Computational Theories of Consciousness Computational Theories of Consciousness: Bibliography for CSE 719, Fall 2009 Last Update: 10 November 2013 Note: or material is highlighted Notes: 1. 2. 3. I. Many of the readings are only available via UB computers. However, some of those are available on the Web in locations other than the given links. o See Chalmers's bibliography or do a Google search on the author's last name + first few words of article title in quotes (e.g.: chalmers "facing up"). A username and password may be required for some online readings. Please contact Bill Rapaport. Philosophical, Psychological, & CognitiveNeuroscientific Theories A. Historical Readings 1. 2. 3. Descartes readings Leibniz a. "17. Moreover, it must be confessed that perception and that which depends upon it are inexplicable on mechanical grounds, that is to say, by means of figures and motions. And supposing there were a machine, so constructed as to think, feel, and have perception, it might be conceived as increased in size, while keeping the same proportions, so that one might go into it as into a mill. That being so, we should, on examining its interior, find only parts which work one upon another, and never anything by which to explain a perception. Thus it is in a simple substance, and not in a compound or in a machine, that perception must be sought for. Further, nothing but this (namely, perceptions and their changes) can be found in a simple substance. It is also in this alone that all the internal activities of simple substances can consist." —From The Monadology (trans. Robert Latta) b. Kulstad, Mark; & Carlin, Laurence (2008), "Leibniz's Philosophy of Mind", in Edward N. Zalta (ed.), Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Tolman, Edward Chace (1927), "A Behaviorist's Definition of Consciousness", Psychological Review 34(6) (November): 433–439. "Whenever an organism at a given moment of stimulation shifts from being ready to respond in some relatively less differentiated way to being ready to respond in some relatively more differentiated way, there is consciousness." B. Literary Background Readings 1. C. General & Introductory Background Readings 1. 2. 3. 4. 5. 6. D. Lem, Stanislaw (1967), "The Seventh Sally, or How Trurl's Own Perfection Led to No Good", from "The Seven Sallies of Trurl and Klapaucius", The Cyberiad: Fables for the Cybernetic Age, trans. by Michael Kandel (New York: Seabury): 161–171. Baars, Bernard J. (1988), A Cognitive Theory of Consciousness (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press); Preface & Ch. 1: What Is to Be Explained? Some Preliminaries. Blackmore, Susan (2005), Consciousness: A Very Short Introduction (New York: Oxford University Press) See also: Blackmore, Susan (2004), Consciousness: An Introduction (New York: Oxford University Press) Flanagan, Owen; & Güzeldere, Güven (1997), "Consciousness: A Philosophical Tour", in in Masao Ito, Yasushi Miyashita, & Edmund T. Rolls (eds.), Cognition, Computation, and Consciousness (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1997): 3–16. O'Shea, Michael (2005), The Brain: A Very Short Introduction (New York: Oxford University Press) Ch. 3: "Signalling in the Brain: Getting Connected", pp. 28-41. Searle, John R. (1997), The Mystery of Consciousness (New York: New York Review of Books) Most of this book is online; links to relevant sections are listed below. For Searle's own view, see: Searle, John R. (1995), "The Mystery of Consciousness: Part I", New York Review of Books 42(17) (November 2), §1. For Searle's critique of Damasio's theory of consciousness, see: Searle, John (2011), "The Mystery of Consciousness Continues", New York Review of Books 58(10) (9 June): 50–52. Van Gulick, Robert (2009), "Consciousness", in Edward N. Zalta (ed.), Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2009 Edition) Major Theories (in alphabetical order) 1. Baars's Global-Workspace Theory: . Baars, Bernard J. (1988), A Cognitive Theory of Consciousness (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press); Ch. 2: "The Basic Model: Conscious Representations Are ‘Internally Consistent’ and ‘Globally Distributed’" See also: i. ii. Baars, Bernard J. (1997), "In the Theatre of Consciousness: Global Workspace Theory, A Rigorous Scientific Theory of Consciousness", Journal of Consciousness Studies 4(4): 292–309. Baars, Bernard J.; & McGovern, Katherine (1997), "Global Workspace: A Theory of Consciousness". iii. a. b. Baars, Bernard J. (2003), "The Global Brainweb: An Update on Global Workspace Theory", Science and Consciousness Review (October). Dehaene, Stanislas; & Naccache, Lionel (2001), "Towards a Cognitive Neuroscience of Consciousness: Basic Evidence and a Workspace Framework", Cognition 79: 1–37. Reprint Background reading: . McCarthy, John (1959), "Discussion on the Paper by Dr. O.G. Selfridge", immediately following Selfridge, Dr. O.G., "Pandemonium: A Paradigm for Learning", in National Physical Laboratory, Mechanisation of Thought Processes (London: Her Majesty's Stationery Office): 511–531; see p.527 This is so good, I can't help but quote it here (Dennett 2005 also cites it): "I would like to speak briefly about some of the advantages of the pandemonium model as an actual model of conscious behaviour. In observing a brain, one should make a distinction between that aspect of the behaviour which is available consciously, and those behaviours, no doubt equally important, but which proceed unconsciously. If one conceives of the brain as a pandemonium—a collection of demons—perhaps what is going on within the demons can be regarded as the unconscious part of thought, and what the demons are publicly shouting for each other to hear, as the conscious part of thought." i. ii. Fodor, Jerry A. (1983), The Modularity of Mind (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press). Fodor, Jerry A. (1985), "Précis of The Modularity of Mind", Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8(1) (March): 1– 42. For more on modularity, see Modularity of Mind 2. Block, Ned (1995), "On a Confusion about a Function of Consciousness", Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18(2): 227–287. Block's Fig. 1 Block's Fig. 2 Block's Fig. 3 3. Chalmers's Theory: . Chalmers, David J. (1995), "The Puzzle of Conscious Experience", Scientific American (December): 62–68. Above PDF version is a 2002 "update" from the original. HTML version of original Both versions include commentary by Crick & Koch. a. b. c. 4. Chalmers, David J. (1996), The Conscious Mind: In Search of a Fundamental Theory (New York: Oxford University Press). For an interesting take on both Chalmers and Block, see: Clark, Andy (2000), "A Case Where Access Implies Qualia?", Analysis 60(1) (January): 30–38. Chalmers, David J. (1997), "Facing Up to the Problem of Consciousness", in Jonathan Shear (ed.), Explaining Consciousness—The ‘Hard Problem’ (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press). Shear's book containing this précis of Chalmers 1996 is an anthology of commentaries on Chalmers's book. Searle, John R. (1997), "Consciousness and the Philosophers", New York Review of Books 44(4) (March 6). At the end, there is a link to a reply by Chalmers; if it is not accessible, try this: Chalmers, David J.; & Searle, John R. (1997), "‘Consciousness and the Philosophers’: An Exchange", New York Review of Books 44(8) (May 15). Crick & Koch's Theory: Crick's "Astonishing Hypothesis": "...‘You’, your joys and your sorrows, your memories and your ambitions, your sense of personal identity and free will, are i fact no more than the behavior of a vast assembly of nerve cells and their associated molecules." a. b. c. d. e. Crick, Francis (1994), The Astonishing Hypothesis: The Scientific Search for the Soul (New York: Simon & Schuster): 3. Crick, Francis; & Koch, Christof (1990), "Towards a Neurobiological Theory of Consciousness", Seminars in the Neurosciences 2: 263–275. For a critique, see: Searle, John R. (1995), "The Mystery of Consciousness: Part I", New York Review of Books 42(17) (November 2). See §2. Crick, Francis; & Koch, Christof (1998), "Consciousness and Neuroscience", Cerebral Cortex 8(2): 97–107. Koch, Christof; & Crick, Francis (2001), "The Zombie Within", Nature 411 (June 21): 893. Crick, Francis; & Koch, Christof (2003), "A Framework for Consciousness", Nature Neuroscience 6(2) (February): 119–126. Koch, Christof (2005), The Quest for Consciousness (Roberts & Co.). For a critique of Koch's latest theory, see: Searle, John R. (2005), "Consciousness: What We Still Don't Know", New York Review of Books 52(1) (January 13). Stevan Harnad replied to Searle; if you can't access their debate from the above link, try this one: Harnad, Stevan; & Searle, John R. (2005), "What Is Consciousness?", New York Review of Books 52(11) (June 23). f. g. 5. Koch, Christof; & Bhattacharjee, Yudhijit (ed.) (2012), "A Vision of How Mouse Vision Can Reveal Consciousness' Secrets: Newsmaker Interview", Science 335(6075) (23 March): 1426– 1427. Koch's answer to the interviewer's first question suggests that he really does understand the importance of "the hard question" Koch, Christof (2012), Consciousness: Confessions of a Romantic Reductionist (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press) Merges his views with those of Tononi. Dehaene, Stanislas (2012), "The Eternal Silence of Neuronal Spaces" (review of Koch 2012), Science 336(6088) (22 June): 1507–1508. Searle, John R. (2013), "Can Information Theory Explain Consciousness?" (review of Koch 2012), New York Review of Books 60(1) (10 January): 54–55, 58. See follow-up letters to the editor: Koch, Christof; & Tonini, Giulio; reply by John R. Searle (2013), "Can a Photodiode Be Conscious?", New York Review of Books 60(4), (7 March): 43–44. Dennett's Theory: . Dennett, Daniel C. (1978), "Two Approaches to Mental Images", in Brainstorms (Montgomery, VT: Bradford): 174–189. on "heterophenomenology" a. Dennett, Daniel C. (1982), "How to Study Human Consciousness Empirically or Nothing Comes to Mind", Synthese 53(2) (November): 159–180. More on "heterophenomenology". This issue of Synthese is a special issue on "Matters of the Mind", and contains a critique of Dennett by Richard Rorty and an article by Douglas Hofstadter, critiqued by Guy Steele. b. Dennett, Daniel C. (1991), Consciousness Explained (Boston: Little, Brown). c. Dennett, Daniel C.; & Kinsbourne, Marcel (1992), "Time and the Observer: The Where and When of Consciousness in the Brain", Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15: 183–247. Note: The published version, unlike the online version, contains numerous commentaries and Dennett's replies. For a recent reply, see: Todd, Steven J. (2009), "A Difference that Makes a Difference: Passing through Dennett's Stalinesque/Orwellian Impasse", British Journal of the Philosophy of Science 60: 497–520. d. Searle, John R. (1995), "The Mystery of Consciousness: Part II", New York Review of Books 42(18) (November 16). See §2. e. Denett, Daniel C. (2001), "Are We Explaining Consciousness Yet?", Cognition 79(1–2) (April): 221–237. A discussion of other papers on consciousness in that issue of Cognition, plus Dennett's new theory of consciousness as "fame in the brai" or "cerebral celebrity". f. Dennett, Daniel C. (2005), Sweet Dreams: Philosophical Obstacles to a Science of Consciousness (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press). g. 6. Cohen, Michael A.; & Dennett, Daniel C. (2011), "Consciousness Cannot Be Separated from Function", Trends in Cognitive Sciences 15(8) (August): 358–364. Edelman, Gerald M. (2003), "Naturalizing Consciousness: A Theoretical Framework", P[roceedings of the ]N[ational ]A[cademy of ]S[ciences] 100(9) (April 29): 5520–5524. Related reading: . a. b. Searle, John R. (1995), "The Mystery of Consciousness: Part II", New York Review of Books 42(18) (November 16). See §1. Reeke, George N., Jr.; & Edelman, Gerald M. (1995), "A Darwinist View of the Prospects for Conscious Artifacts", in Giuseppe Trautteur (ed.), Consciousness: Distinction and Reflection (Naples, Italy: Bibliopolis): 106–130. Tononi, Giulio; & Edelman, Gerald M. (1998), "Consciousness and Complexity", Science 282 (December 4): 1846–1851. See especially: Tononi, Giulio (2008), "Consciousness as Integrated Information: A Provisional Manifesto", Biological Bulletin 215 (December): 216–242. and also: c. d. 7. Koch & Tononi 2008 Koch, Christof (2009), "A Theory of Consciousness", Scientific American Mind 20(4) (July/August): 16–19. Izhikevich, Eugene M.; & Edelman, Gerald M. (2008), "LargeScale Model of Mammalian Thalamocortical Systems", PNAS 105: 3593–3598. Kruglinski, Susan (2009), "What Makes You Uniquely ‘You’?", Discover (February). For a list of all of Edelman's books on consciousness, search amazon.com for "Gerald Edelman", link to Google Books by Gerald Edelman, or link to Edelman's website. Nagel, Thomas (1974), "What Is It Like to Be a Bat?", Philosophical Review 83(4) (October): 435–450. Reprint online here. See also his book: Nagel, Thomas (1989), The View from Nowhere (New York: Oxford University Press). Also see: Nagel, Thomas (2013), "The Core of ‘Mind and Cosmos’", New York Times "Opinionator" (18 August). This is an abstract of his latest, and highly reviled (except by creationists!), book. Related items: c. What is it like…? . i. video of a blind teenager who perceived by echolocation. More: ii. iii. iv. v. vi. vii. viii. ix. x. xi. "Human Echolocation", Wikipedia obituary What is it like to be a rock? Foss, Jeff (1989), "On the Logic of What It Is Like to Be a Conscious Subject", Australasian Journal of Philosophy 67: 205–220. Tye, Michael (1997), "The Problem of Simple Minds: Is There Anything It Is Like to Be a Honey Bee?", Philosophical Studies 88: 289–317. See also Koch 2008-2009, below. Lewis, Peter J. (2000), "What Is It Like to Be Schröinger's Cat?", Analysis 60(1) (January): 22–29. Weisberg, Josh (2008), "What's It Like to Be My Cat?", in Hales, Steven D. (ed.), What Philosophy Can Tell You about Your Cat (Chicago: Open Court): 135–145. Gopnik, Alison (2009), "What Is It Like to Be a Baby? Consciousness and Attention", in Alison Gopnik, The Philosophical Baby: What Children's Minds Tell Us about Truth, Love, and the Meaning of Life, Ch. 4, pp. 106–132. Discussion continued in "Who Am I? Memory, Self, and the Babbling Stream", Ch. 5, pp. 133– 163, see esp. §"Living in the Moment", pp. 152– 154. What is it like to be a dog? Schine, Cathleen (2009), "Grr, Sniff, Arf: A Cognitive Scientist Leads a Tour of the Sensations and Thought Processes of Dogs", New York Times Book Review (September 13): 20–21. What is it like to be yourself? What is it like to be a dolphin? "Dolphin Awareness, or, What is it like to be a dolphin?" White, Thomas (2011), "What Is It Like to Be a Dolphin?", in Philippa Brakes & Mark Peter Simmonds (eds.), Whales and Dolphins: Cognition, Culture, Conservation and Human Perceptions (Earthscan), isbn=9781849712255. Koch, Christof (2008-2009), "What Is It Like to Be a Bee?", Scientific American Mind 19(6) (DecemberJanuary): 18–19. See also: Allen-Hermanson, Sean (2008), "Insects and the Problem of Simple Minds: Are Bees Natural Zombies?", Journal of Philosophy 105(8) (August): 389–415. See also Tye 1997, above. xii. xiii. xiv. xv. xvi. d. Cummins, Robert (2010), "What Is It Like to Be a Computer?", in The World in the Head (Oxford: Oxford University Press), Ch.1, pp.1–10. Birkhead, Tim (2012), Bird Sense: What It's Like to Be a Bird (Walker & Co.) "He acknowledges that in the end science cannot actually say what it's like to be a bird. His subtitle was drawn from the philosopher Thomas Nagel, who wrote an essay about consciousness called ‘What Is It Like to Be a Bat?’ The scientist has no more luck than the philosopher in answering the fundamental question, and for the same reason. We have no way to know the subjective experience of bat or bird, nor neighbor or spouse, no matter how much information we have on how their senses work or on the structure of their brains. The only subjective experience we have is our own. But the attempt to get at what a bird sees, hears, feels and thinks is more than worth the effort because there are so many intriguing facts and stories that the reader learns along the way." — Gorman, James (2012), "The Games Crows Play, and Other Winged Tales", New York Times (12 June): D2. What is it like to be a zombie in philosophy? (humor) What is it like to be an octopus? Godfrey-Smith, Peter (2013), "On Being an Octopus", Boston Review (3 June). The Knowledge Argument (a.k.a. "What is it like to be Mary?") . Jackson, Frank (1982), "Epiphenomenal Qualia", Philosophical Quarterly 32(127) (April): 127–136 i. Jackson, Frank (1986), "What Mary Didn't Know", Journal of Philosophy 83(4) (April): 291–295. ii. Lewis, David (1990), "What Experience Teaches," in William G. Lycan (ed.), Mind and Cognition: A Reader (Oxford: Blackwell): 499–519. Jackson's favorite reply, but see Jackson 2003 below. iii. Conee, Earl (1994), "Phenomenal Knowledge" Australasian Journal of Philosophy 72(2) (June): 136– 150. The reply I currently favor. iv. Lodge, David (2001), Thinks... (Viking). A novel about a professor of cognitive science and a professor of English composition. The latter learns about cognitive sci and has her students write cog-sci-related stories, such as what Mary might do once she sees red. v. Jackson, Frank (2003), "Mind and Illusion", in Anthony O'Hear (ed.), Minds and Persons (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press). In which Jackson recants. vi. Ludlow, Peter; Nagasawa, Yujin; & Stoljar, Daniel (eds.) (2004), There's Something about Mary: Essays on vii. e. Phenomenal Consciousness and Frank Jackson's Knowledge Argument (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press). Chomsky, Noam (2009), "The Mysteries of Nature: How Deeply Hidden?", Journal of Philosophy 106(4) (April): 167–200. (local copy) See pp. 181–183 for Chomsky's (and Bertrand Russell's!) analysis of the knowledge argument. Mysterianism: . McGinn, Colin (1989), "Can We Solve the Mind-Body Problem?", Mind 98(391) (July): 349–366 His answer: No, because we are like Snoopy's ant: 3. f. …or like Lucy's bug: …or like Bliss's dogs: For a discussion of mysterianism in a different context, see: Harnad, Stevan; & Searle, John R. (2005), "What Is Consciousness?", New York Review of Books 52(11) (June 23). Philosophical Zombies: "Q. When referring to a zombie, should I use the relative pronoun who (which would refer to a person) or that (since, technically, the zombie is no longer living)? Essentially, does a zombie cease to become a ‘person’ in the grammatical sense? "A. Let's assume this is a serious question, in which case you, as the writer, get to decide just how much humanity (if any) and grammatical sense you wish to invest in said zombie. That will guide your choice of who or that." i. From February 2013 Questions and Answers, The Chicago Manual of Style Online. Kirk, Robert (1974), "Sentience and Behaviour" Mind 83(329) (January): 43–60. ii. iii. iv. Kirk, Robert; & Squires, J.E.R. (1974), "Zombies v. Materialists", Aristotelian Society Supp. Vol. 48: 135– 163. Harnad, Stevan (1995), "Why and How We Are Not Zombies", Journal of Consciousness Studies 1: 164–167. Kirk, Robert (2005), Zombies and Consciousness (Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press). Ch. 1: Introduction g. h. 8. p. 1 p. 2 p. 3 p. 4 p. 5 p. 6 v. On "blindsmell": 0. Sobel, Noam; Prabhakaran, Vivek; Hartley, Catherine A.; Desmond, John E.; Glover, Gary H.; Sullivan, Edith V.; & Gabrieli, John D.E. (1999), "Blind Smell: Brain Activation Induced by an Undetected Air-Borne Chemical", Brain 122: 209–217. 1. Chen, Denise; & Haviland-Jones, Jeannette (2000), "Human Olfactory Communication of Emotion", Perceptual and Motor Skills 91: 771– 781. Kihlstrom, John F. (1987), "The Cognitive Unconscious", Science 237(4821) (18 September): 1445–1452. A good, general discussion of (un)consciousness. On philosophical zombies and phenomenal-vs."psychological" consciousness: "One thing is now clear: consciousness is not to be identified with any particular perceptualcognitive functions such as discriminative response to stimulation, perception, memory, or the higher mental processes involved in judgment or problem-solving. All of these functions can take place outside of phenomenal awareness. Rather, consciousness is an experiential quality that may accompany any of these functions. The fact of conscious awareness may have particular consequences for psychological function—it seems necessary for voluntary control, for example, as well as for communicating one's mental states to others. But it is not necessary for complex psychological fimctioning." (p. 1450, col. 2.) The following article has nothing whatsoever to do with philosophical zombies, but has a great title and a great illustration :-) Drezner, Daniel W. (2011), "How I Learned to Stop Worrying and Love Zombies", Chronicle [of Higher Education] Review 57(24) (February 18): B13 B14. Rosenthal, David M. (1986), "Two Concepts of Consciousness", Philosophical Studies 49(3) (May): 329–359. §1 is especially good. See also: a. b. c. d. e. E. Rosenthal, David M. (2009), "Higher-Order Theories of Consciousness", in Brian McLaughlin & Ansgar Beckermann (eds.), Oxford Handbook on the Philosophy of Mind (Oxford: Clarendon): 239–252. Rosenthal, David; & Weisberg, Josh (2008), "Higher-Order Theories of Consciousness", Scholarpedia 3(5): 4407. Lau, Hakwan; & Rosenthal, David (2011), "Empirical Support for Higher-Order Theories of Conscious Awareness", Trends in Cognitive Sciences 15(8) (August): 365–373. A debate on HOT: 0. Block, Ned (2011), "The Higher Order Approach to Consciousness Is Defunct", Analysis 71(3) (July): 419–431. 1. Rosenthal, David (2011), "Exaggerated Reports: Reply to Block", Analysis 71(3) (July): 431–437. 2. Weisberg, Josh (2011), "Abusing the Notion of What-It's-Like-Ness: A Response to Block", Analysis 71(3) (July): 438–443. 3. Block, Ned (2011), "Response to Rosenthal and Weisberg", Analysis 71(3) (July): 443–448. Graziano, Michael (2013), "How the Light Gets Out", Aeon (21 August). A neuroscientist's proposal for understanding consciousness that seems related both to Rosenthal's HOT and Dennett's theories, but that mentions neither. Based on a (forthcoming?) book, Consciousness and the Social Brain Also see: Graziano, Michael S.A.; & Kastner, Sabine (2011), "Human Consciousness and Its Relationship to Social Neuroscience: A Novel Hypothesis", Cognitive Neuroscience 2(2) (1 January): 98–113; doi: 10.1080/17588928.2011.565121 Miscellaneous (in chronological order) 1. 2. A critique of Roger Penrose's theory, along with a discussion of Gödel's Proof, is in: Searle, John R. (1995), "The Mystery of Consciousness: Part I", New York Review of Books 42(17) (November 2). See §3. Hesslow, Germund (2002), "Conscious Thought as Simulation of Behaviour and Perception", Trends in Cognitive Sciences 6(6) (June): 242–247. 3. Livingston, Paul M. (2004), Philosophical History and the Problem of Consciousness (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press). Metzinger, Thomas (2005), "Précis: Being No One", Psyche 11(5) (June). Miller, Greg (2005), "What Is the Biological Basis of Consciousness?", Science 309 (1 July): 79. DeWall, C. Nathan; Baumeister, Roy F.; & Masicampo, E.J. (2008), "Evidence that Logical Reasoning Depends on Conscious Processing", Consciousness and Cognition 17(3) (September): 628–645. Pollock, John L. (2008), "What Am I? Virtual Machines and the Mind/Body Problem", Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 76(2) (March): 237–309. Seth, Anil K.; Dienes, Zoltán; Cleeremans, Axel; Overgaard, Morten; & Pessoa, Luiz (2008), "Measuring Consciousness: Relating Behavioural and Neuro-physiological Approaches", Trends in Cognitive Sciences 12(8) (July): 314–321. Chomsky, Noam (2009), "The Mysteries of Nature: How Deeply Hidden?", Journal of Philosophy The Saturday Review", Communications of the ACM 27(11) (November):1114–1119. 4. 5. 6. 7. 8. 9. . General 0. Putnam, Hilary (1964), "Robots: Machines or Artificially Created Life?", Journal of Philosophy 61(21): 668–691. 1. Maudlin, Tim (1989), "Computation and Consciousness", Journal of Philosophy 86(8): 407–432. Argues that consciousness is not computational. 2. Dennett, Daniel C. (1994), "Consciousness in Human and Robot Minds", in Masao Ito, Yasushi Miyashita, & Edmund T. Rolls (eds.), Cognition, Computation, and Consciousness (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1997): 17–29. 3. Steels, Luc (1995), "Is Artificial Consciousness Possible?", in Giuseppe Trautteur (ed.), Consciousness: Distinction and Reflection (Naples, Italy: Bibliopolis): 42–51. 4. Weyhrauch, Richard (1995), "Building Conscious Artifacts", in Giuseppe Trautteur (ed.), Consciousness: Distinction and Reflection (Naples, Italy: Bibliopolis): 18–41. Also online in a slightly different format as "Ideas on Building Conscious Artifacts" Fodor, Jerry A. (1980), "Methodological Solipsism Considered as a Research Strategy in Cognitive Psychology", Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3: 63–73. As reprinted in: Haugeland, John (ed.), (1981), Mind Design: Philosophy, Psychology, Artificial Intelligence (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press): Ch. 11, pp. 307– 338. 5. 6. 7. Perlis, Donald (1997), "Consciousness as Self-Function", Journal of Consciousness Studies 4(5–6) (1997): 509–525. Reprinted in Jonathan Shear & Shaun Gallagher (eds.), Models of the Self (Exeter, UK: Imprint Academic, 2000). §2.2 seems to suggest that possibly there could be nearzombies with only 1 ur-quale 2 other theories make points related to Perlis's focus on the self: a. Kriegel, Uriah (2009), "The SelfRepresentational Theory of Consciousness" b. Hofstadter, Douglas (2007), I Am a Strange Loop (New York: Basic Books). McDermott, Drew V. (2001), Mind and Mechanism (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press). See also: . a. b. c. 8. Akman, Varol (2003), "Reading McDermott", Artificial Intelligence 151(1–2) (December): 227–235. Carruthers, Peter (2003), Review of McDermott 2001, Artificial Intelligence 151(1–2) (December): 237–240 McDermott, Drew (2003), "Reply to Carruthers and Akman", Artificial Intelligence 151(1–2) (December): 241–245. McDermott, Drew (2007), "Artificial Intelligence and Consciousness", in Zelazo, Philip David; Moscovitch, Morris; & Thompson, Evan (eds.), The Cambridge Handbook of Consciousness (New York: Cambridge University Press), Ch.6 (pp. 117–150). The Baars/Franklin Global-Workspace Theory: . Cognitive Computing Research Group How Minds Work: A Cognitive Theory of Everything (IDA tutorial) a. Franklin, Stan (2003), "IDA, a Conscious Artifact?, Journal of Consciousness Studies 10: 47–66. b. Baars, Bernard J.; & Franklin, Stan (2007), "An Architectural Model of Conscious and Unconscious Brain Functions: Global Workspace Theory and IDA", Neural Networks 20: 955–961. From: Taylor, J.G.; Freeman, W.; & Cleeremans, A. (guest eds.) (2007), Special Issue on Brain and Consciousness, Neural Networks 20(9) (November): 929–1060, containing online articles by: Aleksander Rolls Sanz et al. (see below) Sun Taylor et alia c. Baars, Bernard J.; & Franklin, Stan (2009), "Consciousness Is Computational: The LIDA Model of d. Global Workspace Theory", International Journal of Machine Consciousness 1(1) (June): 23–32. A more legible version of Fig. 1 is online as part of their tutorial (see above). Franklin, Stan; D'Mello, Sidney; Baars, Bernard J.; & Ramamurthy, Uma (2009), "Evolutionary Pressures for Perceptual Stability and Self as Guides to Machine Consciousness", International Journal of Machine Consciousness 1(1) (June): 99–110. Franklin et al. occasionally refer to Douglas Hofstader's notion of a "slipnet". Hofstadter & Melanie Mitchell's description of slipnets can be found here (Google books site) or here (PDF) Related reading: A. Surveys 0. 1. 2. 3. 4. B. Shanahan, Murray (2005), "Global Access, Embodiment, and the Conscious Subject", Journal of Consciousness Studies 12(12): 46–66. Sun, Ron (1999), "Computational Models of Consciousness: An Evaluation", Journal of Intelligent Systems 9: 507–562. Morbini, Fabrizio; & Schubert, Lenhart K. (2005), "Conscious Agents", Technical Report 879 (Rochester, NY: University of Rochester Department of Computer Science). Sun, Ron; & Franklin, Stan (2007), "Computational Models of Consciousness: A Taxonomy and Some Examples", in Zelazo, Philip David; Moscovitch, Morris; & Thompson, Evan (eds.), The Cambridge Handbook of Consciousness (New York: Cambridge University Press), Ch.7 (pp. 151–174). Gamez, David (2008), "Progress in Machine Consciousness", Consciousness and Cognition 17(3) (September): 887–910. Clowes, Robert W.; & Seth, Anil K. (2008), "Axioms, Properties and Criteria: Roles for Synthesis in the Science of Consciousness", Artificial Intelligence in Medicine 44(2) (October): 91–104. Anthologies 0. Aleksander, Igor; & Lahnstein, Mercedes (organizers) (2003), "Machine Consciousness: Complexity Aspects" Contains or cites papers or slides by: Aleksander Baars Chrisley Cotterill Franklin Haikonen Holland Kirilyuk Sanz Taylor Torrance Trautteur 1. Holland, Owen (ed.) (2003), Machine Consciousness (Exeter, UK: Imprint Academic). Based on Journal of Consciousness Studies 10(4–5) (May 2003) …which, in turn, was based on 2001 Banbury Workshop on Can a Machine Be Conscious See also: Dietrich, Eric (2001), "Banbury Bound, or Can a Machine Be Conscious?", Journal of Experimental and Theoretical Artificial Intelligence 13(2): 177–180. Table of contents, abstracts, & some full texts at above links. Contains articles by: Aleksander Blackmore Cotterill Franklin (.ppt) Harnad Holland Prinz Sloman & Chrisley Steels Thompson 2. Dautenhahn, Kerstin (ed.) (2005), Proceedings of the Symposium on Next Generation Approaches to Machine Consciousness: Imagination, Development, Intersubjectivity and Embodiment, held at AISB'05, 12–15 April, University of Hertfordshire. Contains papers by: Aleksander Bosse, Jonker, & Treur Calverley Chella, Frixione, & Gaglio Chrisley, Clowes, & Torrance Dautenhahn Gamez Haikonen Ikegami Nomura, Takaishi, & Hashido Shanahan Stuart Ziemke 3. Torrance, Steve; Clowes, Robert; & Chrisley, Ron (guest eds.) (2007), Machine Consciousness: Embodiment and Imagination, Journal of Consciousness Studies 14(7) (July). Table of contents, abstracts, & some full texts at above link. Contains articles by: Aleksander 4. Bringsjord Chrisley Clowes Haikonen Hesslow Holland Ikegami Kiverstein Stuart Torrance Ziemke Chella, Antonio; & Manzotti, Riccardo (eds.) (2007a), Artificial Consciousness (Exeter, UK: Imprint Academic). Contains articles by: Aleksander Cardaci, D'Amico, & Caci Chella Farleigh Faro & Giordano Gaglio Holland Lavazza Manzotti Morasso Parisi Sanz, López, & Bermejo-Alonso Tagliasco Taylor Ziemke For a critical review, see: 5. Aleksander, Igor; Awret, Uziel; Bringsjord, Selmer; Chrisley, Ron; Clowes, Roert; Parthemore, Joel; Stuart, Susan; Torrance, Steve; & Ziemke, Tom (2008), "Assessing Artificial Consciousness: A Collective Review Article", Journal of Consciousness Studies 15(7): 95–110. Chella, Antonio; & Manzotti, Riccardo (eds.) (2007b), AI and Consciousness: Theoretical Foundations and Current Approaches; Papers from the AAAI Fall Symposium, Technical Report FS-07-01 (Menlo Park, CA: AAAI Press). Contains papers (many online) by: Aleksander Boltuc Chella Chrisley Dubois, Poirier, & Nkambou Franklin Haikonen Harnad Hesslow Kuipers Manzotti Marcarelli & McKinsry McCauley Menant Parisi Pirri Rzepka & Araki Samsonovich Sanz, López, & Hernández Shanahan Sloman Stuart Tagliasco Tononi 6. Boltuc, Peter (ed.) (2008), Papers on Robot Consciousness, A[merican ]P[hilosophical ]A[ssociation] Newsletter on Philosophy and Computers 8(2) (Fall). Containing papers by: Baars Chella Franklin Harman Wheeler 7. Buttazzo, Giorgio; & Manzotti, Riccardo (guest eds.) (2008), Special Issue on Artificial Consciousness, Artificial Intelligence in Medicine 44(2) (October): 77–170. Contains online articles by: Buttazzo Chella, Frixione, & Gaglio Clowes & Seth Chrisley Harnad Kuipers Manzotti Tagliasco 8. International Journal of Machine Consciousness Vol. 1, No. 1 (June 2009) contains online articles by: Aleksander Baars Boltuc Chella & Manzotti Chrisley Franklin Hernández, López, & Sanz Hudlicka Samsonovich Seth Taylor C. Tests of Consciousness (Artificial or Otherwise) 0. 1. 2. 3. D. Moor, James H. (1988), "Testing Robots for Qualia", in Herbert R. Otto & James A. Tuedio (eds.), Perspectives on Mind (Dordrecht, Netherlands: D. Reidel): 107–116. Editorial comments on pp. 116–118. Replies (each with editorial comments): . Van Gulick, Robert (1988), "Qualia, Functional Equivalence, and Computation", in Herbert R. Otto & James A. Tuedio (eds.), Perspectives on Mind (Dordrecht, Netherlands: D. Reidel): 119– 126. a. Johnstone, Henry W., Jr. (1988), "Animals, Qualia, and Robots", in Herbert R. Otto & James A. Tuedio (eds.), Perspectives on Mind (Dordrecht, Netherlands: D. Reidel): 127–136. local copy of most of the above Anderson, John R.; & Lebiere, Christian (2003), "The Newell Test for a Theory of Cognition", Behavioral and Brain Sciences 26: 587–637. See also: Anderson, John R. (2007), How Can the Human Mind Occur in the Physical Universe? (New York: Oxford University Press). See especially "The Question of Consciousness", pp. 243–247, where Anderson concludes: "I am willing to declare ACT-R conscious" (p. 247). Floridi, Luciano (2005), "Consciousness, Agents and the Knowledge Game", Minds and Machines 15(3–4) (November): 415–444. . Bringsjord, Selmer (2010), "Meeting Floridi's Challenge to Artificial Intelligence from the Knowledge-Game Test for Self-Consciousness", Metaphilosophy 41(3) (April): 292–312. a. Floridi, Luciano (2010), "The Philosophy of Information: Ten Years Later", Metaphilosophy 41(3) (April): 402– 491; response to Bringsjord on pp. 404–406. Koch, Christof; & Tononi, Giulio (2008), "Can Machines Be Conscious?", IEEE Spectrum (June 2008): 55–59. See also: Tononi & Edelman 1998 Koch, Christof; & Tononi, Giulio (2011), "A Test for Consciousness", Scientific American 304(6) (June): 44– 47. "How will we know when we've built a sentient computer? By making it solve a simple puzzle." Miscellaneous (in chronological order) 0. Marcel, A.J.; & Bisiach, E. (eds.) (1988), Consciousness in Contemporary Science (Oxford: Clarendon) Includes: . a. Shallice, Tim, "Information-Processing Models of Consciousness" Johnson-Laird, Philip N., "A Computational Analysis of Consciousness" 1. 2. 3. Gazzaniga, Michael S. (1999), "The Interpreter Within: The Glue of Conscious Experience", Cerebrum: The Dana Forum on Brain Science 1(1) (Spring):68–78. A theory about the nature of consciousness as an "interpreter" of the brain's modular activities, by one of the pioneers of split-brain research. Buttazzo, Giorgio (2001), "Artificial Consciousness: Utopia or Real Possibility?" IEEE Computer 34(7) (July): 24–30. Haikonen, Pentti O. (2003), The Cognitive Approach to Conscious Machines (Exeter, UK: Imprint Academic). See also: 4. 5. 6. 7. 8. 9. 10. 11. 12. Haikonen, Pentti O. (2007), Robot Brains: Circuits and Systems for Conscious Machines (Wiley-Interscience). Harnad Stevan (2003), "Can a Machine Be Conscious? How?". Adami, Christoph (2006), "What Do Robots Dream Of?", Science 314 (17 November): 1093–1094. Granger, Richard (2006), "Essential Circuits of Cognition: The Brain's Basic Operations, Architecture, and Representations" Granger, Richard (2006), "Engines of the Brain: The Computational Instruction Set of Human Cognition", AI Magazine 27(2) (Summer):15–32. Kiverstein, Julian (2007), "Could a Robot Have a Subjective Point of View?", Journal of Consciousness Studies 14(7): 127–139. Aleksander, Igor (2008), "Machine Consciousness", Scholarpedia 3(2): 4162 Horgan, John (2008), "The Consciousess Conundrum", IEEE Spectrum 45(6) (June):36–41. "The wetware that gives rise to consciousness is far too complex to be replicated in a computer anytime soon." From Special Report: The Singularity Shapiro, Stuart C.; & Bona, Jonathan P. (2009), "The GLAIR Cognitive Architecture", in Alexei Samsonovich (ed.), Biologically Inspired Cognitive Architectures: Papers from the AAAI Fall Symposium, Technical Report FS-09-01 (Menlo Park, CA: AAAI Press). O'Regan, J. Kevin (2011), Why Red Doesn't Sound Like a Bell: Understanding the Feel of Consciousness (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Wonderful title, computationally sympathetic, but ultimately disappointing. Has a terrific chapter (Ch. 8) on the "hard" problem of qualia, which is well worth reading and pinpoints exactly why the problem is hard. But his solution, though offered as a counterpoint to Dennett's view, is ultimately not much better than Dennett's, though offering more detail. One problem is that he analyzes qualia in terms of interaction, but how would he explain mental imagery or memories of qualia, which don't involve interaction? And one of his principal claims… If we take experiencing a raw feel to be an activity of interacting with the world, then by this very definition, there must be something it's like for this interaction to be happening: Interactions always have some quality or other. (Ch. 14, p. 165.) …simply begs the question. (After all, what is it that explains why and how the interactions have quality?) E. For a shorter version of his book, see: O'Regan, J. Kevin (2012), "How to Build a Robot that Is Conscious and Feels", Minds and Machines 22(2) (Summer): 117–136. 0. video 1. transcript Websites 0. 1. 2. Conscious Robots Machine Consciousness "DARPA Workshop on Self-Aware Computer Systems 2004" Includes position statements by Baars, Franklin, Holland, McCarthy, McDermott, Perlis, Schubert, Shapiro, Sloman, inter alia. <="" a=""> Text copyright © 2009–2013 by William J. Rapaport Cartoon links and screen-captures appear here for your enjoyment and are not meant to infringe on any copyrights held by the creators. For more information on any cartoon, click on it, or contact me. (rapaport@buffalo.edu) http://www.cse.buffalo.edu/~rapaport/719/csnessrdgs.html-20131110