Section 1.2 Evidence and Inference Proving Your Point McGraw-Hill © 2013 McGraw-Hill Companies. All Rights Reserved. Logic Logic attempts to determine how people should reason if they want to avoid error and falsehood. 1.2-2 Arguments Argument—a group of statements that attempt to establish a claim. Conclusion—the claim that an argument attempts to establish. Premise—a reason for accepting the conclusion of an argument. 1.2-3 Enthymemes An enthymeme is an argument with an unstated premise or conclusion. For example: “Everybody does it, so I should be allowed to do it, too.” Missing premise: “If everybody does it, it is permissible to do it.” 1.2-4 Principle of Charity When interpreting an argument, choose the interpretation that makes the most sense from a logical point of view. 1.2-5 Steps in Identifying an Argument Identify the conclusion. Identify the premises. Spell out any unstated premises. 1.2-6 Conclusion Indicators “thus,” “therefore,” “hence,” “so,” “then,” “consequently,” “as a result,” “shows that,” “means that,” “implies that,” “establishes that,” “can concluded that,” etc. For example: “Only things made of flesh and blood can think. Therefore computers can’t think.” Sometimes conclusions aren’t preceded by an indicator word. For example: “God exists, since the world needs a designer.” 1.2-7 Premise Indicators “since” “because,” “for,” “if,” “follows from,” “given that,” “provided that,” “assuming that,” etc. For example: “She’s a vegetarian because she things that eating meet is immoral.” Sometimes premises are not preceded by indicator words. For example: “You have no control over the neurons in your brain. It follows that you have no control over anything you do.” 1.2-8 Deductive vs. Inductive Arguments In a valid deductive argument, the truth of the premises guarantees the truth of the conclusion If the premises are true, the conclusion has to be true. In a strong inductive argument, the truth of the premises only makes the conclusion probable If the premises are true, the conclusion may still be false. 1.2-9 Deductive Arguments A deductive argument is valid when the conclusion logically follows from the premises In that case, it’s impossible for the premises to be true and the conclusion false. A deductive argument is sound when it’s valid and all of its premises are true. 1.2-10 Affirming the Antecedent (1) If p, then q. (2) p. (3) Therefore q. For example: (1) If the soul is immortal, then thinking doesn’t depend on brain activity. (2) The soul is immortal. (3) Therefore, thinking doesn’t depend on brain activity. 1.2-11 Denying the Consequent (1) If p, then q. (2) Not q. (3) Therefore, not p. For example: (1) If the soul is immortal, then thinking doesn’t depend on brain activity. (2) Thinking does depend on brain activity. (3) Therefore, the soul is not immortal. 1.2-12 Hypothetical Syllogism (1) If p, then q. (2) If q, then r. (3) Therefore, if p, then r. For example: (1) If the Fed raises interest rates, it will be more difficult to borrow money. (2) If it’s more difficult to borrow money, home sales will fall. (3) Therefore, if the FED raises interest rates, home sales will fall. 1.2-13 Disjunctive Syllogism (1) Either p or q. (2) Not p. (3) Therefore q. For example: (1) Either Sally walked or she rode the bus. (2) She didn’t walk. (3) Therefore, she rode the bus. 1.2-14 Affirming the Consequent (Invalid) (1) If p, then q. (2) q. (3) Therefore, p. For example: (1) If Chicago is the capital of Illinois, then Chicago is in Illinois. (2) Chicago is in Illinois. (3) Therefore, Chicago is the capital of Illinois. 1.2-15 Denying the Antecedent (Invalid) (1) If p, then q. (2) Not p. (3) Therefore, not q. For example: (1) If Joe is a bachelor, then Joe is a male. (2) Joe is not a bachelor. (3) Therefore, Joe is not a male. 1.2-16 Affirming a Disjunct (Invalid) (1) Either p or q. (2) p. (3) Therefore, not q. For example: (1) Either the car battery is dead or the car is out of gas. (2) The car battery is dead. (3) Therefore, the car is not out of gas. 1.2-17 Inductive Arguments A strong inductive argument is one that would establish its conclusion with a high degree of probability if its premises were true. A cogent inductive argument is a strong one which contains only true premises. 1.2-18 Enumerative Induction (1) X per cent of the observed members of A are B. (2) Therefore, X percent of the entire group of A are B. For example: (1) 54 per cent of the students in this college are female. (2) Therefore, probably, 54 per cent of all college students are female. 1.2-19 Analogical Induction (1) Object A has properties F, G, H, etc. as well as the property Z. (2) Object B has properties F, G, H, etc. (3) Therefore, object B probably has property Z. For example: (1) The Earth has air, water, and life. (2) Mars has air and water. (3) Therefore, Mars probably has life. 1.2-20 Hypothetical Induction (Inference to the Best Explanation) (1) Phenomena p. (2) If hypothesis H were true, it would provide the best explanation of p. (3) Therefore, it’s probable that H is true. For example: (1) My car won’t start. (2) The best explanation of that fact is that the battery is dead. (3) Therefore, it’s probable that the battery is dead. 1.2-21 Criteria of adequacy for deciding among competing hypotheses: Consistency—internal and external. Simplicity—number of assumptions made by a hypothesis. Scope—the amount of diverse phenomena explained by a hypothesis. Conservatism—fit with confirmed hypotheses. Fruitfulness—successful novel predictions or problems solved. 1.2-22 Fallacious Arguments Fallacious arguments fail to provide good reasons for accepting a claim because either: The premises are dubious or They do not support the conclusion. 1.2-23 An argument is fallacious if it contains: Unacceptable premises (premises as dubious as they claim they’re trying to support) Irrelevant premises (premises that have no bearing on the truth of the conclusion) or Insufficient premises (premises that do not establish the conclusion beyond a reasonable doubt). 1.2-24 Informal Fallacies Unacceptable Premises: Begging the Question, False Dilemma Irrelevant Premises: Equivocation, Composition, Division, Appeal to the Person, Genetic Fallacy, Appeal to Unqualified Authority, Appeal to the Masses, Appeal to Tradition, Appeal to Ignorance, Appeal to Fear Insufficient Premises: Hasty Generalization, Faulty Analogy, False Cause 1.2-25 Begging the Question An argument begs the question – or argues in a circle – when its conclusion is used as one of its premises. For example: “Jane has telepathy,” says Susan. “How do you know?” asks Jill. “Because she can read my mind,” replies Susan. 1.2-26 False Dilemma An argument that presumes that only two alternatives exist when in actuality there are more than two. For example: “Either science can explain how she was cured or it was a miracle. Science can’t explain how she was cured. So it must be a miracle.” 1.2-27 Equivocation Using the same word in two different senses in a single argument. For example: “(i) Only man is rational. (ii) No woman is a man. (iii) Therefore no woman is rational.” 1.2-28 Composition Claiming that what is true of the parts is true of the whole. For example: “Subatomic particles are lifeless. Therefore anything made out of them is lifeless.” 1.2-29 Division Claiming that what is true of a whole is also true of its parts. For example: “We are alive and we are made out of subatomic particles. So they must be alive too.” 1.2-30 Appeal to the Person The attempt to refute an argument by denigrating its presenter. Also referred to as “ad hominem,” or “to the man.” For example: “You can’t believe Dr. Jones’s claim that there is no evidence for life after death. After all, he’s an atheist.” 1.2-31 Genetic Fallacy Arguing that a claim is true or false on the basis of its origin. For example: “Jones’s idea is the result of a mystical experience, so it must be false (or true).” Or: “Jane got that message from a Ouiji board, so it must be false (or true).” 1.2-32 Appeal to Unqualified Authority Citing a non-expert to make your point. For example: “Psychiatry must be bogus because Tom Cruise says it is.” 1.2-33 Appeal to the Masses Arguing that something must be true (or good) because everybody believes it (or does it).” For example: Said in 1800: “Slavery must be a good thing because every culture has had slaves.” 1.2-34 Appeal to Tradition Arguing that something must be true (or good) because it is part of an established tradition. For example: “Women should work at home because that’s what they’ve always done.” 1.2-35 Appeal to Ignorance Using an opponent’s inability to disprove a conclusion as proof of the conclusion’s correctness, or Using an opponent’s inability to prove a conclusion as proof of its incorrectness. For example: “Bigfoot must exist because no one has been able to prove that he doesn’t.” 1.2-36 Appeal to Fear Using the threat of harm to advance one’s position. For example: “If you do not convict this criminal, one of you may be her next victim.” 1.2-37 Hasty Generalization Drawing a general conclusion about all things of a certain type on the basis of evidence concerning only a few things of that type. For example: “I know one of those psychics. They’re all a bunch of phonies.” 1.2-38 Faulty Analogy Arguing that things that resemble one another in very limited respects resemble one another in other respects. For example: “Astronauts wear helmets and fly in spaceships. The figure in this Mayan carving seems to be wearing a helmet and flying in a spaceship. Therefore it is a carving of an ancient astronaut.” 1.2-39 False Cause Arguing that two events are causally connected when they are not. Latin scholars dubbed this the fallacy of post hoc, ergo propter hoc, which means “After this, therefore because of this.” Example: “My cold got better after I wore this crystal around my neck. So it must have cured it.” 1.2-40