COURTS AND JUDICIAL PROCESS: CJ 4044-001 Juvenile Justice Reform Stella Steele 4/15/2011 i No child is born as a “bad seed”. The one universal truth is that children are born without criminal intent. When a child commits serious criminal acts, society must face the realization that he was molded into a criminal rather than choosing to become one. Whether it is dysfunctional parenting or a culture which glamorizes violence and destructive mindsets, a child is taught to be, not born to be, a criminal offender. At some point society must share in the responsibility of crimes committed by children for creating a culture and conditions where children fall prey to criminal mentalities. A part of sharing in the responsibility of crimes committed by children begins with addressing issues in our criminal justice system. The United States is only one of two countries left in the world that allows children to spend life in prison without the possibility of parole. Many states have no limit on how young a child must be to face trial in adult court, and if guilty can be placed with adult prisoners regardless of their current age. Rather than rehabilitating a young moldable mind, our system elects to throw children in with vultures which creates an even more hardened heart. These moral failures on the part of our nation must be taken into consideration while looking at two primary topics: 1) evaluation of the existing issues in our juvenile justice system and areas to be reformed and 2)analyze the four aspects of criminal justice theory: retribution, incapacitation, deterrence, and rehabilitation. In addition to subjective moral considerations deserve consideration, vast and growing bodies of objective scientific findings have called into question how society should deal with the issue of juvenile justice. Can the justification of deterrence be logically applied to long prison sentences when scientific evidence shows that juveniles have greatly diminished abilities to resist peer pressure or to consider the long term consequences of their actions? Given these factors, it appears clear that the possibility of facing long prison sentences plays a deterrence in few, if any, youthful offenders. Science has also (Steele)1 proven that juveniles have a far greater potential for rehabilitation than adults. The Giddings State School handles the most serious juvenile delinquents in the state of Texas and operates by use of these scientific principles. The purpose of their program is to protect society by holding youth accountable for their behavior, provide individualized education, treatment, life skills, and employment training to reduce recidivism and facilitate successful reintegration into society. The approach used involves the repair of damage done to youth physically, mentally, and environmental factors which led to criminal behavior. The 2010 agency review of Giddings shows that youth completing the high intensity mental health program demonstrated a reduction in re-arrest risk by 39% and re-incarceration by 89%; youth completing specialized treatment programs show re-arrest risk reduction by 50%; and youth who completed the Capital and Serious Violent Offender Treatment Program were 74% less likely to be re‐ arrested. Youth completing any of the programs offered show downward recidivism rate trends (Texas Youth Commission, 2010). Such an approach seems more logical than incarceration in prisons where youth experience greater amounts of victimization, higher suicide rates, inferior treatment services, and higher recidivism rates amongst transferred youth (Myers, 2003). The biological development from childhood into adulthood involves significant changes to the human brain, especially the frontal lobe. The frontal lobe of the human brain concerns itself with “regulating aggression, long-range planning, mental flexibility, abstract thinking, the capacity to hold in mind related pieces of information, and perhaps moral judgment” (Bower, 2004). Biological maturity is not reached until 21 or 22 and brain maturity is estimated around age 25. This accounts for the aforementioned diminished ability to consider the long term consequences of actions: “At least one researcher has found that teenagers typically have a very short time-horizon, looking only a few days into the future when making decisions. Another study concluded that only 25 percent of tenth graders (whose average age is sixteen), compared to 42 percent of twelfth graders (whose (Steele)2 average age is eighteen), considered the long term consequences of important decisions. To the extent that adolescents do consider the implications of their acts, they emphasize short-term consequences, perceiving and weighing longer term consequences to a lesser degree” (Amnesty International; Human Rights Watch, 2005). According to additional research reported by Human Rights Watch “Because their frontal lobes function poorly, adolescents tend to use a part of the brain called the amygdala during decision-making. The amygdala is responsible for impulsive and aggressive behavior, and its dominance makes adolescents ‘more prone to react with gut instincts’. In adult brains, the frontal lobes offer a check on emotions and impulses originating from the amygdala, but this check does not work on the same extent in children’s brains” (Parker, 2005). This creates a vulnerability in children towards criminal influences which is not encountered in adults. It is especially true when the child grows up in an environment with substantial abuse or with criminally minded adults who use the child for criminal exploits and encourage anti-social behavior. Statistics clearly show a correlation between a childhood of abuse and poverty and crime later in life. While fully functioning adults have little justification in trying to use their childhood to deflect responsibility for their actions, adolescents who are “prone to react with gut instincts” have less responsibility for their actions when their “gut instincts” have been programmed from their environment to be violent and asocial. The younger the adolescent the lower the biological capacity to overcome those “gut instincts” is and the less responsibility which can logically be assigned to him. Actions must have consequences and crime must be punished by society in order to maintain justice. Yet justice also requires that punishment must be proportional to the offender’s responsibility and to the crime committed. There is no such thing as a violent crime which is not horrendous or that does not cause serious psychological and/or physical pain to the victims. This leads some to contend that severe sentences always “fit” the crime, but no crime simply rests in the act itself. Intent and degree of (Steele)3 responsibility has always played a role in criminal justice, from the historical justification that a man can kill his wife’s lover to a more modern example of the killing of a person mistakenly, but reasonably, believed to be posing an immediate threat to the life of another. Clearly both cases involve brutality, both cases involve a great deal of pain to the victims and their family, and yet both cases are distinguished by society as being different than a murder out of malice. When the intent of a juvenile crime is considered, even malicious intent must be understood in light of the child’s mental and emotional development. Can society logically view the malicious intent of a fully functioning adult capable of strong rational thought and emotional control the same as the malicious intent of a sixteen year old who has less of an ability to act with rational thought and with emotional control? The answer is no and so the retribution levied at a juvenile offender, no matter the severity of his crime, must be less than that levied at an adult. This does not mean, however that a lengthy prison sentence is not appropriate in some instances. Certainly even the most heartbreaking of childhoods the violent juvenile offender may have experienced will not alleviate the need to protect society by incapacitating him. Even if his upbringing is 100 percent responsible for his actions, society must be protected. There are those who have been ruined for life and may never choose to be responsible citizens. Despite the fact that these situations are devastating tragedies, it does not negate the need for protection of fellow citizens. Once a child becomes criminally violent, no matter the reason, without maturity and rehabilitation, he is likely to offend again. The need to protect society from harm overrides the complete responsibility of third parties for a child’s criminal behavior. Maturity can only come with age and rehabilitation with appropriate program availability. It is important to focus on efforts towards rehabilitation which will not happen in a prison with a lifelong sentence. Parole eligibility should be a possibility once the person has reached full maturity; determining them as ruined for life is premature prior to complete brain development. If the now adult appears to remain a threat to society then they simply stay in prison. (Steele)4 Determining that a youthful offender must be incapacitated, regardless of whether they are tried in adult court and sentenced to 40 years, does not mean that immediate placement into prison necessary. Placing a child in a penitentiary with older hardened criminals should never have become a viable option in a country that has deemed cruel and unusual punishment unconstitutional. There is no punishment crueler and more unusual than housing juveniles with adult sexual predators and violent gang members waiting to violate and extort the week newcomer too young to protect themselves. Considering the fact that many children tried as adults have committed homicide or parricide because they were abused by the perpetrator who later became the victim, a punishment of further abuse is simply outrageous. It is common knowledge that victims of child abuse are often too afraid to go to authorities and eventually take matters in their own hands; as a result of not reporting abuse, there is rarely sufficient evidence to prove abuse existed. Having such evidence may assist in making a decision to retain the case in juvenile court due to mitigating circumstances, therefore avoiding prison abuse. Regardless of whether or not there is any mitigating evidence proving why a juvenile committed a heinous crime, it is never appropriate to incarcerate children with adults. The United States needs to stop ignoring the fact that this practice is in violation of international human rights standards which prohibit combined incarcerations. Separate facilities or segregated areas need to be created for minors serving prison time until they become adults. This should not mean that on their eighteenth birthday an instant move to prison should occur, a mental evaluation should be conducted prior to a move to assure a safe transition. Because a juveniles mind is changing and growing, he is particularly capable of rehabilitation. John Hubner pointed out, “because the brain is still forming [in juvenile offenders], drug treatment, education, vocational training, and anger management for adolescents can have a major impact”. This is borne out in the success rates of the Giddings State School which handled the “worst of the worst” of (Steele)5 juvenile violent offenders in its Capital and Serious Violent Offender Program, as previously mentioned. Offenders who completed the program (as of 2005) had a 55 percent reduction in recidivism for any crime and a 43 percent reduction in felonious reoffending. Only 10 percent of those offenders were rearrested for violent offenses (Hubner, 2005). This is a substantially better rehabilitation rate than any rate demonstrated for adult offenders. Giddings 2005 and 2010 results clearly prove the simple fact that juvenile offenders are highly capable of rehabilitation. This forces society to face important questions about the practicality and morality of continuing to incarcerate a person who is reformed, not a danger to society, and who is no longer the same person they were when they committed their crimes. Few people are the same at age 30 as they were ate age 20 and nobody is the same at age 30 as they were at age 15. In a country swimming in debt with a population demanding more and more services from the government, society cannot afford to expend tens of thousands of dollars each year to incarcerate people who no longer pose a threat to society. That same money can be better spent to protect society with crime prevention programs ,community outreach programs, and facilities that mirror Giddings. Public safety is actually served by rehabilitating juvenile offenders and releasing them sooner than an adult offender. If a juvenile offender is no longer a threat to society, what justification remains for incarcerating him for as long as an adult offender would be? He no longer needs to be incapacitated to protect society and continued incarceration no longer serves any rehabilitation purpose. Unlike with adults, the probability of facing lengthy prison sentences does not serve as a deterrent for juvenile criminals because of their inability to properly weigh the long term consequences of their actions. Continued incarceration of a reformed juvenile offender has no deterrence value upon other juveniles. The only legitimate justification for continued incarceration would be retribution. As shown above, the biological differences between adults and juveniles demonstrate a lower degree of culpability for juveniles in their (Steele)6 actions compared to adults. This weighs against the practice of continued retribution once the juvenile offender has been rehabilitated. An additional problem in the current juvenile justice system, aside from those previously mentioned, is the fundamental lack of due process involved in deciding which children are punished by the juvenile system and which are punished by the adult system. Many states give almost unbridled discretion to district attorneys, whose occupations by nature make them part politician and have to take considerations other than justice alone in making these decisions. This has created a situation where two children of identical age can commit crimes with identical elements of the offense but one can be punished with a far harsher punishment than the other simply due to the decision of one person to move him into adult court. It is purely up to him to decide which facts outside of the elements of the statutory crime justify a harsher punishment and whether or not those facts exist. The solutions to these problems are not complicated nor are they radical, they simply require society to trust the criminal justice system to make the right decision most of the time. The first step is to trust the judges who have heard all the facts of the case, even those facts jurors didn’t hear, to make the right choice in sentencing a juvenile offender-remove the restraints of mandatory sentences. Once a juvenile is sentenced to prison, society must trust the parole board to only release a juvenile offender once he has been rehabilitated. No parole board will release an insubordinate juvenile offender and with the proper programs in place, it will be readily discernable which offenders have truly embraced responsibility for their crimes and have taken rehabilitation seriously versus those who have not. Sentencing schemes must be adjusted to fit the unique circumstances of juveniles who are tried in adult court. The simplest solution would be to allow the sentencing judge to set the minimum amount (Steele)7 of years a juvenile offender must serve before becoming parole eligible-a number which will not be affected by “good time”. For instance, under Colorado law, the maximum aggravated sentence for second degree murder is 48 years, of which an adult offender must serve 75 percent, or 36 years, before becoming parole eligible. Simply allowing a judge to sentence a juvenile to 48 years with, say 10 years minimum, would place the child in a position to prove himself redeemable, yet provide for just as severe a sentence as an adult would serve if he proves to be defiant and unresponsive to treatment. It would allow for severe punishment but also allow for release once continued incarceration is no longer necessary. Such a sentencing scheme could also be used for life sentences. While the cases of the most extreme juvenile murderers may be brought up as examples of why the discretion to impose lighter sentences should not be allowed, it is unreasonable to fear that judges will disregard the gruesomeness of a crime when setting a minimum sentence and it is unreasonable to think that a parole board would release a Charles Manson type juvenile offender into the world. An opportunity for a lower sentence is just that, an opportunity not a certainty. The attractiveness of such discretion in sentencing is also found in that age can be an arbitrary number. Is a person who commits second degree murder dramatically less culpable for his actions five days before his eighteenth birthday than five days after? Of course not, every juvenile’s situation is different. A severely abused seventeen year old with the maturity of a healthy fourteen year old has less culpability than an abnormally mature fifteen year old. A child raised by gang members and taught to be a criminal has less culpability than one raised by responsible parents. Judges need the discretion to use such subjective factors in order to weigh both the rehabilitative potential and culpability of the juvenile offenders who appear before them in order to set just potential minimum sentences. When it comes to increasing the maximum sentence a juvenile is facing, however, it is inappropriate for a judge or a district attorney to make that decision. Currently in Colorado a juvenile who commits first degree (Steele)8 murder either faces up to 5 years to 40 to life is up to the sole discretion of the district attorney with his personal biases, philosophies, and experiences. As pointed out earlier, he decides which facts justify that increase and that those facts exist. This violates the constitution in spirit if not in letter. The legislative branch should be the only body of government to decide which factors justify increasing the maximum punishment for first degree murder from 5 years to 40 to life (or for any crime from 5 years to the statutory maximum for adults). By not delineating specific factors to be considered, the legislature has neglected its duty and has created a system which allows for inconsistent and arbitrary application of the law. No one would seriously dispute that the district attorney for Boulder County has used his discretion to move juveniles into adult court far differently than the district attorney for El Paso County. Integral to any juvenile justice reform in Colorado would be for the legislature to set forth exactly what facts, beyond the element of the crime itself, will move a juvenile into the adult criminal justice system. This would eliminate disparate sentences for identical criminal conduct. Following the reasoning of Justices Scalia and Thomas in Ring vs. Arizona that “the fundamental meaning of the jury trial guarantee of the Sixth Amendment is that all facts essential to the level of punishment that the defendant receives-whether the statue calls elements of the offense, sentencing factors, or Mary Jane-must be found by the jury beyond a reasonable doubt” (Ring vs. Arizona, 2002). It is the jury’s place to decide if those facts which justify the increase in sentencing exist, not the judge’s nor the opposing side of the adversarial system, the district attorney. Society must be able to trust its fellow citizens to make the right decision in cases, to be able to correctly decide if the circumstances of the crime and juvenile offender require placing the child into the adult system. If the citizens of the nation cannot be trusted to make such decisions, that is the problem which must be (Steele)9 addressed rather than not adopting reform. It should be up to a jury of citizens to hear evidence concerning the individual characteristics of the defendant, to assess his culpability in the crime, in order to determine the proper system of punishment for him-juvenile or adult. Only in this manner can the system account for the individual variations among juveniles in their development, their unique personal situations, and remove any extraneous factors in the decision such as political considerations or bias. Juvenile justice reform need not be complicated. Simple reforms can be made which take into account the diminished mental capacities of juveniles and their lessened degree of culpability for their crimes. There is a good reason that society has deemed juveniles as incapable to responsibly drink alcohol, smoke, vote, own a handgun, purchase weapons, and drive without certain restrictions. Their emotional and mental development is clearly far below that of adults. The criminal justice system must account for this along with society’s failure to create a culture which discourages self-centeredness, materialism, and crime. Not only is juvenile justice reform a moral imperative, but the reduction in overall incarceration costs can lead to a greater society to be a member of. There is no downside to properly implemented reform; the only question is if there is someone with the strength of personality to create the will for reform in the halls of the legislature. (Steele)10 Work Cited Ring vs. Arizona, U.S. 584 (Supreme Court of the United States June 24, 2002). Amnesty International; Human Rights Watch. (2005). The Rest of Their Lives: Life without Parole for Child Offenders in the United States. New York, NY; Washington, DC; : Human Rights Watch/Amnesty International. Bower, B. (2004). Teen Brains on Trial: The Science of Neutral Development Tangles With the Juvenile Death Penalty. Science News Online, 299-301. Hubner, J. (2005). Last Cance Texas: The Redemption of Criminal Youth. New York: Random House. Myers, D. L. (2003). Adult Crime, Adult Time: Punishing Violent Youth in the Adult Criminal Justice System. Youth Violence and Juvenile Justice, 173-192. Parker, A. (2005). Thrown Away: Children Sentenced to Life Without Parole In Colorado. New York, NY: Human Rights Watch. Texas Youth Commission. (2010). 2010 Annual Review of Agency: Treatment Effectiveness. (Steele)11