Studying Evolution Adaptation – a trait or suite of traits that increases the fitness of its possessor. The adaptive significance of some traits are not obvious. This lecture and chapter will: • Points out the pitfalls of studying putative adaptations • Cover 5 methods for inferring that a trait is adaptive for a particular function. Studying Evolution The use of the words adaptive, and adaptation is a short cut for explaining a much larger evolutionary journey. However, the shortcut implies that an organism is somehow perfectly matched to it environment. That somehow, the phenotypic traits that we observe are in some way responsible for the success of the species. • Cacti are adapted to hot, dry climates. • Birds are adapted to live in trees.. • Frogs are adapted to live in water. Studying Evolution The phrase ‘X is adapted to live in Y’ may not mean more than: X lives in environment Y. That properties of X constrain it to live only in Y. For an evolutionary biologist – ‘X is adapted to live in Y’ means that environment Y has provided forces of natural selection that have affected the life of X’s ancestors, and have molded and specialized the evolution of X. For an ecologist – ‘X is adapted to live in Y’ means that individuals of X have themselves had some prior experience (e.g. been cold-hardened) that makes life in Y (e.g. an extremely cold winter) possible. Canalization – is a measure of the ability of a population to produce the same phenotype regardless of variability of its environment or genotype (Wikipedia). (robustness) Studying Evolution Alternatively, the statement ‘X is adapted to live in Y’ can mean that a property (an adaptation) has been identified that X possesses and that has been shown to (or at a reasonable guess might) explain why X can live in Y. (e.g. Melanic peppered moths can live in polluted environments because they can avoid predation). Such a property could be either genotypic or phenotypic. Studying Evolution Gould and Lewontin – adaptationist programme – faith in the power of natural selection as an optimizing agent to explain the adaptive value of a phenotypic trait. • This lecture and chapter is about making a connection between a phenotypic trait and it’s adaptive value. • It is not about demonstrating natural selection, but whether a particular trait we observe confers the fitness that we would predict. • This adaptationist programme by itself, (supposedly) takes care and rigor in determining the relationship between form and function. Studying Evolution The adaptationist programme is frequently overexploited. It assumes that all traits have been selected for some fitness value. • It assumes that biological processes appear to have goals Birds fly south to avoid winter Birds have wings so they can fly • The adaptationist programme is often teleological. (Gk. Teleos – “end”) – Using design or purpose to explain a phenomena (particularly natural). The adaptationist programme does a poor job of determining whether the presence of a trait is really the product of selective forces that do not work towards some end. Studying Evolution- the seductiveness of ‘Just So’ stories. It is fairly easy to contrive an evolutionary story to explain a particular trait of an organism. • The greater difficulty is to ascertain whether that the trait as any adaptive value. • And whether our hypothesis of the nature of that adaptive value is supported. Studying Evolution- the seductiveness of ‘Just So’ stories. Oxpeckers & their hosts – a mutualism? • Benefits to the oxpeckers: Easy meal of ticks Safe place to eat ticks Clean open wounds • Benefits to the host: Removal of parasites Careful observation reveals that: • Oxpeckers rarely fed on ticks, instead Licked blood from open wounds Probed host’s ears for wax Gleaned dead skin from host’s hair • Hosts attempted to shoo oxpeckers away 1-2 times/minute Need to design and conduct and experiment to test the hypothesis. Studying Evolution- the seductiveness of ‘Just So’ stories. 3 month experiment with two treatment groups • Business as usual • Oxpeckers excluded (shooed away) Treatment groups switched Treatment groups randomized. Studying Evolution- the seductiveness of ‘Just So’ stories. 3 month experiment with two treatment groups • Business as usual • Oxpeckers excluded (shooed away) Treatment groups switched Treatment groups randomized. Studying Evolution- the seductiveness of ‘Just So’ stories. 3 month experiment with two treatment groups • Business as usual • Oxpeckers excluded (shooed away) Treatment groups switched Treatment groups randomized. Studying Evolution- the seductiveness of ‘Just So’ stories. Conclusion: oxpeckers are vampires and consumers of earwax Treatment groups switched Treatment groups randomized. Studying Evolution- Other considerations 1) Differences among populations or species are not always adaptive. Yellow billed oxpecker Red billed oxpecker • That is, mutations may arise in separate populations, and become fixed by genetic drift. • The trait may be selectively neutral. Studying Evolution- Other considerations 2) Not every trait is an adaptation. Some traits may be used for functions there were not originally selected for. • While feeding on an animal, an oxpecker may find a mate. • This does not mean that feeding on large animals evolved because it creates mating opportunities. Studying Evolution- Other considerations 3) Not every adaptation is perfect. • Feeding on large mammals provides high-quality meals. • Large mammals migrate long distances, exposing oxpeckers to potentially unpredictable food supply. Studying EvolutionRecognizing the many factors other than adaptation that may account for an organism’s features, Williams (1966) wrote that although “adaptation is often recognized in purely fortuitous effects, and natural selection is invoked to resolve problems that do not exist,” we should consider adaptation “an onerous concept that should be used only where it is really necessary.” That is, we all too often consider features to be adaptations (from selection), but we should not assume this unless we have convincing evidence to support this. Studying Evolution5 approaches for studying whether a trait is an adaptation for a particular function. 1) 2) 3) 4) 5) Complexity* Design* Experiments Observational methods Comparative method * Products of inference, and do not demonstrate any advantage of a trait. Studying Evolution- Complexity Even if we cannot immediately guess the function of a trait, we often suspect it has an adaptive function it if is complex, for complexity cannot evolve except by natural selection. A peculiar, highly vascularized structure called a pectin projects in front of the retina in the eyes of birds. Function is uncertain. Generally assumed to play some important functional role because of: • it’s complexity, • it is ubiquitous among bird species (conserved). Studying Evolution- Complexity The histological complexity of the lateral line system of fishes, and its uniformity within many clades, implied to physiologists that it had an adaptive function, which after extensive study, proved to be sensation of differences in water pressure. Assumptions were correct! Studying Evolution- Design The function of a morphological structure is often inferred from its correspondence with the design an engineer might use to accomplish some goal, such as locomotion, or the dissipation or retention of heat. • Artemisia carruthii, a sage that grows in the hot regions of the American Southwest has finely dissected leaves. • Artemisia ludoviciana is more widely distributed in America and Eurasia, has broad, less dissected leaves The trait could also be present due to selection in an ancestor. Studying Evolution- Design Indeed, many structures are analogous in design to human implements. Villi in the small intestine Terry cloth Studying Evolution- Design Mathematical models, based on principles of engineering, explain why, if fleetness is advantageous, horses should have evolved the one-toed condition. A single bone has greater resistance to bending stresses than several bones of the same cross-sectional area and weight – it can bear more weight when running at greater speeds. Studying Evolution- Experiments Experiments are among the most powerful tools in science. Contingent on: • Phrasing the question/hypothesis as specifically as possible. • Listing and testing as many competing hypotheses as possible. (Testing multiple hypotheses divides the affection for an single hypothesis.) Studying Evolution- Experiments What a predator sees Do the wing markings and wing waving of Zonosemata flies mimic the threat displays used by jumping spiders on each other? Studying Evolution- Experiments Erik Greene’s experimental design Studying Evolution- Experiments Erik Greene’s results Studying Evolution- Observational Methods Not all hypothesis can be tested under controlled conditions, nor can all organisms be manipulated like flies. However, some observations do not necessarily lead to cause and effect. That we always find iguana’s with body temperatures that are always near their physiological optimum does not prove that iguana’s are behaviorally selected to actively maintain their body temperature by thermoregulating. It could be that they are just always found in environments in which the temperature is within their thermal optimum. Studying Evolution- Observational Methods A successful observational experiment may require some manipulation so that it can be demonstrated that iguanas make the appropriate choice when provided with a range of temperatures that they may actively choose. • It then remains to demonstrate that such choices are adaptive – that they increase fitness. Studying Evolution- Comparative Method The comparative method tests for patterns across species. • Comparative methods take advantage of natural evolutionary experiments provided by convergent evolution. • If a trait evolves independently in many lineages because of a similar selection pressure, then it suggests that the trait has some adaptive value. • Rigorous methods can produce results consistent with hypothesis. Grey-headed flying fox Relative testes size (adjusted for body size) as a function of roost group size for 17 species of fruit bats and flying foxes. Studying Evolution- Comparative Method A simple correlative analysis provides weak evidence for the relationship between testes size and size of roost group. Theoretical population of six species. Scatterplot based on independent data points. Not strong evidence. Each species could have inherited testes size from a common ancestor – selection not a factor. Testes size not an independent factor. Studying Evolution- Comparative Method Phylogenetically independent contrasts – a more robust approach Studying Evolution- Other pitfalls Pleiotropic effects – when a gene influences more than one trait. Albinism -Individuals lack pigment in skin and hair. Crossed eyes occur at a greater frequency than pigmented individuals. The gene for albinism can cause defects in the nerve connection between the eyes and the brain. Albinism and crossed eyes are not always linked. Phenylketonurea (PKU) - Defect in the liver enzyme phenylalanine hydroxylase leads to excess plasma levels of phenylalanine. This in turn affects myelination of axons in the brain, and ultimately to mental retardation. Decreased pigmentation eczema Marfan’s syndrome – defect in the production of fibrillin-1, resulting in problems with connective tissue throughout the body. Includes long arms, legs, fingers. Tall, thin body. Aortic enlargement Eye problems (nearsightedness, early glaucoma, early cataracts, dislocated lens) Mouse lethal yellow (Ay) – increased activity of the agouti coat color gene. Adult onset obesity Increased somatic growth Increased susceptibility to tumor growth Premature infertility Studying Evolution- Phenotypic plasticity Phenotypic plasticity – variation in the phenotype due to environmental influences. (Chapter 5). Plasticity itself is a trait that can evolve. Studying Evolution- Phenotypic plasticity Phenotypic plasticity – variation in the phenotype due to environmental influences. (Chapter 5). Reaction norms – graphical representation of a genotype’s change in phenotype across a range of environments. Phototactic behavior of Daphnia from different environments (densities of fish predators) Studying Evolution- Phenotypic plasticity On your own 10.6 -Trade-offs and constraints 10.7 - Selection Operates at Different Levels The Spandrels of San Marco The Spandrels of San Marco Panselectionism – natural selection of individuals is the only cause of evolution. The Spandrels have become a euphemism for the excessive use of Natural Selection and adaptation to explain the purpose of all traits. The Spandrels of San Marco Fan-vaulted ceiling at King’s College chapel. • The nature of the architecture dictates the creation of the spaces. • The functionality of the space does not dictate the architecture. The Spandrels of San Marco Dr. Pangloss from Voltaire’s Candide “Things cannot be other than they are…. Everything is made for the best purpose. Our noses were made to carry spectacles, so we have spectacles. Legs were clearly intended for breeches, and we wear them.” The Spandrels of San Marco The Panglossian paradigm emphasizes the near omnipotence of Natural Selection to select the best design (with few constraints) to the exclusion of other possibilities. Some constraints are acknowledged – Phyletic inertia - that humans are not optimally designed for upright posture because so much of our Bauplan evolved for quadrapedal life. But other constraints are considered unimportant or entirely dismissed. The Spandrels of San Marco Studies using the adaptationist programme proceed using the following two steps: 1) An organism is atomized into ‘traits’, which are then explained as being optimally designed for their function by Natural Selection. 2) If part-by-part optimization fails, then an interaction is acknowledged. The optimizing of one feature cannot be done at the expense of another. The notion of trade-offs is introduced, and the optimality of one part is acknowledged to be limited by constraints of another part. • The sub-optimality of a part is explained as its contribution to the best possible design for the whole. The sub-optimality of a part is attributed to the force of Natural Selection and nothing else. The Spandrels of San Marco The narrowness of their adaptationist interpretation of how traits arose results in the following progressive set of explanations for a given trait. (p 586) If one adaptive argument fails, try another. • Zig-zag commissures of clams, once considered as strengthening devices, now become sieves. • Either explanation may be correct. • But, the failure of one explanation should not be the basis for creating a new explanation. Each trait may not be for a specific purpose. The Spandrels of San Marco If one adaptive argument fails, assume another exists, albeit weaker. • In the absence of a good adaptive argument, point out the lack of understanding of the organism and its interactions with its environment. • Emphasize immediate utility, and exclude other attributes of form. • e.g. males of T. rex may have used their small fore limbs to titillate female partners, but G & L argue, they didn’t arose de novo for that end. They are more likely the reduction of a homologous structure in ancestors. The Spandrels of San Marco The problem is, the adaptationist programme often amounts to nothing more than story telling, and does not have a structure in place that would permit the rejection of the story in the face of evidence. As G. & L. point out, “Since the range of adaptive stories is as wide as our minds are fertile, new stories can always be postulated.” • Moreover, confirmation of the ‘story’ is loosely based on evidence that would be consistent with natural selection as the mechanism. • But natural selection is quite frequently not observed. • Excellent example with mountain bluebird aggression (p 588). The Spandrels of San Marco The alternatives? (p 590) • The null hypothesis: No adaptation and no selection at all. Are the presence of polymorphisms the result of selection or mutation and genetic drift? • No adaptation and no selection on the trait in question, but a change in the trait is a consequence for selection occurring on another trait elsewhere, hence the correlation between selection and the trait in question. – this is called? The Spandrels of San Marco Decoupling selection and adaptation. (p592) • Selection without adaptation – selection may occur to favor individuals with high fecundity, but it will not have adaptive value for the population – not enough food, or the high population numbers attract predators. – but high fecundity will almost always be selected for. The Spandrels of San Marco Decoupling selection and adaptation. (p592) • Adaptation without selection - may reflect phenotypic plasticity to the environment, and hence may not be selected for (since it is variable). • Adaptation and selection occur, but there is no selective basis for differences among adaptations. Related species may develop different solutions to the same problem in different areas. One solution is not necessarily better than another – ergo, there is not a perfect solution. (p 593) • Adaptation and selection occur, but the adaptation is a secondary utilization. E.g. the spandrels of san Marco. (p 593) The Spandrels of San Marco Summarizing • The adaptationist programme breaks organisms down into parts and genes. • If selection acts only on the parts, then that diminishes the value of the integrated whole. That is, the integration of traits to produce an organism is less than or only equal to the sum of its parts. • G. & L. argue for a more holistic perspective. Figure 10-22