A Gottfried of All Trades: Leibniz and His Trans-Field Exploits Andrew Nauffts, Benjamin Miller, and Paige Pendleton History of Physical Sciences April 21st, 2015 1 Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz was a man of immense intellect only mirrored by his thirst for knowledge. His entire life’s works all stemmed from the same logic he used to explain the way the world itself worked. Even though his works ranged from philosophy to mathematics to politics and beyond, his same personal logic was the birthplace of it all. He saw reality through his belief in everything falling into either absence or existence, zero or one. Everything had a purpose and a logical means of process to Leibniz, it was discovering the process itself using his logic which would make him famous. His works would later be the origins of Binary Code, Calculus, metaphysics, and monadology. Even more things in modern day life can in some way trace their origins to the works of Leibniz, so much so the list would be nearly impossible to create. This case study will discuss the controversy surrounding his most notable achievement, the discovery of the differential calculus, as well as his famous philosophies which mark him as a great philosopher of the ages. All great men must start off as children however, and the journey of their maturation often holds clues to how they became who they were. Leibniz was no exception. A Lifetime of Work: A Biography of Leibniz Born on July 1st, 1646, Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz would find himself a Philosopher, Mathematician, a Doctor of Law, and Political Adviser before his death in 1716. Successful in each of these professions, he would often juggle several of them at once giving opportunity to fall directly in to the time’s equivalent of the conceptualized old-boy network. His exploits would range in fields stretching even farther beyond these professions, making Leibniz a Renaissance man of sorts. A man of great intellect, Leibniz pushed himself constantly to refine 2 anything he was working on to a point of perfection through a highly systematic process before ever publishing (Jolley, 9). Surprisingly, school wasn’t Leibniz’s path to genius. He was mostly self-taught within his father’s library. In an odd twist of fate, the untimely death of Leibniz’s father when Leibniz was only 6 years old may be responsible for the development of one of the greatest minds in history. This is because Leibniz would only gain access to his father’s library after he passed. Prior to his demise, Leibniz’s father had been teaching Leibniz material well beyond his age, mostly in the fields of history and philosophy. Leibniz would be brought to the University of Leipzig with his father to learn almost every day, and after his father’s death, he was cut off from learning this advanced material. Soon after he would be reprimanded by a school teacher for reading books he had taken from his father’s library, as they were not suitable for a child. His mother, in response, decided to keep him out of the library left by her husband. However, when he was 8, a family friend took interest in the sheer intelligence shown by Leibniz, and convinced his mother to allow him full access to the library. From age 8 on, he was exposed to Latin classics, metaphysical works, and theological manuscripts. The works of Cicero, Pliny, Seneca, Herodotus, Xenophon, Plato and others were at his fingertips. Leibniz would learn much from this, and his entire world view would be shaped by the time spent in the library, and if it weren’t for events transpiring in the way they did, he may never have developed the Leibnizian logic which spawned calculus and binary code alike By 1664, Leibniz would hold a degree of Master of Philosophy from the University of Leipzig, and in 1666 he was rejected for a degree of doctor of law and decided to leave his hometown of Leipzig, Saxony forever. He soon received his doctor of law degree in Nürnberg, from the University of Altdorf. Receiving this degree would be the beginning of a series of 3 events landing Leibniz in Paris by 1672 as a political diplomat (Duigan, 165). However, his financier died, and Leibniz found himself without any financial support. In response to this, Leibniz came up with a plan to both gain him financial support but also a better foothold within the academic world (Ibid). He constructed a calculating machine to present to the Royal Society in England, who made him an external member of the society in 1673 as a result. The Leibniz wheel, as it was called, would later become a key component of the Arithmometer, the first mass-produced mechanical calculator in history. Following this came his discovery of the differential calculus in 1675. Between this time and publishing his work on the differential calculus in 1684, Leibniz worked on theories in regards to metaphysics and motion which would become further sources of controversy because much of this work would not be published (Duigan, 165-6). His published philosophical works caused some controversy as well. His published philosophical writings outlining the concept of this world being the best possible of all worlds was an example of this. Stemming from his work Principles of Sufficient Reason, Leibniz mapped out a series of constructs which, when combined with his belief in God as being necessary, led him to create this idea of an imperfect and yet best possible world. Even after his passing, this work was still receiving criticism, including Voltaire’s Candide in 1759. Candide critiqued several different aspects of society as well as several different philosophies and ideas, but the overall scheme of the book revolved around attacking this notion of the world being the best it could possibly be through the events experience by the main character and his love interest throughout the book. An interdisciplinary thinker, his various philosophical theories have heavy influences from his works in mathematics, motion, and metaphysics. The relationship shared between them created a cohesive Leibniz model of the world in such a way which caught the eye of more than 4 just the Royal Society. By 1700, Leibniz became a foreign member of the Academy of Science of Paris as well. For the next and final 16 years of his life, much of his work was political. Before his death in 1716, Leibniz earned the title of baron and became an official advisor to the Austrian empire. However, in 1714 he would manage to publish 2 philosophical works, Monadology and “Principles of Nature and Grace.” These would be his last works ever published; Monadology would become one of the most recognizable works of his later philosophy. Monadology would not only go on to influence metaphysics but it also was the first monad based theorem, even though the word monad was never used(Duigan, 127; Jolley, 66-8). The final 2 years of his life leading up to his death in 1716 would not be pleasant. His health began to deteriorate rapidly from severe gout and he found himself less mobile by the day until he was eventually bed ridden. These last 2 years would be spent in Hanover, and his death would not be as momentous as it most likely should have been. During his lifetime Leibniz made friend with many people or nobility and royalty from all over Europe. He found himself tutoring the children Queen Sophie Charlotte of Prussia at her personal request, a political advisor to multiple governments including the Austrian and Prussian, he would be visited by men such as Peter the Great in his own home, and even was made a baron out of shear gratitude from the Austrian emperor. However the various controversies surrounding Leibniz eventually caught up to him, and by the time of his death many of those who once praised him no longer viewed him a great man, excluding the more local Germanic royalty. It made sense why the northern German and other nearby kingdoms wouldn’t turn their back on Leibniz, due to him being a correspondent and friend to much of the noble families within the 5 region. Despite his quiet death, Leibniz still went on to be considered a member of the “pantheon of seven great philosophers.”1 A Feud between Giants: Who Discovered the Differential Calculus? Leibniz was a fairly popular man, often rubbing elbows with royalty and intellectuals alike, but one man, Isaac Newton, despised him. Subsequently, a feud spanning several decades ensued over who truly discovered the differential calculus. It began with Leibniz’s time in Paris from 1672-1676. He had no proper mathematical training and was practicing law at the time. However, he was extremely drawn to the ideas of mathematicians. In this short time span, he applied his logic and intellect to the compiled works of his predecessors to create calculus. His notation system was “completely original and ingenious (Bardi, 9).” The decade following the initial discovery was spent working out his system and symbols through the refinement of his work. Leibniz himself devised the name calculus, stemming from the Latin word for a pebble used in various roman tools with the purpose of counting (Bardi 9). The most notable of which being the small stones on Roman abacuses known as calculi and a tool used to measure distance in a similar fashion to an odometer which would drop a calculus (pebble) after each rotation of a wheel across a distance. Leibniz had two scholarly papers of his calculus works published in 1684 and 1686. These two papers serve as the primary evidence in the argument for Leibniz being the true creator of calculus. The following 2 decades were spent refining his work through examination, consulting his equals, and studying the math of others – all in the name of improving his calculus. 1 Ross, page 1 6 It was during the time he spent examining the math of others where Leibniz would eventually come across Newton’s Opticks. It was here, in Opticks, where Newton attempted to lay claim to the title of discoverer of the differential calculus. In 1704, when Newton published “On the Quadrature of Curves” in the back of Opticks, it was his attempt to take back the ownership of his invention. For 20 years Leibniz had been acknowledged as the king of calculus, enjoying the glory he was receiving while Newton quietly stewed with anger. Newton was even deemed a plagiarizer of Leibniz by some (Bardi, 9). Jason Bardi, in his work The Calculus Wars, says: This short treatise in the back of Opticks marked the quiet beginning of the calculus wars because it was the light that revealed the long-hidden feelings of jealousy and resentment between Leibniz and Newton. Newton had suffered in quiet humiliation for years with the knowledge that he was the first inventor of calculus, and he was a smoldering fire ready to be released into the flames. (Bardi, 10) Newton felt this way because he allegedly came up with the idea of calculus in 1666 when he was isolated at his parent’s estate during the outbreak of the Bubonic Plague. He planned on publishing his work on calculus in De Analysi around the same time of his work in the field of optics but Newton swore off publishing after the rejection he received from a letter he wrote titled “New Theory about Light and Colors.” He didn't realize the effects the printing of this would have…the controversy was immense. He didn't account for the time his contemporaries would need to grasp the concept, especially considering it took years to grapple with it himself. There would also be incredible resistance from those whose theories he would be replacing. (Bardi, 4). Essentially, his letter “opened up a new dialogue, and he became embroiled in bitter fights with [Robert] Hooke and others over his new theories-so much so that he swore off publishing for decades. He even once told one of his colleagues that he would rather wait until he died for his works to be published (Bardi, 5).” These feuds would lead Newton to 7 some dark places, including taking and hiding Hooke’s work and notes immediately following his death, delaying physics’ knowledge regarding springs for several years until these notes were later discovered. Newton didn’t publish his work on calculus because of personal reasons, but there were also physical barriers to him printing De Analysi. The London fire of September 1666 destroyed 373 acres of land. Thousands of houses and buildings were scorched and the printing industry took a massive hit. London was rebuilt in 3 years, which is commendable but the industry was shaky. Producing a big book was a risk and very expensive for publishers, so authors of mathematics (especially for such a complicated treatise) had almost no chance of being published (Bardi, 38). Because of this De Analysi was tucked away. This turn of events lead to Leibniz beating him to the punch. The wars began with Newton’s publishing in the back of Opticks when he wanted to claim the glory of the initial creation. In 1705, a European journal (closely associated with Leibniz) printed an unnamed review of Newton’s essay. This escalated the conflict because this anonymous person claimed that Newton had borrowed his ideas from Leibniz. Leibniz continually denied this authorship of the claim, but it was later proved by a biographer that he indeed wrote it (Bardi, 10). From the time of this attack to after Leibniz’s death in 1716, Newton waged a war to claim ownership over calculus. Newton said, "Whether Mr. Leibniz invented it after me, or had it from, is a question of no consequence, for second inventors have no rights (Bardi, 10)." Leibniz took this extremely seriously. The group of masterminds he worked with in Europe soon began writing letters in support of Leibniz. The following years for Leibniz would be spent writing several anonymous attacks against Newton himself, alongside publishing his other papers as well (Bardi, 11). Leibniz died in 1716 during the height of the wars. At this point 8 "he and Newton were old men fighting openly about which of them deserved credit and whether one had plagiarized the other. Their letters and their private writings are bitter testimonies to their respective brilliance and rival's deceit” (Bardi, 11). An Inter-disciplinary Construct: The Logic behind Leibniz’s Philosophies Leibniz isn’t easily categorized in the history of thought, as he was a master of many trades. He was a leading and influential thinker in the both the histories of mathematics and philosophy. Leibniz would be credited with the discovery of binary (or the revision of it), calculus, Boolean algebra, and formal logic. When one takes into account all of his musings and meditations on these subjects, a clear picture emerges of the type of thinker Leibniz was, and what his beliefs were. In his work there are clear overlaps between these disciplines. Leibniz is widely held within the “pantheon of seven great philosophers,” (MacDonald, 1) and is considered a continental rationalist, alongside Descartes and Spinoza. This sort of rational philosophy boiled down to a combination of analytic and symbolic representation, wherein anything-from math to language to philosophy to the spiritual, and everything in between-can be broken down into its most simple parts that comprise the greater concept. For instance, Leibniz helped to refine the binary system, which today is used in cell phones and computers, and many other computer-based technologies and devices. The significance of the binary system, in addition to its practicality and technological uses, is the impact it had on Leibniz’ philosophy. In mathematics, binary is a numeral system that represents numeric values using two symbols: zero (0) and one (1), these being of a set that designates empty or full. This helps us better understand Leibniz’s philosophy, or at least the context for his thought. 9 Because he viewed numbers this way, he also viewed logic in this way, whereas other philosophies and languages, even, focus on empirical evidence within a sentence, Leibniz’s approach shifted focus to “causal relationships between sentences” (MacDonald 55) Just as mathematicians use symbols like x and y in algebra, Leibniz believed words were just hollow symbols that are given meaning, so instead of thinking about the content (as rhetoricians are wont to do), Leibniz focused on the relationships between an x and a y. He is often considered the most important thinker in the history of logic since Aristotle, and he even employed a sort of scholastic and traditional method to his system, known as Genus and Differentia, or the “method of division,” which stemmed from the Greek philosophers themselves (MacDonald, 49-51). This method involved dividing things into branching classes, so that you are left with categories, and subsets of categories, and at any given time there will be a complex concept that is defined by simpler concepts, which in turn are defined by simpler concepts, and so on. One example is “’Paris is the lover of Helen’... (which) asserts a relationship between two subjects...each is true only because the other is true… (and) Ultimately, ‘God made Paris a lover because he was making Helen loved,’” and vice-versa (MacDonald, 55). An easier example is perhaps the concept ‘man,’ which can be understood by the terms ‘rational’ and ‘animal.’ These terms are simpler than the thing defined, and the relationship is of a subject and predicate, where the subject identifies a sentence, and the predicate attributes a certain property to that substance. Another resultant in Leibniz’s numerical approach to thought is his view of the world (in the universe) as God created it. While working on the binary system at the same time as his notations on infinitesimal calculus, it was conceivable to Leibniz to be able to trace or anticipate the path of an unfinished line from just a rate of change-otherwise known as integral calculus. He discovered differential 10 and integral calculus by observing quantities, or functions, and deriving a general principle for constructing trajectories, planetary orbits, etc. However, while important to mathematics, according to Leibniz, “the greatest significance of his discovery was metaphysical, or mystical, as showing how the whole universe could be seen as constructed out of a Number.” Leibniz believed in the existence of One and Zero, or nothing, and consequently that something could be created out of nothing, i.e., the universe. Leibniz’s Principle of Sufficient Reason states that nothing is without reason, and his Principle of Identity states that a principle is necessarily true if it is either itself an identical proposition, or can be reduced to one (identical predicate and subject). These two definitions, and Leibniz’s belief in God, inform us that Leibniz believed God is the necessary truth, and we, his creation, are made in his image (the identical proposition). In this way, Leibniz infamously said “we live in the best of all possible worlds” (MacDonald, 103) I say infamous because this is an Optimistic view of the universe, one that wasn’t shared as wholeheartedly by peer philosophers, and in fact, Leibniz was the cause for and center of the 18th century, FrenchEnlightenment thinker Voltaire’s satirical novel Candide. So furthermore, things might seem bad-for instance, natural disasters, disease etc. (criticisms which were often used against this infamous statement of Leibniz)-but only relatively so, or due to our perspective, whereas they might seem worse by another’s perspective. God wouldn’t create the world another way. So, where in binary everything can be broken down to a 0 or a 1, the creation of the Earth reflects this symbology, too; pure being (God, or a 1), and nothingness (0). God’s creative act was therefore a “voluntary dilution of his own essence, and a mathematical computation” reflecting perfect numbers (MacDonald, 101). 11 Final Thoughts Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz was a man of many talents and great potential. He applied that potential to a life of discovery and thought. From his work came calculus, binary code, the theory of monads, etc. However, Leibniz is not a man heavily discussed in schools. He does not get the attention Newton received in physics classrooms, nor does he receive acknowledgments in the history classrooms. He does get discussed in the calculus classrooms, but not much beyond his notation style vs. Newton’s. Leibniz was a man who works all stemmed from a similar logic, and his logic was in turn often influenced by his own discoveries as well. An example of this being his discovery of integrals through concepts he mentally constructed through his logic led him to actually change his mental construct of the world to being an entirely number based universal order. Evidence of the spiritual part of his logic becomes evidential here as well, as many of his explanations often fall in to the metaphysical realm. He then moved from this point to viewing the world as a binary construct, morphing his ideas in to one slowly evolving view of the universe through numerical pattern identification. In several ways Leibniz created something from nothing. He discovered calculus where there was no calculus before. It took a specific type of understanding of the relationship shared between trajectories, planes, dimensions, and numerical powers to discover the primitive differential and integral calculi, an understanding no one else at the time possessed. However, Leibnitz was careful about making his discovery accessible to others through its meticulously designed notation system. Even Newton didn’t discover calculus through the same mental path, which is most likely why his notation is in many ways nonsensical to most people, because it only made sense to him. Leibniz was a giant among men, and a man who contributed more to the human race than he took from it. It is a crime to not have him be studied in high school history 12 classes at any point, and a shame he is only known for his calculus to most people who have heard of them. However, to those who learn about the man himself. Those who learn about who he was, and what he accomplished, can truly appreciate Leibnitz as the giant he is. In many ways he was a renaissance man among boys, and a giant among men. 13 Work Cited Bardi, J. The calculus wars: Newton, Leibniz, and the greatest mathematical clash of all time. New York: Thunder's Mouth Press, 2006. "Bilder Und Videos Suchen: Leibniz." Bilder Und Videos Suchen: Leibniz. N.p., n.d. Web. 29 Mar. 2015. <https://de.fotolia.com/tag/leibniz>. "Candide (Random House 75th Anniversary Edition)." Barnes and Noble. American Classroom Libraries, n.d. Web. <http%3A%2F%2Fwww.barnesandnoble.com%2Fw%2Fcandide-francoisvoltaire%2F1100189377%3Fean%3D9780679642589>. Duigan, Brian. The 100 Most Influential Philosophers of All Time. 29 East 21st St., New York, NY: Britannica Educational Publishing, 2010. Jolley, Nicholas. Leibniz. 270 Madison Ave, New York, NY: Routledge, 2005. LSNA Conference 2015." LSNA Conference 2015. Ohio State University, n.d. Web. 29 Mar. 2015. <https://u.osu.edu/lsna2015/> Newton and Leibniz. N.d. Department of History University of California, Irvine. Web. 29 Mar. 2015. <http://faculty.humanities.uci.edu/bjbecker/RevoltingIdeas/leibniz.html>. Ross, G. MacDonald. Past Masters: Leibniz. New York: Oxford University Press, 1984.