What creates dimensions fundamentally and the consequences of this property on matrix (Part 1, dimensions) The behaviors and properties of qualities that found exist The first quality that is observed or discovered but not defined or created for one’s own purpose is numbers. Numbers can be and was probably first found by measuring the amount of clearly categorized objects, or counting. By counting, such as counting the number of steps needed to take for one to walk from a point to another, measures the amount of the objects we consider and define as a whole. That is, for instance, we shall define a step to be twice the length of the walker’s feet, by counting the number of steps the walker makes, we measure the amount of “steps”, which is an object we defined by considering the infinitely many points within the length of the walker’s feet as a whole, one complete, single object. In this way, we obtain, or find numbers. In another word, such numbers can all be obtained by counting, measuring the amount of object we define in certain way. We know that such quality, numbers, exists at all times with or without us counting and finding them, since any thing may be considered as a whole according to one’s definition and be counted to measure its amount. When one such number is applied with some calculation and as a result is transformed/becomes another number, we find that with on the calculation and the quality: numbers we defined, there is no barrier or limitation in which a such defined number cannot be obtained by any calculation applied to some other number(s). In other words, for any real number, it can be expressed in terms of some combinations of other real numbers. That is, a real number can always be represented by the resultant number from some certain calculations of some other real numbers; in another word, if we let π₯ and π be any two real numbers, there is at least one relationship π₯ = π(π) that holds true for all real numbers π₯ and π, where the function π is some calculations that only involves real numbers applied to real number π. That is, any one real number is the resultant number of some additions and/or multiplications between some other real numbers. This conclusion shows that any two real numbers can be transformed/become each other through some certain calculations; for one arbitrarily chosen real numbers out of the collection of all real numbers, it can reach any real numbers in such collection through some calculation. In conclusion, we find that: for any one real number N, there exists a real number M such that π = π(π). From the conclusion above, since for real numbers the relationship π = π(π) must holds true, thus any quality which fails to obtain such relationship is not a real number. Therefore, for any one non real-number quality π ′ and some real number M, π ′ ≠ π(π); that is, for any non real-number quality π ′, there does not exist a real number M such that π = π(π). This conclusion shows that a non realnumber quality π ′ cannot, through any calculations, reach/become some real number. There is such a limitation of the qualities it can reach/become through calculations for π ′ ; if one applies the same argument for some real number π, the same conclusion also holds true for the real number N. Since the two qualities π and π ′ cannot reach each other through any calculations, we call them to be different kinds of qualities. That is, the limitation of the qualities one quality can reach creates and determines such quality to be a different kinds of quality than the qualities it wished but cannot become. This conclusion also shows that qualities of the same kind are all able to be found using the same method. That is, if one knows that two qualities are the same kind of quality and the method of obtaining one of these two qualities, then one is also able to find the other quality using such same method. Note that qualities can found but cannot be created, since the relationship between some qualities of the same kind π = π(π) holds true with the restriction of the kinds of quality N and M are, but not with the restriction of the observer’s knowledge of such qualities’ existence. This property of qualities within the same kind can be derived from the conclusion made above as the following. According to the conclusion above, since for any two qualities of the same kind N and M, the relationship π = π(π) must hold true, that is, M must be able to be obtained through some calculations applied to N, thus we also must have the relationship M = g(N) to be true, where the function g is some certain function such that N = f(g(N)). Therefore, from this conclusion, we see that for any two qualities N and M, if they are of the same kind, then N can be obtained by some calculations applied to M, and vice versa, M can be obtained by some calculations applied to N. If the quality N is found using method A, since M = f(N), the other quality M is found using the method of applying some calculations to N, we call this calculation method CN; similarly, if the quality M is found using some method B, since N = g(M), quality N is found using some calculations applied to M, call it method CM, as shown in the figure below. 2 According to the above relationships, there are multiple ways in which quality N can be found, it can be either found through only method A, or through method B to obtain quality M, then through method CM which is applied to M. That is, in short, quality N can be found by method A or methods B & CM, these two methods are considered equivalent for finding quality N; for clear referencing’s sake, we write this conclusion as πππ‘βππ(π΄) = πππ‘βππ(π΅, πΆπ ). Similarly, the same argument can be applied to quality M, too. Thus we also have the conclusion that quality M can be found by method B or methods A & CN according to the above relationships. Thus we now also have πππ‘βππ(π΅) = πππ‘βππ(π΄, πΆπ ). Since πππ‘βππ(π΄) = πππ‘βππ(π΅, πΆπ ), the equation above can be re-written as πππ‘βππ(π΅) = πππ‘βππ(π΅, πΆπ , πΆπ ). Therefore, when applying to some same quality, method B is equivalent to Method B, CM, and CN used together. Since applying methods CM and CN makes no difference in the result of the calculation, thus by applying those two methods, they must cancel each other out and thus make no affect on the result of the calculation. That is, πππ‘βππ(πΆπ ) = −πππ‘βππ(πΆπ ), indicating that applying method CM is the reverse of applying method CN. Since the determination of method A depends on the quality A is applied to, method A is determined once the quality is arbitrarily chosen and A varies for different qualities in order to for such qualities to become quality N after method A is applied to them. That is, in another word, method A may be applied to any quality to get quality N, but with varying determination of A in order to do so. Therefore, the choice of method A is arbitrary, one is able to define A arbitrarily 3 for one’s own purposes, by doing so, one only needs to change the quality A is applied to. Since we can define A arbitrarily, and since both method A and method CM produce quality N (although they may be applied to different qualities), we let A be CM, that is, we define πππ‘βππ(π΄) = πππ‘βππ(πΆπ ). Since method CM is applied to quality M, in order for the above relationship holds true, M must be adjusted according to method A, which is chosen at our will for a certain quality to produce/become quality N. Therefore this definition satisfies the fundamental observation π = π(π) for any two qualities N and M of the same kind, since for any quality N, we are able to define method A arbitrarily, and by varying the quality A is applied to, we can then therefore vary the definition of A for an infinite amount of possibilities; Since A = CM, and CM determines quality M, we are able to change M to be any quality of the same kind as N by varying method A, which then varies method CM, which then determines quality M. Thus the above definition does not only let method A happens to be the same as method CM, but also let the choice of A, which equals to CM, to be in our control and can be arbitrary. (Since A and CM applies to different qualities, they must be defined, or happens to be the same, however, since we can vary A arbitrarily, this restriction will not limit the qualities, which is denoted as M, N can reach through calculations by this definition.) Recall that we defined πππ‘βππ(π΄) = πππ‘βππ(πΆπ ), similarly, we can define πππ‘βππ(π΅) = πππ‘βππ(πΆπ ). In the latter case, since quality M has been determined by our choice of method A, one can only vary the quality to which B is applied in order to vary method B, and hence also vary CN. Within the system shown in the figure, we found that πππ‘βππ(πΆπ ) = −πππ‘βππ(πΆπ ), since we now also defined that πππ‘βππ(π΄) = πππ‘βππ(πΆπ ) and πππ‘βππ(π΅) = πππ‘βππ(πΆπ ), thus we have πππ‘βππ(π΄) = −πππ‘βππ(π΅). That is, we found that method A is the reverse of method B, where A and B are applied to some certain qualities to produce arbitrary qualities N and M respectively, and where N = f(M) for all possible qualities N and M. This relationship is shown below in the figure. We can see that by the fundamental relationship N = f(M), for every quality M there is within the same kind of quality as N and M, besides method A which was 4 used to produce quality N, there is one more method available to be used to produce N and every M we have known. If the collection of a kind of quality consists of infinite amount of qualities, then there are infinite numbers of different methods to produce a quality of this kind, that is, to produce a quality within such collection from another quality within the same collection. If the qualities N, M, and the arbitrary quality are the only three qualities within the collection, then if another quality is said to be one quality in the collection, there must be two and only two methods can be used by N to produce this another quality, and there also must be the reverses of those two and only two methods can be used by N to produce quality M, as shown in the figure below. Note that the same argument can be said for any other known qualities within the collection. In conclusion, if I is a quality within a collection of many qualities of the same kind, then among any other two different qualities in such collection, call them J and K; for each J and K, there must be at least one method for I to produce/become each of the two quality, call them method X and Y for producing J and K respectively; then correspondingly, there must also be a method –Y, which is the reverse of method Y, can be used on I to produce J, similarly, there must be a method –X, as the reverse of method X, can be used on I to produce K. Among any three qualities within the same such collection, the above relationships must hold true. A particular, individual quality within such collection of qualities of the same kind is determined by the relationships created by applying all possible methods to another quality. For two qualities A and B of the same kind, there may be n methods which can be used on A to produce B, that is, there are n functions such that A is a function of B. Therefore, B is a quality which is determined to the quality that can satisfy all those relationships, that is, the quality that can let all n functions hold true. This idea shown below in the figure. 5 Let N and M be two arbitrary qualities in the same collection of qualities of the same kind, let “?” be some other quality that’s different from N and M, call it quality Q. Since N, M, and Q are qualities of the same kind, we have N = f(Q) and N = g(M). Therefore, there must be some methods which can be used by N to produce Q and M according to N = f(Q) and N = g(M), call these two methods method X and Y for N to produce Q and M respectively. According to the conclusion we deduced above, there must also be a method –Y and –X, which are the reverse of method Y and X respectively, can be used by N to produce Q and M respectively, as shown in figure. Since the methods which can be used by quality N to produce Q and M exist, we can use the reverse of those method to reverse the process of producing Q and M to produce N from Q and M. That is, there must be method –X and Y which can be used by Q to produce N, similarly, there must be method –Y and X which can be used by M to produce N. Since in the relationships we deduce in the previous conclusion, the relationships only hold true if the methods are used by one quality to produce some other qualities, thus the methods shown in figure that are methods used by other qualities to produce the quality we are studying does not affect the relationship, for simplicity’s sake, we shall ignore them in the figure and focus on the methods that can be used by the quality we study to produce some other qualities. Let M1 be another quality within the same collection as the collection Q, N, and M are in. Since M1 and Q are within the same collection, there must exist a method, call it method Z, which can be used by Q to produce M1. Then there must also be method –X and Y can be used by Q to produce M1. According to the previous 6 conclusions, we have the following relationships among Q, M1, and the methods producing them. Remember that we use only methods that can be used on quality Q to produce the other qualities since the relationships we deduced in the previous conclusion only hold true for such methods. Since N is also in the same collection as M1, thus there must also be a method, call it P, that can be used by N to produce M1. Then we have the following relationship, built upon the relationships above. 7 With similar procedures, we can also further deduce the relationships among qualities and methods that produce them for every new quality found and added into the collection. Therefore, since we only found and deduced qualities of the same kind to have such relationships shown above, any qualities that does not satisfy the relationships in the above argument are not qualities within the same kind of quality. Structures created by such behaviors and properties of qualities From the conclusion we have in the above session, we see that shown by observations and deductions, for qualities that are of the same kind, certain relationships hold true among them, and changing one of the quality in such relationships will effect other qualities in the relationships for the relationships to hold true. We can also clearly see that the above relationships, although universal and fundamental for any qualities of the same kind, is always restricted to be only said for qualities of the same kind and according only to the above relationships, we cannot say the same relationships hold true for qualities outside this limitation, since the limitation, whether the qualities discussed are of the same kind or not, is defined by the relationships this limitation or restriction is in. Therefore, for different kind of qualities, no such relationships can be said among them, that is, there is no method can be used by a quality to produce another quality of a different kind; qualities of different kinds cannot become each other through some calculations. Such barrier between different kinds of qualities always holds true, since according to the relationships we found and deduced previously, different kinds of qualities are determined by the relationships, if the relationships hold true for all qualities concerned, then such qualities are of the same kind, and vice versa; the same kind of relationships (such as relationships that can produce certain group of qualities) a group of qualities can satisfy determines the barrier between this group of qualities and other groups of qualities that can satisfy different kind of relationships. Through calculations of the same kind of qualities, such group of qualities cannot produce/become qualities that are not within this group; that is, by combining a group of qualities in every way possible, the resultant quality of such combination cannot reach qualities outside this group, such resultant quality can only reach some quality within the group. For a quality A within one collection of qualities of the same kind to reach, or become some other quality B within some other collection of qualities, where A and B are different kinds of qualities, it would require quality A to become the same kind of quality as B to reach 8 anywhere within the collection B is in. This limited amount of qualities one quality can become creates a range, the qualities within this range are all the qualities such quality can reach through calculations. This range separates different kinds of qualities and indicates how far and where a quality can reach. That is, such different kinds of qualities create the ranges which are only accessible by qualities of their own kind, and such range of a quality, which is the limitation this quality can reach, is the dimension of this quality. Since this range is also the limitation of all other qualities of the same kind can reach, this range is also the dimension of all qualities of this kind. A same kind of qualities creates a dimension: a barrier which other qualities of different kinds cannot cross. 9