that the source of wealth is human knowledge and not human labor. That is, wealth is produced by the human mind and is thus free from the actual objective conditions that shape the historical relations of labor and capital. Only Orthodox Marxism recognizes the historicity of labor and its primacy as the source of all human wealth. In this paper I argue that any emancipatory theory has to be founded on recognition of the priority of Marx's labor theory of value and not repeat the technological determinism of corporate theory ("knowledge work") that masquerades as social theory. OFF The United States Federal Government should decriminalize the act of performing sexual activity for hire in the United States. The United States Federal Government should criminalize the purchase of sex for hire in the United States. Legalization increases government regulations that control bodies and spursfurther trafficking and exploitation – decriminalization solves Longworth 10 – U of Victoria Law (Corinne, MALE VIOLENCE AGAINST WOMEN IN PROSTITUTION: WEIGHING FEMINIST LEGISLATIVE RESPONSES TO A TROUBLING CANADIAN PHENOMENON, APPEAL VOLUME 15) Prostitution has been legalized in the Netherlands and Victoria, Australia. In both juris- dictions, not all forms of prostitution are legal: child prostitution, trafficking and some as- pects of street prostitution remain criminalized.100 Legalization often involves removing criminal laws relating to adult prostitution and regulating prostitution through licensing, health and safety regulations.101 Although legalization has some benefits since it does not criminalize prostitutes and attempts to support their well-being, it unfortunately has multiple drawbacks. In both jurisdictions, legalization has spurred a marked growth in the sex industry.102 For example, in Victoria, legal brothels more than doubled over a span of 11 years: “the number of legitimate brothels grew from 40 in 1989 to 94 in 1999.”103 This growth of the sex in- dustry is linked directly to increased demand, which stems from the legitimation and accessibility of prostitution domestically, and these countries’ increased popularity as sex tourist destinations.¶ With an increase in demand, there has been an increase in the legal and illegal, underground forms of the trade. 104 Demand must be met with a supply of bodies, and a be made available for male sexual consumption. Thus, demand has resulted in an increase in the exploitation of women and children who are trafficked or otherwise forced to enter variety thereof, to pros- titution. 105 In the Netherlands, there has been a disturbing increase in child sexual exploitation , with a growth of 11,000 children in the sex trade since 1996, mainly trafficked from other cannot say you’re fighting the trafficking of people and at the same time legalise (brothels) because you open the market. ”107 This seems to be a countries.106 As Anne-Marie Lizin of Belgium has stated, “You sound argument since, in the Netherlands, approximately 80 to 85 percent of prostitutes are non-Dutch108 and thus have voluntarily relocated or been trafficked from other countries to work in locations like Amsterdam. In this way, prostitution, trafficking and child sexual exploitation should be viewed as inextricably linked. For these reasons, it is not surprising that the Mayor of Amsterdam recently announced that a third of the red light dis- trict will be shut down since, not only did legalization not bring the Dutch what they had “hoped and expected,” but it increased organized crime, exploitation and trafficking.109¶ As well, in jurisdictions with legalization, an increase in legal indoor prostitution has increased illegal street prostitution rather than moving women in off the streets ,110 thus al- lowing the nuisance associated with prostitution to linger or worsen. Of course, this is not surprising since legalization does not ameliorate the basic conditions of disadvantage that keep women— particularly the centred woman— poor, homeless and on the street to begin with. Overall, legalizing prostitution has not decreased nuisance or exploitation, but has largely exacerbated them.¶ Legalization has also failed to lessen the stigma and extreme violence associated with prostitution. In Amsterdam, known internationally for its open-minded attitudes toward the sex industry, legalization has not minimized the stigma attributed to prostitutes.111 Instead, as businesswomen, “ accountants, banks and health insurance companies want nothing to do with [prostitutes].”112 This stigma may relate to Radin’s recognition that many feel unease and disapprobation at a person commodifying their sexuality. Not surprisingly, just as stigma remains, violence also still pervades and is a recognized reality within the legalized sex industry, even though indoors.113 As one brothel owner in Amsterdam stated, “[y]ou don’t want a pillow in your room. It’s a murder weapon.”114 Some even suggest that violence has increased, particularly for those who work in the illegal sectors and, thus, are still alienated from police protection .115 A further concern is that violence has been legitimated and normalized as simply a “workplace hazard” that prostitutes must accept and prepare for.116 In some locales, panic buttons are affixed in rooms and prostitutes are encouraged to un- dergo hostage negotiation training.117 These precautions indicate that violence remains a serious, alarming and consistent risk.¶ Yet another drawback of legalization is that it has generally not empowered prostitutes to get out of the sex trade if they wish nor enjoy better working conditions. In the Netherlands, only four percent of prostitutes have registered with authorities118 to access the health and safety regulations, pension benefits and employment rights available. Therefore, only a small proportion of prostitutes have bettered their legal status in the system, and even then they are still subject to social stigma and violence. The prostitutes in the Netherlands who refrain from the legalized regime do so for many reasons: fear of the stigma and repercussions that would flow from being officially recognized as a prostitute,119 ineligibility be- cause of age or illegal immigrant status,120 and unwillingness to declare a commitment to work they view as temporary. Thus, even in jurisdictions where prostitution is legalized, a large proportion of the sex trade still operates illegally and underground, unable to benefit from the legalized regime in place. As well, most prostitutes have not been empowered to “move indoors” and enjoy “better” working conditions or exit the trade since the same socio-economic reasons that put them on the street remain.¶ For these many reasons, very few people suggested legalization or regulation to the 2006 Standing Committee as an approach to adopt in Canada.121 Furthermore, both sides of the feminist debate strongly discourage legalization. Clearly, the centred woman would largely not benefit from legalization: she would be excluded from the legal regime as a street prostitute and the stigma, violence and disadvantage that informs her life would likely not abate. ¶ D. Decriminalization¶ Instead of legalization, full-decriminalization feminists advocate “decriminalization” as separate from, and more advantageous than, legalization. The jurisdiction that full-de- criminalization feminists usually refer to as a success is New Zealand, which adopted a de- criminalized regime in 2003. Decriminalization in New Zealand is similar to legalization in Victoria, Australia and the Netherlands in terms of enabling prostitutes to access better working conditions via employment contracts, lessened stigma and better relations with law enforcement officials. New Zealand differs from legalized regimes in that street pros- titution has been decriminalized and child sexual exploitation has been more seriously criminalized. These are both commendable improvements over legalization regimes. Also, there is less of a division between the il/legal sex trade for workers in terms of in/out-door prostitution given the decriminalization of street prostitution. Yet, it is still illegal for im- migrants to be sex workers and access the labour and employment benefits of legal work- ers. Despite the advantages of decriminalization over legalization and an optimistic report from the New Zealand Prostitution Law Review Committee (the “Committee”), many problems still remain and “progress [has been] slower tha[n] may have been hoped.”122 Regulation intensifies marginalization and stigma against prostitutes, and causes a more violent market to form Mgbako & Smith 10 (Chi Mgbako* and Laura A. Smith** 2010 *Clinical Associate Professor of Law, Fordham Law School; Director, Walter Leitner International Human Rights Clinic; J.D. Harvard Law School Fordham International Law Journal 33 Fordham Int'l L.J. 1178 April, 2010 (Lexis) The main aim of government regulation of sex work is to control the excesses, abuses, disorders, and other undesirable social and public health consequences associated with its operation. 204 Proponents of legalization also contend that legalization reduces criminal activity associated with prostitution (e.g., organized crime, police and state corruption, child prostitution, and sex trafficking); decreases the level of street prostitution and relocates prostitution to controlled environments away from residential areas; provides regular health checks to women in licensed brothels; controls the spread of STIs and HIV/AIDS; and protects sex workers from violence and coercive pimps. 205 Legalized regimes, however, face practical obstacles. Many sex workers may not want to register because of the stigma associated with prostitution or may be unable to register because of their illegal immigration status. 206 Legalized systems therefore may lead to two classes of sex workers - those who register and are regulated by the state and an underground class of sex workers who do not register and remain marginalized and vulnerable. Decriminalization is the legal regime most often embraced by prosex-worker advocates and stands against the legal control of people in prostitution. Decriminalization is the removal of all laws relating to prostitution. 207 Decriminalization addresses the negative impact that criminalization has on sex workers. For example, criminal records for prostitution-related offenses reinforce the marginalization of sex workers, while making it more difficult for workers in the sex industry to find alternative [*1209] employment. 208 This increased marginalization heightens sex workers' vulnerability to abuse and assault from clients, pimps, and partners, who violate the rights of sex workers with impunity. 209 Sex workers' illegal status acts as a barrier to reporting abuse and creates difficulties in accessing necessary health and social services. 210 Decriminalization would safeguard the human rights of sex workers, alleviate the social exclusion that people in prostitution endure, and improve sex workers' health and working conditions. 211 The difference between legalization and decriminalization lies in the means by which prostitution is "made legal." Legalization imposes more state regulations to control prostitution, while decriminalization removes all laws that criminalize prostitution. Those who support decriminalization over legalization argue that legalization essentially exchanges one exploitative system for another. 212 Under a legalized system, women work out of government-regulated brothels, which can leave sex workers with little control over their work conditions and which can substitute abuse and exploitation by police officers and pimps with rights violations by the state. 213 Both laws which legalize and regulate prostitution and laws that criminalize prostitution target the sex worker. 214 Furthermore, the main goal of regulationist policies, including legalization, is often to keep prostitutes isolated and separate from the rest of society, which reinforces the stigma surrounding prostitution. 215 Dems Good: 1NC Dems will hold the Senate now—most accurate models Logiurato 9-17-14 (Brett, staff writer, "Meet The New Nate Silver" Business Insider) www.businessinsider.in/Meet-The-NewNate-Silver/articleshow/42727612.cms In 2012, as President Barack Obama fell behind in pre-election polls but not in election statistician Nate Silver's odds, this phrase quickly caught on: "Keep calm and trust Nate Silver!" This summer, Democrats have a new election guru to turn to for comfort: Sam Wang, a neuroscientist and professor at Princeton University who runs a model at Princeton's Election Consortium. Most of the 2014 election models - from The Washington Post, The New York Times, and from Silver, among others - have for a while projected Republicans not only furthering their grip on control of the House of Representatives, but also having a good chance of flipping Senate control as well. But Wang's model has been the most bullish for Democrats. His model has two forecasts: If the election were held today, Democrats would have an 80% chance of retaining control of the Senate. Predicting for Election Day, he estimates slightly less bullish 70% odds. He predicts that as of today, Senate Democrats and Independents that caucus with the party will make up 50 seats in the chamber, enabling them to keep control by the thinnest of margins. (In such a 50-50 situation, Vice President Joe Biden would cast the theoretical deciding vote.) On Tuesday, other models began shifting toward a better chance for Democratic control of the Senate. The Washington Post on Tuesday put Democrats' odds at 51%. The New York Times' new "Leo" model has control of the Senate at a 50-50 tossup. And Silver's site, FiveThirtyEight, has Republicans' chances slimming to about 53%. "My model is slightly more favorable because it relies on current polling conditions" as its main factor, Wang said in a recent interview with Business Insider. The differences between their models - and their differing predictions - has opened up a pseudo-rivalry between Wang and Silver in the lead-up to the midterm elections. During an interview with WNYC's Brian Lehrer last week, Silver claimed Wang's model uses "arbitrary assumptions," something Wang rejected as an "out-and-out falsehood." In a blog post on Tuesday, Wang playfully responded to a comment from Silver in which he said he'd like to "place a large wager against" Wang. He called Silver's forecast that day, which gave Republicans a 64% chance of swinging Senate control, into question, saying the "special sauce" (or formula) Silver uses for his model is "messy stuff." But the difference between Wang and Silver, Wang says, is substantive. It is predicated on the divide between the models - Wang's relies only on a reading of the latest polls, while Silver's model adds in the "fundamentals" of the race when making predictions. Those fundamentals vary by state. They can take into account fundraising, the liberal-conservative ideology of individual candidates, and national factors like presidential approval rating and the history of the president's party performing badly in the sixth year of his presidency, for example. "When he started in 2008, he brought lively commentary and the addition of econometric assumptions to predict the future," Wang told Business Insider of Silver. "He made the hobby fun for people to read about. All horse race commentators owe him a debt. "The difference between us is substantive. In most years, adding assumptions doesn't alter the picture too much: 2008, 2010, and 2012 were not hard prediction problems. However, this year's Senate race is as close as 2004, and giving an accurate picture of the race is challenging. Adding assumptions can bias an analyst's interpretation ." Nate Silver's model relies on more than just polls. Somewhat similar to Silver, Wang's interest in political prognostication grew out of the insatiable need to fuel what had been a hobby. He is the son of Taiwanese immigrants, grew up in California, graduated with a B.S. from the California Institute of Technology by the age of 19, and subsequently graduated with a PhD from Stanford. He began his model in 2004, when he was intensely following the presidential campaign that pitted President George W. Bush against Democrat John Kerry. In the constant horse-race mentality and the over-reporting on single polls, he said, he saw an opportunity to contribute a new, more comprehensive and accurate element to the conversation. "I was motivated by the extreme closeness of the Kerry-Bush contest, and the news stories about single polls were driving me crazy," Wang told Business Insider. "I thought a simple way to summarize all the polls at once would improve the quality of coverage." Since then, his model has nearly nailed the result in every national election . In 2004, the model predicted Bush would grab 286 electoral votes to Kerry's 252. That was off by only a single electoral vote. (He made a personal prediction that turned out to be wrong.) The 2008 presidential election was similar - off by a single vote in each direction. The model only missed Nevada's Senate race in 2010, a race in which nearly every poll was off the mark. And the model in 2012 correctly predicted the vote in 49 of 50 states, the popular vote count of 51.1% to 48.9%, and 10 out of 10 tight Senate races - including Montana and South Dakota, which Silver missed. To Wang, it proves that a model that solely focuses on polls is a reliable indicator of eventual electoral outcomes. And he thinks models based on "fundamentals" like Silver's and like The New York Times' new model, dubbed "Leo," significantly alter the picture this year . "As of early September, both the New York Times's model 'Leo' and the FiveThirtyEight model exert a pull equivalent to adjusting Senate polls in key races by several percentage points. In other words, Republican candidates have slightly underperformed analyst expectations," Wang said. And this year, that could mean the expected Republican "wave" might never materialize. Wang sees Democratic candidates outperforming expectations all over the map. Plan hurts the Democrats—majority opposes legalization YouGov, staff, “68% Favor Legalized Gambling, 39% Would Legalize Prostitution,” 8—25—11, http://today.yougov.com/news/2011/08/25/68-favor-legalized-gambling-39-would-legalize-pros/, accessed 9-4-14. Americans have very different views about legalizing prostitution. 52% oppose that. And support differs from one group to the next. Those under 30 are divided about the prospect ; those 65 But and older are overwhelmingly opposed. Men are more favorable to legalizing prostitution than women are; college graduates more positive than those with less education. And while 49% of independents and 42% of Democrats would legalize prostitution, only 26% of Republicans agree. Voters will hold them accountable—voters react to political stances Stephen Ansolabehere, Professor, Government, Harvard and Philip Edward Jones, Assistant Professor, Political Science and International Relations, University of Delaware, “Constituents’ Responses to Congressional Roll-Call Voting,” AMERICAN JOURNAL OF POLTIICAL SCIENCE v. 54 n. 3, 7—10, pp. 583-597. constituents have the capacity to and do in fact hold their members of Congress accountable for roll-call votes. When people are asked about specific roll-call votes, they express definite The central conclusion of our analysis is that preferences on the matters at hand; further, most harbor beliefs about how their member of Congress voted. In addition, the extent to which a constituent agrees with the policy positions of the member of Congress strongly affects the constituent’s approval rating of the member and likelihood of voting for the member. That conclusion is strengthened in instrumental variables estimates that correct for possible measurement error and simultaneity biases. Citizens do not, of course, pay attention to every roll-call vote, and not every citizen is attentive, but the instrumental variables estimates reveal that actual roll- call votes directly affect constituents’ beliefs, and those roll-call votes, in turn, have substantial effects on approval ratings and electoral behavior. We are agnostic about how people learn about the voting behavior of their members of Congress. We suspect it is based partly on facts learned from the media and campaigns and partly on inferences, but it is more than just guessing or partisan projections. The two stages of our analysis reveal that constituents respond directly to their Representatives’ roll-call voting behavior. This conclusion is the starting point for most contemporary theorizing about Congress, especially spatial theories of politics. But, this has been a surprisingly elusive conjecture to establish empirically. At least since Miller and Stokes’s (1963) seminal work on this topic, the dominant view has held that constituents don’t have prefer- ences on the matters considered by Congress, they don’t have clear opinions about how their legislators act on such the link does exist; it is quite strong; and it creates the conditions for electoral accountability. Why questions, and they don’t hold their members of Congress accountable on important subjects. This study reveals that does our account differ from prior survey re- search, especially Miller and Stokes’s classic study? One possibility is the nature of the times. Miller and Stokes asked about racial and foreign policies during the 1950s, a decade in which the politics of race and of foreign trade became complicated and volatile. Voters may have been confused about where their Representatives stood on these questions. We think the real answer lies with measurement. With the exception of isolated cases, surveys have not asked directly about the roll-call votes of Representatives, even though that is the focus of much of the congressional research. Direct measure of constituents’ preferences on salient roll calls and perceptions of their legislators’ behavior reveals that voters indeed harbor beliefs about their legislators’ policy choices and hold the representatives’ accountable. Improved measurement, of which the methods here are just one development, promises to clarify further the nature of substantive policy representation. Finally, there is the question of aggregate accountability and congruence. Our results yield a picture strongly consistent in the aggregate with the reigning model of representation. Constituents have preferences about the important matters of the day; they have beliefs, formed through whatever means, about their representatives’ policy decisions. In the aggregate, constituents’ beliefs are approximately right. That is, on average, voters see their politicians as taking approximately the general overall position across a variety of roll-call votes as the Representatives in fact did. And, as the regression analyses show, constituents rely on perceived policy agreement to hold legislators accountable. The electorate rewards those seen to be in agreement with their views, and they punish those seen to be out of step. GOP Senate will reverse Obama’s climate change initiatives Amy Harder, journalist, “Care About Energy and Environment Policy? Watch These Eight Races,” NATIONAL JOURNAL, 12— 31—13, www.nationaljournal.com/energy/care-about-energy-and-environment-policy-watch-these-eight-races-20131231, accessed 3-20-14. For environmentalists, the 2014 midterm elections are about settling for the lesser of two evils. Several conservative Democrats up for reelection in red states are facing tough competition, and if enough of these members lose, the Senate could flip to Republican control. That would be the worst outcome for environmentalists, who need a Democrat-controlled Senate to defend against efforts to undo President Obama's climate-change agenda and other tough environmental policies. For the fossil-fuel industries, it's more of a mixed bag. Many major energy companies are backing conservative—and influential—Democrats who champion their cause. But at the same time, this industry also generally supports the Republican quest to take back control of the Senate. When it comes to how the Senate's handling of energy and environment issues could change in 2015, the trio of vulnerable incumbent Democrats to watch the closest include Sens. Mary Landrieu of Louisiana, Mark Begich of Alaska, and Mark Pryor of Arkansas. Here's a roundup of those races and others you should watch. Ensures warming—global deal, economic/culture shift Matt Hoffman and Steven Bernstein, Political Science, University of Toronto, “The Real Reason Obama’s Climate Plan Could Change the Game,” GLOBE AND MAIL, 6—5—14, www.theglobeandmail.com/globe-debate/the-real-reason-obamas-climate-plancould-change-the-game/article18997712/, accessed 8-26-14. The regulations can be a tipping point if they produce new coalitions for action on climate change and are attentive to the interests of those negatively affected by the transition away from fossil fuels. More broadly, these regulations can contribute to developing decarbonization pathways by shifting the U.S. political debate to look more like Europe’s, where the question is how, not whether, to act on climate change. The critical juncture for such a shift already occurred when the Obama administration moved to treat carbon dioxide like other harmful substances regulated by the EPA. But this is the pathway’s first real test. If the regulation survives legal and the entrenchment and institutionalization of this understanding in national regulation is the real game changer . This focus on the instruments of policy – how fast and in what ways – as opposed legislative challenges, to debating abstract future goals to cut emissions also distances the U.S. from Canada, where the debate is still over whether to decarbonize. It’s thus no surprise U.S. ambassador to Canada Bruce Heyman publically urged Canada to take more aggressive action on climate change the very same day President Obama announced the new regulations, recognizing that the oil sands and the controversial Keystone XL pipeline are the next stops along this policy pathway if the U.S. is to re-take leadership on climate change internationally. Social science research tells us that when a policy goal starts to become taken for granted, following this pattern, it can have far-reaching effects. Normalization of climate policy leaves opponents fighting a rearguard action because it changes the commonsense around an issue. It also provides a long-term signal that could change how major players think about where to move capital and investments –towards renewables and energy efficiency. Once cities, states, and corporations begin to work towards the emissions targets in the proposed regulations, their orientation towards energy and climate may significantly change and they may take up different practices in multiple areas (transportation, buildings, urban development). The combination of aggressive targets in a particular sector and flexibility mechanisms that encourage a diverse range of action in multiple sectors have the potential to produce ripple effects that put the U.S. on a different trajectory, away from fossil fuels. Those catalytic effects could also extend to the moribund international negotiations where a major sticking point for the last 20 years has been complaints from developing countries that the U.S. has done too little to address climate change. These proposed regulations will nudge the U.S. closer to the ‘leader’ category in the global response to climate change (or at least further from the laggard label that has dogged the U.S. for years) perhaps making a global deal more palatable and realizable. The carbon pathway has been locked in for over a hundred years, which has created strong coalitions of entrenched interests to support it. The battle is not so much over this about its ability to create new coalitions and entrench interests that further institutionalize and normalize the national and international policy pathways towards decarbonization. single initiative, as Warming is real, human caused, and causes extinction—acting now is key to avoid catastrophic collapse Dr. David McCoy et al., MD, Centre for International Health and Development, University College London, “Climate Change and Human Survival,” BRITISH MEDICAL JOURNAL v. 348, 4—2—14, doi: http://dx.doi.org/10.1136/bmj.g2510, accessed 8-31-14. The Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change (IPCC) has just published its report on the impacts of global warming. Building on its recent update of the physical science of global warming [1], the IPCC’s new report should leave the world in no doubt about the scale and immediacy of the threat to human survival , health, and well-being. The IPCC has already concluded that it is “ virtually certain that human influence has warmed the global climate system” and that it is “ extremely likely that more than half of the observed increase in global average surface temperature from 1951 to 2010” is anthropogenic [1]. Its new report outlines the future threats of further global warming: increased scarcity of food and fresh water; extreme weather events; rise in sea level; loss of biodiversity; areas becoming uninhabitable; and mass human migration, conflict and violence. Leaked drafts talk of hundreds of millions displaced in a little over 80 years. This month, the American Association for the Advancement of Science (AAAS) added its voice: “the well being of people of all nations [is] at risk.” [2] Such comments reaffirm the conclusions of the Lancet/UCL Commission: that climate change is “the greatest threat to human health of the 21st century.” [3] The changes seen so far—massive arctic ice loss and extreme weather events, for example—have resulted from an estimated average temperature rise of 0.89°C since 1901. Further changes will depend on how much we continue to heat the planet. The release of just another 275 gigatonnes of carbon dioxide would probably commit us to a temperature rise of at least 2°C—an amount that could be emitted in less than eight years. [4] “ Business as usual ” will increase carbon dioxide concentrations from the current level of 400 parts per million (ppm), which is a 40% increase from 280 ppm 150 years ago, to 936 ppm by 2100, with a 50:50 chance that this will deliver global mean temperature rises of more than 4°C. It is now widely understood that such a rise is “incompatible with an organised global community.” [5]. The IPCC warns of “ tipping points ” in the Earth’s system, which, if crossed, could lead to a catastrophic collapse of interlinked human and natural systems. The AAAS concludes that there is now a “real chance of abrupt, unpredictable and potentially irreversible changes with highly damaging impacts on people around the globe.” [2] And this week a report from the World Meteorological Office (WMO) confirmed that extreme weather events are accelerating. WMO secretary general Michel Jarraud said, “There is no standstill in global warming . . . The laws of physics are non-negotiable.” [6] Warming disproportionately affects developing countries Carrington 11 – Head of the environment at The Guardian (Damian, “Map reveals stark divide in who caused climate change and who's being hit”, http://www.guardian.co.uk/environment/damian-carringtonblog/2011/oct/26/climate-change-developing-country-impacts-risk?CMP=twt_gu, October 26th, 2011, KTOP) When the world's nations convene in Durban in November in the latest attempt to inch towards a global deal to tackle climate change, one fundamental principle will, as ever, underlie the negotiations. Is the contention that while rich, industrialized nations caused climate change through past carbon emissions, it is the developing world that is bearing the brunt. It follows from that, developing nations say, that the rich nations must therefore pay to enable the developing nations to both develop cleanly and adapt to the impacts of global warming. The point is starkly illustrated in a new map of climate vulnerability (ommitted): the rich global north has low vulnerability; the poor global south has high vulnerability. The map is produced by risk analysts Maplecroft by combining measures of the risk of climate change impacts, such as storms, floods, and droughts, with the social and financial ability of both communities and governments to cope. The top three most vulnerable nations reflect all these factors: Haiti, Bangladesh, Zimbabwe. But it is not until you go all the way down 103 on the list, out of 193 nations, that you encounter the first major developed nation: Greece. The first 102 nations are all developing ones. Italy is next, at 124, and like Greece ranks relatively highly due to the risk of drought. The UK is at 178 and the country on Earth least vulnerable to climate change, according to Maplecroft, is Iceland. " Large areas of north America and northern Europe are not so exposed to actual climate risk, and are very well placed to deal with it," explains Charlie Beldon, principal analyst at Maplecroft. The vulnerability index has been calculated down to a resolution of 25km2 and Beldon says at this scale the vulnerability of the developing world's fast growing cities becomes clear. "A lot of big cities have developed in exposed areas such as flood plains, such as in south east Asia, and in developing economies they so don't have the capacity to adapt." Of the world's 20 fastest growing cities, six are classified as 'extreme risk' by Maplecroft, including Calcutta in India, Manila in the Philippines, Jakarta in Indonesia and Dhaka and Chittagong in Bangladesh. Addis Ababa in Ethiopia also features . A further 10 are rated as 'high risk' including Guangdong, Mumbai, Delhi, Chennai, Karachi and Lagos. "Cities such as Manila, Jakarta and Calcutta are vital centres of economic growth in key emerging markets, but heat waves, flooding, water shortages and increasingly severe and frequent storm events may well increase as climate changes takes hold," says Beldon. Case: Trafficking They don’t solve – don’t increase targeting of sex purchasers – no ev, that was cross-x Legalization causes trafficking, doesn’t solve support Sabasteanski 14 (Nika, staff writer, John Hopkins University Newsletter, 1/30/14, "US should emulate Sweden, not Germany, on prostitution decriminalization", http://www.jhunewsletter.com/2014/01/30/us-should-emulate-sweden-not-germany-onprostitution-decriminalization-27360 ) ¶ This all sounds well and good, but the fact remains that out of the 400,000 female and male prostitutes in Germany, only 44 are signed up to receive the health and welfare benefits provided. An article published in Spiegel comments, “In Hamburg, with its famous Reeperbahn red-light district, only 153 women are in compliance with regulations and have registered with the city’s tax office.” A report done by the German Federal Ministry for Family Affairs, Senior found that most women were not signed up to receive their social security benefits and employment contracts were used only by 1 percent of the women, because “the prostitutes did not consider it a financially attractive option.”¶ Additionally, there were few cases where a prostitute brought a client to German court to sue for fair pay. The same report also found that brothels were kept at substandard conditions and repeatedly stated that there had not been enough effort to reach the government’s goal of providing an exit strategy from prostitution. Perhaps the worst unintended consequence of legalization has been the significant Citizens, Women and Youth in 2007, reflecting on the social benefits provided to prostitutes in a 2002 piece of legislation, increase in sex trafficking in these areas . While police presence would seem like a positive regulatory frightened the women, mostly brought in illegally and underground from Eastern Europe, and made it difficult to expose trafficking rings, including those exploiting children. A study done by Axel Dreher of the University of Heidelberg et al., published a year ago, concluded after analyzing statistics from 150 countries, “On average, countries where prostitution is legal experience larger reported human mechanism, instead it has trafficking inflows.” The overall aim of legalization of prostitution was to protect the women, but this observation shows how pimps and traffickers instead exploited the attitude of lenience. The same study concluded that based on the two established and competing economic models in this field, the scale effect prevailed: The legalization of prostitution resulted in an overall increase in trafficking as the supply in the industry rose to balance with demand . The authors did note that there is an opposing force called the substitution effect, which relies on the fear of prosecution if trafficked women are used in legal brothels, but their data show this effect is generally dominated by the scale effect. ¶ Legalization increases violence against women IT ‘08 (The Irish Times citing Cari Mitchell a spokeswoman for the English Collective of Prostitutes (ECP), a network of women working in different areas of the sex industry “Should the laws against prostitution be abolished?” February 11, 2008 Monday, Lexis, TSW) Cari Mitchell is writing on behalf of the English Collective of Prostitutes NO: Legalising prostitution does not protect those involved but rather acts to expand the sex industry and normalise the exploitation of women. This has been proven in other jurisdictions such as the Netherlands. A woman seldom finds herself legalising the practice there is a failure to acknowledge that prostitution preys on particularly vulnerable individuals. Women in prostitution suffer violence or the threat of violence on a regular basis. Legalisation does not protect the women from violence, rape and murder, which are endemic in the sex industry and involved in prostitution as a result of unlimited choices, but rather as a consequence of very constrained circumstances. Prostitution is a survival strategy. By are understood to be "occupational hazards". Women prostituted in legal brothels in Victoria, Australia are given guidelines that dictate how to negotiate with a violent customer. In what other non-military profession is it necessary to handle hostage situations in a "normal" working day? No state has yet effectively regulated the sex industry. A woman seldom finds herself involved in prostitution as a result of unlimited choices, but rather as a consequence of very constrained circumstances. Prostitution is a survival strategy. By legalising the practice there is a failure to acknowledge that prostitution preys on particularly vulnerable individuals. The Netherlands believed that legalising prostitution would end child prostitution, but instead it has seen a huge increase in numbers of child prostitutes. The same phenomenon has occurred in Victoria, Australia. Legalised prostitution has contributed to an increase in organised crime within the industry and this has led to an increase in violence against the women. Calculation is good, inevitable and ethical Richard L. Revesz, Professor, Law, NYU and Michael A. Livermore, Executive Director, Institute for Policy Integrity, RETAKING RATIONALITY: HOW COST-BENEFIT ANALYSIS CAN BETTER PROTECT THE ENVIRONMENT AND OUR HEALTH, 2008, p. 14. Governmental decisions are also fundamentally different from personal decisions in that they often affect people in the aggregate. In our individual lives, we come into contact with at least some of the consequences of our decisions. If we fail to consult a map, we pay the price: losing valuable time driving around in circles and listening to the complaints of our passengers. We are constantly confronted with the consequences of the choices that we have made. Not so for governments, however, which exercise authority by making decisions at a distance. Perhaps one of the most challenging aspects of governmental decisions is that they require a special kind of compassion—one that can seem, at first glance, cold and calculating, the antithesis of empathy. The aggregate and complex nature of governmental decisions does not address people as human beings, with concerns and interests, families and emotional relationships, secrets and sorrows. Rather, people are numbers stacked in a column or points on a graph, described not through their individual stories of triumph and despair, but by equations, functions, and dose-response curves. The language of governmental decisionmaking can seem to —and to a certain extent does—ignore what makes individuals unique and morally important. But, although the language of bureaucratic decisionmaking can be dehumanizing, it is also a prerequisite for the kind of compassion that is needed in contemporary society. Elaine Scarry has developed a comparison between individual compassion and statistical compassion.' Individual compassion is familiar— when we see a person suffering, or hear the story of some terrible tragedy, we are moved to take action. Statistical compassion seems foreign—we hear only a string of numbers but must comprehend "the concrete realities embedded there."' Individual compassion derives from our social nature, and may be hardwired directly into the human brain.' Statistical compassion calls on us to use our higher reasoning power to extend our natural compassion to the task of solving more abstract—but no less real— problems. Because compassion is not just about making us feel better—which we could do as easily by forgetting about a problem as by addressing it—we have a responsibility to make the best decisions that we can. This book argues that cost-benefit analysis, properly conducted, can improve environmental and public health policy. Cost-benefit analysis—the translation of human lives and acres of forest into the language of dollars and cents—can seem harsh and impersonal. But such an approach is also necessary to improve the quality of decisions that regulators make. Saving the most lives, and best protecting the quality of our environment and our health—in short, exercising our compassion most effectively—requires us to step back and use our best analytic tools. Sometimes, in order to save a life, we need to treat a person like a number. This is the challenge of statistical compassion. This book is about making good decisions. It focuses on the area of environmental, health and safety regulation. These regulations have been the source of numerous and hard-fought controversies over the past several decades, particularly at the federal level. Reaching the right decisions in the areas of environmental protection, increasing safety, and improving public health is clearly of high importance. Although it is admirable (and fashionable) for people to buy green or avoid products made in sweatshops, efforts taken at the individual level are not enough to address the pressing problems we face—there is a vital role for government in tackling these issues, and sound collective decisions concerning regulation are needed. There is a temptation to rely on gut-level decisionmaking in order to avoid economic analysis, which, to many, is a foreign language on top of seeming cold and unsympathetic. For government to make good decisions, however, it cannot abandon reasoned analysis. Because of the complex nature of governmental decisions, we have no choice but to deploy complex analytic tools in order to make the best choices possible. Failing to use these tools, which amounts to abandoning our duties to one another, is not a legitimate response. Rather, we must exercise statistical compassion by recognizing what numbers of lives saved represent: living and breathing human beings, unique, with rich inner lives and an interlocking web of emotional relationships. The acres of a forest can be tallied up in a chart, but that should not blind us to the beauty of a single stand of trees. We need to use complex tools to make good decisions while simultaneously remembering that we are not engaging in abstract exercises, but that we are having real effects on people and the environment. In our personal lives, it would be unwise not to shop around for the best price when making a major purchase, or to fail to think through our options when making a major life decision. It is equally foolish for government to fail to fully examine alternative policies when making regulatory decisions with life-or-death consequences. This reality has been recognized by four successive presidential administrations. Since 1981, the cost-benefit analysis of major regulations has been required by presidential order. Over the past twenty-five years, however, environmental and other progressive groups have declined to participate in the key governmental proceedings concerning the cost-benefit analysis of federal regulations, instead preferring to criticize the technique from the outside. The resulting asymmetry in political participation has had profound negative consequences, both for the state of federal regulation and for the technique of cost-benefit analysis itself. Ironically, this state of affairs has left progressives open to the charge of rejecting reason, when in fact strong environmental and public health pro-grams are often justified by cost-benefit analysis. It is time for progressive groups, as well as ordinary citizens, to retake the high ground by embracing and reforming cost-benefit analysis. The difference between being unthinking—failing to use the best tools to analyze policy—and unfeeling—making decisions without compassion—is unimportant: Both lead to bad policy. Calamities can result from the failure to use either emotion or reason. Our emotions provide us with the grounding for our principles, our innate interconnectedness, and our sense of obligation to others. We use our powers of reason to build on that emotional foundation, and act effectively to bring about a better world. Default to consequences—anything else is tautological and irrational Joshua Greene, Associate Professor, Harvard University, “The Secret Joke of Kant’s Soul,” 20 10, www.fed.cuhk.edu.hk/~lchang/material/Evolutionary/Developmental/Greene-KantSoul.pdf What turn-of-the-millennium science is telling us is that human moral judgment is not a pristine rational enterprise, that our moral judgments are driven by a hodgepodge of emotional dispositions, which themselves were shaped by a hodgepodge of evolutionary forces, both biological and cultural. Because of this, it is exceedingly unlikely that there is any rationally coherent normative moral theory that can accommodate our moral intuitions. Moreover, anyone who claims to have such a theory, or even part of one, almost certainly doesn't. Instead, what that person probably has is a moral rationalization. It seems then, that we have somehow crossed the infamous "is"-"ought" divide. How did this happen? Didn't Hume (Hume, 1978) and Moore (Moore, 1966) warn us against trying to derive an "ought" from and "is?" How did we go from descriptive scientific theories concerning moral psychology to skepticism about a whole class of normative moral theories? The answer is that we did not, as Hume and Moore anticipated, attempt to derive an "ought" from and "is." That is, our method has been inductive rather than deductive. We have inferred on the basis of the available evidence that the phenomenon of rationalist deontological philosophy is best explained as a rationalization of evolved emotional intuition (Harman, 1977). Missing the Deontological Point I suspect that rationalist deontologists will remain unmoved by the arguments presented here. Instead, I suspect, they will insist that I have simply misunderstood whatKant and like-minded deontologists are all about. Deontology, they will say, isn't about this is about taking humanity seriously. Above all else, it's about respect for persons. It's about treating others as fellow rational creatures rather intuition or that intuition. It's not defined by its normative differences with consequentialism. Rather, deontology than as mere objects, about acting for reasons rational beings can share. And so on (Korsgaard, 1996a; Korsgaard, 1996b).This is, no doubt, how many deontologists see deontology. But this insider's view, as I've suggested, may be misleading. The problem, more specifically, is that it defines deontology in terms of values that are not distinctively deontological, though they may appear to be from the inside. Consider the following analogy with religion. When one asks a religious person to explain the essence of his religion, one often gets an answer like this: "It's about love, really. It's about looking out for other people, looking beyond oneself. It's about community, being part of something larger than oneself." This sort of answer accurately captures the phenomenology of many people's religion, but it's nevertheless inadequate for distinguishing religion from other things. This is because many, if not most, non-religious people aspire to love deeply, look out for other people, avoid self-absorption, have a sense of a community, and be connected to things larger than themselves. In other words, secular humanists and atheists can assent to most of what many religious people think religion is all about. From a secular humanist's point of view, in contrast, what's distinctive about religion is its commitment to the existence of supernatural entities as well as formal religious institutions and doctrines. And they're right. These things really do distinguish religious from non-religious practices, though they may appear to be secondary to many people operating from within a religious point of view. In the same way, I believe that most of the standard deontological/Kantian self-characterizatons fail to distinguish deontology from other approaches to ethics. (See also Kagan (Kagan, 1997, pp. 70-78.) on the difficulty of defining deontology.) It seems to me that consequentialists, as much as anyone else, have respect for persons, are against treating people as mere objects, wish to act for reasons that rational creatures can share, etc. A consequentialist respects other persons, and refrains from treating them as mere objects, by counting every person's well-being in the decision-making process. Likewise, a consequentialist attempts to act according to reasons that rational creatures can share by acting according to principles that give equal weight to everyone's interests, i.e. that are impartial. This is not to say that consequentialists and deontologists don't differ. They do. It's just that the real differences may not be what deontologists often take them to be. What, then, distinguishes deontology from other kinds of moral thought? A good strategy for answering this question is to start with concrete disagreements between deontologists and others (such as consequentialists) and then work backward in search of deeper principles. This is what I've attempted to do with the trolley and footbridge cases, and other instances in which deontologists and consequentialists disagree. If you ask a deontologically-minded person why it's wrong to push someone in front of speeding trolley in order to save five others, you will getcharacteristically deontological answers. Some will be tautological: "Because it's murder!"Others will be more sophisticated: "The ends don't justify the means." "You have to respect people's rights." But, as we know, these answers don't really explain anything, because if you give the same people (on different occasions) the trolley case or the loop case (See above), they'll make the opposite judgment, even though their initial explanation concerning the footbridge case applies equally well to one or both of these cases. Talk about rights, respect for persons, and reasons we can share are natural attempts to explain, in "cognitive" terms, what we feel when we find ourselves having emotionally driven intuitions that are odds with the cold calculus of consequentialism. Although these explanations are inevitably incomplete, there seems to be "something deeply right" about them because they give voice to powerful moral emotions. But, as with many religious people's accounts of what's essential to religion, they don't really explain what's distinctive about the philosophy in question. Health 1NC Legalization improving health is a myth—stigma and zoning mean this has never been the case in a country with legalized sex work Farley 4 (Melissa, University of Iowa (Ph.D., Counseling Psychology, 1973), San Francisco State University (MS, Clinical Psychology, 1966), Mills College (BA, Psychology, 1964), Prostitution Research and Education 1996–present, Kaiser Foundation Research Institute (Oakland, CA), 1993–2000, ‘“Bad for the Body, Bad for the Heart”: Prostitution Harms Women Even if Legalized or Decriminalized’, Violence Against Women, Vol. 10 No. 10, October 2004, www.prostitutionresearch.com/FarleyVAW.pdf ) Advocates of decriminalization argue that the health of those in prostitution will be improved by decriminalization because otherwise women will not have access to health care. It is assumed that women will seek health care as soon as the stigma of arrest is removed from prostitution. If the stigma is removed, advocates argue, women will then file a complaint whenever they are abused, raped, or assaulted in prostitution. They assume that the complaint will be followed with a police response that treats women in prostitution with dignity and as ordinary citizens. Unfortunately, health care workers and police too often share the same contempt toward those in prostitution that others do.¶ A former prostitute in NZ said to the Parliament: ¶ “This bill pro- vides people like me . . . with some form of redress [italics added], for the brutalisation that may happen...when you’re with a client and you have a knife pulled on you” (Georgina Beyer, speech, Wellington, NZ, June 26, 2003). The specific form of redress offered by the NZ decriminalization law was not described by the speaker, nor is it articulated in the law. The dilemma for the person in prostitution is not that there is no legal redress for coercion, physical assault, and rape in the new law or in old laws. The dilemma is that in prostitution there is no avoiding sexual harassment, sexual exploitation, rape, and acts that are the equivalent of torture.¶ Decriminalization in NZ was promoted as a means of providing those in prostitution with legal redress against violent johns. However, prostituted women could already take legal action under existing laws but rarely did so. Explaining this situation, a NZ Prostitutes Collective member stated, “They don’t want to draw attention to themselves and what they’re doing” (Else, 2003, n.p.). Women in the Netherlands have expressed similar sentiments, even though prostitution has been legal there for many¶ years. Their concern was the loss of anonymity that exists in legal prostitution . Once officially registered as prostitutes, Dutch women feared that this designation would pursue them for the rest of their lives. Despite the fact that if officially registered as prostitutes they would accrue pension funds, the women still preferred anonymity (Schippers, 2002). They wanted to leave prostitution as quickly as possible with no legal record of having been in prostitution (Daley, 2001). Similarly, despite attempts to unionize women in Germany’s $16.5 billion legal prostitution industry, the women not only avoided unions, they avoided registering with the government and they continued to engage in illegal prostitution in part because they felt that the remote areas where prostitution is zoned put them at increased , not decreased, risk of physical danger (Taubitz, 2004). HIV is decreasing now Kelland 14 7/16 (Kate, contributor, Kate, Global AIDS epidemic can be controlled by 2030, U.N. says <http://www.reuters.com/article/2014/07/16/us-health-hiv-unaids-idUSKBN0FL0RX20140716>, TF) New HIV infections and deaths from AIDS are decreasing , the United Nations said on Wednesday, making it possible to control the epidemic by 2030 and eventually end it " in every region, in every country".¶ "More than ever before, there is hope that ending AIDS is possible. However, a business-as-usual approach or simply sustaining the AIDS response at its current pace cannot end the epidemic," the U.N. AIDS program UNAIDS said in a global report issued ahead of an AIDS conference in Melbourne, Australia next week. ¶ It said the number of people infected with HIV was stabilizing at around 35 million worldwide. The epidemic had killed some 39 million of the 78 million people it has affected since it began in the 1980s.¶ "The AIDS epidemic can be ended in every region, every country, in every location, in every population and every community," Michel Sidibe, the director of UNAIDS, said in the report. "There are multiple reasons why there is hope and conviction about this goal." ¶ The human immunodeficiency virus (HIV) that causes AIDS can be transmitted via blood, breast milk and by semen during sex, but can be kept in check with cocktails of drugs known as antiretroviral therapy or ART. ¶ UNAIDS said that at the end of 2013, some 12.9 million HIV positive people had access to antiretroviral therapy - a dramatic improvement on the 10 million who were on treatment just one year earlier and the only 5 million who were getting AIDS drugs in 2010.¶ Since 2001, new HIV infections have fallen by 38 percent, it said. AIDS deaths have fallen 35 percent since a peak in 2005.¶ "The world has witnessed extraordinary changes in the AIDS landscape. There have been more achievements in the past five years than in the preceding 23 years," the report said.¶ The U.N. report said ending the AIDS epidemic by 2030 would mean the spread of HIV was being controlled or contained, and that the impact of the virus in societies and in people's lives had been reduced by significant declines in ill health, stigma, deaths and the number of AIDS orphans.¶ "It means increased life expectancy, unconditional acceptance of people's diversity and rights, and increased productivity and reduced costs as the impact diminishes."¶ According to UNAIDS, $19.1 billion was available from all sources for the AIDS response in 2013, and the estimated annual need by 2015 is currently between $22 billion and $24 billion. ¶ Sidibe said the international community should seize the opportunity to turn the epidemic around. ¶ "We have a fragile five-year window to build on the rapid results that been made," he said. "If we accelerate all HIV scale-up by 2020, we will be on track to end the epidemic by 2030. If not, we risk significantly increasing the time it would take - adding a decade, if not more."¶ He said controlling the epidemic by 2030 would avert 18 million new HIV infections and 11.2 million AIDS deaths between 2013 and 2030.¶ In 2011, U.N. member states agreed to a target of getting HIV treatment to 15 million people by 2015. As countries scaled up treatment coverage, and evidence showed how treating HIV early also reduces its spread, the World Health Organization (WHO) set new guidelines last year, expanding the number of people needing treatment by more than 10 million. ¶ Jennifer Cohn, medical director of the access campaign for the charity Médecins Sans Frontières (MSF), said millions of HIV positive people still do not get the drugs they needed.¶ "Providing life-saving HIV treatment to nearly 12 million people in the developing world is a significant achievement, but more than half of people in need still do not have access," she said. "We know that early treatment helps prevent transmission of HIV and keeps people healthy; we need to respond to HIV in all contexts and make treatment accessible to everyone in need as soon as possible." 2NC CP legalization and decrim are distinct, legalization controls their lives Prostitutes Education Network no date (informational site about prostitution legalization, http://www.bayswan.org/defining.html) Decriminalisation Decriminalisation refers to the removal of all criminal laws relating to the operation of the sex industry. The decriminalisation model aims to support occupational health and safety and workplace issues through existing legal and workplace mechanisms.¶ Legalisation¶ Refers to the use of criminal laws to regulate or control the sex industry by determining the legal conditions under which the sex industry can operate. Legalisation can be highly regulatory or merely define the operation of the various sectors of the sex industry. It can vary between rigid controls under legalised state controlled systems to privatising the sex industry within a legally defined framework. It is often accompanied by strict criminal penalties for sex industry businesses that operate outside the legal framework. ¶ Defining terms for contemporary discussion¶ Although there have always been reformist efforts and movements concerning prostitution, the prostitutes' rights movement, as we know it today, began in the late 60's and early 70's. The difference between the contemporary prostitutes' movement and previous efforts is that the current movement has been defined in a large part by prostitutes themselves. Prostitute activists have defined prostitutes' legal status in specific ways since the beginning of the prostitutes' rights movement. The current movement includes a recognition of the rights of prostitutes to autonomy and self-regulation. ¶ Common definitions of legalization¶ There is no official definition of legalized or decriminalized prostitution. Those who are not familiar with the contemporary discussion about prostitution law reform usually use the term "legalization" to mean any alternative to absolute criminalization, ranging from licensing of brothels to the lack of any laws about prostitution. Most references to law reform in the media and in other contemporary contexts use the term "legalization" to refer to any system that allows some prostitution. These common definitions of legalization are extremely broad. Conflicting interpretations of this term often cause confusion in a discussion of reform. ¶ Many (or most) societies that allow prostitution do so by giving the state control over the lives and businesses of those who work as prostitutes. Legalization often includes special taxes for prostitutes, restricting prostitutes to working in brothels or in certain zones, licenses, registration of prostitutes and government records of individual prostitutes, and health checks which often means punitive quarantine . The term legalization does not necessarily have to refer to the above sorts of regulations. In fact, in one commonly accepted definition of legalization, legal can simply mean that prostitution is not against the law. ¶ Legalization¶ From sociological perspective, the term legalization usually refers to a system of criminal regulation and government control of prostitutes , wherein certain prostitutes are given licenses which permit them to work in specific and usually limited ways. Although legalization can also imply a decriminalized, autonomous system of prostitution, in reality, in most "legalized" systems the police are relegated the job of prostitution control through criminal codes. Laws regulate prostitutes businesses and lives, prescribing health checks and registration of health status (enforced by police and, often corrupt, medical agencies), telling prostitutes where they may or may not reside, prescribing full time employment for their lovers, etc. Prostitute activists use the term legalization to refer to systems of state control , which defines the term by the realities of the current situation, rather than by the broad implications of the term itself.¶ Because of the range of definitions of legalization, it is difficult to use the term in a discussion of reform. When the general public concerned with civil rights, privacy, etc., call for "legalization," they may not be aware implications of that term, or of the problems inherent in many legalized systems. ¶ Decriminalization¶ Prostitutes' rights organizations (ie, COYOTE, National Task Force on Prostitution) use the term decriminalization to mean the removal of laws against prostitution. Decriminalization is usually used to refer to total decriminalization, that is, the repeal of laws against consensual adult sexual activity, in commercial and non-commercial contexts. (Prostitutes' rights organizations such as US PROS, English Collective of Prostitutes prefer to refer to 'the abolition of laws against prostitutes'). Prostitutes' rights advocates call for decriminalization of all aspects of prostitution resulting from individual decision. Asserting the right to work as a prostitutes, many claim their right to freedom of choice of management. They claim that laws against pimping (living off the earnings) are often used against domestic partners and children, and these laws serve to to prevent prostitutes from organizing their businesses and working together for mutual protection. They call for the repeal of current laws that interfere with their rights of freedom of travel and freedom of association . Civil rights and human rights advocates from a variety of perspectives call for enforcement of laws against fraud, abuse, violence and coercion to protect prostitutes from abusive, exploitative partners and management. Legalization includes regulation- decriminalization does not- Swedish model does decrim Micah Schwartzbach No Date (Either 2013 or 2014), Micah Schwartzbach joined Nolo’s editorial staff in 2013. Before that he was a criminal defense lawyer specializing in research and writing, first in Berkeley, then in Marin County. In 2008 he served as co-counsel in the landmark acquittal of an organ transplant surgeon accused of attempting to accelerate a potential organ donor’s death. (People v. Roozrokh, San Luis Obispo Superior Court Case No. F405885.) He writes and edits content across a range of practice areas. He also authors Uncuffed: A Candid Take on Crime and Society, a blog that dissects the world of criminal law. Micah earned his B.A. from the University of California, Davis, where he graduated with highest honors, and his J.D. from the University of California, Hastings College of the Law, where he graduated cum laude. “Decriminalizing Prostitution“ http://www.criminaldefenselawyer.com/resources/decriminalizing-prostitution.htm ac 8-18 Legalization vs. Decriminalization¶ Those who oppose the criminalization of prostitution typically advocate one of two approaches : legalization (which involves regulation ) or decriminalization ( no regulation). Legalization is what Nevada practices: the direct regulation of prostitution by the government . This regulation may include an array of methods, from zoning requirements and advertising restrictions to mandatory tests for sexually transmitted diseases. (For more information on Nevada's prostitution laws, see Prostitution, Pimping, and Pandering Laws in Nevada.) ¶ Decriminalization is the removal of laws and regulation; under this model, prostitution is treated just like any other occupation. Sweden takes a partial decriminalization approach, under which the sale of sex is not illegal, but its purchase is. New Zealand, on the other hand, has decriminalized both the purchase and sale of sexual activity . Critics of decriminalization point to studies regarding New Zealand’s sex trade that show that violence against sex workers has persisted in that country. Decriminalization solves the aff—permutation can’t solve because the regulations of the aff are mutually exclusive Oakford 14 Cartographer, Researcher at New Economy Project SEO Specialist / Contributor at BabyMed Cartographer and Researcher at Cartography Lab, SUNY Binghamton, Samuel,“Want to Combat AIDS? Decriminalize Sex Work, Researchers Say,” July 24, 2014, https://news.vice.com/article/want-to-combat-aids-decriminalize-sex-work-researchers-say) Efforts to prevent HIV usually consist of proactive interventions — but when it comes to sex workers, leaving them alone may be the best prescription of all. A study presented by researchers at the 20th International AIDS Conference in Melbourne this week determined that decriminalizing sex work would have “the greatest effect on the course of HIV epidemics” across the world. Female sex workers in low- and middle-income countries are more than 13 times as likely to contract HIV than women outside the industry, and are at high risk of transmitting the virus to others. In order to lower HIV rates worldwide, researchers at the conference argued, countries should make improving the circumstances of sex workers a top priority. The study, which was published by the British medical journal The Lancet as the first in a series partly funded by the United Nations Population Fund, found that criminalization makes sex workers more likely to be beleaguered or abused by police and less likely to use condoms or seek treatment for HIV and other diseases. Prominent HIV/AIDS researchers among those killed in Malaysia Airlines crash. Read more here. Using a statistical model informed by previous surveys, the researchers calculated the potential diminishment in HIV infections over the next ten years in three cities — Vancouver, Canada; Mombasa, Kenya; and Bellary, India — should they decriminalize the trade. They found that this policy would lower HIV’s prevalence among sex workers in Vancouver by 37 percent, by 33 percent in Mombasa, and by 46 percent in Bellamy. “We did a systematic review of the literature of the past five years,” Steffanie Strathdee, director of the University of California at San Diego’s Global Health Initiative and one of the paper’s authors, told VICE News. “Our evidence from the modeling supports full decriminalization.” Public health advocates hailed the study’s conclusion. “It highlights, for the first time, the intimate connection between a criminalized status and the risks that are associated with it,” Marine Buissonniere, director of the Open Society Public Health Program, told VICE News. The World Health Organization earlier this month called for decriminalizing the “behavior of key populations” at risk for HIV. “In places where sex work is criminalized you tend to find a community that is extremely vulnerable and marginalized, where they are subject to abuse in the healthcare system and more generally don’t enjoy the same set of human rights,” said Buissonniere. “When a country criminalizes either sex work or drug use it tends to push people underground and away from services.” Uganda's truck stop prostitutes are in the country's AIDS epicenter. Read more here. Though countries like the Netherlands and Germany have legalized sex work in defined contexts, and nations like Denmark have decriminalized it in certain circumstances (soliciting on the street is still illegal), the only two places in the world to have fully decriminalized it are New Zealand the Australian state of New South Wales. The distinction is important — decriminalization removes all “prostitution-specific regulations imposed by the state,” while legalization introduces new laws and regulations that are less punitive. In the latter framework, sex workers without proper permits or access are still forced to work underground . “ Legalization actually replicates some of the same problems that criminalization does, ” Strathdee said. “ The perspective is about taxes and control and not about human rights. Even in legalized environments there are police crackdowns. ” CP Better Sex workers want decrim Lutnick and Cohan 9 (Alexandra Lutnick, Public Health Analyst, Research Triangle Institute International. Deborah Cohan, Associate Professor, Department of Obstetrics, Gynecology and Reproductive Sciences, University of California San Francisco. “Criminalization, legalization or decriminalization of sex work: what female sex workers say in San Francisco, USA”, Reproductive Health Matters, 2009) ac 8-17 Decriminalization The majority of study participants expressed sup- port for certain tenets of a decriminalized model. Seventy-one per cent agreed or strongly agreed that courts should get rid of laws that make sex work illegal. A large portion felt that they should be allowed to trade sex in strip clubs and mas- sage parlors (68%), on the streets (77%), and in escort agencies and brothels (87%). The majority of the women, 82%, preferred street-based sex work to happen in commercial areas and red light districts. Ninety-one per cent wanted laws that protected the rights of sex workers. Legalization The legalization of sex work often times results in sex workers and their businesses experiencing heightened forms of regulation that are not wit- nessed in other businesses . One-third of the women thought that the San Francisco Health Department should regulate sex work, and 84% felt that they should have to undergo health screening to be able to engage in sex work. Discussion The sex workers in this study were predominately those who are considered the most marginalized . In the qualitative phase, one-third of the women were street-based sex workers, and 25% were current injection drug users. Over two-thirds of those in the quantitative phase reported cur- rent street-based sex work, and over half were current injection drug users. These are the work- ers who are likely most at risk for physical and sexual assault, as well as arrest. Taking all the women's responses into consideration, their pref- erences do not fit neatly into any one of the three pre-existing legal frameworks. The majority of sex workers voiced a preference for removing the statutes that criminalize sex work in order to facilitate a social and political environment where they would have legal rights and could seek help when they were victims of violence. They did not want to be arrested for their sex work, yet they also did not want to be regulated by government or pay taxes, sentiments that hold true for many people. Likewise, with over half the women receiving some type of federal or state financial assistance, if they reported sex work income they would likely cease to be eligible for assistance. While many women voiced their opposition to government oversight, some advocated for ele- ments of regulation that are found in legalized systems, including mandated health screening, and decriminalized models, such as zoning restric- tions. It is possible that these responses were influ- enced by the setting where the interviews were conducted – a sex worker health clinic. As such, they may have felt that health examinations would be done in a community-based, peer-led clinic. The preference that street-based sex work be covered by zoning restrictions may have been informed by the reality that those who work on the street in a criminalized system have very little control over their work situation. If there were specified areas for street prostitution, women might feel safer due to the more controlled nature of the work environment. An argument frequently used against crimi- nalization is the rampant violence sex workers experience in criminalized settings. 1,2,9,17 – 24 Police abuse, such as sexual demands in lieu of arrest 19,23 and excessive use of physical force have been reported, e.g. in Canada and the United States. 21,25 Most crimes against sex workers go unpunished, as most sex workers do not go to the police when they have been victimized. 3,22,23,26 Few papers address the risk of violence among femalesexworkersinSanFrancisco.Inacross- sectional study of 783 adults accessing health care at St. James Infirmary from 19992004, we found that 36.3% of the women experienced sex work-related violence, and 7.9% police violence. 24 Another study conducted in San Francisco in 1990-91 found that female sex workers, as com- pared to male and transgender workers, were at higher risk of rape and arrest for prostitution- related offences. 27 Hay's article about police abuse of prostitutes in San Francisco acknowledges that the most frequent type of police abuse reported by sex workers, the demand for sex in lieu of arrest, is the hardest to verify. Many of the women in that study reported not filing a complaint when abused by a police officer as they doubted it would result in any positive change. Hay sees police abuse as just another occupational hazard, 19 but it is presumably one th at could be challenged more readily if prostitution were decriminalized. Even if sex work were to be decriminalized or legalized, many things might not change. If prostitution codes were removed, there are still other legal codes such as loitering, trespassing, public nuisance and narcotics which could be used to target sex workers. Additionally, given the deep cultural beliefs about sex work, decrim- inalization or legalization would likely not elim- inate the stigma associated with prostitution. A change in the criminal code would also not guar- antee access to the health and social services the women want. Incarceration should not be the only way for the women to stop using/drinking or accessing vital services such as health care, drug treatment or housing. Any future work towards decriminalization will need to be coupled with a commitment that the health and social services sex workers want will be available. The vast majority of women in this study did not want sex work to be a criminal offence, but they did not want to be regulated by government or pay taxes either. This disparate set of preferences cannot co-exist under the framework of decriminalization. Therefore, it is clear that future work by advocacy groups needs to explore with a diversity of sex workers the compromises they are willing to make to ensure safe working con- ditions and the same legal protections afforded to other workers. More of the women might be willing to pay taxes and accept the same regu- lations as other businesses if they knew it would result in the acquisition of legal protection. This requires further inquiry. It is also probable that marginalized sex workers have not been as visible in previous decriminalization campaigns because their basic needs are not being met, and organizing for legal change is not their immedi- ate priority. Advocacy groups need to work with sex workers – women, men and transgender – who are most marginalized, to understand their immediate needs and how these can be addressed through decriminalization. T 2NC 2NC – Prostitution--Includes the Patron Supreme court and layperson understanding go neg- patron is included Noldon, 4 -- J.D. Candidate, University of Virginia School of Law [Tonya, Virginia Sports and Entertainment Law Journal articles editor, "Challenging First Amendment Protection of Adult Films with the Use of Prostitution Statutes," Virginia Sports & Entertainment Law Journal, Spring 2004, 3 Va. Sports & Ent. L.J. 310, l/n, accessed 6-21-14] A. The Federal Prostitution Statute - The Mann Act The federal statute commonly known as the Mann Act (or the White Slave Traffic Act) prohibits the transportation, through interstate commerce, of any individual with the intent to have that individual engage in prostitution. n22 The [*315] highest court ruling on the applicability of the Mann Act to adult films is the Tenth Circuit's decision in United States v. Roeder. n23 The Act was successfully used in that case to uphold the conviction of a maker of adult films for unlawfully, willingly, and knowingly transporting in interstate commerce an individual for the purpose of prostitution, debauchery, or other immoral purposes, in violation of the Act. n24 In this case, the court used the Supreme Court's definition of prostitution from Cleveland v. United States, which broadly defined prostitution as "sexual relations for hire." n25 In Roeder, a filmmaker drove a woman from Missouri to Kansas for the purpose of having her perform sexual acts with him to make a pornographic movie. n26 Because the woman had been hired to engage in sexual relations, thereby satisfying the Supreme Court's definition of prostitution, and had been driven across state lines for this purpose, the Mann Act had been violated. n27 The fact that the filmmaker not only paid the woman to perform sexual acts in the movie, but was himself in the movie acting as her sexual partner, creates a transparent analogy between the making of this adult film and traditional prostitution transactions. As part of any layperson's understanding of prostitution, a "customer" pays an individual to engage in sexual activity with him or her. The facts of this case seem to suggest that Roeder's conviction rested not only on his transporting the woman through interstate commerce to participate in a pornographic film, but additionally on the fact that the filmmaker was himself a participant in the film. n28 In essence, he fulfilled not only the broad Supreme Court definition of prostitution, but the more basic and narrower understanding of prostitution by being the "customer" who paid a woman to have sex with him. Includes buyer and seller Alaska Statues, 13 [Title 11. Criminal Law, Chapter 66. Offenses Against Public Health and Decency, Article 1. Prostitution and Related Offenses, Alaska Stat. § 11.66.100, 4-1-14, l/n, accessed 6-21-14] Sec. 11.66.100. Prostitution (a) A person commits the crime of prostitution if the person (1) engages in or agrees or offers to engage in sexual conduct in return for a fee; or (2) offers a fee in return for sexual conduct. (b) Except as provided in (c) of this section, prostitution is a class B misdemeanor. (c) Prostitution is a class C felony if (1) the defendant violates (a) of this section as a patron of a prostitute; (2) the prostitute is under 18 years of age; and (3) the defendant is over 18 years of age and at least three years older than the prostitute. (d) In a prosecution under (c) of this section, it is an affirmative defense that, at the time of the alleged offense, the defendant (1) reasonably believed the prostitute to be 18 years of age or older; and (2) undertook reasonable measures to verify that the prostitute was 18 years of age or older. 1NR Ext1--Trafficking 2NC Legalizing prostitution results in a net increase of prostitution – Netherlands proves that it makes it harder to prosecute. Raymond, professor at the University of Massachusetts, ‘3 [Janice, “Ten Reasons for Not Legalizing Prostitution And a Legal Response to the Demand for Prostitution”, Journal of Trauma Practice, 2, 2003: pp. 315-332, RSR] Legalized or decriminalized prostitution industries are one of the root causes of sex trafficking. One argument for legalizing prostitution in the Netherlands was that legalization would help to end the exploitation of desperate immigrant women who had been trafficked there for prostitution. However, one report found that 80% of women in the brothels of the Netherlands were trafficked from other countries (Budapest Group, 1999)(1). In 1994, the International Organization of Migration (IOM) stated that in the Netherlands alone, “nearly 70 % of trafficked women were from CEEC [Central and Eastern European Countries]” (IOM, 1995, p. 4). The government of the Netherlands presents itself as a champion of anti-trafficking policies and programs, yet it has removed every legal impediment to pimping, procuring and brothels. In the year 2000, the Dutch Ministry of Justice argued in favor of a legal quota of foreign “sex workers,” because the Dutch prostitution market demanded a variety of “bodies” (Dutting, 2001, p. 16). Also in 2000, the Dutch government sought and received a judgment from the European Court recognizing prostitution as an economic activity, thereby enabling women from the European Union and former Soviet bloc countries to obtain working permits as “sex workers” in the Dutch sex industry if they could prove that they are self employed. Non-governmental organizations (NGOs) in Europe report that traffickers use the work permits to bring foreign women into the Dutch prostitution industry, masking the fact that women have been trafficked, by coaching them to describe themselves as independent “migrant sex workers” (Personal Communication, Representative of the International Human Rights Network, 1999). In the year since lifting the ban on brothels in the Netherlands, eight Dutch victim support organizations reported an increase in the number of victims of trafficking, and twelve victim support organization reported that the number of victims from other countries has not diminished (Bureau NRM, 2002, p. 75). Forty-three of the 348 municipalities (12%) in the Netherlands choose to follow a no-brothel policy, but the Minister of Justice has indicated that the complete banning of prostitution within any municipality could conflict with the federally guaranteed “right to free choice of work” (Bureau NRM, 2002, p.19). The first steps toward legalization of prostitution in Germany occurred in the 1980s. By 1993, it was widely recognized that 75% of the women in Germany’s prostitution industry were foreigners from Uruguay, Argentina, Paraguay and other countries in South America (Altink, 1993, p. 33). After the fall of the Berlin wall, 80% of the estimated 10,000 women trafficked into Germany were from Central and Eastern Europe and CIS countries (IOM. 1998a , p. 17). In 2002, prostitution in Germany was established as a legitimate job after years of being legalized in tolerance zones. Promotion of prostitution, pimping and brothels are now legal in Germany. The sheer volume of foreign women in the German prostitution industry suggests that these women were trafficked into Germany, a process euphemistically described as facilitated migration. It is almost impossible for poor women to facilitate their own migration, underwrite the costs of travel and travel documents, and set themselves up in “business” without intervention. In 1984, a Labor government in the Australian State of Victoria introduced legislation to legalize prostitution in brothels. Subsequent Australian governments expanded legalization culminating in the Prostitution Control Act of 1994. Noting the link between legalization of prostitution and trafficking in Australia, the US Department of State observed: “Trafficking in East Asian women for the sex trade is a growing problem…lax laws – including legalized prostitution in parts of the country – make [antitrafficking] enforcement difficult at the working level” (U.S. Department of State, 2000, p. 6F). Legalization increases human trafficking – provides a legal shield for these operations. Hodge, Associate Professor in the School of Social Work at Arizona State University, ‘8 [David, “Sexual Trafficking in the United States: A Domestic Problem with Transnational Dimensions”, Social Work, Vol. 53, No. 2, April 2008, RSR] One of the more controversial proposals to address trafficking is to legalize adult prostitution (Long, 2004). Proponents of this approach argue that the sex industry should be brought out of the shadows and subjected to government regulation. Subsequently, child prostitution will be eliminated and women will be protected from violence and exploitation. Little if any research, however, has illustrated that legalizing certain forms of adult prostitution decreases illegal forms of prostitution (Farley, 2004). Rather the converse seems to be more accurate —legalization appears to increase the prevalence of illegal and legal prostitution (Farley, 2004; Raymond, 2004). Illegal activities are shielded behind legal activities. Nations such as the Netherlands, which have legalized prostitution, appear to have become magnets for traffickers and have witnessed significant increases in child prostitution (Raymond, 2003; Sullivan & Jeffreys, 2001). Similarly, in the U nited S tates, research suggests that the presence of large adult prostitution markets fosters higher levels of child sexual exploitation (Estes & Weiner, 2001). Data from Australia proves that it leads to massive growth in the trafficking industry. Sullivan and Jeffreys, ‘1 [Mary (PhD, Political Science, University of Melbourne) and Sheila (Associate Professor in the Department of Political Science at the University of Melbourne), “LEGALISING PROSTITUTION IS NOT THE ANSWER: THE EXAMPLE OF VICTORIA, AUSTRALIA”, COALITION AGAINST TRAFFICKING IN WOMEN (AUSTRALIA), 2001, RSR] Legalisation was intended to eliminate organised crime from the sex industry. In fact the reverse has happened. Legalisation has brought with it an explosion in the trafficking of women into prostitution by organized crime. Convicted criminals, fronted by supposedly more reputable people, remain in the business. Fred Lelah who ran Sasha’s International, one of Melbourne’s inner suburban legal brothels, appeared before the Melbourne Magistrate’s court in February 2000 for introducing girls 10-15 into his business. Lelah has already served a two year term for the same offence. sex “businessmen” are involved in the lucrative international sex trade run by crime syndicates which is worth $A30 million in Australia. An Australian Institute of Criminology study estimated that Australian brothels earned $1 million a week from this illegal trade . Some examples of the trade came to light in 1999. One Melbourne sex trafficker brought 40 Thai women into Victoria as “contract workers,” depriving them of their passports and earnings until their contracts were worked off. This is called debt bondage . The women had to have sex with 500 men before Recently it has been revealed that Victorian receiving any money and were imprisoned by him (The Age, 9 May 1999). This man has since received an 18 month suspended sentence and a fine, to the outrage of those who want the traffic of women into sex slavery taken seriously. In another case 25 Asian women were found in similar circumstances in one of Melbourne's legal brothels. These incidences are likely to be but the tip of the iceberg , and The Age newspaper states that a number of legal brothels are known to contain such “contract workers.” The commercial sexual exploitation of young people in Metropolitan Melbourne is also rife. ECPAT (End Child Prostitution and Trafficking) conducted research in 1998 for the Australian National Inquiry on Child Prostitution by asking youth and community agencies in Melbourne how many young people that had used their services had been used in prostitution. The figure was 1 in 7. In a study conducted by the Victorian Department of human services, young people involved in commercial sexual activities reported having “significant” contact with child sexual abuse (“paedophile”) rings. These young people disclosed that as a consequence of their involvement with “paedophile” rings, they experienced rape and were forced into pornography Feminist campaigners who worked through the League of Nations against the traffic in women between the licensed brothels acted as warehouses for trafficked women (Jeffreys, Sheila, 1997. The Idea of Prostitution. Melbourne: Spinifex). Currently these brothels create a demand for constant new recruits, and fuel the illegal trafficking industry. The U.S. State Department’s Human Rights Of all the states and World Wars I and II argued that territories, the highest number of reported incidences of children involved in prostitution c ame from Victoria. There was also clear evidence of organised commercial exploitation of children.11 Report for 1999 criticises Australia for lax laws on prostitution, including legalisation, which make it difficult to act against trafficking. It is not possible to tackle the trafficking in women with any seriousness until brothels are abolished. Ext2—Violence Turn 2NC Extend 1NC 2 the violence turn The aff normalizes exploitation—that increases violence—netherlands proves IT ‘08 (The Irish Times citing Cari Mitchell a spokeswoman for the English Collective of Prostitutes (ECP), a network of women working in different areas of the sex industry “Should the laws against prostitution be abolished?” February 11, 2008 Monday, Lexis, TSW) Legalization schemes lead to a greater underground market, decreases women’s control over their bodies and rights, recreates the state as a pimp, reinforces sex discrimination and leads to labor rights violations Miller and Haltiwanger 4 (Coty and Nuria, CRIME AND PUNISHMENT LAW CHAPTER: Prostitution and The Legalization/Decriminalization Debate, The Georgetown Journal of Gender and the Law, 5 Geo. J. Gender & L. 207, Spring 2004, p. 240-41) Feminist theorists on both sides of the debate, while acknowledging the success in preventing the spread of disease, criticize the Nevada legalization scheme as serving "the interests of men, of brothel keepers, and of tax collectors ... while imposing heavy, and seemingly unjustified burdens on working women ." They question the effectiveness of these regulations, pointing to the fact that illegal prostitutes in the large cities of Las Vegas and Reno (where all forms of prostitution are prohibited) still outnumber the legal prostitutes working in brothels throughout the rest of the state. Their strongest criticisms, however, focus on what they perceive as a loss of independence faced by the women within the brothel system and the inherent patriarchy of the labor relationship. The first issue of much criticism involves institutionalization of brothel-prostitution. Unlike decriminalization that would permit all forms of prostitution, the Nevada system only allows and protects prostitution within a licensed brothel. This policy initiative in and of itself eliminates the option of women to work on their own where they would keep their earnings rather than share them with a brothel's management . Many view this institutionalization of brothels as a redefinition of the "pimp-prostitute" relationship, replacing individual pimps with a limited number of brothel owners directly linked to the government. These critics go as far as to say that the government is now the pimp, controlling "with whom, when, and where the prostitute engages in prostitution through a rigid series of time, place, and manner restrictions." Once a prostitute is licensed, she is subject to state and county regulations, as well as brothel "house rules" that all involve the surrender of certain rights. In many counties, for example, women cannot "have their children live in the community in which they work, they cannot drive a car in the city limits, and they must be off the streets by 5 p.m." Apart from these restrictions, a brothel prostitute has little to no options in choosing her clients or work hours. A typical working shift for a brothel prostitute involves twelve to fourteen hour days, every day for three weeks straight. Even faced with these restrictions on liberty, many women still choose to enter into the brothel system because of the possibility of substantial income. However, once a prostitute has finished paying expenses, such as room and board, maid services, condoms, mandatory tipping of employees, and the weekly venereal disease checkups, she nets only about fifty percent of her gross earnings. As a result, many women rather risk violence and arrest in illegal prostitution than surrender many of their rights and half of their income. Similarly, many prostitutes do not want to incur further stigmatization by going public as a prostitute through the licensing process. Critics of this licensing scheme assert that even if "prostitutes are no longer stigmatized as criminals," they still suffer stigmatization as "bad girls." These critics unlike the prostitutes that must first obtain public licenses, patrons "do not face registration or risk friends and family finding out emphasize the disparate treatment of prostitutes and customers, arguing that, about their activities." The last major criticism made by feminists involves the labor classifications of women within the brothel system. Presently, prostitutes within the brothels are considered independent contractors rather than employees. This classification has a significant impact on benefits and social safety nets that a prostitute would enjoy if categorized as an employee. Since prostitutes are regarded as independent contractors, brothel owners are not required to, and thus do not, provide health insurance, workers' compensation, unemployment insurance, vacation pay, sick leave or retirement benefits. Legalization increases abuse against women via brothel owners and pimps, trafficking, child prostitution and violence Curva 12 (Ione Curva is the Research Editor, Rutgers Law Review. Candidate for J.D., Rutgers School of Law - Newark, 2012, Thinking Globally, Acting Locally: How New Jersey Prostitution Law Reform Can Reduce Sex Trafficking, Rutgers Law Review, 64 Rutgers L. Rev. 557, Winter 12, pp. 587-88) In order for individual prostitutes to make money (since they must give a portion of their earnings to the brothel owners), they must see as many clients as they can each night to earn a profit. Teri, a prostitute from a Nevada brothel stated, "The brothel owners are worse than any pimp. They abuse and imprison women and are fully protected by the state." The legislation seems to have the opposite effect of deterring pimps and traffickers . Moving prostitution indoors makes it more invisible so that women can be controlled in more violent ways. "Indoor prostitution, above all, protects the trick. Men are physically and psychologically safer when prostitution is indoors." Legalization has not resulted in a decrease of trafficked women, which was one of the law's objectives; to the contrary, rates of trafficking have increased in places where prostitution is legal: "The European nations that have legalized, the Netherlands and Germany, have the highest numbers of trafficked women... . The increase in numbers of male buyers that results from legalization increases the demand for prostitution, which is met by the trafficking of women into both legal and illegal sectors ... ." [*588] In addition to an increase in the number of trafficked women, rates of child prostitution and child trafficking have flourished since legalization . Interpol, the British police, and the Dutch police all agree that the Netherlands is "a prime destination and home for child sexual abusers, also known as pedophiles." Arguments that legalization would help to "control and reduce child prostitution have not proved true, with police suspecting that child prostitute abusers choose the Netherlands because of its prostitution-promoting environment." Similarly there are high rates of child prostitution and trafficking in Nevada, prompting various groups - including police, the FBI, juvenile court system, and advocacy groups - to unite to aid child victims. Nevada police have estimated that approximately 400 children are forced into prostitution each year, though "former prostitutes say the number of children is much higher and pimps much [sic] are more devious." In sum, though places with legalized prostitution have done so in an effort to decrease sexual exploitation, in reality the opposite effect has occurred. In fact, female prostitutes believe that legalized prostitution benefits the state above all. There is no evidence that legalization protects victims of trafficking and forced prostitution; the opposite has been shown to be true. In reality, "legal prostitution is "statesponsored prostitution" with "legal brothels" akin to "little prisons." Sex workers themselves vote neg Farley 4 (Melissa, University of Iowa (Ph.D., Counseling Psychology, 1973), San Francisco State University (MS, Clinical Psychology, 1966), Mills College (BA, Psychology, 1964), Prostitution Research and Education 1996–present, Kaiser Foundation Research Institute (Oakland, CA), 1993–2000, ‘“Bad for the Body, Bad for the Heart”: Prostitution Harms Women Even if Legalized or Decriminalized’, Violence Against Women, Vol. 10 No. 10, October 2004, www.prostitutionresearch.com/FarleyVAW.pdf//candle) Can the physical, social, and psychological harms of prostitution be controlled or decreased by decriminalization, regulation, or other state monitoring? Is there any way to make prostitution safer? Is it possible to protect the human rights of those in prostitution? Does legalization or decriminalization decrease the dangers of prostitution?¶ In May 2003, prostitution was decriminalized in New Zealand (NZ) by a one-vote majority of its Parliament. Throughout this article, examples from NZ will be used to analyze arguments that decriminalizing prostitution would make prostitution safer for the women in it. Four of the five reasons proposed for the decriminalization of prostitution in NZ had to do with public health. In the law’s language, these were to safeguard the human rights of sex workers, to protect sex workers from exploitation, to promote the welfare and occupational safety and health of sex workers, and to create an environment that is conducive to public health. It was also alleged that the law would protect children from the exploitation of prostitution (New Zealand Justice and Electoral Committee, 2001).2¶ Underpinning laws that legalize or decriminalize prostitution is the belief that prostitution is inevitable. This notion is advanced from different quarters: from pimps and johns,3 governments, public health officials, and from sexologists and evolutionary psychologists. Pimps have, for example, promoted legalized prostitution with the following arguments:¶ Why make a married man who is looking for nothing more than an alternative to masturbation, get busted in a sting, have his name and picture be published in his local paper and have to explain everything to his wife? Isn’t that destructive to society? Why have a legion of free-lance STD-spreaders when you could control and regulate sex-field workers’ health? Why consume law- enforcement time and resources to the tune of hundreds-of- thousands of dollars per year instead of collecting at least an equal amount in real estate and income tax withholding? It only makes sense. (Patrick, 2000, p. 12)¶ Public statements by pimps emphasize that prostitution is here to stay, with Dennis Hof in Las Vegas, repeating the mantra that “boys will be boys.”4 A Canadian attorney defended legal prostitution stating that prostitution “is a bottomless market” (Young, 2003). These stereotypes about men not only normalize and trivialize prostitution but are also good Nevada, and Heidi Fleiss in Sydney, Australia, business strategy, relieving johns of any doubts regarding the social acceptability of their sexual predation while at the same time inviting them to spend their money. ¶ Prostitution has been proposed as development policy for newly industrializing and developing countries. Often, those promoting prostitution are sex industry businessmen and government officials. Sex businesses such as escort prostitution, mas- sage brothels, strip clubs, phone sex businesses, and Internet prostitution have been described by Lim (1998) as the sex sector of a state’s economy. In some countries, profits from the sex sector are included in estimates of its economic activity. For example, in¶ the Netherlands, the sex industry constitutes 5% of the GDP (Daley, 2001). Women in Dutch prostitution tell us that although legalization of prostitution was promoted as a way to improve their lives, they view it primarily as a way for the State to tax their earnings (Schippers, 2002). Often they do not think that their health has benefited or that they are offered more protection under legalized or decriminalized prostitution.¶ Some social scientists define the predatory behaviors of men buying women in prostitution as normal, maintaining that prostitution is simply part of human nature (Ahmad, 2001; Fisher, 1992; Masters & Johnson, 1973; Pheterson, 1996; Scambler & Scambler, 1995). This definition of normalcy is then reflected in public policy that defines prostitution as a form of labor (sex work), where prostitution is considered an unpleasant job but not different from other kinds of unpleasant jobs, such as factory work. From this perspective, prostituted women are viewed as simply another category of workers with special problems and needs (Bullough & Bullough, 1996; Kinnell, 2001; Nairne, 2000). The World Health Organization (WHO) defined prostitution as a dynamic and adaptive process that involves a transaction between seller and buyer of a sexual service (World Health Organization, 1988). WHO has since recommended decriminalization of prostitution (Ahmad, 2001). Much of the health sciences literature has viewed prostitution as a job choice (Deren et al., 1996; Farr, Castro, DiSantostefano, Claassen, & Olguin, 1996; Green et al., 1993; Romans, Potter, Martin, & Herbison, 2001; UN/AIDS, 2002). Yet the notion that prostitution is work tends to make its harm invisible. ¶ Where did the idea that prostitution is work originate? In 1973, the U.S. organization COYOTE (Call Off Your Old Tired Ethics) declared that prostitution was legitimate service work. In the 1980s, COYOTE capitalized on the AIDS epidemic as a health cri- sis, keeping its organizational focus on increasing its customer base but shifting its strategy to educational outreach in addition to advocacy of decriminalization of prostitution (Jenness, 1993). These goals are reflected in the activities of the New Zealand Prostitutes’ Collective (NZPC), one of many COYOTE offshoots that provide union-style organizing for those in prostitution. When prostitution is understood as violence, however, unionizing prostituted women makes as little sense as unionizing battered women. A2 Stigma They don’t solve stigma CAASE ‘07 (Chicago Alliance Against Sexual Exploitation “ADDRESSING MISCONCEPTIONS: Legalization” After July 2007 http://media.virbcdn.com/files/e1/FileItem-150147-AM_Legalization.pdf, TSW) Misconception: Women involved in the sex trade would prefer to work in the regulated environment that legalization would provide. REALITY: Arguments stating that individuals involved in the sex trade would prefer to work in a regulated environment are negated by the fact that very few of the women in legalized prostitution actually register. For instance, membership in the official service union in Germany, which requires employer health care, legal aid, three paid holidays a year, and a five-day workweek, remains very low – less than five percent of the 400,000 individuals eligible for the union actually register. 7 The reason behind this hesitance to register shows that, though the stigma of buying sex is erased when prostitution is legalized, the stigma of selling it is not . Evidence shows that women are not eager to self identify and tend to avoid official registrations, even when registering comes with substantial benefits . One researcher found that women involved in prostitution in the Netherlands were concerned about the loss of anonymity that registration would require; once officially registered as prostitutes, Dutch women feared that this designation would pursue them for the rest of their lives. Despite any “employment” benefits that registration would provide, the women stated that they wanted to leave prostitution as quickly as possible with no legal record of having been in prostitution. 8 Another study in the Netherlands found that only three percent of individuals involved in prostitution believed that legalization was a good thing . 9 Health 2NC Health 2NC No matter legal status, prostitution always harms women—high levels of rape, assault, and STD’s remain even in places where legalization has taken place Farley 4 (Melissa, University of Iowa (Ph.D., Counseling Psychology, 1973), San Francisco State University (MS, Clinical Psychology, 1966), Mills College (BA, Psychology, 1964), Prostitution Research and Education 1996–present, Kaiser Foundation Research Institute (Oakland, CA), 1993–2000, ‘“Bad for the Body, Bad for the Heart”: Prostitution Harms Women Even if Legalized or Decriminalized’, Violence Against Women, Vol. 10 No. 10, October 2004, www.prostitutionresearch.com/FarleyVAW.pdf//candle) VIOLENCE IS PERVASIVE IN LEGAL AS WELL AS ILLEGAL PROSTITUTION¶ It is a cruel lie to suggest that decriminalization or legalization will protect anyone in prostitution. There is much evidence that whatever its legal status, prostitution causes great harm to women. The following sections summarize some of the many studies that now document the physical and emotional harm caused by prostitution. ¶ In the past two decades, a number of authors have documented or analyzed the sexual and physical violence that is the normative experience for women in prostitution, including Baldwin (1993, 1999); Barry (1979, 1995); Boyer, Chapman, and Marshall (1993); Dworkin (1981, 1997, 2000); Farley, Baral, Kiremire, and Sezgin (1998); Giobbe (1991, 1993); Hoigard and Finstad (1986); Hughes (1999); Hunter (1994); Hynes and Raymond (2002); Jeffreys (1997); Karim, Karim, Soldan, and Zondi (1995); Leidholdt (1993); MacKinnon (1993, 1997, 2001); McKeganey and Barnard (1996); Miller (1995); Silbert and Pines (1982a, 1982b); Silbert, Pines, and Lynch (1982); Valera, Sawyer, and Schiraldi (2001); Vanwesenbeeck (1994); and Weisberg (1985). ¶ Sexual violence and physical assault are the norm for women in all types of prostitution. Nemoto, Operario, Takenaka, Iwamoto, and Le (2003) reported that 62% of Asian women in San Francisco massage parlors had been physically assaulted by customers. These data were from only 50% of the massage parlors in San Francisco. The other 50%—those brothels controlled by pimps/ traffickers who refused entrance to the researchers—were probably even more violent toward the women inside. Raymond, D’Cunha, et al. (2002) found that 80% of women who had been trafficked or prostituted suffered violence-related injuries in pros- titution. Among the women interviewed by Parriott (1994), 85% had been raped in prostitution. In another study, 94% of those in street prostitution had experienced sexual assault and 75% had been raped by one or more johns (Miller, 1995). In the Netherlands, where prostitution is legal, 60% of prostituted women suffered physical assaults; 70% experienced verbal threats of physical assault; 40% experienced sexual violence; and 40% had been forced into prostitution or sexual abuse by acquaintances (Vanwesenbeeck, 1994). Most young women in prostitution were abused or beaten by johns as well as pimps. Silbert and Pines (1981, 1982b) reported that 70% of women suffered rape in prosti- tution, with 65% having been physically assaulted by customers and 66% assaulted by pimps.¶ Of 854 people in prostitution in nine countries (Canada, 71% experienced physical assaults in prostitution, and 62% reported rapes in prostitution (Farley, Cot- ton, et al., 2003). Eighty-nine percent told the researchers that they wanted to leave prostitution but did not have other options for economic survival. To normalize prostitution as a reasonable job choice for poor women makes Colombia, Germany, Mexico, South Africa, Thailand, Turkey, United States, and Zambia), invisible their strong desire to escape prostitution. ¶ Vanwesenbeeck (1994) found that two factors were associated with greater violence in prostitution. The greater the poverty, the greater the violence; and the longer one is in prostitution, the more likely one is to experience violence. Similarly, the more time women spent in prostitution, the more STDs they reported (Parriott, 1994).¶ Those promoting prostitution rarely address class, race, and ethnicity as factors that make women even more vulnerable to health risks in prostitution. Farley (2003a) found that in NZ, as¶ elsewhere, indigenous women are placed at the bottom of a brutal race and class hierarchy within prostitution itself. When the researchers compared Maori/Pacific Islander New Zealanders to European-origin New Zealanders in prostitution, the Pacific Islander/Maori were more likely to have been homeless and to have entered prostitution at a young age. Mama Tere, an Auckland community activist, referred to NZ prostitution as an “apartheid system” (Farley, 2003a). Plumridge and Abel (2001) similarly described the NZ sex industry as “segmented,” noting that 7% of the population in Christchurch were Maori; however, 19% of those in Christchurch prostitution were Maori. ¶ Women in prostitution are treated as if their rapes do not matter. For example, in Venezuela, El Salvador, and Paraguay, the penalty for rape is reduced by one fifth if the victim is a prostitute (Wijers & Lap-Chew, 1997). Many people assume that when a prostituted woman is raped, that rape is part of her job and that she deserved or even asked for the rape. In an example of this bias, a California judge overturned a jury’s decision to charge a customer with rape, saying “a woman who goes out on the street and makes a whore out of herself opens herself up to anybody” (Arax, 1986, p. 1).¶ We asked women currently in prostitution in Colombia, Germany, Mexico, South Africa, and Zambia whether they thought that legal prostitution would offer them safety from physical and sexual assault. Forty-six percent of these women in prostitution from six countries felt that they were no safer from physical and sexual assault even if prostitution were legal . Brothel prostitution is legal in Germany, one of the countries surveyed. In an indict- ment of legal prostitution, 59% of German respondents told us that they did not think that legal prostitution made them any safer from rape and physical assault (Farley et al., 2003). A comparable 50% of 100 prostitutes in a Washington, D.C., survey expressed the same opinion (Valera et al., 2001).¶ It is not possible to protect the health of someone whose “job” means that they will get raped on average once a week (Hunter, 1993). One woman explained that prostitution is “like domestic violence taken to the extreme” (Leone, 2001). Another woman said, “What is rape for others, is normal for us” (Farley, Lynne, & Cotton, in press). AIDS 2NC Extend 1NC 2 - Threat is decreasing—it will be controlled within 20 eyars—deaths are falling across the board—that’s Kelland—prefer her, she cites a UN report