Moral Theory An explanation of why an action is right or wrong or why a person or a person’s character is good or bad Tells us what it is about an action that makes it right Moral Theory cont. Moral theories alone are not the ultimate authority in moral deliberations. Moral deliberations involve both the general and the particular—theory, principles, and considered judgments. Moral Theory cont. Consequentialist/Teleological theory— Asserts that the rightness of actions depends solely on their consequences Categorical/Deontological theory—Asserts that the rightness of actions is determined partly or entirely by their intrinsic value Moral Criteria of Adequacy Criterion I: Consistency with our considered moral judgments Criterion II: Consistency with the facts of the moral life Criterion III: Resourcefulness in moral problem-solving Utilitarianism “Greatest Happiness/Pleasure for the Greatest Number” Jeremy Bentham (1748-1832) “Nature has placed man under the governance of two masters, pain and pleasure.” The only thing intrinsically good is pleasure The only thing intrinsically bad is pain Principle of Utility: “The principle which approves or disapproves of every action whatsoever, according to the tendency which it appears to have to augment or diminish the happiness of the party whose interest is in question.” May be paraphrased simply as “The greatest good for the greatest number.” “Calculus of Felicity/Hedonistic Calculus” Intensity: How strong is the sensation (of pain or pleasure)? Duration: How long does the sensation last? Certainty: How clear and distinct is the sensation? Propinquity: How soon will it be experienced? Fecundity: What other sensations of pleasure/pain will follow? Purity: How free from pain is the pleasure, and vice versa? Extent: How many persons will be affected by it, one way or the other? Nozick’s “Experience Machine” The thought experiment is an argument against hedonism, i.e. the position that good is to be defined in terms of pleasure alone. Argues that “what matters” includes more than simply having an experience, we wish to do certain things and be a certain way, and hedonism doesn’t fully answer the question of motivation/what matters. Thus hedonism is insufficient. J.S Mill (1806-1873) Mill’s version of Utilitarianism seeks to respond to charges that Bentham’s moral system is a “pig philosophy,” i.e. base pleasures trump all. Seeks to distinguish “happiness” from mere sensual pleasure, so for Mill “good” in the principle is equated with happiness. Notes that there is a qualitative difference between pleasures, and this fact must be factored in if one is to try to distinguish goods based upon ability to produce happiness. This distinction makes it difficult to apply a “hedonistic calculus” as Bentham envisioned due to difference in values of opposing “pleasures.” What is required are competent judges who can rule between competing pleasures. “Rule-Utilitarianism” Many examples can given where an act might be morally justified on an act-based system of consequentialism, but that would fail a test for overall utility, e.g. “Bob for spare parts.” Thus it seems the best way to salvage consequentialism is to argue for a rules-based system, where the rules guiding action are in place to maximize utility. “Each act, in the moral life, falls under a rule; and we are to judge the rightness or wrongness of an act, not by its consequences, but by the consequences of its universalization – that is, by the consequences of the rule under which this act falls.