The Criminological Moment: On the Limits of Theoretical Explanations of Criminogenic Agency1 Michael W. Raphael CUNY Graduate Center Abstract Several texts on theoretical criminology organize themselves in various ways. Yet, the correlation of the types of crime these theories purport to explain at the phenomenological level at which factors orbit and exert their social facts to correlate an individual with a criminal act is not altogether clear. This paper presents a framework for a new ‘theoretical organization’ aimed at clarifying the requisite qualifications for theoretical explanations to apply to six types of crime and proposes three phenomenological levels of agency around which criminogenic factors tend to coalesce in the hope that new criminological theory can emerge and their subsequent policies will be better informed given this re-organization. Introduction The word crime is derived from the Latin root cernō, meaning “I decide, I give judgment” (Klein, 1971) while the term’s Latin cognate, crīmen, meant “charge” or “cry of distress.” The Ancient Greek word krima (κρίμα), from which the Latin cognate derives, typically referred to an intellectual mistake or an offense against the community, (Bakaoukas, 2005) rather than a private or moral wrong as current legal theory suggests. (Cf. Garland, 2008: 56) This socio-legal construct has accumulated a stigma (Cf. Goffman, 1963) since Ancient Greece whereby the criminal signified trended between the imagery of the demonically possessed (Cf. Pfohl, 2009) and the imagery of “an anomaly, partly pathological and partly atavistic, a revival of the primitive savage.” (Lombroso-Ferrero, 2009: xii) Hence, criminological theory developed around the conception of the uncivilized creature committing heinous acts on the street that needed to be disciplined and punished. (Cf. Foucault, 1977) 1 Last updated: 3/15/2016 4:24 AM; Preparing for Submission to the British Journal of Sociology. 1 Given this socio-legal construct, which by definition varies by jurisdiction, several scholars suggest avoiding the issue by defining a category wider than ‘crime’ typically referred to as “social deviance” (Felson, 2006: 33) yet that also has definitional issues. Instead, Felson goes on to later state that “Crime is impelled by life itself. All people have a natural capacity to discover and enjoy what they are not supposed to do. Sometimes people stumble across illicit opportunities quite by accident. Other times they set out to find these opportunities, perhaps with care, perhaps without.” (2006: 357) Therefore the question stumbled upon is not why people commit crime but to theorize what factors impose an individual to be found in a setting where an action would provide the police with justification for enforcing the law. The criminological literature organizes these factors into theories. When a factor that tends to correlate an individual with the setting of a criminal act, the factor is considered to be criminogenic.2 When an individual possesses an aggregate of these factors, they are said to have the criminogenic character and are more likely to be found in a situation where the police would have to enforce the law than individuals without such a character. The level of criminogenic agency, or the location in which these factors orbit, can be organized at the individual level, the environmental level and at the group level. This taken together with the type of crime to be explained will perhaps provide further clarity on the relationships among the criminological theories to the extent they theorize crime and not more general social behaviors. Types of Crime With the imagery of the demonic savage in mind, one might be led to think that criminological theory tries to explain street crime (Cf. Hallsworth, 2005) and violence but in fact the body of criminological theory is broader than that. Larry J. Siegel suggests that the types of crime can be clustered into six 2 Rather than defining criminogenic as the tendency to cause crime or criminality, this paper asserts this definition. 2 groups: (1) violent crime, (2) political crime, (3) property crime, (4) enterprise crime, (5) public order crime, and (6) cybercrime. (Siegel, 2009: 299) The relationship between the type of offense and the type of offender has become the study of criminal typologies. Historically, these typologies have become a subject of study in their own right. (Cf. Roebuck, 1967; Meier, 1984; Clinard et al., 1994 [1967]; Garland, 2008; Hagan, 2009) One of the more notable classification schemes for categorizing types of criminals comes from the work of Clinard, Quinney, & Wildeman (1994 [1967]) where they develop nine types of criminal behavior systems in relation to the five theoretical dimensions.3 Their scheme divides the types of criminals as follows: (1) Violent Personal Criminal Behavior; (2) Occasional Property Criminal Behavior; (3) Public Order Criminal Behavior; (4) Conventional Criminal Behavior; (5) Political Criminal Behavior; (6) Occupational Criminal Behavior; (7) Corporate Criminal Behavior; (8) Organized Criminal Behavior; and (9) Professional Criminal Behavior. (1994 [1967]: 15) Since this paper attempts to organize the types of crime correlated with criminological theory stratified by the level of criminogenic agency, the type of crime needs to become divorced from the ideal and empirical types of criminals. Given this, Robert F. Meier published in 1984 an edited volume entitled Major Forms of Crime in which, through the use of Clinard’s typology, different authors discuss the definitional issues in defining types of crime. Within the following discussion, then, consider how the interaction of Clinard, et al.’s typology of criminals with Meirer’s and other’s definitions & characterizations fit in with Siegel’s typology of crime such that the degree of broadness falls within the “Goldilocks” zone. 3 These theoretical dimensions are (1) Legal Aspects of Selected Offenses; (2) Criminal Career of the Offender; (3) Group Support of Criminal Behavior; (4) Correspondence between Criminal and Legitimate Behavior; and (5) Social Reaction and Legal Processing. (Ibid.: 14) 3 Violent Crime Discussions of violence and its illegitimate implications present the following qualifications: 1. “Crimes involving the use of force or the threat of force against persons (murder, manslaughter, rape, assault, robbery) were considered violent.” (Heilbrun, 1979: 511) 2. “Violence refers to a broader class of action. In general, it refers to any transaction in which one party uses physical force to manipulate another. Thus, violence includes a wide variety of transactions: from group confrontations, such as riots and revolutions, to interpersonal struggles, such as schoolyard scuffles and domestic fights; from legitimate encounters, in which the use of force is legally approved, as when two men square off in a prizefight, to illegitimate encounters, in which the use of force is disapproved, as when a man kills his unfaithful wife; and so forth. These transactions share a fundamental quality: they are instances of coercion based on physical force. Yet they are distinctive, involving different kinds of people, featuring different dynamics, and eliciting different reactions from others.” (Luckenbill, 1984: 19) 3. “Felonious violent crimes against the person include acts in which physical injury is inflicted against one or more others, including criminal homicide, aggravated assault, forcible rape or attempts to inflict such injuries. What has been referred to as "suicide by proxy," where a despondent and depressed person kills his or her loved ones and himself/herself in order to spare them humiliation, falls into the same category (Livingston 1992, 165). So-called ‘assisted deaths’ (in the style of Dr. Jack Kevorkian), wherein one person aids and abets the death of another, have been defined legally as homicides. Kidnapping involves the element of physical force, and child abuse sometimes also involves the use of force and violence against the person. Armed robbery involves an element of force, such as the use of a gun, knife or threat of violence in obtaining money, jewelry or other items of value.” (Clinard et al., 1994 [1967]: 25) Based on the intersections and interactions of these discussions then in regard to the issue at hand, the condition required for selecting the applicability of a criminological theory to this crime type would be whether it could explain what factors impose an individual or group to either coerce another through the threat of physical injury or the induction of physical injury, lethal or otherwise. Political Crime Political crime as a category varies in its perception and definition in contrast to definitions of to some scholarship that suggests white-collar crime should subsume these types of acts. The literature presents the follow characterizations: 4 1. “Illegal acts that are designed to undermine an existing government and threaten its survival. Political crimes can include both violent and non-violent acts and range in seriousness from dissent, treason, and espionage to violent acts such as terrorism and assassination.” (Siegel, 2009: 506) 2. Political crimes are “acts which officials treat as if they were political and criminal regardless of their real nature and the motivation of their perpetrators.” (Ingraham, 1979) 3. Political crime is “whatever is recognized or anticipated by authorities to be resistance threatening the established structure of differential resources and opportunities.” (Turk, 1984: 120) 4. “Political crimes—crimes by or against the government—are particularly difficult to view objectively, for they always involve moral and ideological positions. Any discussion of political crime is bound to be complicated by what are often conflicting views of a situation. A wide variety of crimes against the government are crimes of omission, crimes such as evasion of income tax laws, violations of customs regulations or operating or acting without a license when one is required.” (Clinard et al., 1994 [1967]: 141-2) 5. “Political crime has been defined in a number of different ways but, apart from a broad definition which sees all crime as political, most seek to make a distinction between political crime and ordinary crime either because of the different motivations or ideology of the individuals involved or the different context in which the crime takes place.” (Hillyard, 2006: 300) 6. “Similarly, state crime research distinguishes between political crimes— those illegal activities committed by state actors for the fulfillment of personal goals or those of non-polity organizations working within, and other state crimes. Political crimes, such as corruption and election fraud, are typically done by state actors who use their access to state resources for the accomplishment of the criminal act. Yet, motivational drives and criminal outcomes are focused on personal enrichment and/or direct benefit to non-state groups, such as political parties. As with occupational crime, I see the key trait of political crimes being individuals taking advantage of their occupational positions of trust (Sutherland 1939) to enhance their own social status and positions. Archetypical cases of this type of political crime include Boss Tweed's corruption of Tammany Hall, the Teapot Dome Scandal of the Harding Administration, and the Watergate break-ins ordered by the Nixon White House. Such scandals and abuses of power are nearly omnipresent in modern states (see Ross's 2003 volume for a comprehensive list of criminal corruption in modern democratic states). While others do classify this type of behavior as a form of state crime, I view these as occupational crimes—for self-gain, not in pursuit of organizational goals as such; they are out of the purview of what I consider to be forms of state crime.” (Rothe, 2009: 22) Again, the question arises what these depictions have in common that would allow a criminological theory suggest what factors qualify an individual or group to partake in a specific action that can 5 legitimately be said to be motivated by a desire to affect a significant portion of society, including one or another of its institutions, and it involves as one of the elements of its intention a rejection of the legitimacy of calling the act a crime and an additional intention, that may or may not be carried out depending on circumstances and ratios of cost to benefits, to treat the prosecution of the crime as itself a political act. Property Crime Siegel’s classification of this crime type has subsumed two criminal typologies: those who commit such crimes occasionally and those who commit such crimes professionally. Therefore, in order to acquiesce upon property crimes’ constitution, consider the following characterizations: 1. “Crimes against property are those offenses in which the criminal steals or damages something that belongs to someone else. These crimes are far more common than those involving violence: on average, one occurs every 3 seconds. The main forms of this offense are burglary, which involves an unlawful entry to commit a theft or other serious crime (one every 10 seconds); larceny, or theft (one every 4 seconds); motor-vehicle theft (one every 24 seconds); and arson, or maliciously setting fire to property.” (Robertson, 1988: 124) 2. Occasional Property Crime 1. “Criminal laws protect the material interests of the propertied classes. Specific laws prohibit forgery, shoplifting, vandalism and auto theft.” (Clinard et al., 1994 [1967]: 18) 2. “There is general agreement that burglary, theft, fraud, and larceny are instances of property crime, for the owner's illegal loss of property (that is, goods or money) is apparent in such activities. Robbery and arson also result in property loss or damage, but these criminal acts frequently are thought of as crimes against persons rather than as property crimes, because they involve a threat of injury to persons. For our purposes, however, property crime is defined to include any criminal behavior by which property is damaged or by which possession of property is transferred, regardless of whether that behavior involves the threat or use of physical force to accomplish that objective.” (Hepburn, 1984: 73) 3. Professional Theft 1. “Professional theft traditionally refers to nonviolent forms of criminal behavior that are undertaken with a high degree of skill, for monetary gain, and that exploit interests which tend to maximize financial opportunities and minimize the possibilities of apprehension. 6 As such, it is a highly specialized variety of crime, reflecting an occupational structure similar to many of the ‘learned’ professions and other vocational pursuits. The most typical forms of criminal activity engaged in by professional thieves include pickpocketing, burglary, shoplifting, forgery and counterfeiting, extortion, sneak theft, and confidence swindling.” (Inciardi, 1984: 223) 2. “The professional thief is one who steals professionally. This means, first, that he makes a regular business of stealing. He devotes his entire working time and energy to larceny and may steal three hundred and sixty-five days a year. Second, every act is carefully planned. The selection of spots, securing of the property, making a get-away, disposing of the stolen property, and fixing cases in which he may be pinched (arrested) are all carefully planned. Third, the professional thief has technical skills and methods which are different from those of other professional criminals. Manual skill is important in some of the rackets, but the most important thing in all the rackets is the ability to manipulate people. The thief depends on his approach, front, wits, and in many instances his talking ability. The professional burglar or stickup man (robber with a gun), on the other hand, uses violence or threat of violence even though he may on occasion use soothing language in order to quiet people. Fourth, the professional thief is generally migratory and may work in all the cities of the United States.” (Conwell & Sutherland, 1956: 3) Given these portrayals, the question arises what these descriptions are collectively – meaning what would let a criminological theory propose factors to qualify an individual or group to participate in a specific action that can legitimately be said to be a ‘property crime’. Since the scope of this section is focused on crimes and not criminals, the distinction between occasional and professional can be eschewed although such a distinction frames the method and frequency by which the act is mediated – it does not alter the fact that an act occurred. What this leaves the criminologist with is determining which factors motivate offenders aimed at denying others their material interests. Enterprise Crime Several typologies of crime arrange notions of white collar, corporate and organized crime at different levels of classification similar to how ‘occasional property crime’ and ‘professional theft’ are subordinate to ‘property crime.’ For this crime type, Peter Gill suggests that the distinction of ‘enterprise crime’ should be a subordinate category to ‘organized crime’ and not a superior classification. It appears 7 Gill asserts this because for him, the literature suggests white collar crime is a category in its own right and that ‘organized crime’ commonly draws the specific distinction “between ‘ordinary’ criminals, even if in gangs, whose crimes are ‘predatory’, that is, concerned with the illegal redistribution of already existing wealth, and criminal organizations committing ‘enterprise’ crime: the production and distribution of new [wealth] though illegal, goods and services.” (2006: 280; Cf. Levi, 2002: 885) Yet, Siegel appears to reconcile the subordination of white collar and organized crime (Siegel, 2009: 396) with the latter half of his textbook definition: “The use of illegal tactics to gain profit in the marketplace. Enterprise crimes can invoke and both the violation of law in the course of an otherwise legitimate occupation or the sale or distribution of illegal commodities.” (Ibid: 501) In order to properly classify and induce the applicable criminological theories to this crime type, consider how the literature characterizes what Siegel sees as sub-categories: 1. White Collar Crime 1. “The white-collar criminal is defined as a person with high socio-economic status who violates the laws designed to regulate his occupational activities.” (Sutherland, 1949: 511; Cf. Geis, 2007 for a discussion of Sutherland’s various attempts to define this.) 2. “Illegal acts that capitalize on a person’s status in the marketplace. White collar crimes can involve theft, embezzlement fraud, market manipulation, restraint of trade, and false advertising.” (Siegel, 2009: 512) 3. White Collar Crime is “a heterogeneous group of offences committed by people of relatively high status or enjoying relatively high levels of "trust, and made possible by their legitimate employment. Such crimes typically include fraud, embezzlement, tax violations and other accounting offences, and various forms of workplace theft and fiddling in which the organization, its customers or other organizations are the victims.” (Tombs & Whyt, 2006a: 462) 4. Corporate Crime 1.“White collar crime involving a legal violation by a corporate entity, such as pricefixing, restraint of trade, or hazardous waste dumping.” (Siegel, 2009: 498) 2.“The study of corporate crime examines the extensive illegal behavior of organizations that are formally legal.” (Gill, 2006: 281) 3.“Illegal acts or omissions, punishable by the state under administrative, civil or criminal law, which are the result of deliberate decision-making or culpable negligence within a legitimate formal organization. These acts or omissions are based 8 in legitimate, formal, business organizations, made in accordance with the normative goals, standard operating procedures, and/or cultural norms of the organization, and are intended to benefit the corporation itself.” (Tombs & Whyt, 2006b: 74-75) 2. Organized Crime 1. “This concept emerged first in the United States in the 1920s but is now used internationally, for example, by the United Nations and G8 countries, as shorthand to describe a range of serious crimes that are deemed especially difficult to control. It may be defined as the ongoing activities of those collectively engaged in production, supply and financing for illegal markets in goods and services.” (Gill, 2006: 280) 2. “Illegal activities of people and organizations whose acknowledged purpose is profit through illegitimate business enterprise.” (Siegel, 2009: 505) 3. “The most essential feature of the criminal gang is that its members routinely engage in law violation behavior.” (Knox, 1993:1) Hence, the issue at-hand can be framed by finding the question within Gill’s statement, “Overall, the enterprise model is at the heart of the common metaphor of the criminal ‘firm’” (Gill, 2006: 281) and that is what is the crime in enterprise? This leaves the criminologist with the task of determining which factors qualify an individual or group to participate in a specific action that can legitimately be said to be the perversion of the legal rules of commercial conduct for illegitimate purposes. Public Order Crime This crime type is where controversy arises – as Victoria L. Swigert wrote, “There are other offenses, however, in which the activities condemned seem less attuned to the reciprocal interests of the state and individual or which involve harms that are much less self-evident.” (1984: 95) If there was anything intrinsic to the offences discussed so far, ignoring Durkheim for a moment (1938: 70), here is where that intrinsicality would evaporate. Swigert makes this argument very clear: “Not only are most people breaking America's laws, but changes in the law convert conformists into criminals and criminals into conformists at the stroke of a pen. Furthermore, there are perfectly legal behaviors that, upon closer inspection, look like ones that are vigorously condemned. It does little good to study individual actors 9 when the ultimate cause of their status as deviant or conformist lies in the rules themselves.” (1984: 107) Nevertheless, during the midst of developing this framework, consider these characterizations: 1. “Acts that are considered illegal because they threaten the general well-being of society and challenge its accepted moral principles.” (Siegel, 2009: 507-8) 2. “Specific criminal laws embody the moral sense of particular segments of the community. Such offenses as prostitution, homosexuality, drunkenness and drug use are disturbing to some community members. Many of the crimes are ‘victimless’ in that only willing participants are involved. Yet it is easier for the power elite to outlaw these behaviors than to either accept them or to change the social arrangements that produced the behavior.” (Clinard et al., 1994 [1967]: 18) 3. “There is an entire category of offenses from which nobody usually suffers directly, except perhaps the offenders themselves. These are the victimless crimes, such as gambling, prostitution, vagrancy, illicit drug use, prohibited sexual acts between consenting adults, and the like. … Victimless crime is notoriously difficult to control. One reason, of course, is that there is no aggrieved victim to bring a charge, or to give evidence, against the offender. Another reason is that the offenders often regard the laws, not themselves, as wrong.” (Robertson, 1988: 125) Given these depictions and Swigert’s formidable “stroke of pen” (representing law as the cause of crime) and the wide variable nature of possible offenses, here criminologists are handed a brick wall to run into. For if “stroke of pen” is the case, then criminological theory would not suffice and might represent a call for a general theory of deviance and would be outside the scope of this analysis… (For a discussion on how police deal with the “stroke of pen” in practice Cf. Manning, 2010: 209.) Therefore the question determining which factors qualify an individual or group to participate in a specific action purports to situate the calculus (however faulty) of the individual over the calculus (again, however faulty) of society. Cybercrime While most of the offenses discussed so far have been occurring for centuries, this crime type is younger than criminological theory. According to Mark Sherman of the Federal Judicial Center, “Cybercrime is difficult to define because it ranges from crimes that cannot be committed without a computer or 10 connected device to traditional crimes that are merely facilitated by computers or connected devices.” (2000: 5) In light of this, examine these subsequent depictions: 1. One “might characterize information age crime as being illegal, immoral or antisocial behavior that is directed either explicitly against computer resources, or that uses computers in an incidental manner, or that could not be possible without the involvement of computers.” (Barrett, 1997: 32) 2. “Cybercrimes are illegal acts committed with the assistance of, or by means of, computers, computer networks, the Internet and web-based information and communications technologies (ICTs).” (Jewke, 2006: 106) 3. “Cybercrimes are “criminal or harmful activities that are informational, global and networked. They are the product of networked technologies that have transformed the division of criminal labor to provide entirely new opportunities for, and indeed, new forms of crime which typically involve the acquisition or manipulation of information and its value across global networks.” (Wall, 2007: 4) 4. “The use of modern technology for criminal purpose.” (Siegel, 2009: 499) 5. “Law enforcement officers divide cybercrime into three categories: crimes in which a computer is the target of the offense, crimes in which a computer is used as a tool in committing the offense, and crimes in which a computer plays an incidental role in the commission of the offense.” (Brenner, 2010: 39) These depictions taken together, organized in historical order, suggests a new Pandora’s Box that criminological theory is not prepared for. Susan W. Brenner’s characterization (No. 5 above) emphasizes the distinction of the computer as either the means or the target. The implications for criminological theory in terms of the computer/internet as the means, theory need not attempt explain who the offender is because the factors that explain the ‘violent’ offender (Cf. Jolson, 2011) or ‘professional thief’ might as well explain the ‘e-offender’ since the act is still fundamentally personal injury or the denial of another’s material interests. The computer/internet as the means basically allows offenders to become more sophisticated with their methods: “If ‘Slick’ Willie Sutton, the oft-quoted 1930s gentleman bank robber, was embarking on his criminal career today he would, likely as not, be contemplating using the internet to commit his robberies: 'because that’s where the money [now] is!’ The difference between then and now is that Willie would no longer be planning arduous and dangerous million-dollar bank robberies 11 because networked technologies enable him to commit millions of $1 robberies with much less risk.” (Wall, 2007: 70) However, the point where Pandora opens her box, has little to do with the electronic means approach since the laws for various types of crime were simply modified to include the electronic means like identity theft and cyber stalking. (Cf. Ibid, 69-102; Siegel, 2009: 472-8) Since the electronic means is not the end goal, unlike where the computer is the target, there is some sort of extra-electronic action occurring after the cyber act like the transfer of funds resulting from the theft of an identity. Thus, current theories may still apply. The box opens when discussing the computer as the target. (Cf. Wall, 2007: 52-68) This is the relatively new category of crime. When the computer is the target, the digital signature of the act itself is context-free and indistinguishable from cyber activism (Leonard, 2011b) or coincidence. (Cf. Cross & Shinder, 2008; Leonard, 2011a) Aside from the fact that there has not been enough “stroke of pen” in legislating conduct pertaining to the computer as the target, the law once written, cannot keep up with the exponential growth of technology and its vulnerabilities to be exploited. (Cf. Brenner, 2007) This taken together with the lag of development of computer forensics (Cf. Cross & Shinder, 2008) makes proving criminal intent extremely difficult since the attack of computers, not people, without a calling card, is indistinguishable from 1 person controlling a hundred computers or 100 people coordinated to attack one computer. This fact alone will make it difficult for criminologists to collect data. The only foreseeable way to close Pandora’s Box is for criminological theory to somehow determine or at least propose what factors qualify an individual or group to participate in a specific action with criminal intent that can legitimately be perceived as targeting another person’s computer. 12 Summary Now that the reality purported by the imagery of the demonic savage is to some extent shattered, Siegel’s typology of crime with some personal touches on definitional issues appears after all to be sufficient for the proposed level of analysis. In sum, for criminological theoretical explanations to apply to a certain type of crime, it must answer what factors impose an individual or group, in terms of… 1. Violent crimes, to either coerce another through the threat of physical injury or the induction of physical injury, lethal or otherwise. 2. Political crimes, to obtain a desire to affect a significant portion of society, including one or another of its institutions, and it involves as one of the elements of its intention a rejection of the legitimacy of calling the act a crime. 3. Property crimes, to deny others their material interests. 4. Enterprise crimes, to resonate in a specific action that results in the perversion of legal rules of commercial conduct for illegitimate purposes. 5. Public Order crimes, in order for the calculus, however faulty, of the individual or subgroup, to outweigh the calculus, again, however faulty, of society. 6. Cybercrimes, to resonate in a specific action to be conducted with criminal intent that targets another’s computer. The Levels of Criminogenic Agency Now that some clarity is present on the crime typology this paper wishes to purport, it is time to examine the levels of criminogenic agency. Although a brief content analysis of theoretical criminology textbooks reveals a body of theoretical knowledge organized in various ways, it is generally unclear in a prima facie glance, what types of crime these theories purport to explain. (Cf. Vold, et al., 1998; Curran & Renzetti, 2000; Cote, 2002; Akers & Sellers, 2008; Miller, et al., 2008; Cullen & Agnew, 2011) While it is true that some of these texts take a historical approach by presenting material in the order it was developed and some present material organized by school of thought, the correlation of the types of 13 crime these theories purport to explain at the phenomenological level at which factors orbit and exert their social facts to correlate an individual with a criminal act is not altogether clear. Take Curran & Renzetti’s Theories of Crime (2000) for example; it opens with a discussion of three paradigms (Cf. Kuhn, 1962) – the classical school, the positivist school, and the Marxist/radical school. Each of these schools of thought asserts some fundamental assumptions about human behavior: 1. Classical: “Human beings are rational hedonists; they seek out the greatest pleasure at the least cost to themselves.” (Curran & Renzetti, 2000: 24) 2. Positivist: “Human behavior is more or less determined by internal factors or external environmental factors. Human behavior is measurable/ quantifiable.” (Ibid.) 3. Marxist: “Humans are natural workers. The most basic human activity is laboring to meet one's survival needs. While humans are born into particular circumstances that shape their behavior, they are capable of acting back on and reshaping these conditions.” (Ibid.) Curran & Renzetti assert that “Positivists seek to discover the causes of crime, which may be biological, psychological, and/or social [compared to] Classicists [who] assume that human beings have free will and, therefore, are responsible for their behavior, including crime, [while] Neo-Classicists emphasize the importance of considering mitigating factors.” (2000: 25) While accepting the notion that paradigms are intended to be broad, this theoretical organization asserts some fundamental assumptions concerning human behavior that gives a reasonable person pause and thus cause to ask, “what is really going on here and where is here?” Given this, I propose an alternative somewhat integrated approach considering the age-old debate of human behavior. The problem of “free will” vs. “determinism” is known to go back millennia. The SAGE Dictionary of Criminology suggests defining the former as the “ability to choose a certain course of action against another” (Westmarland, 2006a: 177) while “determinism can be taken in the sense of inevitability: once the antecedents to an event are understood, so prediction of future similar events becomes possible.” 14 (Hollin, 2006a: 124) Given that the discussion of determinism goes on to state, “regardless of whether the antecedents are said to be inside the person or in the environment (or a combination of the two), human action is a function of its antecedent conditions” (Ibid) then from a rational standpoint, for the purposes of this discussion, free will can be considered ‘an antecedent condition,’ thus, merging classism, neo-classism and positivism to a certain degree. This taken together with my conception of signifying a factor as criminogenic4 suggests three levels of agency, the individual, environment and group where factors tends to correlate an individual with the setting of a criminal act. The Individual Level of Criminogenic Agency The individual level of criminogenic agency is derived from notions of classicism, neo-classicism, individual and sociological positivism. For the purposes of this paper, criminogenic factors are deterministic insofar as such factors tend to correlate an individual with the setting of a criminal act. At the individual level theoretical explanations tend to coalesce around four types of determinism. The individualistic determinism of the criminogenic character can be (a) rational, (b) biological, (c) psychological, (d) sociological, or a combination thereof. Rational Determinism Rational determinism is the coalescence of an inter-subjective view of rationality derived from classicism and neo-classicism. Louise Westmarland succinctly summarizes the role individual rationality plays in classicism: “Individualism and self-interest are placed at the forefront of explanations about why some people commit crime and how they should be punished. One of the first proponents of this 4 When a factor that tends to correlate an individual with the setting of a criminal act, the factor is considered to be criminogenic. When an individual possesses an aggregate of these factors, they are said to have the criminogenic character and are more likely to be found in a situation where the police would have to enforce the law than individuals without such a character. 15 approach was the Italian philosopher Cesare Beccaria, with his work on the right to punish and methods to prevent crime, first published in 1764. He argued that society should create laws that may infringe upon the personal liberty of a few, but result in the greater happiness of the majority. His approach to the prevention of crime was that the pain of punishment should be greater than the potential pleasure resulting from the act. Hence, the punishment should be proportionate to the harm it causes society.” (Westmarland, 2006b: 41; Cf. Vold, et al., 1998: 1421; Akers & Sellers, 2008: 17-19) Neo-classicism on the other hand posits “a revised version of classical theory that acknowledges individual and situational differences in motivation, rationality, and free will (that is, bounded free will).” (Curran & Renzetti, 2000: 27) More contemporary neo-classicists describe the rationality of offending in the misnomer of rational choice theory – the central thesis being that the “starting point [is] an assumption that offenders seek to benefit themselves by their criminal behavior; that this involves the making of decisions and choices, however rudimentary on occasion these processes might be; and that these processes exhibit a measure of rationality, albeit constrained by limits of time and ability and the availability of relevant information.” (Cornish & Clarke, 1986: 1; Cf. Akers & Sellers, 2008: 26-31) This thesis is distinct from classicism in that it does not assume people are equally rational – thus permitting other factors to coalesce in the rational determinism of criminal action. The intersubjectiveness of this rationality is clearer if this determinism is understood as a portion of individual criminogenic agency in combination with a bio-psycho-sociological determinism. Biological Determinism Biological determinism is largely a product of Cesare Lombroso’s work presented in the classic 1876 The Criminal Man (Cf. Lombroso-Ferrero, 2009) and from the work that followed. (Cf. Akers & Sellers, 2008: 48-52) According to Miller, et al., the significance of this is in that it “gave rise to attempts to scientifically explain and understand behavior. This should be expected; however, since several centuries ago people did not understand social influences on behavior or have very developed ways of thinking about psychology. What was available was the body and people's behaviors. So when 16 we wanted to better understand how and why certain people acted in certain ways, we looked at what was available for inspection: the body.” (2008: 56) While it is understandable at the time that theorists work with what they had, biological determinism, as the beginnings of individual positivism, now recognizes “that there are so many different characteristics of people, environments, and other influences that one quality of a person cannot and will not control his or her behavior. Today's theories that include biological components place these factors in a social context and emphasize that physical/biological factors may make it more or less likely that someone will act in particular ways.” (Ibid) The more recent work of Ellis and Walsh (Cf. 1997) and David Rowe (Cf. 2011) emphasize how chromosomal makeup, inherited traits, or internal chemical composition provide a predisposition towards various behaviors that is likely to be criminalized. (Cf. Vold, et al., 1998: 40-87; Akers & Sellers, 2008: 53-69) It is this biological predisposition that determines the degree of applicability of inter-subjective rationality as it interacts with possible socially situated triggers – and that is how biology is deterministic. Psychological Determinism Psychological determinism expands upon earlier notions of individual positivism found within biological determinism. “Psychologists working within positivist frameworks argue that there could be an individual explanation in terms of personality characteristics which might predispose some people to commit crime.” (Westmarland, 2006b: 41; Cf. Muncie, 2006a) While Akers & Sellers (2008: 71) note that there is a broad range of psychological theories of crime and deviant behavior (behavioral, neuropsychological, developmental et al.), other texts emphasize a psychoanalytic perspective (Valier, 2006: 320; Miller, et al. 2008) and personality theory (Cullen & Agnew, 2011) as the source of the criminogenic character. According to Clive Hollin, 17 “The core of personality theory lies in attempting to understand the behavioral variance that can be ascribed to factors internal to the person, as opposed to the effects of the environment. Thus, personality can be thought of as the stable structure and pattern of an individual's thoughts and feelings which, in turn, are related to distinctive styles of behavior. Personality theorists might look for basic dimensions, or types, of personality that can be ascribed to distinctive psychological factors such as beliefs or emotions.” (2006b: 293) Hollin goes on to suggest that the personality theory of Hans Eysenck (Cf. 1977) is essentially a control theory much like of psychoanalysis – as Miller, et al. writes “one way that psychoanalytic theory stands apart from most other theories is in its assumption that people are basically antisocial from the start. Most theories seek to explain why some people commit crime, which is thought of as the exception and the ‘different’ behavior.” (2008: 65) However, more recent psychological research conducted by Caspi, et al. across ‘countries, genders, races, and methods’ (1994) expands upon Eysenck’s work and argues that the presence of “super-traits” given the social environment are criminogenic because “individuals high in negative emotionality and low in constraint are more likely to interpret events as threatening and act on those impulses.” Cullen & Agnew (2011: 69) recognize the relationship of these super-traits to Gottfredson & Hirschi’s control theory, just like Hollin recognized Eysenck, but state that their concept is ‘too simple’ and single-dimensional. Caspi, et al. also mention how Gottfredson & Hirschi (1990) essentially ignore the advances in personality theory and assessment. Caspi, et al. justify this based on the methodological problems that occurred in a range of previous studies. From reviewing the paper, Personality and Crime: Are Some People Crime-Prone? resulting from their study, it appears these methodological problems were addressed. As such, these ‘super-traits’ cannot be ignored, at the very least, in the form of a psychological predisposition. And of course, it is this predisposition that determines the degree of applicability of inter-subjective rationality as it interacts with possible socially situated triggers – thus describing how psychology is deterministic. 18 Sociological Determinism Sociological determinism stems from the sociological positivism “first developed by philosophers such as Comte and Saint-Simon in the early nineteenth century. Comte's insistence that society both predates and shapes the individual psychologically provided the foundation for sociological criminology.” (Muncie, 2006b) What is sociological per se was explicated by Emile Durkheim in The Rules of the Sociological Method where he discusses the normality of crime as a social fact: “Since there cannot be a society in which the individuals do not differ more or less from the collective type, it is also inevitable that, among these divergences, there are some with a criminal character. What confers this character upon them is not the intrinsic quality of a given act but that definition which the collective conscience lends them. If the collective conscience is stronger, if it has enough authority practically to suppress these divergences, it will also be more sensitive, more exacting; and, reacting against the slightest deviations with the energy it otherwise displays only against more considerable infractions, it will attribute to them the same gravity as formerly to crimes. In other words, it will designate them as criminal.” (Durkheim, 1938: 70) These notions of the ‘collective consciousness’ were later taken up by Eviatar Zerubavel in his discussion of ‘thought communities’ in Social Mindscapes: An Invitation to Cognitive Sociology. (1999: 17-22) These thought communities lend themselves to a view of “cognitive sociology” where people think, and thus make decisions, “(a) as individuals, (b) as social beings, and (c) as human beings.” (Zerubavel, 1999: 5) This relies on a distinction between the subjective mind where the “individualistic” mind produces “the unmistakably non-universal mental ‘software’ we use when we think” and objective mind where the ‘universal,’ mind produces a remarkably detailed picture of how people are cognitively ‘hard wired.’” Thus, though “some aspects of our thinking are indeed either purely personal or absolutely universal, [the fact is that] many others are neither.” A synthesis of these two views arrives at an inter-subjective view of the mind. This entails the existence of an integrative social world that transcends both subjectivity and objectivity and “can therefore be commonly shared by entire thought communities.” Zerubavel argues that this explains the remarkably similar manner in which different 19 individuals actually perceive the world and classify its elements, focus their attention, reckon time, assign meaning, and remember thoughts or experiences. (Zerubavel, 1999: 3) It is with this intersubjective view of the mind that adds clarity to the rational determinism I have proposed. It also follows from this in that the individual level of criminogenic agency acts upon a social being and it is here that one arrives at the need for a ‘cognitive sociology’ that is also phenomenological. In describing the faults of the individually subjective view of the mind to justify such a form of sociology, Zerubavel summarizes cognitive individualism as the “general vision of thinking on the image of a solitary thinker whose thoughts are a product of his or her own unique personal experience and idiosyncratic outlook on the world. In fact, if scientists were to study idiosyncratic thought patterns that apply only to particular individuals, we probably would not even consider their findings ‘scientific.’” (1999: 2) Describing the limitations of the objective view of the mind, Zerubavel writes: “Cognitive universalism is clearly the dominant vision of the mind in modern cognitive science, much of which revolves around the search for the universal foundations of human cognition. Even psychologists, philosophers, linguists, and students of artificial intelligence who do not study the brain itself nonetheless claim to explore the way humans think. As evident from their general indifference to their research subjects’ biographical background, most cognitive scientists today assume a universal, human mind. It is certainly such universalistic sensitivity that allows cognitive scientists to unravel the universal foundations of human cognition. It is precisely their concern with our cognitive commonality that has helped neuroscientists, psychologists, linguists, and students of artificial intelligence to discover universal patterns in the way we form concepts, process information, activate mental ‘schemas,’ make decisions, solve problems, generate meaningful sentences from "deep" syntactic structures, access our memory, and move through the various stages of our cognitive development. Yet it is precisely this commitment to cognitive universalism that is also responsible for what is probably cognitive science’s most serious limitation. While it certainly helps cognitive scientists produce a remarkably detailed picture of how we are cognitively ‘hard wired,’ it also prevents them from addressing the unmistakably non-universal mental ‘software’ we use when we think.” (1999: 3) It is with this unmistakably non-universal mental ‘software’ that rational bio-psychological determinism acts upon. Unlike classicism, naturalistic decision-making is not conducted by the non-social thinker but by the social thinker, and that this is true about situations, like chess and when crimes are committed 20 that seem on the surface to be technical and radically individualized. The ‘social thinker’ is a ‘social being’ whose, “Inter-subjective, social world is quite distinct from the subjective world of the individual as well as from the objective world of nature and logic. It is a world where time is reckoned according to neither the sun or the moon nor our own inner sense of duration but rather, in accordance with standard, conventional time-reckoning systems such as clock time and the calendar. It is a world where the conventional categories into which we force different ‘types’ of books, films, and music are based on neither our own personal sensations nor any objective logical necessity. Such a world, of course, constitutes the distinctive domain of the sociology of the mind. The epistemological effort to refrain from attributing objectivity to that which is only inter-subjective has some important methodological implications. Since the social world is regarded as natural only by those who happen to inhabit it and therefore take it for granted, the more we can gain access to social worlds that are different from the one we have come to regard as a given the more we will be able to recognize the social nature of both. Thus, in marked contrast to the tendency among most psychologists, philosophers, linguists, and neuroscientists today to focus on our cognitive commonality as human beings, cognitive sociology tries to promote greater awareness of our cognitive diversity as social beings. The more we become aware of our cognitive differences as members of different thought communities, the less likely we are to follow the common ethnocentric tendency to regard the particular way in which we ourselves happen to process the world in our minds as based on some absolute standard of “logic” or “reason” and, thus, as naturally or logically inevitable.” (Zerubavel, 1999: 9-10) This unmistakably non-universal mental ‘software’ is programmed by others within even the simplest conversational encounter. Goffman eloquently describes the obligations co-participants have to each other: “Thus, as Adam Smith argued in his Theory of the Moral Sentiments, the individual must phrase his own concerns and feelings and interests in such a way as to make these maximally usable by the others as a source of appropriate involvement; and this major obligation of the individual qua interactant is balanced by his right to expect that others present will make some effort to stir up their sympathies and place them at his command. These two tendencies, that of the speaker to scale down his expressions and that of the listeners to scale up their interests, each in the light of the other's capacities and demands, form the bridge that people build to one another, allowing them to meet for a moment of talk in a communion of reciprocally sustained involvement. It is this spark, not the more obvious kinds of love, that lights up the world.” (Goffman, 1967: 116117) 21 These obligations constitute the self-regulation of the interaction ritual (Goffman, 1967: 44-45) and are dependent on two conditions: (1) the imputation of sincerity to the other and a corresponding willingness to be vulnerable on the part of each party; (2) meaning as an ongoing accomplishment. (C.f. Garfinkel, 1967: 11) The social thinker who partakes in the interaction ritual is a description of how individuals react to each other – beginning with those immediate present and how that presence lingers after the end of the encounter and it is from here that the social bonds begin to form. Travis Hirschi’s Causes of Delinquency integrated earlier varieties of social control theories (Cf. Nye, 1958; Reckless, 1955; Reiss, 1951; Toby, 1957) and asserted that social bonds are a means by restraint is imposed on each other, stating that “delinquent acts result when an individual's bond to society is weak or broken.” (1969: 18) Hirschi posited the elements of the bond consisted of attachment, commitment, involvement and belief and was provided with at least 25 subsequent years of empirical support. (Miller, et al., 159) Yet, some 20 years later, Gottfredson & Hirschi (1990) expressed a revised position on Hirschi’s part. They define crime as “acts of force or fraud undertaken in pursuit of selfinterest” (1990:15) and are subsequently a result of a person with low self-control. Sampson and Laub (1993) suggest that stability and change characterize the lives of people which place people on a life course trajectory. The departure/development from Hirshi is that the “nature and strength of social bonds changed over the life course” (Miller, et al. 2008: 166) and that the degree of self-control possible varies throughout the life course. These things taken together – the social thinker within the interaction ritual who develops social bonds and various degrees of self-control throughout the life course – with Durkhiem’s theory of anomie, “human activity aspires beyond assignable limits and sets itself 22 unattainable goals” (1897: 241) where too many social facts exert pressure and this pressure5 is criminogenic – and that is how sociology is deterministic at the individual level of criminogenic agency. The Environmental Level of Criminogenic Agency The environmental level of criminogenic agency is derived primarily from notions of sociological positivism found within the Chicago School of Sociology. “Renowned for establishing links between environmental factors and crime,” (Hayward, 2006: 37) the Chicago School’s line of enquiry began with Robert Park's ‘theory of human ecology’ (Park, et al., 1925) where portions of Park’s theory later developed into Social Disorganization Theory (Shaw and McKay, 1942). Miller, et al. generously summarizes this perspective along with Routine Activities Theory: “Theories that focus on the social ecology of crime offer something different from many of the theories of crime that we have discussed so far. Rather than looking at how offenders differ from non-offenders, these theories instead give attention to how situations or places with high levels of crime differ from those with little crime. Social disorganization theory claims that disorganization undermines ties and institutions within a community, thus making it impossible for residents to work collectively to deal with crime problems in the area. Routine activities theory gives its attention to the immediate situation where crime occurs, namely, situations where motivated offenders are in proximity to poorly guarded suitable targets. Both theories have received support in the empirical literature, and both at present are the focus of extensive attention from criminologists. Another common theme for these theories is that neither proposes the rehabilitation of people to prevent future crime from occurring, but they instead suggest that best results might be obtained from changing the situation or the context.” (2008: 106; Cf. Cohen and Felson, 1979) Environmental Determinism Environmental determinism is largely derived from Park’s human ecological theory and its subsequent research like that of social disorganization theory. In order to avoid becoming a misnomer, by Robert Merton later revived Durkheim’s concept in 1938. While Durkheim conceived of anomie as a problematic social condition resulting from sudden and rapid social change, Merton saw it as an endemic feature of the everyday operation of certain types of societies. (Curran & Renzetti, 2000: 114) This strain resulting from the pressure later developed into Strain Theory and subsequently Agnew’s General Strain Theory. 5 23 ‘environment’ it is meant the immediate physical space in which a community resides and that communities are generally qualified by neighborhood locales. This is suggested largely by the body of work of Robert J. Sampson. In these locales, there is a possibility for what Sampson calls ‘collective efficacy’ which is defined as social cohesion among neighbors combined with their willingness to intervene in each other’s social encounters on behalf of the common good. (Sampson & Wilson, 1995; Sampson, et al., 1997) His research suggests that the lack of this factor, rather than its presence, is criminogenic. Furthermore, “human ecological theory facilitates an investigation into the way in which social structure produces this convergence, hence allowing illegal activities to feed upon the legal activities of everyday life.” (Cohen and Felson, 1979: 1) It is in this way that routine activities permit the environment to present ‘poorly guarded suitable targets’ and Cohen and Felson suggest these targets particularly criminogenic if a motivated offender comes across it. The work of James Q. Wilson suggests that the phenomena of ‘broken windows’ in a neighborhood environment are criminogenic and suggests in Varieties of Police Behavior that police need to perform “order maintenance”. (1978: 16) For several fundamental semiotic and sociological reasons, this is wrong because each of these signs in “order maintenance” have implicit within them arguments about the nature of social order. Garfinkel suggests (C.f. 2002: 22-25) that the nature of social order should be the primary study of sociology and he takes this discussion very seriously. In that tradition, from readings of both Goffman and Garfinkel, the concept of disorder is not only foreign but not useful and distracting from matter at hand. Wilson’s conception of “order maintenance” suggests that there is a threshold from which, when crossed, the arrangement of orderly things becomes disarrayed and can be restored. Perhaps, within frameworks of mathematical hierarchies this conception may be enlightening, since for the necessity of arithmetic, the arrangement of numbers, thus their signifieds, is fundamental 24 for numbers to have meaning. Yet, for social science, and the study of criminal justice, given that the arrangements of the events of history as occurred (and not written) cannot be changed, only re-written, social occurrences and social facts are arranged in an array that is constantly changing much like that of a game of chess in progress. After all, a game of chess can be examined at any given point yet reflects history and the potential for the future. Occurrences happen within this array over an X period of time and because time moves on, whether a second, minute or a week, some of these occurrences are discovered by others (i.e. the police) who then attempt to incorporate each occurrence (i.e. a crime and the resulting investigation) into their own biography. Perhaps, a given discovery is the result of patrolling or a call for service, yet there is nothing ‘maintaining’ about it. The common apology, “I know what I did was wrong, and if I could go back and change it, I would…” is beneficial to the merits of this case. Relationships may be able to be fixed or mended but the actual arrangement of events cannot be changed, only re-written. Any subsequent action occurring from patrolling social order merely sustains the order itself; it reconstitutes it only insofar as by every second, as the world turns, more events occur. Men and women act and the source of that action is at issue for many disciplines; whether that act is considered criminal, as Durkheim suggests, is conferred by the collective consciousness, but there is nothing intrinsic to the act itself that makes it criminal. (Durkheim, 1938: 70) Therefore, the nature of social order is constituted by the arrangement of men, women and children, with their actions and their biographies, some intertwined, some not aligned, but all arranged within their own respective space and time. It is the relationship among these factors that is the social – how all these beings are interdependent, for the appearance of no relationship is a relationship itself: every being exists in time and space and that relationship alone is enough to be arranged within social order. Any remedy taken would be analogous to the function of tort law, a treatment of some wrong-doing after the fact – merely 25 providing some form of compensation as a means to attempt ‘cooling the mark out’. (C.f. Goffman, 1952) 6 In sum, this paper theorizes that the environment is deterministic to the extent that this nature of social order, taken together with the described social ecology, provides the medium for the factors orbiting the individual level to be triggered so that they may express their agency in the form of criminal action. The Group Level of Criminogenic Agency The group level of criminogenic agency is derived from notions of sociological positivism much like the notions operating at the environmental level. At the group level, theoretical explanations tend to coalesce around a hierarchy four sub-levels of sociological determinism. This sociological determinism lies within the social structure of the group and its respective size producing the criminogenic character at either, (a) intimate personal groups, (b) subcultures, (c) institutions, (d) society, or a combination thereof where the influence of such factors vary by their degree of proximity among the sub-levels themselves (i.e. factors operating at level a and b are going to exert more influence than a and d). Sociological Determinism at the Sub-Level of Intimate Personal Groups The sociological determinism operating at the level of intimate personal groups is predicated upon how meaning is established and shared at basic levels of social interaction. (Cf. Goffman, 1967; Zerubavel, 1999) In criminology, this is taken to be the underpinnings of Sutherland's theory of differential association. First published in 1939, this is a statement of how normative conflict, in which crime is The idea of restitution is crucial to Durkheim’s distinction between criminal and civil law, and it implies a sense of a greater distinction than may be warranted. Thus, in civil law, order is restored because the victim of the tort or a violation of a contract is compensated and thereby put back in their original condition. But it is clear that “restitution,” which assumes that compensation is sufficient to reverse time (restore a prior order), is not satisfactorily exemplified by compensation. The latter effectively buys off the complainant, it does not restore order. The fact that the tort occurred is itself a harm, or aspect of harm, for which there is no remedy in the civil law any more than the victim of a crime can be put back, as it were, “whole.” 6 26 rooted, produces criminality in some individuals and not in others. (Sutherland, 1939: 1-9; Cf. Cressey, 1979) Sutherland emphasized within socialization, the process through which the interaction ritual is learned, two basic factors – agency and content. With ‘agents’ acting as the ‘whom’ and ‘content’ acting as the ‘what’, Sutherland formalized his theory into nine propositions with the 1st, 5th and 6th being of the greatest import: 1st Proposition: “Criminal behavior is learned.” (Sutherland, 1939) 5th Proposition: “The specific direction of motives and drives is learned from definitions of legal codes as favorable and unfavorable.” (Ibid) 6th Proposition: “A person becomes a delinquent because of an excess of definitions favorable to violation of law over definitions unfavorable to violation of law.” (Ibid) For Sutherland, intimate personal groups are the primary agents of socialization (3rd Proposition; Ibid) and when the ‘content’ learned consists of techniques of committing the crime, which are sometimes very complicated and sometimes very simple, and the specific direction of motives, rationalizations, and attitudes (4th Proposition; Ibid), those within an individual’s intimate personal group are going to assist that individual in becoming correlated with the setting a criminal act. The main criticism of Sutherland’s theory is the ‘how’ the ‘who’ teach the ‘what’. Ronald Akers set out to address this with his Social Learning Theory. The theory “offers an explanation of crime and deviance that embraces variables that operate both to motivate and control criminal behavior, both to promote and undermine conformity. … The probability of criminal or conforming behavior occurring is a function of the balance of these influences on behavior operative in one’s learning history, at a given time or in a given situation” (Akers & Sellers, 2008: 89-90) relying on differential association, 27 definitions, differential reinforcement and imitation as the operative variables in which an individual is correlated with the setting a criminal act. Therefore, with Sutherland and Akers taken together, intimate personal groups are sociologically deterministic to the extent that intimate personal groups provide the opportunity for individuals to learn the interaction ritual required for violating the law. Sociological Determinism at the Sub-Level of Subcultures The sociological determinism operating at the level of subcultures is predicated upon how the role of image, style, representation and meaning is organized around symbolic communication, shared aesthetics and collective identity (Ferrell, 2006: 104) that tend to repudiate societal standards (Miller et al., 2008: 127) as an ongoing social accomplishment where the membership of this social group has permanence, closure, and common pursuits that condone, promote, or otherwise make possible the commission of delinquent acts. (Rock, 202: 73) Criminologically, this rose as a critique of Merton’s strain theory and is swiftly summarized by Curran & Renzetti: “Albert Cohen (1955) criticized Merton for making it appear as if individuals' reactions to strain are uninfluenced by their interactions with other people around them. Cohen also took exception to Merton's depiction of criminal (innovative) behavior as a rational means to a desired end or goal, that is, as utilitarian. While this may be the case for some types of crime, Cohen argued, it does not apply to most of the activities of delinquent gangs that are concentrated in lower-class neighborhoods.” (2000: 118) Miller, et al. (2008) traces the rise, demise, and re-rise of the subcultural perspective from the 1950s to the 1990s where they arrive at the foremost contemporary statement on subculture and crime, Elijah Anderson’s work, Code of the Street. (1999) This ‘code’ is seen a subculture of honor where requisite retaliatory and defensive violence for protection and defense of social status threats and personal insults occurs is contextually based in family and immediate group interaction. (2008:123-128) 28 Based on these considerations, subcultures are sociologically deterministic to the extent that an individual’s membership requires the tendency to repudiate societal standards and assume a collective identity sustained through honor and physical aggression. This means that if that ‘honor’ is perceived to be ‘lost’ by a member of the collective identity, it can only be re-gained by correlating an individual with an opportunity to use physical aggression to win back the honor lost. Sociological Determinism at the Sub-Level of Institutions The sociological determinism operating at the level of institutions within the United States coalesce around two manifestations: institutional anomie and systematic labeling. Institutional Anomie Messner & Rosenfeld (2001) discuss how institutional anomie is sociologically deterministic in their book, Crime and the American Dream. As an extension of the work of Durkheim, Merton, and Marx, Messner & Rosenfeld seek to “rethink some basic assumptions and interpretations of anomie theory” (Ibid: x) by identifying the “anomic tendencies of the American Dream and show how these tendencies are both reflected and reproduced by an institutional structure dominated by the economy.” (Ibid: xi) Their analysis focuses on four social institutions—the economy, the political system, the family, and the educational system and recognizes that in the United States, there is an “inability of other social institutions to tame economic imperatives [meaning that the …] institutional balance of power is tilted toward the economy. (Ibid: 68) They substantiate this claim by identifying three symptoms of economic dominance – “the devaluation of noneconomic institutional functions and roles, the accommodation to economic requirements by other institutions, and penetration of economic norms into other institutional domains.” (Ibid: 70) While this supports the existence of institutional anomie, this has yet to present the case how it is sociologically deterministic. This case is made in the synthesis of two separate passages: 29 “As a result of this economic dominance, the inherent tendencies of a capitalist economy to orient the members of society toward an unrestrained pursuit of economic achievements are developed to an extreme degree. These tendencies are expressed at the cultural level in the preeminence of the competitive, individualistic pursuit of monetary success as the overriding goal—the American Dream—and in the relative de-emphasis placed on the importance of using normative means to reach this goal—anomie. The anomie nature of the American Dream and the institutional structure of American society are thus mutually supportive and reinforcing.” (Ibid: 76) The strength of capitalism lies, then, in the very fact of its support for anomie. But this implies that the institutions which are increasingly capitalist are also increasingly weak. “Hence, the very sociocultural dynamics that make American institutions weak also enable and entitle Americans to defy institutional controls. If Americans are exceptionally resistant to social control—and therefore exceptionally vulnerable to criminal temptations—the resistance occurs because they live in a society that enshrines the unfettered pursuit of individual material success above all other values. In the United States, anomie is considered a virtue.” (Ibid: 79) It is here that Messner & Rosenfeld’s claim shines – when the institutional balance of power is tilted toward the economy and anomie ensues to the extent that the individual experiences a lack of control at the level of institutional relationships parallels and complements the lack of control at the cultural level of social norms. This invites the individual to becoming correlated with the setting of a criminal act in pursuit of material success above all else. Systematic Labeling At the institutional level, systematic labeling is characterized by “media, public, political and criminal justice responses to crime and deviancy. These responses often stereotype, stigmatize, label, criminalize, scapegoat and/or amplify the behaviors of certain individuals and groups.” (Duncan, 2006: 407) Lemert (1951) undertook a study of sociopathic behavior and systematically analyzed the societal responses to deviation. His book, Social Pathology: A Systematic Approach to the Theory of Sociopathic Behavior asserts that social control created deviance: “Distinguishing between original causes and effective causes, he argued that there were many original causes of initial or 'primary' deviance, but that importantly this deviance was of little consequence to one's self-concept. Societal reaction, however, was seen as the effective cause of 'secondary' deviance, whereby an individual used their deviant behavior or status to defend, 30 attack or adjust to the problems created by societal responses to primary deviance. Lemert suggested that responses to deviation ranged from strong approval to indifference to strong disapproval, but that sociopathic behavior was that which was effectively disapproved. Furthermore, one's deviant identity was shaped by the level of deviation engaged in, its social visibility, and the exposure, nature and strength of societal reaction. Recognizing both formal and informal responses to crime and deviance, he argued that formal agents of social control extended and formalized informal responses.” (Duncan, 2006: 407) Bemburg, et al. (2006: 22) provides some recent empirical verification of Lemert’s theory. Their examination analyzes “the short-term impact of formal criminal labeling on involvement in deviant social networks and increased likelihood of subsequent delinquency. According to labeling theory, formal criminal intervention should affect the individual’s immediate social networks. In many cases, the stigma of the criminal status may increase the probability that the individual becomes involved in deviant social groups. The formal label may thus ultimately increase involvement in subsequent deviance. … Using measures from three successive points in time, the [study found] that juvenile justice intervention positively affects subsequent involvement in serious delinquency through the medium of involvement in deviant social groups, namely, street gangs and delinquent peers.” The idea of the self-fulfilling prophecy is useful here – for example, a person accidentally commits vehicular manslaughter and is sent to prison, where, for better or for worse, he is forced to associate with ‘criminals’ on a constant basis. Given that the crime this person is incarcerated for was an accident, it is possible that this person never consciously considered breaking the law. This person gets out of prison with a record and is forced to check the box on job applications concerning criminal offenses and it subsequently turned down. Just like the blockbuster movie, Inception, the stigmatization of being a convicted ‘criminal’ ‘plants’ the idea in the person’s mind that they are a criminal and as Goffman (1967: 117) would suggest, “in the light of the other's capacities and demands” that person might try to live up to those expectations. (Goffman, 1963: 27-31, 58) 31 With these considerations in hand, where people are labeled by criminal justice institutions, are stigmatized, develop criminal identities, and are sent to prison, systematic labeling at the institutional level is sociologically deterministic to the extent that societal reaction to an individual’s previous actions excludes that individual from conventional, and likely legitimate, means of providing for oneself, leading the individual little choice but to live up to the societal label provided. The Institutional Manifestation A fractal is a geometric pattern that is repeated at every scale and are typically wondrous to the to the mind’s eye – just like how social scientists look at groups of individuals and zoom out. This analogy is helpful here – since the degree of proximity among the sub-levels can represent the geometric pattern at the scale of c within the geometric pattern at the scale of b within the same (but perceptually larger) geometric pattern at the scale of a. C being the most proximate to the individual is going to exert more determinism than that at scale a since as the degree of proximity zooms out, the less criminogenic agency is based on inter-subjective rationality and individual bio-psycho-sociological predisposition and the more criminogenic agency exerts influences that correlate the individual with the setting of a criminal act (1) in pursuit of material success above all else, as Rosenfeld & Messner suggest, or (2) because societal reaction to an individual’s previous actions excludes that individual from conventional, and likely legitimate, means of providing for oneself, leading the individual little choice but to live up to the societal label provided as Lemert suggests – and that is how institutions are sociologically deterministic. Sociological Determinism at the Sub-Level of Society The sociological determinism operating at the level of society is predicated upon how inequality in power and material well-being creates conditions of vast inequality that impoverishes many – and here 32 is where the fractal analogy is most useful as it is time to examine the pattern at its largest scale. For it is only natural for an individual to hear the statement, “Society causes crime” and dismiss it out right because how would it not sound ridiculous to the layperson’s ear? Yet, as critical criminology suggests, (Cf. Vold, et al., 1998: 260-283) there is some merit to the case found within the work of Williem Bonger. Ian R. Taylor, et al. (1973) in their discussion of Marx, Engles and Bonger on Crime and Social Control take on the task of contrasting Bonger’s foundational work, Criminality and Economic Conditions (1916) with formal Marxism, writing that, “Bonger’s criminology is an attempt to utilize some of the formal concepts of Marxism in the understanding of the crime-rates of European capitalism in the late nineteenth and early twentieth centuries. Importantly, however, Bonger’s efforts appear, for us, not so much the application of a fully-fledged Marxist theory as they are a recitation of a ‘Marxist catechism’ in an area which Marx had left largely untouched—a recitation prompted by the growth not of the theory itself, but by the growth of a sociological pragmatism. Bonger must, therefore, be evaluated in his own terms, in terms of the competence of his extension of the formal concepts of Marxism to the subject-matter, rather than in terms of any claim that might be made for him as the Marxist criminologist. In at least two respects, Bonger’s analysis of crime differs in substance from that of Marx. On the one hand, Bonger is clearly very much more seriously concerned than Marx with the causal chain linking crime with the precipitating economic and social conditions. On the other, he does not confine his explanations to working-class crime, extending his discussions to the criminal activity of the industrial bourgeoisie as defined by the criminal laws of his time. Whilst differing from Marx in these respects, however, Bonger is at one with his mentor in attributing the activity itself to demoralized individuals, products of a dominant capitalism. Indeed, in both Marx and Bonger, one is aware of a curious contradiction between the ‘image of man’ advanced as the anthropological underpinning of ‘orthodox’ Marxism and the questions asked about men who deviate.” Now that it is clear that Bonger himself, and not Marx, should be the subject of consideration, Bonger frames and answers the problem as follows: “The period of civilization during which the social modification mentioned above has taken place is generally lauded to the skies, as compared with preceding epochs. In certain relations this is justifiable. Technique has made immense progress during the last phase of civilization, capitalism; the power of man over nature has advanced greatly; the productivity of labor has 33 been so increased that one class of men, exempted by this from permanent care for their daily bread, are able to devote themselves to the arts and sciences. All this is indisputable. But the development of the arts and sciences and of technique has only an indirect importance for the etiology of crime. The question first of all to be asked is this: What influence has this modification in the economic and social structure had upon the character of man? And the answer to this question can only be the following: this modification has engendered cupidity and ambition, has made man less sensitive to the happiness and misery of his fellows, and has decreased the influence exercised upon men’s acts by the opinions of others. In short, it has developed egoism at the expense of altruism.” (1916: 401) Therefore, society is sociologically deterministic to the extent that the structure of social life, framed by the tendency of industrial capitalism, produces social facts of ‘egoism’ rather than social facts of ‘altruism’ that coerce the individual into correlating with the setting of a criminal act. New Directions for Criminological Theory Given that crime is still rampant throughout society, and always will be, thanks to Durkheim, laws change and subsequently change what is considered criminal behavior; the strength of theoretical explanations of crime will wax and wane. Yet theoretical organization changes at a much slower pace and has less re-organization than the roster of the United States Senate. Here, this paper presents the case for a theoretical re-organization that identifies six categories of crime and three phenomenological levels of agency around which criminogenic factors tend to coalesce. This identification produces a new framework to reconsider the relationships among theoretical explanations and the social facts they purport to organize. This grants provisions for possible integrative theoretical progress given the new clarity revealed on types of crime and the integrative approach of classicism and neo-classicism, thus unveiling a correlative determinism that is not absolute but perhaps enough grounds for some reconsideration in public policy given the social thinker. 34 Bibliography Akers, R.L., and C.S. Sellers. 2008. Criminological Theories: Introduction, Evaluation, and Application. New York: Oxford University Press. Anderson, Elijah. 1999. Code of the Street: Delinquency, Violence and the Moral Life of the Inner City. New York: Norton. Bakaoukas, Michael. 2005. "The Conceptualisation of 'Crime' in Classical Greek Antiquity." European and International Research Group on Crime, Social Philosophy and Ethics. Barrett, N. 1997. Digital crime: policing the cybernation: Kogan Page. Bernburg, J.G., M.D. Krohn, and C.J. Rivera. 2006. "Official Labeling, Criminal Embeddedness, and Subsequent Delinquency: A Longitudinal Test of Labeling Theory." Journal of Research in Crime and Delinquency 43(1):22. Bernburg, J.G., M.D. Krohn, and C.J. Rivera. 2006. "Official Labeling, Criminal Embeddedness, and Subsequent Delinquency: A Longitudinal Test of Labeling Theory." Journal of Research in Crime and Delinquency 43(1):22. Brenner, S.W. 2007. Law in an era of "smart" technology: Oxford University Press. Brenner, S.W. 2010. Cybercrime: Criminal Threats From Cyberspace: Praeger. Caspi, A., T.E. Moffitt, P.A. Silva, M. Stouthamer-Loeber, Robert F. Krueger, and P.S. Schmutte. 1994. "Personality and Crime: Are Some People Crime-Prone? Replications of the Personality-Crime Relationship across Countries, Genders, Races, and Methods." Criminology 32:163. Clinard, M.B., R. Quinney, and J. Wildeman. 1994 [1967]. Criminal Behavior Systems: A Typology: Anderson Pub. Co. Cohen, A.K. 1955. Delinquent Boys: The Culture of the Gang. New York: The Free Press. Cohen, L.E., and M. Felson. 1979. "Social change and crime rate trends: A routine activity approach." American Sociological Review:588-608. Conwell, C., and E.H. Sutherland. 1956. The professional thief: by a professional thief: University of Chicago Press. Cornish, D.B., and R.V.G. Clarke. 1986. "Introduction." Pp. 1-16 in The Reasoning Criminal: Rational Choice Perspectives on Offending, edited by D.B. Cornish and R.V.G Clarke. New York: Springer-Verlag. Cote, S. 2002. Criminological theories: bridging the past to the future: Sage Publications. 35 Cressey, Donald R. 1979. "Fifty Years of Criminology: From Sociological Theory to Political Control." The Pacific Sociological Review 22(4):457-80. Cross, M., and D.L. Shinder. 2008. Scene of the Cybercrime: Syngress Pub. Cullen, F.T., and R. Agnew. 2011. Criminological Theory: Past to Present : Essential Readings: Oxford University Press. Curran, D.J., and C.M. Renzetti. 2000. Theories of Crime. Boston: Allyn and Bacon. Duncan, Anna. 2006. "Social Reaction." Pp. 407-08 in The Sage Dictionary of Criminology, edited by E. McLaughlin and J. Muncie. Thousand Oaks: SAGE. Durkheim, Emile. 1897. Suicide: A Study in Sociology: The Free Press. Durkheim, E. 1938. The Rules of Sociological Method: Transaction Publishers. Ellis, L., and A. Walsh. 1997. "Gene-Based Evolutionary Theories in Criminology." Criminology 35:229. Eysenck, H.J. 1977. Crime and Personality: Routledge & K. Paul. Felson, M. 2006. Crime and Nature: Sage Publications. Ferrell, Jeff. 2006. "Cultural Criminology." Pp. 103-06 in The Sage Dictionary of Criminology, edited by E. McLaughlin and J. Muncie. Thousand Oaks: SAGE. Foucault, M. 1977. Discipline & Punish: Knopf Doubleday Publishing Group. Friedrichs, D. 2004. "White Collar Crime in a Globalized World." Presentation at Western Michigan University. Garfinkel, H. 1967. Studies in Ethnomethodology: Prentice-Hall. Garfinkel, H. 2002. Ethnomethodology's Program: Working out Durkeim's Aphorism: Rowman & Littlefield Pub Inc. Garland, N.M., and N. Garland. 2008. Criminal Law for the Criminal Justice Professional: McGrawHill. Geis, G. 2007. White-collar and corporate crime: Pearson Prentice Hall. Gill, Peter. 2006. "Organized Crime." in The Sage Dictionary of Criminology, edited by E. McLaughlin and J. Muncie. Thousand Oaks: SAGE. Goffman, E. 1952. "On Cooling the Mark Out: Some Aspects of Adaptation to Failure." Psychiatry 15(4):451. Goffman, Erving M. 1963. Stigma: Notes on the Management of Spoiled Identity. Englewood Cliffs, New Jersey: Prentice-Hall. 36 Goffman, Erving M. 1967. Interaction Ritual: Essays on Face-to-Face Behavior. New York: Doubleday Anchor. Gottfredson, M.R., and T. Hirschi. 1990. A General Theory of Crime: Stanford University Press. Hagan, F.E. 2009. Crime Types and Criminals: Sage Publications. Hallsworth, S. 2005. Street Crime: Willan. Hayward, Keith. 2006. "Chicago School of Sociology." in The Sage Dictionary of Criminology, edited by E. McLaughlin and J. Muncie. Thousand Oaks: SAGE. Heilbrun, Alfred B. 1979. "Psychopathy and Violent Crime." Journal of Consulting and Clinical Psychology 47(3):509-16. Hepburn, John R. 1984. "Occasional Property Crime." in Major Forms of Crime, edited by R.F. Meier. Beverly Hills: Sage Publications. Hillyard, Paddy. 2006. "Political Crime." in The Sage Dictionary of Criminology, edited by E. McLaughlin and J. Muncie. Thousand Oaks: SAGE. Hirschi, T. 1969. Causes of Delinquency. Berkeley: University of California Press. Hollin, Clive. 2006a. "Determinism." in The Sage Dictionary of Criminology, edited by E. McLaughlin and J. Muncie. Thousand Oaks: SAGE. Hollin, Clive. 2006b. "Personality Theory." in The Sage Dictionary of Criminology, edited by E. McLaughlin and J. Muncie. Thousand Oaks: SAGE. Inciardi, James A. 1984. "Professional Theft." in Major Forms of Crime, edited by R.F. Meier. Beverly Hills: Sage Publications. Ingraham, B.L. 1979. Political Crime in Europe: A Comparative Study of France, Germany, and England. Berkeley: University of California Press. Jewke, Yvonne. 2006. "Cyber Crime." in The Sage Dictionary of Criminology, edited by E. McLaughlin and J. Muncie. Thousand Oaks: SAGE. Jolson, Jeffrey. 2011. "Black Hat: Hackers Can Now Kill People Remotely." Las Vegas: Hollywood Today. Klein, E. 1971. "crime." in A Comprehensive Etymological Dictionary of the English language: Dealing with the Origin of Words and their Sense Development thus Illustrating the History of Civilization and Culture: Elsevier Pub. Co. Knox, G.W. 1993. An Introduction to Gangs: Vande Vere Pub. 37 Kuhn, Thomas S. 1962. The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press. Lemert, E.M. 1951. Social Pathology: A Systematic Approach to the Theory of Sociopathic Behavior. New York: McGraw-Hill. Leonard, Carl. 2011a. "The Cybercrime ‘Five’: Are all hackers the same?". San Diego: Websense, Inc. Leonard, Carl. 2011b. "The Cybercrime ‘Five’ Part Two: Hacktivist." San Diego: Websense, Inc. Levi, Michael. 2002. "The Organization of Serious Crimes." Pp. 878-913 in The Oxford Handbook of Criminology, edited by M. Maguire, R. Morgan, and R. Reiner. New York: Oxford University Press. Lombroso-Ferrero, Gina. 2009. "Criminal Man: According to the Classification of Cesare Lombroso." Project Gutenberg: http://www.gutenberg.org/files/29895/29895-h/29895-h.htm. Luckenbill, David F. 1984. "Murder and Assult." in Major Forms of Crime, edited by R.F. Meier: Sage Publications. Manning, Peter K. 2010. Democratic Policing in a Changing World. Boulder, CO: Paradigm Publishers. McLaughlin, E., and J. Muncie. 2006. The Sage Dictionary of Criminology. Thousand Oaks: SAGE. Meier, R.F. 1984. Major Forms of Crime: Sage Publications. Miller, J.M., C.J. Schreck, and R. Tewksbury. 2008. Criminological Theory: A Brief Introduction. Boston: Allyn & Bacon, Inc. Muncie, John. 2006a. "Individual Positivism." Pp. 214-16 in The Sage Dictionary of Criminology, edited by E. McLaughlin and J. Muncie. Thousand Oaks: SAGE. Muncie, John. 2006b. "Sociological Positivism." Pp. 410-12 in The Sage Dictionary of Criminology, edited by E. McLaughlin and J. Muncie. Thousand Oaks: SAGE. Nye, F. I. 1958. Family Relationships and Delinquent Behavior. New York: Wiley. Park, R.E., E.W. Burgess, and R.D. McKenzie. 1925. The City. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press. Pfohl, S.J. 2009. Images of Deviance & Social Control: A Sociological History: Waveland Pr Inc. Reckless, W. 1955. The Crime Problem. New York: Appleton-Century Crofts. Reiss, A. J. 1951. "Delinquency as the Failure of Personal and Social Controls." American Sociological Review 16:196-207. Robertson, I. 1988. Society: A Brief Introduction: Worth Publishers. 38 Rock, Paul. 2002. "Sociological Theories of Crime." Pp. 51-82 in The Oxford Handbook of Criminology, edited by M. Maguire, R. Morgan, and R. Reiner. New York: Oxford University Press. Roebuck, J.B. 1967. Criminal Typology: The Legalistic, Physical-Constitutional-Hereditary, Psychological-Psychiatric, and Sociological Approaches: C. C. Thomas. Rothe, D. 2009. State Criminality: the Crime of All Crimes. Lanham: Lexington Books. Rowe, D. 2011. "Does the Body Tell? Biological Characteristics and Criminal Disposition." Pp. 59 in Criminological Theory: Past to Present : Essential Readings, edited by F.T. Cullen and R. Agnew. New York: Oxford University Press. Sampson, R.J., and J.H. Laub. 1993. Crime in the Making: Pathways and Turning Points Through life. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Sampson, R.J., S.W. Raudenbush, and F. Earls. 1997. "Neighborhoods and Violent Crime: A Multilevel Study of Collective Efficacy." Science 277(5328):918. Sampson, R.J., and W.J. Wilson. 1995. "Toward a theory of race, crime, and urban inequality." Race, crime, and justice: A reader:177–90. Shaw, C.R., and H.D. McKay. 1942. Juvenile Delinquency and Urban Areas. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press. Sherman, Mark. 2000. "Introduction to Cyber Crime." in Special Needs Offenders Bulletin. Washington, D.C.: Federal Judicial Center. Siegel, L.J. 2009. Criminology: Theories, Patterns, and Typologies: Cengage Learning. Sutherland, Edwin H. 1939. Principles of Criminology. Philadelphia, PA: Lippincott. Sutherland, E. H. 1949. "The White-Collar Criminal." in Encyclopedia of Criminology, edited by Vernon C. Branham and Samuel B. Kutash. New York: Philisophical Library. Taylor, Ian R., Paul Walton, and Jock Young. 1973. "Marx, Engles and Bonger on Crime and Social Control." in The New Criminology: For a Social Theory of Deviance. London. Toby, J. 1957. "Social Disorganization and Stake in Conformity: Complementary Factors in the Predatory Behavior of Hoodlums." Journal of Criminal Law, Criminology and Police Science 48:12-17. Tombs, Steve, and Dave Whyt. 2006a. "White Collar Crime." in The Sage Dictionary of Criminology, edited by E. McLaughlin and J. Muncie. Thousand Oaks: SAGE. 39 Tombs, Steve, and Dave Whyt. 2006b. "Corporate Crime." in The Sage Dictionary of Criminology, edited by E. McLaughlin and J. Muncie. Thousand Oaks: SAGE. Turk, Austin T. 1984. "Political Crime." in Major Forms of Crime, edited by R.F. Meier. Beverly Hills: Sage Publications. Valier, Claire. 2006. "Psychoanalytic Criminology." Pp. 320-22 in The Sage Dictionary of Criminology, edited by E. McLaughlin and J. Muncie. Thousand Oaks: SAGE. Vold, G.B., T.J. Bernard, and J.B. Snipes. 1998. Theoretical criminology: Oxford University Press. Wall, D. 2007. Cybercrime: the transformation of crime in the information age: Polity. Westmarland, Louise. 2006a. "Free Will." Pp. 177-78 in The Sage Dictionary of Criminology, edited by E. McLaughlin and J. Muncie. Thousand Oaks: SAGE. Westmarland, Louise. 2006b. "Classicism." Pp. 40-41 in The Sage Dictionary of Criminology, edited by E. McLaughlin and J. Muncie. Thousand Oaks: SAGE. Wilson, J.Q. 1978. Varieties of Police Behavior: The Management of Law and Order in Eight Communities. Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press. Zerubavel, E. 1999. Social Mindscapes: An Invitation to Cognitive Sociology. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. 40