1ac Plan The United States Federal Government should make legal nearly all marihuana prohibited under the Controlled Substances Act in the United States. Adv 1 Advantage 1 is Agriculture -Federal law blocks the application of certified organic standards t0 marijuana cultivation – that inhibits sustainable growth Rogers 12 [Intern at the Mattole Restoration Council, a wildlife restoration non-profit located along the Mattole River in Northern California. [Robert Rogers, “How Conscientious Consumerism Could Re-shape the Marijuana Industry,” Earth Island Journal, July 25, 2012, pg. http://tinyurl.com/ca9xxwz] Under existing market conditions, a joint rolled with marijuana grown outdoors, in the lush heat of the Southern Humboldt/ Mendocino sun and with a fraction of the carbon footprint, is sold as an equivalent product on the black market and in many dispensaries, and is worth less to wholesalers who value THCcontent and aesthetic uniformity over a crop’s environmental footprint. These economic realities, coupled with fears of federal law enforcement retaliations against blatant outdoor grows, have been pushing marijuana grows indoors for decades, where carbon footprints are mightier than Shaquille O’Neal’s slippers. It is high time that the rules governing the economic value of marijuana crops in states with medical laws be amended, enabling sustainable, low-impact grows and family homesteads to gain a premium price for their environmentally conscious bud. But how do we, as consumers, initiate such a change? One way for consumers to lobby for change is by pushing dispensaries to advertise the method of origin of their marijuana, an easy alteration that many dispensaries and collectives have begun making already. Tea House Collective, a Berkeley, CA-based collective that sources its weed from Humboldt growers, is well-known for marketing sun-grown marijuana and claims on its website that it only buys from growers who adhere to strict, organically-inspired cultivation methods. (Marijuana cannot legally – as of now -- be declared “organic” by the USDA or other certifiers due to the federal prohibition .) Nudging local dispensaries and collectives to do the same can be as easy as demanding sun-grown marijuana at your local dispensary, talking to owners or staff about whether their dispensary is implementing growing standards, and leaving harsh reviews on websites and internet forums like WeedMaps.com for dispensaries that can’t or won’t offer sun-grown products. Dispensaries are just like any other retailer – their prerogative is customer service, and if enough customers are unhappy with the way they do business, substantive change can and will happen. The wave of the future for sun-grown, sustainable marijuana growers, however, is undoubtedly third-party certification . We’ve got fair trade coffee. So why not fair trade herb? While there are many factors that have propelled the success of the organic food movement in the United States, third-party certifiers such as California Certified Organic been instrumental in laying the groundwork for a thriving sustainable foods movement. While second-party certifications – such as assurances from collectives like Tea House that its member farmers are using best practices to cultivate their bud – are useful to consumers, third-party certifications are essential for creating and enforcing industry-wide standards in sustainable marijuana cultivation. Such a system would not only alleviate the conscience of dope-smokers aware of marijuana’s ecological externalities, but could incentivize sustainable practices for marijuana growers who aren’t motivated simply by altruism. A simple “eco-grown” label for sungrown pot could shake up the entire industry , transforming low-value outdoor weed into a desirable, boutique product. Much as consumers are willing to pay a market premium for produce with a USDA organic label, “eco-grow” labels would allow green-thumbed marijuana growers to receive compensation commensurate with the value consumers put on high-quality, environmentally sustainable goods. That 15 to 20 percent premium may look awful sweet to Farmers [CCOF] have pot growers considering the switch to more sustainable growing techniques, and may even convince growers who don’t value environmental sustainability to change their growing habits in order to gain access to this lucrative market, just as CCOF has made organic farming methods attractive to many “conventional” farmers. Sustainable marijuana demonstrates the economic feasibility of small farms – this creates a global model Fine, 13 [Doug, B.A Stanford, journalist in Washington Post, Salon, and NPR, “Making Sure the End of Cannabis Prohibition Benefits the Small Farmer,” Alternet, February 7, 2013, pg. http://tinyurl.com/l72zvya] the stacked deck at the mass production level is explicitly why the cultivators of the Emerald Growers Association (EGA), a cannabis farmer trade group based in Northern California, prefer describing the “craft brew” model for the post-prohibition cannabis economy. In a world of Coors, these farmers plan to provide Fat Tire Ale. “We’re not afraid of what might be stocked next to cheap beer and cigarettes at the corner store,” says Tomas Balogh, EGA board member. “Let’s remember that American craft beer was nearly an $8 billion market in the U.S. last year.” So when people ask him if globalized corporate models or small farming community-based models will emerge when the drug war ends here in a few years, Balogh says, “Both.” His point is that of course major players are going to enter the fray when we’re talking about what is already a $35-billion-a-year crop in the U.S., greater than the combined value of corn and wheat. Although the end of cannabis prohibition will almost certainly cause short-term wholesale price drops, what Balogh says to jittery farmers like Mark is, “even if your worst, most paranoid fears about modern corporate ethics are correct, there is still a lucrative (and expanding) niche for top-shelf, organically grown cannabis like the Emerald Triangle provides.” If it’s done right. The same shopper who today looks for local broccoli at her food co-op is going to demand organic techniques in her morning cannabis health shake. If a black-market farmer is Regardless of corporate boardroom strategy, simply churning out quick turnaround, pesticide-heavy, indoor-grown popcorn buds to pay the mortgage, that farmer is going to lose out to Coors-style mass-produced if the three-generation knowledge base that caused Michael Pollan to call cannabis cultivators “the best farmers of my generation ” is put to use in the cause of long-term product quality and local community health, small-scale (maybe we can call it “microbud”) cultivators will help the region become an internationally recognized paragon of consistent top-shelf production. That is called a brand. “The best part is farmers can keep the industry benefiting their local economy ,” Balogh told me from his own Mendocino County farm in 2011. Indeed, local farmers already hold meetings (I’ve attended several) in which they discuss the fact that the economy of cannabis cultivation communities can expand beyond the already considerable value of the psychoactive flower. To give one example, the Bavarian community of Feldheim, Germany has become entirely energy independent (while nearly eliminating local unemployment ) by generating municipal power generated from the unused stalks from the rural community’s farms. When cannabis comes aboveground, its cultivators are likewise in prime position to benefit from fermenting or gasifying stalks that would otherwise be compost. Where would cannabis, because he’s essentially growing a Coors-quality product already. But funding for such planet-saving entrepreneurialism come from? Perhaps from the 21st-century Homesteading Act that fifth-generation Colorado rancher Michael Bowman and others are proposing: these would be micro-grants for micro-intensive, local community-enriching farming projects. (Social/medicinal cannabis is a specialty crop requiring a great deal of farmer attention to every plant. For industrial cannabis in places like North Dakota and Kentucky, the grants might be on a larger scale, reflecting larger farming Such plans are very much in the blackboard stage. After all, cannabis isn’t legal yet. That can throw up roadblocks in the federal grant application process. Yet the discussions continue. In the Emerald Triangle, farmers have brainstormed about cost-saving techniques for the local industry that include centralized bud-trimming facilities, warehousing and quality testing services. These will bring local employment, as will “bud-and-breakfast” value-added tourism. You can’t talk to operations.) an EGA farmer without hearing how Mendocino and Humboldt counties are going to do for cannabis “what Napa did for wine.” (Napa did $11 billion just in tourism business in 2011.) It sets the tone for a sustainable model of agriculture Fine, 13 [Doug, B.A Stanford, journalist in Washington Post, Salon, and NPR, “Can the Cannabis Economy Be Ecologically Sustainable?” Huffington Post, Updated: March 17, 2013, p. http://tinyurl.com/qzfwoqd] Because of this isolation, prohibition, and now, cultural tradition, Northern California's remote Emerald Triangle is poised to provide a model for a sustainable post-prohibition cannabis industry. In particular, this model, which was institutionalized in a landmark cannabis farmer permitting program by the Sheriff's Department in Mendocino County in 2011, can provide a farmer-owned, outdoor cultivation playbook to counter some of the grow room-based models that are in danger of becoming institutionalized in the first U.S. states to re-legalize full adult use of the plant. "This is part of the larger food revolution we're seeing everywhere," the overalls-wearing Fuzzy told me during what became a sodden farmer caucus during a break between speakers at the Cup, contemplatively stroking his red chest length beard. While thick, icy raindrops fell quite audibly from redwood eaves all around me, I thought about my own produce shopping preferences. I wouldn't buy a spear of supermarket hothouse broccoli when there's a local organic heirloom variety available at the weekend farmer's market. This kind of conversation was the explicit reason why I had jetted into the ankle-soaking winter puddles and moss-covered power lines of Redway, Calif. to give my own talk at The Cup: I believe that figuring out how to keep the cannabis industry decentralized, farmercontrolled and sustainable once prohibition ends is a key piece in the "allow my kids to inherit an inhabitable planet" puzzle . I'm a sustainability journalist and solar-powered goat rancher who's just reported just from the front lines of the Drug War for a year. We're talking about the United States' number one crop, already worth $35 billion per year, according to ABC News. We don't have the time or resources to initiate any more carbon intensive industries. The good news is that cannabis is now, in 2013, in the blueprint phase. I think we're three to five years from full federal cannabis legalization. That's enough planning time. What can be done to make sure the planet's greenest industry is born Green? It's about incorporating sustainable cannabis methods no matter how and where the plant is cultivated -- and this includes the industrial side (hemp) in places like North Dakota. If I weren't already driving on vegetable oil and being routinely outwitted by goats, I would have become aware of the sustainable cannabis imperative when Nobel Laureate Evan Mills, a researcher on the United Nations Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change team that won the prize, approached me after a live event I was doing in support of my recent book, Too High to Fail: Cannabis and the New Green Economic Revolution. As a follow-up project to his UN panel work, Mills had in 2011 published a much-discussed report on the energy demand of California's (mostly indoorgrown) cannabis industry (which he concluded is responsible for 3 percent of all of California's energy use). Our email dialogue since meeting has been spirited: as a guy who has visited probably three dozen cannabis farms, both indoor and outdoor, in the course of my research, I find myself with notes on farming techniques that not only help with my own tomatoes and beans, but which represent the cutting edge of an agricultural sector that Michael Pollan describes as including "the best farmers of my generation." Yet exchanges with Mills always force me to more critically ask questions like, "Is that farmer's drip irrigation technique really sustainable?" and "Does the Mendocino County, California locavore permitting program that worked so well locally scale to mass industrial sizes?" Although I followed intentionally sustainable cannabis farmers in my book, I'd have to be blind not to be aware that a segment of the outdoor farming community in the U.S. and Mexico requires as much education as indoor gardeners do when it comes to issues like waterway diversion and pesticide use. The truth is, most farmers here in the Emerald Triangle get it. A third generation Humboldt County farmer named Mike told me as he stared admiringly at the rows of finalist buds behind the glass display at the Emerald Cup's straw bale-lined Growers' Tent, "The plants adapt to the climate. Why wouldn't I use God's own sun instead of a generator?" Case in point, this year's winner of the Emerald Cup grand prize (a trip to Jamaica), Leo Bell of nearby Laytonville (for his "exceptionally smooth, enticing and very sticky...nasturtium-scented" Chem Dawg strain, according to judges), noted in his victory speech that during the 2012 growing season (a region-wide vintage said to be the best in a decade and a half), "I watered by hand, and gave my heart to these plants, five (pause while choked up) hours every day." Now, if all of humanity's agricultural engineers operated according to such principles, climate change would be a much more relaxed discussion. This moment presents the opportunity for the cannabis industry to chart the very best course , or the very worst. On the dark side, you have the Drug War-inspired violent cartels, profiteers, and poison pesticide purveyors that prohibition economies create. On the positive side, think of the Doctor Bronner's Soap model, where organic and Fair Trade principles are embedded in every product (many of which derive from hemp) and the CEO makes five times the salary of the lowest-paid employee. This is the model that the farmers of the Emerald Growers Association trade group (EGA) are using as they brand the region's cannabis crop in anticipation of a time when busy moms in the Whole Foods cannabis section will be seeking "organic, fairly traded, local farmer-owned" plants for Sunday's Super Bowl party dip. As for farmer Fuzzy's point about the importance of native soil, I can tell you after two decades of sustainability journalism that he is spot-on: when I visited a local cannabis strain developer named Rock on his coastal farm, he showed me that his technique basically involves crossing two promising strains and seeing if they like the local dirt. And Rock's strains have placed very high at past Emerald Cups. The Emerald Triangle's barn-side genetics laboratories work. My year of touring cannabis farms has taught me that without question, no hydroponic set-up or garden store soil mix can approach the complex microbial soup found in a mature Emerald Triangle farm. These are the same regional conditions and knowledge of how to exploit them that long ago branded places like Champagne, France and Parmesan, Italy: you can't, by international law, call the same cheese from somewhere else by the name Parmesan. And only family-level farming allows the kind of tender loving care that results in such universally recognized branding. "Water your plants with a cup while singing to them" could never be taught at an ag school. Will the Emerald Triangle farmer survive the inevitable period of instability and likely price drops which will follow the start of the Drug Peace era? "I think so," said Cup organizer Blake. "We're a culture." The branding of this culture and its famous flowers is already underway. "We want people to associate the Emerald Triangle with top shelf cannabis the way they do Napa with wine and wine tourism," explained Tomas Balogh, board member of the EGA. The worldwide post-Drug War cannabis industry train has left the station. Working against Emerald farmer organization is the longstanding cultivator fear that legalization will bring millions of consumers are going to be seeking the cannabis version of Fat Tire Ale. If the region's cultivators band together to aim for the microbrew aficionado, the EGA thinking goes, there's nothing to fear from Coors. Craft beer was a $7.6 billion market in 2010. For the plan to work, sustainable practices have to be taught, followed and certified in the Emerald Triangle. Especially to newer and younger about the Coors or Marlboro version of cannabis production. And I think that concern is legitimate -- for the run of the mill farmer. But farmers. Even Fuzzy got serious for a moment when I asked him if, alongside his own efficiently drip-irrigated crops, he sees non-sustainable practices, such as river diversion, among his farming neighbors. "We do need standards," he admitted. It's a small planet, and the EGA's Balogh says that cultivators have to prepare now to take advantage of the legalization free-for-all and emerge as the world's number one sustainable crop . "We don't have a choice with this," he says. "We have to get it right." Small scale food production is important for ecological sustainability – the alternative is irreversible planetary harm Altieri, 08 [Professor of agroecology @ University of California, Berkeley [Miguel Altieri (President, Sociedad Cientifica LatinoAmericana de Agroecologia (SOCLA), “Small farms as a planetary ecological asset: Five key reasons why we should support the revitalization of small farms in the Global South,” Food First, May 9, 2008, p. http://www.foodfirst.org/en/node/2115] The Via Campesina has long argued that farmers need land to produce food for their own communities and for their country and for this reason has advocated for genuine agrarian reforms to access and control land, water, agrobiodiversity, etc, which are of central importance for communities to be able to meet growing food demands. The Via Campesina believes that in order to protect livelihoods, jobs, people's food security and health, as well as the environment, food production has to remain in the hands of small- scale sustainable farmers and cannot be left under the control of large agribusiness companies or supermarket chains. Only by changing the export-led, free-trade based, industrial agriculture model of large farms can the downward spiral of poverty, low wages, rural-urban migration, hunger and environmental degradation be halted. Social rural movements embrace the concept of food sovereignty as an alternative to the neo-liberal approach that puts its faith in inequitable international trade to solve the world’s food problem. Instead, food sovereignty focuses on local autonomy, local markets, local production-consumption cycles, energy and technological sovereignty and farmer to farmer networks. This global movement, the Via Campesina, has recently brought their message to the North, partly to gain the support of foundations and consumers, as political pressure from a wealthier public that increasingly depends on unique food products from the South marketed via organic, fair trade, or slow food channels could marshal the sufficient political will to curb the expansion of biofuels, transgenic crops and agro-exports, and put an end to subsidies to industrial farming and dumping practices that hurt small farmers in the South. But can these arguments really captivate the attention and support of northern consumers and philanthropists? Or is there a need for a different argument—one that emphasizes that the very quality of life and food security of the populations in the North depends not only on the food products, but in the ecological services provided by small farms of the South. In fact, it is herein argued that the functions performed by small farming systems still prevalent in Africa, Asia and Latin America—in the post-peak oil era that humanity is entering—comprise an ecological asset for humankind and planetary survival . In fact, in an era of escalating fuel and food costs, climate change, environmental degradation, GMO pollution and corporate- dominated food systems, small, biodiverse, agroecologically managed farms in the Global South are the only viable form of agriculture that will feed the world under the new ecological and economic scenario. There are at last five reasons why it is in the interest of Northern consumers to support the cause and struggle of small farmers in the South: 1. Small farmers are key for the world’s food security While 91% of the planet’s 1.5 billion hectares of agricultural land are increasingly being devoted to agro-export crops, biofuels and transgenic soybean to feed cars and cattle, millions of small farmers in the Global South still produce the majority of staple crops needed to feed the planet ’s rural and urban populations. In Latin America, about 17 million peasant production units occupying close to 60.5 million hectares, or 34.5% of the total cultivated land with average farm sizes of about 1.8 hectares, produce 51% of the maize, 77% of the beans, and 61% of the potatoes for domestic consumption. Africa has approximately 33 million small farms, representing 80 percent of all farms in the region. Despite the fact that Africa now imports huge amounts of cereals, the majority of African farmers (many of them women) who are smallholders with farms below 2 hectares, produce a significant amount of basic food crops with virtually no or little use of fertilizers and improved seed. In Asia, the majority of more than 200 million rice farmers, few farm more than 2 hectares of rice make up the bulk of the rice produced by Asian small farmers. Small increases in yields on these small farms that produce most of the world´s staple crops will have far more impact on food availability at the local and regional levels, than the doubtful increases predicted for distant and corporate-controlled large monocultures managed with such high tech solutions as genetically modified seeds. 2.Small farms are more productive and resource conserving than large-scale monocultures Although the conventional wisdom is that small family farms are backward and unproductive, research shows that small farms are much more productive than large farms if total output is considered rather than yield from a single crop. Integrated farming systems in which the small-scale farmer produces grains, fruits, vegetables, fodder, and animal products outproduce yield per unit of single crops such as corn (monocultures) on large-scale farms. A large farm may produce more corn per hectare than a small farm in which the corn is grown as part of a polyculture that also includes beans, squash, potato, and fodder. In polycultures developed by smallholders, productivity, in terms of harvestable products, per unit area is higher than under sole cropping with the same level of management. Yield advantages range from 20 percent to 60 percent, because polycultures reduce losses due to weeds, insects and diseases, and make more efficient use of the available resources of water, light and nutrients. In overall output, the diversified farm produces much more food, even if measured in dollars. In the USA, data shows that the smallest two hectare farms produced $15,104 per hectare and netted about $2,902 per acre. The largest farms, averaging 15,581 hectares, yielded $249 per hectare and netted about $52 per hectare. Not only do small to medium sized farms exhibit higher yields than conventional farms, but do so with much lower negative impact on the environment. Small farms are ‘multi-functional’– more productive, more efficient, and contribute more to economic development than do large farms. Communities surrounded by many small farms have healthier economies than do communities surrounded by depopulated, large mechanized farms. Small farmers also take better care of natural resources, including reducing soil erosion and conserving biodiversity. The inverse relationship between farm size and output can be attributed to the more efficient use of land, water, biodiversity and other agricultural resources by small farmers. So in terms of converting inputs into outputs, society would be better off with small-scale farmers. Building strong rural economies in the Global South based on productive small-scale farming will allow the people of the South to remain with their families and will help to stem the tide of migration. And as population continues to grow and the amount of farmland and water available to each person continues to shrink, a small farm structure may become central to feeding the planet, especially when large- scale agriculture devotes itself to feeding car tanks. 3. Small traditional and biodiverse farms are models of sustainability Despite the onslaught of industrial farming, the persistence of thousands of hectares under traditional agricultural management documents a successful indigenous agricultural strategy of adaptability and resiliency. These microcosms of traditional agriculture that have stood the test of time, and that can still be found almost untouched since 4 thousand years in the Andes, MesoAmerica, Southeast Asia and parts of Africa, offer promising models of sustainability as they promote biodiversity , thrive without agrochemicals, and sustain year-round yields even under marginal environmental conditions. The local knowledge accumulated during millennia and the forms of agriculture and agrobiodiversity that this wisdom has nurtured, comprise a Neolithic legacy embedded with ecological and cultural resources of fundamental value for the future of humankind . Recent research suggests that many small farmers cope and even prepare for climate change, minimizing crop failure through increased use of drought tolerant local varieties, water harvesting, mixed cropping, opportunistic weeding, agroforestry and a series of other traditional techniques. Surveys conducted in hillsides after Hurricane Mitch in Central America showed that farmers using sustainable practices such as “mucuna” cover crops, intercropping, and agroforestry suffered less “damage” than their conventional neighbors. The study spanning 360 communities and 24 departments in Nicaragua, Honduras and Guatemala showed that diversified plots had 20% to 40% more topsoil, greater soil moisture, less erosion, and experienced lower economic losses than their conventional neighbors. This demonstrates that a re-evaluation of indigenous technology can serve as a key source of information on adaptive capacity and resilient capabilities exhibited by small farms—features of strategic importance for world farmers to cope with climatic change . In addition, indigenous technologies often reflect a worldview and an understanding of our relationship to the natural world that is more realistic and more sustainable that those of our Western European heritage. 4. Small farms represent a sanctuary of GMO-free agrobiodiversity In general, traditional small scale farmers grow a wide variety of cultivars . Many of these plants are landraces grown from seed passed down from generation to generation, more genetically heterogeneous than modern cultivars, and thus offering greater defenses against vulnerability and enhancing harvest security in the midst of diseases, pests, droughts and other stresses. In a worldwide survey of crop varietal diversity on farms involving 27 crops, scientists found that considerable crop genetic diversity continues to be maintained on farms in the form of traditional crop varieties, especially of major staple crops. In most cases, farmers maintain diversity as an insurance to meet future environmental change or social and economic needs. Many researchers have concluded that this varietal richness enhances productivity and reduces yield variability. For example, studies by plant pathologists provide evidence that mixing of crop species and or varieties can delay the onset of diseases by reducing the spread of disease carrying spores, and by modifying environmental conditions so that they are less favorable to the spread of certain pathogens. Recent research in China, where four different mixtures of rice varieties grown by farmers from fifteen different townships over 3000 hectares, suffered 44% less blast incidence and exhibited 89% greater yield than homogeneous fields without the need to use chemicals. It is possible that traits important to indigenous farmers (resistance to drought, competitive ability, performance on intercrops, storage quality, etc) could be traded for transgenic qualities which may not be important to farmers (Jordan, 2001). Under this scenario, risk could increase and farmers would lose their ability to adapt to changing biophysical environments and increase their success with relatively stable yields with a minimum of external inputs while supporting their communities’ food security. Although there is a high probability that the introduction of transgenic crops will enter centers of genetic diversity, it is crucial to protect areas of peasant agriculture free of contamination from GMO crops, as traits important to indigenous farmers (resistance to drought, food or fodder quality, maturity, competitive ability, performance on intercrops, storage quality, taste or cooking properties, compatibility with household labor conditions, etc) could be traded for transgenic qualities (i.e. herbicide resistance) which are of no importance to farmers who don’t use agrochemicals . Under this scenario risk will increase and farmers will lose their ability to produce relatively stable yields with a minimum of external inputs under changing biophysical environments. The social impacts of local crop shortfalls, resulting from changes in the genetic integrity of local varieties due to genetic pollution, can be considerable in the margins of the Global South. Maintaining pools of genetic diversity, geographically isolated from any possibility of cross fertilization or genetic pollution from uniform transgenic crops will create “islands” of intact germplasm which will act as extant safeguards against potential ecological failure derived from the second green revolution increasingly being imposed with programs such as the Gates-Rockefeller AGRA in Africa. These genetic sanctuary islands will serve as the only source of GMO-free seeds that will be needed to repopulate the organic farms in the North inevitably contaminated by the advance of transgenic agriculture. The small farmers and indigenous communities of the Global South, with the help of scientists and NGOs, can continue to create and guard biological and genetic diversity that has enriched the food culture of the whole planet. 5. Small farms cool the climate While industrial agriculture contributes directly to climate change through no less than one third of total emissions of the major greenhouse gases — Carbon dioxide (CO2), methane (CH4), and nitrous oxide (N2O), small, biodiverse organic farms have the opposite effect by sequestering more carbon in soils. Small farmers usually treat their soils with organic compost materials that absorb and sequester carbon better than soils that are farmed with conventional fertilizers. Researchers have suggested that the conversion of 10,000 small- to medium-sized farms to organic production would store carbon in the soil equivalent to taking 1,174,400 cars off the road. Further climate amelioration contributions by small farms accrue from the fact that most use significantly less fossil fuel in comparison to conventional agriculture mainly due to a reduction of chemical fertilizer and pesticide use, relying instead on organic manures, legume-based rotations, and diversity schemes to enhance beneficial insects. Farmers who live in rural communities near cities and towns and are linked to local markets, avoid the energy wasted and the gas emissions associated with transporting food hundreds and even thousands of miles. Conclusions The great advantage of small farming systems is their high levels of agrobidoversity arranged in the form of variety mixtures, polycultures, crop-livestock combinations and/or agroforestry patterns. Modeling new agroecosystems using such diversified designs are extremely valuable to farmers whose systems are collapsing due to debt, pesticide use, transgenic treadmills, or climate change. Such diverse systems buffer against natural or human-induced variations in production conditions. There is much to learn from indigenous modes of production, as these systems have a strong ecological basis, maintain valuable genetic diversity, and lead to regeneration and preservation of biodiversity and natural resources. Traditional methods are particularly instructive because they provide a long-term perspective on successful agricultural management under conditions of climatic variability. Organized social rural movements in the Global South oppose industrial agriculture in all its manifestations, and increasingly their territories constitute isolated areas rich in unique agrobiodiversity, including genetically diverse material, therefore acting as extant safeguards against the potential ecological failure derived from inappropriate agricultural modernization schemes. It is precisely the ability to generate and maintain diverse crop genetic resources that offer “unique” niche possibilities to small farmers that cannot be replicated by farmers in the North who are condemned to uniform cultivars and to co-exist with GMOs. The “ cibo pulito, justo e buono” that Slow Food promotes, the Fair Trade coffee, bananas, and the organic products so much in demand by northern consumers can only be produced in the agroecological islands of the South. This “difference” inherent to traditional systems, can be strategically utilized to revitalize small farming communities by exploiting opportunities that exist for linking traditional agrobiodiversity with local/national/international markets, as long as these activities are justly compensated by the North and all the segments of the market remain under grassroots control. Consumers of the North can play a major role by supporting these more equitable markets which do not perpetuate the colonial model of “agriculture of the poor for the rich,” but rather a model that promotes small biodiverse farms as the basis for strong rural economies in the Global South. Such economies will not only provide sustainable production of healthy, agroecologically-produced, accessible food for all, but will allow indigenous peoples and small farmers to continue their millennial work of building and conserving the agricultural and natural biodiversity on which we all depend now and even more so in the future. Adv 2 Advantage 2 is Cartels -Legalization eliminates illicit markets that drives unprecedented waves of violence Armentano, 09 [Paul Armentano is the Deputy Director of NORML and the NORML Foundation. Mr. Armentano is recognized as an expert on the subject of marijuana policy.ARTICLE How to End Mexico's Deadly Drug War NOVEMBER 18, 2009 by PAUL ARMENTANO, http://www.fee.org/the_freeman/detail/how-to-end-mexicos-deadly-drug-war] officials estimate that approximately half the marijuana consumed in the have identified Mexico as far and away America’s largest pot How much of this goes directly to Mexican cartels is difficult to quantify, but no doubt the percentage is significant. Government United States originates from outside its borders, and they provider. Because Mexican-grown marijuana tends to fetch lower prices on the black market than domestically grown weed (a result attributed largely to lower production costs—the Mexican variety tends to be grown outdoors, while an increasing percentage of American-grown pot is produced hydroponically indoors), it remains consistently popular among U.S. consumers, particularly in a down economy. As a result, U.S. law officials now report that some Mexican cartels are moving to the United States to set up shop permanently. A Congressional Research Service report says low-level cartel members are now establishing clandestine growing operations inside the United States (thus eliminating the need to cross the border), as well as partnering with domestic gangs and other criminal enterprises. A March 23 New York In short, America’s multibillion-dollar demand for pot is fueling the Mexican drug trade and much of the turf battles and carnage associated with it. Same Old “Solutions” So what are the administration’s plans to quell the cartels’ growing influence and surging violence? Troublingly, the White House Times story speculated that Mexican drug gangs or their affiliates are now active in some 230 U.S. cities, extending from Tucson, Arizona, to Anchorage, Alaska. appears intent on recycling the very strategies that gave rise to Mexico’s infamous drug lords in the first place. In March the administration requested $700 million from Congress to “bolster existing efforts by Washington and Mexican President Felipe Calderón’s administration to fight violent trafficking in drugs . . . into the United States.” These efforts, as described by the Los Angeles Times, include: “vowing to send U.S. money, manpower, and technology to the southwestern border” and “reducing illegal flows (of drugs) in both directions across the border.” The administration also announced that it intends to clamp down marijuana production is a lucrative business that attracts criminal entrepreneurs precisely because it is a black-market (and highly sought after) commodity. As long as pot remains federally prohibited its retail price to the consumer will remain artificially high, and its production and distribution will attract criminal enterprises willing to turn to violence (rather than the judicial system) to maintain their slice of the multi-billion-dollar pie. Second, the United States is already spending more money on illicit-drug law enforcement, drug treatment, and drug courts than at on the U.S. demand for illicit drugs by increasing funding for drug treatment and drug courts. There are three primary problems with this strategy. First, any time in our history. FBI data show that domestic marijuana arrests have increased from under 300,000 annually in 1991 to over 800,000 today. Police seizures of marijuana have also risen dramatically in recent years, as has the amount of taxpayer dollars federal officials have spent on so-called “educational efforts” to discourage the drug’s use. (For example, since the late 1990s Congress has appropriated well over law enforcement’s recent attempts to crack down on the cartels’ marijuana distribution rings, particularly new efforts launched by the Calderón administration in Mexico, are driving the unprecedented wave in Mexican violence—not abating it. The New York Times states: “A crackdown begun more than two years ago by President Felipe Calderón, coupled with feuds over turf and control of the organizations, has set off an unprecedented wave of killings in Mexico. . . . Many of the victims were tortured. Beheadings have become common.” Because of this escalating violence, Mexico now ranks behind only Pakistan and Iran as the administration’s top international security concern. Despite the rising death toll, drug war hawks at the U.S. Drug Enforcement Administration (DEA) remain adamant that the United States’ and a billion dollars in anti-pot public service announcements alone.) Yet despite these combined efforts to discourage demand, Americans use more pot than anyone else in the world. Third, Mexico’s “supply side” strategies are in fact successful. “Our view is that the violence we have been seeing is a signpost of the success our very courageous Mexican counterparts are having,” acting DEA administrator Michele Lionhart said recently. “The cartels are acting out like caged animals, because they are caged animals.” President Obama also appears to share this view. After visiting with the Calderón government in April, he told CNN he intended to “beef up” security on the border. When asked whether the administration would consider alternative strategies, such as potentially liberalizing pot’s criminal classification, Homeland Security Secretary Janet Napolitano replied that such an option “is not on the table.” A New Remedy By contrast the Calderón administration appears open to the idea of legalizing marijuana—or at least reducing criminal sanctions on the possession of small quantities of drugs—as a way to stem the tide of violence. Last spring Mexican lawmakers made the possession of personal-use quantities of cannabis and other illicit substances a noncriminal offense. And in April Mexico’s ambassador to the United States, Arturo Sarukhan, told CBS’s Face the Nation that legalizing the marijuana trade was a legitimate option for both the Mexican and U.S. governments. “[T]hose who would suggest that some of these measures [legalization] be looked at understand the dynamics of the drug trade,” Sarukhan said. Former Mexican President Vicente Fox recently echoed Sarukhan’s remarks, as did a commission of former Latin American presidents. “I believe it’s time to open the debate over legalizing drugs,” Fox told CNN in Jeffrey Miron said that ending drug prohibition—on both sides of the border—is the only realistic and viable way to put a permanent stop to the rising power and violence associated with Mexico’s drug traffickers. “Prohibition creates violence because it drives the drug market underground,” he wrote. “This means buyers and sellers cannot resolve their disputes with lawsuits, arbitration or advertising, so they resort to violence instead. . . . The only way to reduce violence, therefore, is to legalize drugs.” Growing May. “It can’t be that the only way [to try to control illicit drug use] is for the state to use force.” Writing recently on CNN.com, Harvard economist and Freeman contributor Support Americans’ support for legalizing the regulated production and sale of cannabis—an option that would not likely rid the world of cartels, but would arguably reduce their primary source of income—is at all an all-time high. In May a national Zogby telephone poll of 3,937 voters by the Republican-leaning O’Leary Report discovered, for the first time ever, that a slight majority (52 percent) of Americans “favor the Predictably, critics of marijuana legalization claim that such a strategy would do little to undermine drug traffickers’ profit margins because cartels would simply supplement their revenues by selling greater quantities of other illicit drugs. legalization of marijuana.” A separate Zogby poll reported even stronger support (58 percent) among west-coast voters. Although this scenario sounds plausible in theory, it appears to be far less likely in practice. As noted, Mexican drug lords derive an estimated 60 to 70 percent of their illicit income from pot sales. (By comparison, only about 28 percent of their profits are derived from the distribution of cocaine, and less than 1 percent comes from trafficking methamphetamine.) It is unrealistic to think that cartels could feasibly replace this void by stepping up their sales of cocaine, methamphetamine or heroin—all of which remain far less popular among U.S. drug consumers anyway. Just how much less? U.S. Department of Health and Human Services survey data show that roughly two million Americans use cocaine, compared to 15 million for pot. Fewer than 600,000 use methamphetamine, and fewer than 155,000 use heroin. In short, this is hardly the sort of demand that would keep Mexico’s drug barons in the lucrative lifestyle to which they’ve become accustomed. Of course, it’s unrealistic to think that pot legalization would wipe out prohibition-inspired violence altogether. After all, ending alcohol prohibition in America didn’t singlehandedly put the Mafia out of business (though it greatly reduced its power and influence). And it’s always possible that Mexico’s drug cartels would continue to engage in violent acts toward one another as it’s equally unrealistic, if not more so, to think that continuing our same failed drug war policies will do anything but exponentially increase the catastrophe they’ve spawned, both in Mexico and at home. It’s time to engage in a different strategy. It’s time to seriously consider legalizing marijuana and other drugs. competing factions fought over the crumbs of America’s drastically shrunken illicit-drug market. That said, Cartel violence must be stopped otherwise mass violence and atrocities will continue unabated Farah, 14 [Senior Fellow of Financial Investigations and Transparency @ International Assessment of Strategy Center, Douglas Farah (President of IBI Consultants, national security consulting firm) “Loss of Central America’s Northern Triangle,” Miami Herald, February 2, 2014] the Northern Triangle of Central America (Guatemala, Honduras and El Salvador) has earned the unenviable position as the world’s most violent corner . The growing importance of the region as a multifaceted transshipment corridor for transnational organized crime (TOC) groups — primarily Mexican drug trafficking syndicates — has brought a new and dangerous alignment in the region’s power structures. The decapitations and dismemberments are copycat rituals of Los Zetas , the feared Mexican drug trafficking enterprise that now controls significant territory in Central America . The U. S. government estimates that Over the past decade, approximately 95 percent of the cocaine leaving South America for the United States moves through the Mexico and Central America corridor. As pressure on the TOC groups has increased in Mexico, the criminal enterprises have migrated southward with a vengeance. The result has been that the three governments of the Northern Triangle have moved from being weak, somewhat corrupt and unresponsive to almost nonfunctional in much of their national territories. The region’s civil wars in the 1970s and 1980s, in which the United States, Cuba and the Soviet bloc were deeply involved, left hundreds of thousands dead. But the negotiated end to the wars also left a sense of hope that the nations could rebuild with new institutions, new laws and a commitment to address the social issues that drove the conflicts. That hope is gone, replaced by deep cynicism and dismay that governments of both the right and the left immediately sought to turn their countries into piñatas in which only a few on either side benefited. The far left and far right, after decades of blood letting, found they could make money together while their countries entered into downward spirals of impunity, violence and massive corruption. While none of the issues driving the collapse are new, they now appear to have driven the governments past a tipping point in the correlation of forces between the state and TOC organizations. Transnational criminal organizations are on the rise and the positive state presence ever less accessible to citizens. The governments are largely incapable of solving most of the serious issues in ways that strengthen the democratic process, rule of law of citizen security. The Northern Triangle is emerging as a region where the state is often no longer the main power center or has become so entwined with a complex and inter-related web of illicit activities and actors that the state itself at times becomes a part of the criminal enterprise. There are virtually no “ungoverned spaces” in the region. Some group exercises real political and military control in almost every corner of every country. What has changed is that the authority is less and less often the state. Sunday’s elections in El Salvador, in which the gang truce is a major issue, offer cautionary tales. President Mauricio Funes won as a candidate for the former guerrilla Farabundo Martí National Liberation Front (FMLN) party despite never having been a member of the group. He has presided over a stagnant economy, the failed gang “truce” and a rising tide of narco activity. Rather than broker a transparent pact between the MS-13 (Mara Salvatrucha) and Calle 18 gangs — the two largest transnational gangs — the opaque process begun in March 2012 has benefited drug trafficking organizations, expanded the territories under gang control, given the gangs their first real taste of political power and completely ignored the victims. Yet, the pact has the backing of the the number of people “disappeared” has risen sharply and the likely hundreds of bodies in the clandestine cemeteries that are now coming to light indicate how untrue that promise was. Rather than dumping the bodies of their victims on the streets, the gangs simply buried them in shallow graves scattered across the country, giving a short-lived appearance of ebbing violence. The gangs negotiated as equals with the government to gain complete control of the prisons in which their leaders are kept, controlling the flow of prostitutes, drugs, cash and mobile phones into the facilities. In much of the country the gangs are the true authority on the ground. In addition to killing with impunity , they check the ID cards of strangers in their neighborhoods and deny access to those they don’t like. They regularly collect taxes, in the form of Organization of American States. The sole justification for the truce was the drop in homicides it promised to bring, and in the early days the promise seemed to bear fruit. But after almost two years, extortion, and control the sale of crack and cocaine in their neighborhoods. The state, rather than benefiting the populace, is relegated to the role of broker among illicit power actors in which the brokers reap The results have been catastrophic , both for the people of El Salvador and the rule of law in the region. The grisly bodies still being excavated from the multiple clandestine cemeteries include those of small children, street vendors and the elderly, an evangelical preacher, and rival gang members. The level of mutilation is something not seen since the 1980s, when death squads dumped bodies at designated sites for the vultures to pick at. The emergence of some branches of the transnational gangs as major enormous benefits but the country reaps only chaos. new actors in the drug trade, particularly in El Salvador, adds a new level of complexity to the regional dynamics and underscores the powerlessness of the states. The current FMLN candidate, Salvador Sánchez Cerén, a former FMLN commander, has promised to move El Salvador to the radical populism that Hugo Chávez pioneered, where the states become increasingly authoritarian, intolerant and criminalized. Awash in millions of dollars in campaign cash, whose origin the party cannot or will not explain, the FMLN is now heavily favored to win and the promise of revolutionary transparency is unkept. Norman Quijano, the candidate for the conservative Republican Nationalist Alliance (ARENA) — a party founded on death squad activity — has promised a harsh crackdown on the gangs and a return of power to the traditional business class who tend to run the country as their estates, the very reason his party was voted out of office in 2009. Antonio Saca, a former president who formed his own party, was expelled by ARENA after his presidential term for alleged massive corruption that surpassed the patience of even those long accustomed to running a kleptocracy. His enormous new mansions and unexplained fortune have done little to dispel suspicions of the origin of his money. These options are emblematic of the Hobbesian choices facing most countries in Central America. None of the leaders of the Northern Triangle are offering new thinking on how to tackle the multiple, complex problems in the region. The reality is that the host of factors driving the violence and the hollowing out of the states can only be tackled at a regional level. Each individual country is too small, too insular and too poor to do much on its own. The United States must engage with the region as a whole, both out of self-interest and the interests of those in the region seeking a new paradigm that moves beyond transactional politics of corruption and violence to rule of law, economic freedom and transparency. Yet, the U.S. cannot want change more than the Central American governments do, nor can it help when the elites — both the traditional and emerging groups — do not view real reform as in their self-interest. Policy options are limited and complex, but the crisis is growing quickly. This violence is a function of the war on drugs which necessitates an ever increasing death count --- this wreaks an immense psychological toll on hundreds of thousands of people Lohmuller, 14 [The Drug War and Post-Traumatic Stress Disorder: Mexico’s Hidden Epidemic August 22, 2014 · by COHA · in COHA Research, Drug Trafficking, Mexico, Publications Print Friendly By: Michael Lohmuller, Research Associate at the Council on Hemispheric Affairshttp://www.coha.org/the-drug-war-and-post-traumatic-stress-disordermexicos-hidden-epidemic/] In recent years, the Mexican drug war has consistently made headlines for its appalling levels of violence and ever-increasing death count; with a figure approaching 70,000 people killed since 2006. Previously, violence in Mexico had largely been associated with drug trafficking and was concentrated in a handful of regions along key smuggling routes, especially near the U.S. border. However, under the Felipe Calderón administration (2006-2012), Mexico’s drug cartels faced rising pressure from state security forces, resulting in their fragmentation and the dispersal of criminal violence around the country. Drug cartels responded to enhanced counternarcotics operations by expanding their criminal portfolios into locally focused crime in order to supplement their earnings. This has led to a sharp increase in cases of extortion and kidnapping (979 and 3,634 cases, respectively, were reported through the first six months of 2014), wreaking havoc on Mexican society.[1] A side effect of this violence that has received relatively little attention is the impact on the mental health of victims and the community at-large. More specifically, violence accompanying the Mexican drug war has contributed to a pervasive sense of fear and insecurity, creating conditions that have put millions of Mexican citizens at risk for developing post-traumatic stress disorder (PTSD). PTSD is most commonly associated with soldiers returning from war, and has attracted widespread attention in the United States for its effects on veterans of the Iraq and Afghanistan wars. Yet, while Mexico is not at war in the traditional sense, many Mexican communities live in a state of siege—either actual or perceived. While some areas are affected more than others, the majority of Mexican communities have been exposed—directly or indirectly—to various degrees of traumatic violence. Nevertheless, the Mexican state has not devoted adequate attention to those victimized by violence. This role has largely been taken up by a number of civil society organizations, such as Ciudadanos en Apoyo a Los Derechos Humanos (CADHAC) in Nuevo León and the Movimiento por la Paz con Justicia y Dignidad (Movement for Peace with Justice and Dignity). In conjunction with the important role of these organizations, however, it is imperative that the Mexican government and health system acknowledge and research the problem of PTSD in victimized populations. The short- and long-term effects of high levels of violence on the mental health and fabric of Mexican society could potentially be grave. For the sake of Mexico’s future generations, it is therefore crucial that the Mexican state begin allocating sufficient resources towards supporting those victimized by violence in order to mitigate the growth of PTSD’s nefarious consequences. Mexico’s Escalation of Crime & Violence Felipe Calderónis widely regarded as one of the catalysts for Mexico’s current wave of violence. Upon taking theoffice of the presidency in 2006, Calderón declared a war against Mexico’s drug cartels. This consisted of an aggressive strategy of confrontation and, with the deployment of the armed forces into Mexico’s streets and communities, the increasing militarization of policing functions. Drug cartels, now finding themselves the target of antagonistic governmental policies, escalated the brutality of their tactics. This was done in order both to defend themselves against incursions by state security forces and to exploit any openings created to win territory from rivals. Violence quickly spiraled out of control, and has been extraordinary in its severity and indiscriminate targeting. Mass killings, torture, dismemberment, disappeared persons, extortion, and kidnapping have become all too commonplace, leaving a wake of destruction rippling through Mexican society as hundreds of thousands suffered. The scale of violence in Mexico is difficult to grasp. During the six years of Calderón’s term (2006-2012), more than 50,000 people were killed (a total of over 70,000 have reportedly died through 2014), 250,000 were displaced from their homes, 10,000 disappeared, and 8,000 wereorphaned.[2] By 2010, the homicide rate was double that of 2006.[3] Fortunately, homicide figures for 2012 and 2013 have shown a slight declining trend. However, extortion and kidnapping levels have increased at an alarming rate. According to official statistics from Mexico’s Interior Ministry (SEGOB), there were 8,199 reported incidences of extortion in 2013, higher than any other year in the past decade.[4] There has also been a steady rise in documented cases of kidnapping, climbing from 438 in 2007 to 1,698 in 2013.[5] Nonetheless, it is estimated that the vast majority of kidnappings and extortions have gone unreported. Victims are often reluctant to seek help from officials for fear of retribution by criminal groups or that the police are corrupt and in cahoots with the criminals. Overall, after nearly eight years of elevated levels of criminal violence, hundreds of thousands of people have been directly or indirectly victimized. Many Mexican citizens rightfully perceive the government as inept and unable to provide adequate security and justice. This has contributed to the creation of a far-reaching climate of insecurity, fear, and helplessness. High rates of exposure to traumatic experiences among Mexico’s populace, along with extensive and often graphic media coverage, have produced degrees of trauma similar to those usually characterized with war zones. Consequently, many experts now say mental health conditions typically associated with war veterans, such as PTSD, are on the rise in Mexico. What is PTSD? According to The National Institute of Mental Health (NIMH), PTSD develops after a person experiences “a terrifying ordeal that involved physical harm or the threat of physical harm.”[6] Someone who develops PTSD “may have been the one who was harmed,” but the harm may also “have happened to a loved one, or the person may have witnessed a harmful event that happened to loved ones or strangers.”[7] According to the Mayo Clinic, the most common events driving PTSD’s development include combat exposure, childhood neglect and physical abuse, sexual assault, physical attack, and being threatened with a weapon.[8] Other events that may also bring about PTSD are, among others, natural disasters, robbery, torture, and kidnapping. The Mayo Clinic also reports that those who do suffer from PTSD have demonstrated difficulties in maintaining their job, relationships, health, and quality of life. In addition, PTSD has been found to increase the risk of developing other mental health problems, such as depression and anxiety, as well as substance abuse or suicidal thoughts and actions.[9] While PTSD can cause numerous symptoms, the NIMH classifies them into three broad categories: reexperiencing symptoms, avoidance symptoms, and hyperarousal symptoms.[10] Bad dreams or flashbacks are examples of re-experiencing symptoms. Avoidance symptoms may include feelings of strong guilt or depression, loss of interest in activities one enjoyed in the past, and staying away from places or objects that are reminders of the traumatic experience. Hyperarousal symptoms may consist of being easily startled, feeling tense or “on edge,” having difficulty sleeping, and angry outbursts. To be diagnosed with PTSD, a person must exhibit at least one re-experiencing symptom, at least three avoidance symptoms, and at least two hyperarousal symptoms for at least one month.[11] PTSD in Civilian Populations Several existing studies on the mental health of civilian populations living in violent communities in U.S. cities offer a source for drawing comparisons with the case of Mexico. Despite cross-cultural differences, the studies demonstrate that PTSD can indeed have a wide presence in civilian populations affected by disconcerting levels of violence; a concerning find for Mexican society given the wide percentage of Mexico’s population that has been exposed to traumatic experiences. An investigationby theGrady Trauma Projectstudied residents of violent inner-city communities in Atlanta.[12] Interviews with 8,000 inner city residents found that one in three reported experiencing symptoms consistent with PTSD at some point in their lives. Dr. Kerry Ressler, the lead researcher of the project, said, “The rates of PTSD we see are as high or higher than Iraq, Afghanistan or Vietnam veterans. We have a whole population who is traumatized.”[13] Another study took place in Chicago’s Cook County Hospital, which treats around 2,000 patients per year for gunshots, stabbings, and other violent injuries.[14] Beginning in 2011, researchers screened patients for PTSD, and observed that four in 10 patients displayed symptoms. There was an even higher rate among those wounded by guns—over 50 percent. “We knew these people were going to have PTSD symptoms,” said Kimberly Joseph, a trauma surgeon at the hospital. “We didn’t know it was going to be as extensive.”[15] The two studies’ conclusions suggest that traumatic violence has influenced entire communities in these areas. This cumulative social stress can undermine the fundamental institutions of family, work, and education, both at an individual and a collective level. At a broad level, these Atlanta and Chicago communities have much in common with their Mexican counterparts: they are extremely poor, are plagued by inequality and violent crime, and have limited access to hospitals or mental health services. Given comparable violence-levels and circumstances to these U.S. inner city communities, it is likely that many Mexican communities exhibit similar patterns of PTSD rates among residents. PTSD Among Mexican Civilians Indeed, many experts now say PTSD is on the rise in Mexico due to the extreme violence seen over the past decade. The border city of Ciudad Juárez, the epicenter of Mexico’s drug war from 2007-2012, has been particularly impacted. In 2010, homicide levels in the city peaked at roughly 60 murders per week.[16] In fact, in 2010 more than half of all executions, shootings, disappearances, and kidnappings that occurred in Mexico were concentrated in Ciudad Juárez. Consequently, according to figures cited in a 2013 study by researchers from the National Autonomous University of Mexico, the Ciudad Juárez Municipality has estimated that 14-30 percent of the city’s more than 1.3 million residents suffer from PTSD due to both direct and indirect exposure to violent acts.[17] At first, the hardest hit communities, such as Ciudad Juárez, were located in Mexico’s outlying states where the drug cartels are most powerful. However, Mauricio Meschoulam from the Ibero-American University has said the psychosocial damage has spread beyond those areas, so that the prevalence of PTSD symptoms is now not exclusively found in Mexico’s most violent municipalities. Meschoulam attributes this to heavy media coverage, remarking that “people’s stress levels are directly proportional to their exposure to the mass media,” which transmits terror and panic.[18] This, he insists, indicates a contagious phenomenon, with PTSD “spreading rapidly in populations like that of the capital and other cities in Mexico.” A study conducted by Meschoulam, Estudio sobre efectos psicosociales por violencia en México (Study on Psychosocial Effects of Violence in Mexico), provides some indicators of the violence’s detrimental repercussions on citizens’ mental health. The research was based on a sample of 333 people from 15 of Mexico’s 32 states, who were given a questionnaire. The results discovered that 51 percent of the interviewees said violence affected their work life, 72 percent their social life, and 58 percent their family life.[19] A further 42 percent of the respondents asserted violence had an impact on their economic status, and 60 percent reported that it had influenced their mental health. Half of the respondents perceived the media to be the principal transmission channel of stress. Furthermore, 10 percent changed their residence out of fear, 80 percent had stopped frequenting places out of fear, and 54 percent had altered their daily routine.[20] The 2012 National Survey on Victimization and Perception of Public Security, administered by the Mexican government’s statistics agency INEGI, reported the number of households with at least one adult victim of crime to be 9,261,721—nearly 31 percent of Mexican households.[21] However, most Mexicans are indirect victims of violence; as a result, they cannot be figured into any official government statistics measuring victimization rates. Many people, however, feel that they are more than mere bystanders because they have been forced to change how they live, work, travel, and conduct their social activities.[22] México Evalúa, a Mexican government watchdog, totaled the number of visible and invisible victims of serious crime between 1997 and 2011 at 12,993,010—of which 3,208,213 are “visible” victims, while 9,748,797 are the “invisible” victims. It has been estimated that only 22 percent of total crimes committed are reported, with the remaining 72 percent referred to as Mexico’s cifra negra, or “black statistic.”[23] Raúl Villamil Uriarte, a social psychologist and anthropologist at the Metropolitan Autonomous University in Mexico City, stated, “People are experiencing terror from this world of death and violence. The nation is suffering post-traumatic stress disorder from all this violence playing out.”[24] Civil Society Responds Access to mental health services is limited because of Mexico’s centralized health care system, meaning the majority of establishments are located in large cities. An investigation into Mexico’s mental health system published in April 2013 found that only 30 percent of primary care services possess protocols for the evaluation and treatment of mental disorders. Additionally, the report discovered Mexico’s meager mental health facilities, with the low ratios of 1.6 psychiatrists, 1.3 other physicians, 3.4 nurses, and 1.5 psychologists per 100,000 of the population.[25] Dr. Elena Azaola, a prominent social anthropologist in Mexico City, said that while the government has been trying to implement more programs to prevent crime, there are no programs dedicated to working with these types of PTSD victims. Furthermore, Dr. Azaola mentioned that there is a general lack of awareness on the need to provide mental health services, with extremely low budgets and professional abilities to manage the issue. Support groups—religious, community, or family—have therefore been critical in helping people deal with the negative side effects of exposure to traumatic experiences. A number of civil society organizations also provide vital support and mental health services for victims of traumatic violence. These are largely organized on a local basis, and have sprung up in various localities around Mexico.[26] One of these organizations, Ciudadanos en Apoyo a Los Derechos Humanos (CADHAC), is based in the Mexican state of Nuevo León. CADHAC has been working with human rights victims by offering legal services as well as psychosocial support. Starting in 2011, CADHAC began to pay particular attention to psychological support for family members of people who had disappeared as a result of organized crime. Liz Sánchez Reyna and Ana Luna, two employees at CADHAC with experience working with victims, said the violence has been particularly intense since 2009—including executions, disappearances, extortion, arbitrary detentions, and torture.[27] Between the effects documented, CADHAC has observed a general fear in the population, which they assert has resulted in people living in a different manner than pre-2009. Now, people are more reluctant to be on the streets for fear they may be victimized. This fear, Reyna and Luna say, has impacted the community in general, damaging the overall social fabric.[28] CADHAC has also witnessed an increase in the number of cases of people with PTSD, which Reyna and Luna directly relate to the presence of violence and high incidences of disappearances, torture, abuse of authority, extrajudicial executions, and domestic violence. Governmental institutions, they declare, were not prepared to handle the violence’s ramifications and have had to learn on the fly. Reyna and Luna also likened Mexico to a war zone, and spoke of an inter-generational impact that violence will have, saying, “It will take many years for the population to recuperate from this wound that is still open.”[29] Moving Forward In the near-term, the immediate goal for Mexico needs to be the strengthening of police and judicial institutions to betterprotect and provide justice for victims of violent crime. Mexico’s powerful criminal organizations must be prevented from waging war against the citizenry with near total impunity. Statutory change is key to end prohibition – the CSA itself chills access to marijuana Gettman, 14 [4/19/14, Jon, Ph.D. in public policy, teaching undergraduate criminal justice and graduate level management courses., “Remove Marijuana from the Controlled Substances Act” http://www.hightimes.com/read/remove-marijuana-controlled-substances-act] Marijuana does not belong in the Controlled Substances Act. Any scheduling of marijuana in the Controlled Substances Act is a threat to state laws medical marijuana use and medical marijuana . Rescheduling is an obsolete remedy, once long overdue but now its only value would be to provide a pretext to roll back or eliminate the advances brought about by state level reform. The CSA is intended to regulate pharmaceutical products, manufactured by corporations, and provided to patients according to prescriptions issued by doctors. Marijuana is not a pharmaceutical product, it is grown not manufactured, and no doctor in the United States can write a prescription for a substance that remains unapproved by the Food and Drug Administration. State medical marijuana laws challenge the premise that marijuana should be subject to this federal regulatory framework. State medical marijuana law are part of a process, governed by the principles of federalism, to develop alternative regulatory approaches that better serve the needs of patients and caregivers. Rescheduling is advanced today as a means of expediting research on medical marijuana that would provide the means to successfully challenge the DEA’s opposition to recognizing the therapeutic If Congress is willing and able to pass a law providing protection for state programs and medical benefits of cannabis. Some also hope the provisions of any bill passed by Congress to change marijuana’s placement in the CSA would include protections for state medical marijuana programs and patients. This poses an obvious question. why not just remove marijuana from the CSA and provide such protections? cannabis users, then Also, as a related but perhaps separate matter, if Congress is willing and able to pass a law to expedite research on the medical use of cannabis, why not establish appropriate regulations outside the framework of the Controlled Substances Act? The reader may have noticed that this discussion has not included any explanation of the differences in the various schedules of the CSA and how placement in one schedule or another would affect research or medical availability. This is because it doesn’t matter. A different schedule for marijuana would make research easier, but Congress could accomplish that with specific legislation. As long as marijuana is subject to the CSA, there There was a time when the symbolic ramifications of rescheduling would have helped to advance reform of the nation’s marijuana laws. That time is past. Passage of state-level medical marijuana laws has accomplished that, and much more – they have provided legitimacy, access and legal protections At the federal level it is time for substantive changes in federal law and policy, not symbolism, nor halfwill be no legal medical use under federal law until there is FDA approval of corporate, patented, pharmaceutical cannabis products. . measures, nor tinkering around with the CSA to provide the appearance of action without providing any significant relief for patients Imagine the following scenario. . Marijuana is rescheduled and the DEA then aggressively attempts to make all medical marijuana access in the US subject to the regulatory restrictions established by the CSA. Access to marijuana is reduced and made much more complicated as tighter controls are enacted medical under state programs . Within a few years Sativex, a cannabis pharmaceutical product, will be approved for sale in the US by the Food and Drug Administration. The DEA will probably make it a Schedule III substance, like Marinol (the THC pill) or maybe even something less restrictive. The DEA will then argue that while access to medical marijuana may have been necessary in years past, this new pharmaceutical product has rendered medical marijuana obsolete. Is this the Obama Administration’s plan? Maybe, but However, Obama will only be in office until 2016. What then? Who knows? What we do know is that the CSA is not a practical regulatory framework for medical cannabis and that it can be used to roll back cannabis access. Right now, everybody involved in medical cannabis distribution can be indicted under federal law if not now under this Attorney General then later under another one. Rescheduling marijuana once had potential to advance marijuana law reform. It no longer does It’s time to change probably not. or eliminate medical , . State level reform has changed the playing field in significant and profound ways. federal law to address the legitimate needs of patients in every state . This means removing marijuana from the Controlled Substances Act and federal passage of a new piece of legislation granting every American access to marijuana in a legal regulated market. Specific engagement with the nuances of institutional reform serves to repurpose broader systems towards desirable ends Ferguson, 11 [Professor of Anthropology at Stanford, 11 (The Uses of Neoliberalism, Antipode, Vol. 41, No. S1, pp 166–184] If we are seeking, as this special issue of Antipode aspires to do, to link our critical analyses to the world of grounded political struggle—not only to interpret the world in various ways, but also to change it —then there is much to be said for focusing, as I have here, on mundane, real- world debates around policy and politics, even if doing so inevitably puts us on the compromised and reformist terrain of the possible, rather than the seductive high ground of revolutionary ideals and utopian desires. But I would also insist that there is more at stake in the examples I have discussed here than simply a slightly better way to ameliorate the miseries of the chronically poor, or a technically superior method for relieving the suffering of famine victims.¶ My point in discussing the South African BIG campaign, for instance, is not really to argue for its implementation. There is much in the campaign that is appealing, to be sure. But one can just as easily identify a series of worries that would bring the whole proposal into doubt. Does not, for instance, the decoupling of the question of assistance from the issue of labor, and the associated valorization of the “informal”, help provide a kind of alibi for the failures of the South African regime to pursue policies that would do more to create jobs? Would not the creation of a basic income benefit tied to national citizenship simply exacerbate the vicious xenophobia that already divides the South African poor, ¶ in a context where many of the poorest are not citizens, and would thus not be eligible for the BIG? Perhaps even more fundamentally, is the idea of basic income really capable of commanding the mass support that alone could make it a central pillar of a new approach to distribution? The record to date gives powerful reasons to doubt it. So far, the technocrats’ dreams of relieving poverty through efficient cash transfers have attracted little support from actual poor people, who seem to find that vision a bit pale and washed out, compared with the vivid (if vague) populist promises of jobs and personalistic social inclusion long offered by the ANC patronage machine, and lately personified by Jacob Zuma (Ferguson forthcoming).¶ My real interest in the policy proposals discussed here, in fact, has little to do with the narrow policy questions to which they seek to provide answers. For what is most significant, for my purposes, is not whether or not these are good policies, but the way that they illustrate a process through which specific governmental devices and modes of reasoning that we have become used to associating with a very particular (and conservative) political agenda (“neoliberalism”) may be in the process of being peeled away from that agenda, and put to very different uses. Any progressive who takes seriously the challenge I pointed to at the start of this essay, the challenge of developing new progressive arts of government , ought to find this turn of events of considerable interest.¶ As Steven Collier (2005) has recently pointed out, it is important to question the assumption that there is, or must be, a neat or automatic fit between a hegemonic “neoliberal” politicaleconomic project (however that might be characterized), on the one hand, and specific “neoliberal” techniques , on the other. Close attention to particular techniques (such as the use of quantitative calculation, free choice, and price driven by supply and demand) in particular settings (in Collier’s case, fiscal and budgetary reform in post-Soviet Russia) shows that the relationship between the technical and the political-economic “ is much more polymorphous and unstable than is assumed in much critical geographical work”, and that neoliberal technical mechanisms are in fact “deployed in relation to diverse political projects and social norms” (2005:2).¶ As I suggested in referencing the role of statistics and techniques for pooling risk in the creation of social democratic welfare states, social technologies need not have any essential or eternal loyalty to the political formations within which they were first developed. Insurance rationality at the end of the nineteenth century had no essential vocation to provide security and solidarity to the working class; it was turned to that purpose (in some substantial measure) because it was available, in the right place at the right time, to be appropriated for that use. Specific ways of solving or posing governmental problems, specific institutional and intellectual mechanisms, can be combined in an almost infinite variety of ways, to accomplish different social ends. With social, as with any other sort of technology, it is not the machines or the mechanisms that decide what they will be used to do. ¶ Foucault (2008:94) concluded his discussion of socialist government- ality by insisting that the answers to the Left’s governmental problems require not yet another search through our sacred texts, but a process of conceptual and institutional innovation . “[I]f there is a really socialist governmentality, then it is not hidden within socialism and its texts. It cannot be deduced from them. It must be invented”. But invention in the domain of governmental technique is rarely something worked up out of whole cloth. More often, it involves a kind of bricolage (Le ́vi- Strauss 1966), a piecing together of something new out of scavenged parts originally intended for some other purpose. As we pursue such a process of improvisatory invention, we might begin by making an inventory of the parts available for such tinkering, keeping all the while an open mind about how different mechanisms might be put to work, and what kinds of purposes they might serve . If we can go beyond seeing in “neoliberalism” an evil essence or an automatic unity, and instead learn to see a field of specific governmental techniques , we may be surprised to find that some of them can be repurposed, and put to work in the service of political projects very different from those usually associated with that word. If so, we may find that the cabinet of governmental arts available to us is a bit less bare than first appeared, and that some rather useful little mechanisms may be nearer to hand than we thought. Institutions are inevitable and pragmatic engagement best facilitates change – deferring responsibility for the sake of philosophical interrogation leads to policy failure Themba-Nixon 2K – Makani Themba-Nixon, “Changing the Rules: What Public Policy Means for Organizing,” Colorlines. Oakland: Jul 31, 2000. Vol. 3, Iss. 2; pg. 12 Policies are the rules of the world we live in. Changing the world means changing the rules. So, if organizing is about changing the rules and building power, how can organizing be separated from policies? Can we really speak truth to power, fight the right, stop corporate abuses, or win racial justice without contesting the rules and the rulers, the policies and the policymakers? The answer is no-and double no for people of color. Today, racism subtly dominates nearly every aspect of policymaking. From ballot propositions to city funding In essence, policies are the codification of power relationships and resource allocation. priorities, policy is increasingly about the control, de-funding, and disfranchisement of communities of color. What Do We Stand For? Take the public conversation about welfare reform, for example. Most of us know it isn't really about putting people to work. The right's message was framed around racial stereotypes of lazy, cheating "welfare queens" whose poverty was "cultural." But the new welfare policy was about Many of us were too busy to tune into the welfare policy drama in Washington, only to find it washed up right on our doorsteps. Our members are suffering from workfare policies, new regulations, and cutoffs. Families who were barely getting by under the old rules are being pushed over the edge by the new policies. Policy doesn't get more relevant than this . And so we got involved in policyas defense. Yet we have to do more than block their punches. We have to start the fight with initiatives of our own . Those who do are finding offense a bit more fun than defense alone. Living wage ordinances, youth development initiatives, even gun control and alcohol and tobacco policies are finding their way onto the public agenda, thanks to focused community organizing that leverages power for community-driven initiatives. - Over 600 local policies have been passed to regulate the tobacco industry. Local coalitions have taken the lead by writing ordinances that address local problems and organizing broad support for them. - Nearly 100 gun control and violence prevention policies have been enacted since 1991. - Milwaukee, Boston, and Oakland are among the cities that have passed living wage ordinances: local laws that guarantee higher moving billions of dollars in individual cash payments and direct services from welfare recipients to other, more powerful, social actors. These are just a few of the examples that demonstrate how organizing for local policy advocacy has made inroads in areas where positive national policy had been stalled by conservatives. Increasingly, the local policy arena is where the action is and where activists are finding success. Of course, corporate interests-which are usually the target of these policies-are gearing up in defense. Tactics include front groups, economic pressure, and the tried and true: cold, hard cash. Despite these barriers, grassroots organizing can be very effective at the smaller scale of local politics. At the local level, we have greater access to elected officials and officials have a greater reliance on their constituents for reelection. For example, getting 400 people to show up at city hall in just about any city in the U.S. is quite impressive. On the other hand, 400 people at the state house or the Congress would have a less significant impact. Add to that the fact that all 400 people at city hall are usually than minimum wages for workers, usually set as the minimum needed to keep a family of four above poverty. constituents, and the impact is even greater. Recent trends in government underscore the importance of local policy. Congress has enacted a series of measures devolving significant power to state and local Welfare, health care, and the regulation of food and drinking water safety are among the areas where states and localities now have greater rule. Devolution has some negative consequences to be sure. History has taught us that, for social services and civil rights in particular, the lack of clear federal standards and mechanisms for accountability lead to uneven enforcement and even discriminatory implementation of policies. Still, there are real opportunities for advancing progressive initiatives in this more localized environment. Greater local control can mean greater community power to shape and implement important social policies that were heretofore out of reach. To do so will require careful attention to the mechanics of local policymaking and a clear blueprint of what we stand for. Getting It in Writing Much of the work of framing what we stand for takes place in the shaping of demands. By getting into the policy arena in a proactive manner, we can take our demands to the next level. Our demands can become law, with real consequences if the agreement is broken . After all the organizing, press work, and effort, a group should leave a decisionmaker with more than a handshake and his or her word. Of course, this work requires a certain amount of interaction with "the suits," as well as struggles with the bureaucracy, the technical language, and the all-too-common resistance by decisionmakers. Still, if it's worth demanding, it's worth having in writing-whether as law, regulation, or internal policy. From ballot initiatives on rent control to laws requiring worker protections, organizers are leveraging their power into written policies that are making a real difference in their communities. Of course, policy work is just one tool in our organizing arsenal, but it is a tool we simply can't afford to ignore. Making policy work an integral part of government. organizing will require a certain amount of retrofitting. We will need to develop the capacity to translate our information, data, and experience into stories that are designed to affect the public conversation. we will need to move beyond fighting problems and on to framing solutions that bring us closer to our vision of how things should be. And then we must be committed to making it so. Perhaps most important, Situating educational experimentation in the context of political actions reframes agency in a mutually beneficial way Zanotti 14 (Dr. Laura Zanotti is an Associate Professor of Political Science at Virginia Tech. Her research and teaching include critical political theory as well as international organizations, UN peacekeeping, democratization and the role of NGOs in post-conflict governance.“Governmentality, Ontology, Methodology: Re-thinking Political Agency in the Global World” – Alternatives: Global, Local, Political – vol 38(4):p. 288-304, obtained via school library being awesome.) In a similar vein, in a refreshing reading of realism, Brent Steele has highlighted the problematic aspects of assessing political agency based upon actors’ intention and focused on contexts as the yardstick for assessing political actions . 79 For Steele, ‘‘as actors practice their agency within the space of a public sphere, intentionality—at best—becomes dynamic as new spaces in that sphere open up. Intentions, even if they are genuine, become largely irrelevant in such a dynamic, violent, and vibrant realm of human interaction.’’ 80 In shifting attention from ‘‘intention’’ to the context that made some actions possible, Steele sees agency as a ‘‘redescription’’ of existing conditions, rather than the total ‘‘rejection’’ of or ‘‘opposition’’ to a totalizing ‘‘script.’’ As a consequence, Steele advocates ‘‘pragmatist humility’’ for politicians and scholars as well. 81 In summary, in non-substantialist frameworks, agency is conceptualized as modest and multifarious agonic interactions, localized tactics, hybridized engagement and redescriptions, a series of uncertain and situated responses to ambiguous discourses and practices of power aimed at the construction of new openings, possibilities and different distributive processes, the outcomes of which are always to an extent unpredictable. Political agency here is not imagined as a quest for individual authenticity in opposition to a unitary nefarious oppressive Leviathan aimed at the creation of a ‘‘better totality’’ where subjects can float freed of ‘‘oppression,’’ or a multitude made into a unified ‘‘subject’’ will reverse the might of Empire and bring about a condition of immanent social justice. By not reifying power as a script and subject as monads endowed with freedom non-substantialist positions open the way for conceptualizing political agency as an engagement imbricated in praxis. The ethical virtue that is called for is ‘‘pragmatist humility,’’ that is the patience of playing with the cards that are dealt to us, enacting redescriptions and devising tactics for tinkering 82 with what exists in specific contexts. Conclusion In this article, I have argued that, notwithstanding their critical stance, scholars who use governmentality as a descriptive tool remain rooted in substantialist ontologies that see power and subjects as standing in a relation of externality. They also downplay processes of coconstitution and the importance of indeterminacy and ambiguity as the very space where political agency can thrive. In this way, they drastically limit the possibility for imagining political agency outside the liberal straightjacket. They represent international liberal biopolitical and governmental power as a homogenous and totalizing formation whose scripts effectively oppress ‘‘subjects,’’ that are in turn imagined as free ‘‘by nature.’’ Transformations of power modalities through multifarious tactics of hybridization and redescriptions are not considered as options. The complexity of politics is reduced to homogenizing and/or romanticizing narratives and political engagements are reduced to total heroic rejections or to revolutionary moments. Our rhetorical strategy attempts to channel the process of competition into a productive politics – retaining a forum of argumentative disagreement retains debates radical potential Crosswhite 2 (James Crosswhite, Professor, Department of English, University of Oregon, Ph.D. Philosophy, UC San Diego, B.A. Philosophy, UC Santa Cruz, “Conflict in Concert: Fighting Hannah Arendt's Good Fight,” JAC, 22(4), Fall 2002, pp.948-959, http://www.jaconlinejournal.com/archives/vol22.4/crosswhite-conflict.pdf) Early in her essay, and again at the end, Roberts-Miller shakes hands with her opponent and acknowledges that there is a legitimate grievance against agonistic rhetoric. The basic problem with valuing agonistic rhetoric is that one seems at the same time to be promoting mere wrangling. The opponents of agonistic rhetoric have opposed it on these grounds. One needs a way to distinguish between agonistic rhetoric that is merely succeed-at-all-costs-andnever-give-in combat and agonistic rhetoric that uses competition and struggle to accomplish something greater than simple conquest. She is not sure that she has a satisfying way of addressing this problem, but she cites a passage from John Locke in which the essence of wrangling is that the wranglers are incapable of changing their minds, of being convinced by opposing arguments. Later in her essay, in her gloss on a passage from Arendt, she develops this important feature of agonistic discourse: "It is not asymmetric manipulation of others ... it must be a world into which one enters and by which one can be changed" (593). This is a familiar condition by which argumentation theorists attempt to delineate just what argumentation is. If the interlocutors are not willing to change their minds, then they are not engaged in argumentation. Near the end of her article, she regrets that Arendt did not do more to distinguish polemical agonism from wrangling, and then she drops the discussion. It would of course be very interesting to hear more about this. The agonistic/collaborative distinction is made in large part, according to Roberts-Miller herself, because one cannot distinguish the valuable kind of rhetoric from the destructive kind. If neither Arendt nor Roberts-Miller can address this, then something is seriously amiss. At this point, it is just impossible not to regret that the last half-century's resurgence of argumentation theory is not more broadly acknowledged by those who make a profession of rhetoric , writing, and literacy. Chaim Perelman and Lucie Olbrechts-Tyteca labor carefully in The New Rhetoric to describe what makes possible the "contact of minds" that is a condition for the possibility of genuine argumentation. Franz van Eemeren and the late Rob Grootendorst worked for years on their "pragma-dialectical" rules for argumentative discourse. And more recently, in The New Dialectic, Douglas Walton has systematized his thinking on the rules for argumentative dialogues and distinguished the rules for eristic dialogues from the rules for inquiry dialogues, deliberative dialogues, and other kinds of argumentative discourse. It would be interesting to know whether Roberts- Miller would find in this work a way to elaborate the concept of polemical agonism and save it from its indistinguishability from wrangling. However the threat of agonism's logical indistinguishability from wrangling is only part of the problem. There also a psychological dimension to the objection to agonistic argumentation. Some people are just is psychologically defeated by it. Their experience-in childhood, in a bad marriage, in the course of life in general, or even in court and with lawyers, and perhaps in education-is to have been outdone by argumentation. It has not been a way for them to gain a hearing, or a way to negotiate, or a way to resolve conflict, or a way to learn, or a way to gain self-knowledge. They have succumbed to the threat that Socrates feared for his own interlocutors- misology, the hatred of arguments-because of the experience of being constantly defeated by them and by those who wield them with virtuosity . This is not a problem that can be directly addressed by theorizing and argumentation , although the theory of argumentation is quite an important part of it. It requires rather a practical kind of wisdom and virtuous action . When Socrates breaks off the argument with young Theaetetus in Plato's dialogue of that name, it is because he understands Theaetetus and his condition, the stage of his formation, and the threat of misology, and because he has the virtue to act on the younger man's behalf, to keep a space open for his individual development . One of the less noted objections to agonistic rhetoric is that it damages those who are defeated by it, that it creates an association between reason and failure, reason and psychological pain. It would be interesting to hear Roberts-Miller address this objection. What would it take not only to theorize a logical distinction between agonistic rhetoric and wrangling but also to make use of the distinction in our practice and teaching? The central move in Roberts-Miller's deployment of Arendt's thinking is to accept the distinction between agonistic and collaborative rhetoric but to present arguments that reverse the value hierarchy that the split sets up: to replace "much of our dislike of conflict with a dislike of consensus." Here she gives us Arendt at her most Heideggerian. Human beings are beset by a powerful drift toward conformity that is an evasion of individual responsibility. This drift is not simply a superficial, external conformity but a deep one in which our thinking becomes the thinking of no one in particular and in which our individual identities meld in an anonymous social self. Ironically, this conformity is so deep that we can be most social even while most isolated; in fact, conformity depends in part on a certain kind of isolation, an unwillingness to express our disagreements and test them by arguments in some public way. Instead, one's social and institutional identities pretty much determine how one should think and act on almost all occasions. This conformist sociality is the absolutization of bureaucracy and the apotheosis of collaborationism. In Arendt's and Roberts-Miller's hands, the idea of the collaborative takes on all the resonance the word had when it was used of those who capitulated to the Nazis. One can almost see and hear scenes from The Sorrow and the Pity as one ponders these Arendtian ideas. And, of course, Arendt's prime exhibit of "collaborative man" is the desk murderer Adolph Eichmann, the perfect administrator who, even after recognizing his complicity in the murder of millions, could understand his guilt only as the guilt of obedience to his superiors, the guilt of doing his official duties. Eichmann is the thoroughly historicist, perfectly formed social constructionist. To the challenge that he should have spoken out against what was going on, he replied: "Under the circumstances then prevailing such an attitude was not possible. Nor did anyone behave in this fashion. From my experience I know that the possibility, which was alleged only after the War, of opposing orders is a self-protective fairy tale. " Arendt's argument depends on Eichmann's words never losing their power to chill us. And so Roberts-Miller looks to Arendt for help in "replacing our mistrust of conflict with a mistrust of consensus." What Eichmann and collaborationism both lack is a capacity for being hospitable to a conflict of ideas. True individuality (and not the passive isolation of the "personal"; even Eichmann was not "personally" in favor of the persecution of the Jews) requires active political interaction that involves conflict and competition and the struggle and testing of competing perspectives in argumentation. True individuality requires risk-the exposure of our individual thoughts to the sometimes painful experience of their public examination. This is the heroism of thinking. One always risks losing and having to change. However, as Stanley Cavell would point out, this is also the joy and adventure of individuality: to change, to imagine oneself as on some kind of path, to think of change as (sometimes painful) transformation. This conflict, says Roberts-Miller, need not be forced. It is the form taken by open this can all take place only when there is some kind of social space for it and when there are individuals capable of it . And so, says Roberts-Miller, we should trust collaborationism less and look acknowledgment of difference. We find identities in the course of these conflicts; we set out on paths toward ourselves. And to the agonism that allows for individuality and openness to difference. In some ways, I am perhaps the worst person to comment on this argument because I so wholeheartedly endorse it and because my own interest is in amplifying and promoting it. It is hard to think of what major shift in rhetoric, writing, and literacy studies would be more salutary than the one Roberts-Miller is leading us toward here. However, for just this reason I find her qualifications and reservations about this project almost incomprehensible. A primary Roberts-Miller fret is that this ideal of agonistic rhetoric is somehow "elitist." In the context of this doubt, she describes agonism as requiring that one "simultaneously trust and doubt one's perceptions, rely on one's own judgments and consider the judgments of others, think for oneself and imagine how others think" (597). Now, since she is promoting a greater mistrust of collaborationism and a greater trust of the agonistic, it is hard to see how this in itself might be "elitist." Nowhere is a demonstrated capacity for agonistic rhetoric represented as a qualification for political participation or social privilege. Why should the mere argument that agonistic rhetoric has important social, political, and individual value be suspected of furthering some kind of elitism? If there is a kind of discourse that undermines the thoughtless intellectual and practical conformity on which totalitarianisms of all kinds depend, and if this kind of discourse develops human individuality and allows for the expression of the differences on which the idea of a free society depends, then its value goes way beyond the interests of some elite faction. Part of RobertsMiller' s discussion suggests that perhaps not everyone can engage in Arendtian "thought" of this kind, that the ideal is somehow too high. However, it is difficult to see how this counts against the ideal. The ideal of informed voters going through careful deliberations about social and political goods when they vote is also an "elitist" ideal if elitism simply means that not all voters are capable of this. Many of the most worthwhile social ideals for which human beings strive—tolerance, freedom, justice—are beyond the current capabilities of many people, even the people that are striving for them. This does not mean that the ideal cannot orient their thinking and their action or their work on law and policy – or their teaching and writing. Part of this vague notion that agonistic rhetoric is somehow elitist rests on a reified and destructively essentialist idea of what human beings are capable of. To say that agonistic rhetoric is not a kind of thought in which everyone can engage is to try to confine human beings to a current historical situation and educational system that are not the results but the causes of this purported incapacity. If agonistic rhetoric is really what Roberts-Miller says it is, then the point would seem to be to change our educational practices and work tirelessly to amplify the attractiveness of agonistic rhetoric in all the spheres where it might have some effect. If there are those who are incapable of both thinking for themselves and imagining how others think, incapable of the internal dialogue of reason, incapable of the transformation that occurs when we risk our perspectives in the attempt to understand the perspectives of others (and, as Gadamer says, simply to understand is to be transformed and partly convinced), then what is education for but to develop the capacity for this? I take it that someone who sees the truth in Arendt's description of thoughtlessness will not be involved in education that is simply aimed toward producing efficient laborers who will fill the slots that the reigning bureaucracies have identified as needing to be filled (see Gadamer 379,567). Roberts-Miller cites a telling passage from Arendt: "As a living experience, thought has always been assumed, perhaps wrongly, to be known only to the few" (597). First, we must accentuate the "perhaps wrongly!" It is not presumptuous to believe that people everywhere have struggled to develop Arendtian "thinking," and that they have struggled, too, to participate in agonistic rhetoric, and that where they have failed to do so, it is because they were held back, either materially or socially, by design or by misfortune. However, this passage is also reminiscent of the Kantian ideas of freedom and morality. Even though we have no sense experience of freedom, even though it is an idea of "reason" alone, and so according to Kant should not be a fact, he still regards freedom as a fact because it is proved by morality itself. And even if no one has ever acted morally, freely, and Kant at one point openly doubts whether anyone ever has, it would still be a fact because freedom is necessary for morality, and to deny it altogether is to deny what moral experience we do have. The tradition of critical theory that follows from Kant, the tradition in which Arendt herself partly stands, makes a great deal of these kinds of ideas. Herbert Marcuse sometimes calls them "utopian," but he does this in the context of a rehabilitation of utopian thinking. In his view, whether utopian ideals are realizable or not, they still provide a critical standard by which we can measure our current social condition and the direction in which our political programs are taking us. They provide a measure. They are partly constitutive of our thought and action, which would be very different without them. Jiirgen Habermas uses the idea of an ideal speech situation in much the same way. He knows that this idea is "counterfactual," that there has never in reality been such a situation. However, if it is an illusion, it is a "constitutive illusion" that gives us a more complete understanding of our actual situation by providing a measure, for insofar as our actual communicative situations fail to realize this ideal, they are potentially criticizable. It is finally up to actual interlocutors to decide how much falling short is tolerable in each situation. Agonistic rhetoric and Arendtian thought are themselves ideas of this sort, capable of lighting up a direction for educational efforts and providing a measure for the actual thinking and communication we are attempting to understand and evaluate. They are not the only such ideas, but as Roberts-Miller argues, they are significant ones, and, I would add, significantly undervalued just now, when cultural and political and economic conflicts are too easily conceptualized-on all sides-on the model of a clash of civilizations which only violence can adequately address . As Arendt wrote: "We do not know where ... developments will lead us, but we know, or should know, that every decrease in power is an open invitation to violence" (87). Power, for Arendt, is the ability to act in concert, and the agonistic rhetoric of the public sphere is the ability to have conflict-inconcert. The issue is not elitism. The issue on an educational level is how to address the situation of those who have not yet developed their capacity for this kind of thinking and argumentation-and I don't believe that there is a general educational-bureaucratic solution or a scientific pedagogy that will come to the rescue here. I am much more inclined to the Socratic view that you have to know the psyche with which you are dealing. Because individuals vary so greatly in their psychological formation around experiences of argumentative discourse, and because the rhetorical psyche also fractures along all the usual multiple and unsystematic lines of race, gender, and so on, this will always be a matter that individual teachers must address with individuals and classes as best they can-and against whatever educational-bureaucratic power has installed itself and its general "solutions" at the time. The issue on a political level is always to fight to keep this public sphere open . The courage and vigilance required here have not been exaggerated. There are a few other remaining challenges in Roberts-Miller's argument. In her own polemical agonism, she exaggerates the distinction between the agonistic and the collaborative. Anyone who thinks through the relation between agonistic and collaborative rhetoric more thoroughly will find a great deal of the collaborative in the agonistic and the agonistic in the collaborative – enough, perhaps, to begin to destabilize the distinction itself. In fact, agonistic rhetoric may require a depth of cooperation and mutual practical respect that collaborative rhetoric does not. After all, the practical respect required to go on discoursing with someone who does not agree with you requires a more profound moral relation than that required to go on speaking with someone with whom you are reaching an agreement. There are many other deep interactions and inter-identities to be explored in these concepts. Any program that would follow from Roberts-Miller's arguments would have to be aware of these to be practicable at anything more than an abstract level. In fact, it is here that we encounter another of the formal ironies in Roberts-Miller's approach. At her most polemical moment, when she begins the hyperdistinguishing that finds a new binary in agonistic rhetoric itself, she at the same time begins to reconcile the social and the individual, the collaborative and the agonistic. The new pair is persuasive agonism (associated with John Gage) and polemical agonism (associated with Hannah Arendt). Persuasive agonism is aimed at gaining the agreement of others and so the criterion of its success is persuasion. Polemical agonismis aimed partly at the invention and clarification of the ideas themselves, as well as at their public testing and further develop ment. The criterion of success is the quality of the subsequent controversy. Although this distinction doesn't quite capture the Gagean position (since Gage describes the argumentation he teaches as a way of discovering the best grounds for a position), it does allow Roberts-Miller a very interesting and Quintilianesque move that tells us how speaking well is different from speaking persuasively, for persuasion is not the ultimate goal. Polemical agonism is not the asymmetric work of a single rhetor bent on overpowering an interlocutor in a competition. Instead, its success lies in the continuing agreement of the conflicting parties to persevere in argumentation, to go on testing ideas together . This new distinction allows Roberts-Miller to find in polemical agonism a deeper kind of "collaboration," a conflict-in-concert. Polemical agonism is not the simple resolution of conflict in agreement but the continuation of conflict in a creative and valuable way, a way of having conflict that requires deep kinds of cooperation. Now, one could try to undermine this new pair in the usual ways. For example, it is difficult to imagine how polemical agonism would take place unless it somehow integrated persuasive agonism. Without the provisional goal of persuasion, it is hard to see how polemical agonism could achieve its aim of sustaining a high quality of public controversy. The athletic analogy comes to mind here. We play to win because that is how the best playing gets accomplished . And in the end this is the position Roberts-Miller herself takes when she writes that Arendtian rhetoric leads not to ultimate Truth but to decisions, for decisions come only when we do come to agreement, only when an argument does persuade--and yet, as Roberts-Miller also points out, these decisions must be reconsidered later, and so a continuing controversy must be possible. This is certainly an integrating of the polemical and the persuasive. Perhaps the most striking fact about Roberts-Miller's overall argument is not just that it is so timely and appropriate but that it implicitly forecasts a reconvention of rhetoric itself. I have already mentioned that argumentation studies have for the last half-century labored to develop theories of argumentation that would capture much of what Roberts-Miller needs to flesh out this case for agonistic rhetoric and to distinguish it from wrangling. However, this work is still too little known among rhetoricians and receives little detailed attention in their literature. Yet, it represents perhaps the greatest development of rhetoric in our lifetimes. And then, from another side, there has been a complicated and troubling discussion of the relations among language, discourse, power, and violence that would intensify and deepen this worry that Roberts-Miller has about domination and wrangling. From Walter Benjamin through Arendt's own important elaboration of the distinction between power and violence, through the conversation between Levinas and Derrida on metaphysics and violence, to Foucault's back and forth on power and violence, all the way to two recent books on just this issue, Beatrice Hanssen's Critique of Violence and Hent De Vries's Religion and Violence-both of which try to organize and sustain the controversy on exactly the issue of the difference between debate and discussion, on the one hand, and domination and violence and entrenched antagonisms on the other-the ideal of something like an agonistic rhetoric has been at stake. At the unstable center of this highly developed controversy, the difference and identity of violence and power hold sway. Arendt had a big stake in this, and insisted on the difference between power and violence and on a polemical agonism helps to sustain societies in which power keeps violence at bay . When Foucault was confronted form of power in which people could act in concert-a form of power not at all unrelated to the way with Arendt's idea, he of course could not consent to this valorizing even of the provisional consensus that comes out of polemical agonism because Foucault had great difficulty acknowledging that power might not involve domination. His finessing of the issue was to say that "perhaps one must not be for consensuality, but one must be against nonconsensuality" (379). As Derrida finesses the same issue, one can hope to avoid only "the worst violence" and hope "to choose the lesser violence within an economy of violence" (152, 313n.). Is it utopian to imagine that Roberts-Miller's call for a new trust of conflict, a call for an integration of Arendt's "thought" into rhetorical studies, might be a forecast of a more general call to reconvene rhetoric itself, to call back argumentation studies and the now decades-long conflicts in critical theory and post-structuralism into the history of rhetoric, where they belong? There are powerful arguments to be made on behalf of the general approach of Hannah Arendt to show how discourse-and argumentation in particular-can be a way of having conflict, conflict that might otherwise be carried out in actual violence or some other kind of overt domination . And not only are there powerful arguments to be made, but there are powerful attractions in the kind of sociality opened up by those discursive practices, many of them described in a compelling way by Roberts-Miller. One can always take the critical position and search out the domination lurking in every concrete experience of peace and freedom, but this is only natural. Real wisdom lies in knowing when and where to do this. In the end, thinking all of this through will mean seeing how agonism thought through becomes acting-in-concert and how the critique of domination thought through becomes, as Foucault shows in his refusal of both polemics and of consensus, a way of keeping the fight going. There is reason to believe that the recent popular favoring of collaboration is a kind of practical acting-out of a fear of domination, but a discourse founded in a vision that sees only domination in agonistic rhetoric and so has to seclude itself in a carefully controlled process of deindividualization so only the collaborative can dominate will not easily survive this thinking-through. Whether and how an agonism motivated by the ideals so well expressed by Patricia Roberts-Miller in her essay will itself survive a careful thinking-through remains to be seen. But she has my fighting gratitude for making such a thought-provoking case. The ballot is a referendum of the desirability of our heuristic of government as it pertains the desirability of legalization – this channels debate into a recognition of difference that otherwise erupts into open hostility Kalyvas, 09 (Andreas Kalyvas, Associate Professor of Political Science, Department of Politics, The New School for Social Research, Ph.D. Political Science, Columbia University, M.A. Columbia University, B.A. National and Kapodistrian, University of Athens, Greece, “The Democratic Narcissus: The Agonism of the Ancients Compared to that of the (Post)Moderns,” in Law and Agonistic Politics, ed. Andrew Schaap, Ashgate Publishing, 2009, p.31-36, Google Book) Undoubtedly, the emphasis on disagreement, contestation and strife remains constant in contemporary agonistic theories and testifies to a conceptual continuity. Agonism, ancient and 'postmodern" alike, consists of confrontational strategies and adversarial acts. Both Ancients and ‘postmoderns' view political conflict as central to democracy. They understand politics as the enactment of public disagreement and dissent . Reminiscent of classical agonism's inclusion of the lower popular social strata into political adversarial contests, 'postmodern' agonism solicits the inclusion of difference and otherness in the public realm. Its call for the politicization of identities echoes ancient agonism's politicization of Narcissus. It incites a multiplicity of particularities and cultures to participate within a common symbolic space and display themselves in the course of public debate and political strife against each other. Notwithstanding these affinities and continuities, the current revival of the agon in political theory does not suggest a nostalgic appeal to a pre-modern Greek past. It does not indicate yet another neoclassical revival. Quite the opposite. I would argue, it represents a 'de-Hellenization’ of agonism, a considerable divestment of its ancient significations and a radical redefinition. At least four broad changes are involved in the post-structural appropriation. Although they do not appear together in all contemporary agonistic theories, they indicate certain of their most vocal and influential properties. First, there is a comprehensive shift regarding the subject of the agon from the individual person to the identity of a group, that is, to a collective entity with a shared sense of existence (but see Deranty and Renault in this volume). ‘Postmodern’ agonism focuses on ‘contending identities' or 'opposing hegemonic projects’ rather than concrete individuals and their narcissistic urges (Connolly 1991, 166: Mouffe 2005, 21). Whereas for the Ancients, the agon was predominantly understood and practised in personalistic idioms, for the contemporary proponents it designates mostly subject positions and relationships of collective identity formation. For instance, Honig (1995,155) writes ‘agonistic feminism also departs from the implied individualism of Arendt’s pariah ... The identities engaged by agonistic feminists are shared, public practices not merely markers of individual personalities.’ After the long-fought battles against the theo-philosophy of the subject and free will, this de-centring of ancient agonism and its disassociation from agonistic individualism should not come as a surprise. Second, and quite predictably, the strong connotations of masculinity and the aesthetics of manliness are denounced and often replaced by an expressivist concept of agonistic subjectivity, with a much greater emphasis on playfulness, virtuosity, acting and gaming ( fully 1999; Huizinga 1950, 11). With the ‘postmoderns', the actor comes to replace the athlete: the dancer and the flute-player supplant the wrestler and the boxer. Equally telling is the purge of the agon from its archaic and classical invocations of heroism. The ‘postmodern’ agon 'does not usually take heroism’ (Connolly 2008, 209); it seeks to be post- or antiheroic. It does not describe extraordinary acts and exceptional endeavours beyond measure. And although an aesthetical appreciation is still expressed in certain agonistic theories today, something their critics are always eager to point out. it is of an altogether different kind. Neither masculine nor martial, ‘postmodern’ agonism seems at times to indulge in the celebration of diversity, fluid identities and dissension. Third, the concrete outcome of ancient contest, the telos of the agon - to win by defeating one's opponents is almost being displaced in favour of the more abstract notion of disruption, subversion, and perpetual contestation of existing power relations, fixed identities, and closed meanings. Here, the reason for this change could be the anti-teleological current in post-structural thinking, its critique of philosophies of history and its commitment to contingency and indeterminacy. Whereas in antiquity the political agon was intrinsically related to victory and success and as a type of performance it clearly consisted of instrumental and utilitarian significations, in contemporary theories agonism becomes conflated to pure performativity. independently of concrete outcomes. Fourth, the gains or benefits of agonism have also shifted. From a positive contest for greatness, glory and prominence, the agon is mostly converted into a reactive resistance against the negative and anti-political forces of rational consensus, deliberation, neutrality and abstract universalism, often associated to liberal normative discourses. The broader agonistic effects of social admiration and praise are retrofitted and transformed into a struggle for inclusion, recognition and respect (Connolly 1995b, note 40, 235). In certain cases, however, this transfiguration retains some of its past connotations, as for instance in Honig's (1995, 159) suggestion for an alternative reading of ‘distinction*, which draws nearer to the Ancients: ‘The agonal passion for distinction, which so moved Arendt’s theoretical account, may also be read as a struggle for individuation, for emergence as a distinct self.' These four moves away from ancient democratic agonism suggest a radical re-orientation toward questions of power and culture, identity formation and exclusion. What the anthropological narcissistic drive was for the ancients, identity and its exclusion are for the ‘postmodems*. Hence, a key theoretical innovation of the ‘postmodern’ accounts is to have brought into attention the relevance of identity and difference to agonistic politics. Agonal democracy, in its various guises, addresses the possibility of constructing a relatively stable, plural and inclusive political order without generating sameness and an oppressive consensus, that is, without eradicating disagreement and contestation in the name of an over-assertive and universal good, it is still participatory and democratic. Politicization and conflict become the vital mechanisms of political inclusion and social integration in the face of pluralism and diversity. The ‘postmodern* agon provides a relative solution to this predicament as the classical agon was a solution to the conundrum of narcissism and civic virtue, the tension between the drive for pre-eminence and the principle of equality. For contemporary approaches, exclusion represents the main threat to politics. Against this risk, agonistic contest is treated as a force that disturbs, relativizes and de-naturalizes the fixity of established identities, allowing for a more hospitable and inclusive attitude toward the other. Agonistic practices, it is argued, ‘challenge existing distributions of power, disrupt the hegemonic social, and proliferate political spaces when they interrupt the routine, predictability, and repetition on which ... dominant patterns of private realm identity depend' (Honig 1993b, 532; Connolly 1991, 193, 200). Inclusion and respect for the other is the ultimate prize of this kind of agonism and democracy is praised for the space it creates within which a greater expression of identities is realized through their confrontational interactions. ‘Postmodern’ agonism, therefore, expresses the hope that the politicization of difference and the intensification of strife will foster inclusion, secure plurality, and safeguard differences (Honig 1993b, 532; Connolly 2004, 510-11). In its strongest version, agonism cultivates an ethical respect for one's opponent and keeps open the politics of renewal and augmentation. William Connolly expresses this faith better than anyone else, when he asserts that: in a democratic, pluralizing ethos, agents of enactment would exercise a certain forbearance in pressing their claims, and agents of reception would exercise a reciprocal generosity in responding to productions that disrupt what they arc. This agonistic reciprocity is the pathos of distance in politics. (Connolly 1995b, 193; see also, Connolly 2005, 123-8) This optimism is coupled by a dear normative orientation, shared by most agonistic theories today. Democratic agonism does not seek to describe real existing democracies but rather to point at a normative vision. Democracy ought to be a permanent and open-ended contest among identities and particularities struggling over self-affirmation, recognition, inclusion, power distribution and the definition of collective meaning. If one probes deeper, one discovers that this normative ideal is derived from the fundamental value ascribed to the principle of the greatest inclusion of differences, which itself presupposes a particular ontology of life. Life is abundant, plural and rich and so should be the best political regime. This celebration of otherness and the worth of its inclusion in the public realm is perhaps one of the most original aspects of contemporary agonistic theories compared to the Ancients. It is here that the departure from ancient democratic agonism becomes more poignant. I only can briefly clarify certain crucial points of divergence, in need of further elaboration elsewhere. The first pertains to a certain optimism of the ‘postmodern’ agonists that departs significantly from the pessimism that informed ancicnt agonistic culture. This discrepancy is due, I think, to the fact that contemporary theories have disassociated the agon from the logic of winning and losing, of victory and defeat, pain and agony. It is as if no one wins and, respectively, no one loses; or better, for the ‘postmodems’ everybody wins. The experience of defeat is eliminated from the democratic agon and with it the feelings of shame and humiliation, stigmatization and inner exclusion which the ancient agon generated. Also lost is the motivation for victory, with its symbolic pleasures, libidinal investment and civic rewards. Likewise, contemporary discourses on agonism, with the exception of Chantal Mouffe, have done away with the realistic attitude of the Ancients toward the inexorable presence of Narcissus in the human and the individual urge to distinguish oneself from others. It should be reminded that ancient democratic agonism was primarily a form of a necessary, pragmatic accommodation informed by a mytho- philosophical anthropology. It was based on a descriptive understanding of human nature and for this reason it lacked the celebration of otherness that is so central to contemporary approaches. In fact, agonistic theories today assume that conflict will mostly be good and advantageous as they interconnect and bind rivals together and cultivate respect among contending identities. This assumption, however, remains to be proven. What guarantees that conflict will make identities more receptive and respectful to otherness instead of inducing them to an existential entrenchment by closing up on themselves in an effort to defend their views, values, and ways of life, especially when they are confronted with more powerful identities? Disagreement and confrontation might as well accentuate differences by making collective identities better realize what they do not share with others and what unique beliefs and axiological world-views distinguish them from their opponents (Wenman 2003, 172-4). Agonism could as well foster exclusion rather than inclusion. It is not clear, therefore, why conflict destabilizes and challenges the fixity of group identities, encouraging the inclusion of and respect for ethical and cultural differences. Politicization could lead to polarization, the polemization of political contests, to hostility and aggression, and finally to factionalization and violent dissolution (Deveaux 1999, 15; Schaap 2007, 68). This precisely is what many thinkers and historians in the course of Western political theory perceived as the fatal cause of the decline of ancient democracies. For this reason the Ancients developed a complex institutional system, what I described as a counter-narcissistic legal apparatus, to contain the agony of agonism as they were worried about the destructive effects of the agon. The ‘postmoderns’ do not exhibit the same institutional imagination as they primarily share a positive view of political contest and public confrontation. Hence, an institutional and legal deficit is evident in their approaches. Adopting a rather abstract and normative discourse they tend to subordinate political reality and the intricacies of institutional design to philosophical speculation. As a result, the institutionalization of agonal democracy remains an unfulfilled promise (Schaap 2007, 68-9). Finally, by eliminating Narcissus from the agon, ‘postmodern’ theories dispense with a theory of civic motivation like the one developed by the Ancients. Given the fact that the agonistic politics of confrontation and contestation might be quite demanding, arduous and sometimes painful, contemporary perspectives cannot account for those who might chose a more passive, peaceful, and tranquil non- political life. Especially so, when ‘postmodern' agonism endorses plural identities, which means, it accepts a plurality of cultural, ethical and religious groups, some which may not appreciate the political life of the agon as fitting to their particular world-views, values and beliefs. Would then democratic agonism appeal to the superiority of a singular concept of the good, that of the agon, at the detriment of all those identities that opt for a non-agonistic, consensual, even private life (Deveaux 1999, 5; Connolly 2008, 210)? Without the passions of the Narcissus and an appropriate institutional structure that drives individuals to compete and struggle for greatness by participating and accomplishing positive deeds for their political community, ‘postmodern’ theories of agonism face an important challenge: to reconcile the worth of the agon with a plurality of identities that may not be as sympathetic or inclined to confrontational and argumentative politics. These differences between the two kinds of democratic agonism, however, should not be overstated nor projected to the entire range of ‘postmodern’ agonistic theories. In fact, in one particular version the spirit of classical democratic agonism re-asserts itself, even if indirectly and reluctantly. Mere I have in mind Chantal Mouffe’s work, which stands apart from the other theories of agonism although it certainly shares certain central ontological and political attributes. Mouffe’s approach is predominantly pragmatic rather than normative or celebratory and here lies its core affinity with the Ancients and its disagreement with her contemporaries. The value and merit of democratic agonism does not pertain merely to how inclusive it is or how many differences it incorporates into the public sphere. Instead, Mouffe recognizes the inexorable fact of exclusion and its necessary role in consolidating collective identities and political unity. Contrary to other contemporary thinkers of democratic agonism. Mouffe (2005, 15-16) takes seriously the irreducibility of an outside that can neither be fully incorporated, eradicated or repressed. And since there is no objective, transcendental or rational ground to reconcile or overcome differences, antagonism remains ineradicable in political life, an everlasting presence and challenge to politics. For Mouffe, the main task of radical democracy is to allow agonism while taming and containing antagonism. Agonism is precisely what makes possible the conflictual character of politics without falling into a destructive war of all against all. By turning the enemy into an adversary and antagonism into agonism, democracy enables a regulated conflict among competing hegemonic projects to unfold while taming its disruptive and destructive tendencies (Mouffe 2005,20): Envisaged from the point of view of ‘agonistic pluralism', the aim of democratic politics is to construct the ‘them’ in such a way that is no longer perceived as an enemy to be destroyed but as an adversary, that is, somebody whose ideas we combat but whose right to defend those ideas we do not put into question . (Mouffe 2000. 102) Mouffe’s agonistic democracy seeks to avoid both de-politicization and over- politicization in an effort to keep political confrontation alive without being destroyed by it. The agon, which occupies a middle position between deliberative models of rational consensus on the one hand and identity politics on the other, aims at deflating conflicts through inclusion and politicization but without erasing them. Reminiscent of the Ancients’ realism that the narcissistic passion to excel may engulf politics if left to its own devices, Mouffe’s (2005. 21) version is predicated on a similar prudential rule that ‘antagonistic conflicts are by directly discussing the role and significance of passions and affects in politics, Mouffe moves closer to the Ancients with her psychoanalytically oriented approach that takes into consideration the libidinal forces of identification, reminiscent of the force of Narcissus. Agonistic democracy acknowledges the libidinal pleasure of identification while it seeks to curb its dangerous and violent impulses. ‘Understood in an agonistic way’, she claims, ‘democratic institutions can contribute less likely to emerge as long as agonistic legitimate political channels for dissenting voices exist’ (but see Breen in this volume). In addition, to this disarming of the libidinal forces leading towards hostility which are always present in human societies’ (MoufTe 2005, 26). Without the good Eris (agonism/the adversary) there is only a bad Eris (antagonism/the enemy). Agonal plural democracy aims to transform conflict into a form of regulated public contest in order to avoid the eruption of violent antagonisms into politics . Thus, Mouffe’s pragmatic and realist theory of plural c democracy, informed by a similar awareness of the threatening and unpredictable potentialities of the political, retains certain affinities with classical democratic agonism, mediating between Ancients and ‘postmodems’. Legal strategy is a process and a constant struggle, not an end-point – risks of cooption, rollback and masking exist only because progressives turned away from state-based legal strategies. Lobel, 7 - Assistant Professor of Law, University of San Diego (Orly, “THE PARADOX OF EXTRALEGAL ACTIVISM: CRITICAL LEGAL CONSCIOUSNESS AND TRANSFORMATIVE POLITICS“ HARVARD LAW REVIEW [Vol. 120:937, http://www.harvardlawreview.org/media/pdf/lobel.pdf) Once again, this conclusion reveals flaws parallel to the original disenchantment with legal reform. Although the new extralegal frames present themselves as apt alternatives to legal reform models and as capable of producing significant changes to the social map, in practice they generate very limited improvement in existing social arrangements. Most strikingly, the cooptation effect here can be explained in terms of the most profound risk of the typology — that of legitimation. The common pattern of extralegal scholarship is to describe an inherent instability in dominant structures by pointing, for example, to grassroots strategies,223 and then to assume that specific instances of counterhegemonic activities translate into a more complete transformation. This celebration of multiple micro-resistances seems to rely on an aggregate approach — an idea that the multiplication of practices will evolve into something substantial. In fact, the myth of engagement obscures the actual lack of change being produced , while the broader pattern of equating extralegal activism with social reform produces a false belief in the potential of change. There are few instances of meaningful reordering of social and economic arrangements and macro-redistribution. Scholars write about decoding what is really happening, as though the scholarly narrative has the power to unpack more than the actual conventional experience will admit.224 Unrelated efforts become related and part of a whole through mere reframing. At the same time, the elephant in the room — the rising level of economic inequality — is left unaddressed and comes to be understood as natural and inevitable .225 This is precisely the problematic process that critical theorists decry as losers’ self-mystification, through which marginalized groups come to see systemic losses as the product of their own actions and thereby begin to focus on minor achievements as representing the boundaries of their willed reality. The explorations of micro-instances of activism are often fundamentally performative, obscuring the distance between the descriptive and the prescriptive. The manifestations of extralegal activism — the law and organizing model; the proliferation of informal, soft norms and norm-generating actors; and the celebrated, separate nongovernmental sphere of action — all produce a fantasy that change can be brought about through small-scale, decentralized transformation . The emphasis is local, but the locality is described as a microcosm of the whole and the audience is national and global. In the context of the humanities, Professor Carol Greenhouse poses a comparable challenge to ethnographic studies from the 1990s, which utilized the genres of narrative and community studies, the latter including works on American cities and neighborhoods in trouble.226 The aspiration of these genres was that each individual story could translate into a “time of the nation” body of knowledge and motivation.227 In contemporary legal thought, a corresponding gap opens between the local scale and the larger, translocal one. In reality, although there has been a recent proliferation of associations and grassroots groups, few new localstatenational federations have emerged in the United States since the 1960s and 1970s, and many of the existing voluntary federations that flourished in the mid-twentieth century are in decline.228 There is, therefore, an absence of links between the local and the national, an absent intermediate public sphere, which has been termed “the missing middle” by Professor Theda Skocpol.229 New social movements have for the most part failed in sustaining coalitions or producing significant institutional change through grassroots activism. Professor Handler concludes that this failure is due in part to the ideas of contingency, pluralism, and localism that are so embedded in current activism.230 Is the focus on small-scale dynamics simply an evasion of the need to engage in broader substantive debate? It is important for next-generation progressive legal scholars, while maintaining a critical legal consciousness, to recognize that not all extralegal associational life is transformative. We must differentiate, for example, between inward-looking groups, which tend to be self- regarding and depoliticized, and social movements that participate in political activities, engage the public debate, and aim to challenge and reform existing realities.231 We must differentiate between professional associations and more inclusive forms of institutions that act as trustees for larger segments of the community.232 As described above, extralegal activism tends to operate on a more divided and hence a smaller scale than earlier social movements, which had national reform agendas. Consequently, within critical discourse there is a need to recognize the limited capacity of smallscale action. We should question the narrative that imagines consciousness-raising as directly translating into action and action as directly translating into change. Certainly not every cultural description is political. Indeed, it is questionable whether forms of activism that are opposed to programmatic reconstruction of a social agenda should even be understood as social movements. In fact, when groups are situated in opposition to any form of institutionalized power, they may be simply mirroring what they are fighting against and merely producing moot activism that settles for what seems possible within the narrow space that is left in a rising convergence of ideologies. The original vision is consequently coopted, and contemporary discontent is legitimated through a process of selfmystification. V. RESTORING CRITICAL OPTIMISM IN THE LEGAL FIELD “La critique est aisée; l’art difficile.” A critique of cooptation often takes an uneasy path. Critique has always been and remains not simply an intellectual exercise but a political and moral act. The question we must constantly pose is how critical accounts of social reform models contribute to our ability to produce scholarship and action that will be constructive. To critique the ability of law to produce social change is inevitably to raise the question of alternatives . In and of itself, the exploration of the limits of law and the search for new possibilities is an insightful field of inquiry. However, the contemporary message that emerges from critical legal consciousness analysis has often resulted in the distortion of the critical arguments themselves. This distortion denies the potential of legal change in order to illuminate what has yet to be achieved or even imagined . Most importantly, cooptation analysis is not unique to legal reform but can be extended to any process of social action and engagement. When claims of legal cooptation are compared to possible alternative forms of activism, the false necessity embedded in the contemporary story emerges — a story that privileges informal extralegal forms as transformative while assuming that a conservative tilt exists in formal legal paths. In the triangular conundrum of “law and social change,” law is regularly the first to be questioned, deconstructed, and then critically dismissed. The other two components of the equation — social and change — are often presumed to be immutable and unambiguous. Understanding the limits of legal change reveals the dangers of absolute reliance on one system and the need, in any effort for social reform, to contextualize the discourse, to avoid evasive, open-ended slogans, and to develop greater sensitivity to indirect effects and multiple courses of action. Despite its weaknesses, however, law is an optimistic discipline. It operates both in the present and in the future. Order without law is often the privilege of the strong. Marginalized groups have used legal reform precisely because they lacked power. Despite limitations, these groups have often successfully secured their interests through legislative and judicial victories. Rather than experiencing a disabling disenchantment with the legal system, we can learn from both the successes and failures of past models, with the aim of constantly redefining the boundaries of legal reform and making visible law’s broad reach. 2ac AT: Second off Cole memo Fails Kamin, 14 [Sam Kamin, Professor and Director, Constitutional Rights and Remedies Program, University of Denver, Sturm College of Law; J.D., Ph.D., University of California, Berkeley, “Cooperative Federalism and State Marijuana Regulation”, University of Colorado Law Review, Fall, 85 U. Colo. L. Rev. 1105, Lexis] II. A Step in the Right Direction - But Problems Remain By forestalling, at least for now, the threat of federal injunctive suit, the second Cole memo removed much of the uncertainty that has governed federal-state interaction in this area for the last five years. Although the memo was too long in coming, it made clear that the federal government would give the states an opportunity to prove themselves capable of managing the negative externalities of marijuana legalization, regulation, and taxation. As such, it is a no similar memorandum could remove the ancillary consequences of marijuana remaining a Schedule I narcotic under the CSA. As marijuana-law reform moves from a focus on medical use to an increasing emphasis on adult or recreational use, it confronts the consequences of marijuana's continuing federal prohibition. This Part sets forth some of the principal problems caused by marijuana's continued prohibition before turning to a solution in the next Part. A. Consequences for the Industry 1. Contracting Because marijuana remains illegal at the federal level, much of the predictability that comes from enforceable contracts is unavailable to marijuana practitioners. In 2012, for example, an Arizona state court refused to enforce a loan agreement between two Arizona residents and a Colorado marijuana dispensary on the basis that the contract was void as against public policy. positive, cooperative vision for the future of marijuana regulation in this country. n32 But the second Cole memo did not - and n33 Although this ruling had the effect of [*1114] providing a windfall to the illegally-operating dispensary, the court felt itself without recourse; so long as the trafficking of marijuana remains illegal under federal law, contracts designed to facilitate that conduct remain void. This result reminds us why the enforceability of contracts is important not just to the parties but to society more generally. When those who have loaned $ 500,000 (the amount in issue in the Arizona case) to a cash business find themselves without recourse to the courts, they might be tempted to engage in what the law euphemistically refers to as "self-help." 2. Banking Marijuana businesses are also currently denied one of the most basic of business needs: access to banking services. As has been widely reported, n34 threats of money-laundering prosecution from the federal government n35 have made banks gun-shy about lending to marijuana businesses. Currently, in Colorado, no bank will do business with marijuana businesses. n36 There are many negative consequences of withholding banking services from marijuana businesses. Principally, the lack of banking services keeps marijuana businesses operating in the shadows of society. As cash businesses, they are targets for violent crime. Faced with Everyone is better off when contracts are enforced by courts rather than by individuals with an ax to grind. this ever-present threat, marijuana business operators are left with [*1115] a Hobson's choice: they can either remain cash businesses and accept the risk and stigma that comes with that, or they can attempt to bank surreptitiously, through the use of their personal accounts or holding companies designed to purge the taint of marijuana transactions. These latter options, of course, open practitioners to the same threat of money-laundering charges that led to the unavailability of banking services in the first place. The governors of Colorado and Washington appealed to the federal government for assistance with this problem, n37 and in February of 2014 the Department of Justice and the Department of Treasury's Financial Crimes Enforcement Network released memos purporting to permit banks to do business with those in the marijuana industry. n38 the banking memos, like the second Cole memo which preceded it, stopped short of removing the specter of future enforcement actions. n39 One leading bank official was immediately quoted as saying, "We're still not going to bank them." n40 3. Legal Services The legal minefield described in the previous Section calls out for experienced legal counsel to help marijuana practitioners negotiate the complicated, everchanging web of marijuana rules and regulations. Marijuana's continuing illegality makes the provision of these legal services particularly fraught, however. As long as marijuana remains a prohibited substance and as long as the CSA continues to criminalize those who aid and abet marijuana distribution or [*1116] join in a conspiracy to distribute it - lawyers who assist their marijuana clients in setting up or running marijuana businesses necessarily put themselves at risk. Although the second Cole memo declares that states decriminalizing marijuana would generally be permitted to enforce marijuana laws themselves, the specter of federal prosecution of marijuana lawyers for aiding and abetting the illegal conduct of their clients continues to loom . Model Rule of Professional Conduct 1.2(d) n41 and its state analogs prohibit attorneys from knowingly facilitating criminal conduct. A literal reading of that rule However, would preclude a lawyer from providing any assistance - e.g., drafting contracts, negotiating leases - to clients whom the attorney knows are engaged in on-going violations of the CSA. In fact, there is a split of authority among those states that have considered whether providing legal services to the marijuana industry violates a lawyer's obligations under the rules of professional responsibility. n42 Colorado, having previously found such conduct to violate its state ethics rules, n43 later amended those [*1117] rules to explicitly permit lawyers to serve marijuana industry clients. n44 As I have argued elsewhere, I believe that other, countervailing policy considerations argue against such a literal reading of Rule 1.2(d) and its state-law equivalents. n45 Because states that are legalizing marijuana - either for medical patients or for adult users - are creating a complex regulatory apparatus, fairness requires the assistance of lawyers in navigating that system. Without the assistance of competent counsel, a state regulatory regime becomes a trap for the unwary. Furthermore, denying competent legal counsel to those engaged in the marijuana industry can have profound distributive effects. Powerful actors will be able either to secure legal assistance or to proceed without it; those without the same means will necessarily be disadvantaged and subject to considerable risk. Nonetheless, marijuana's continuing federal illegality means that attorneys may be unwilling to serve those who are in critical need of legal services. B. Consequences for Marijuana Users While negative externalities discussed above primarily affect marijuana practitioners, the consequences are no less profound for those simply wishing to consume marijuana in compliance with their state's are real and will persist so long as marijuana remains prohibited by the CSA; promises from the federal government to let the states [*1118] take the lead in marijuana enforcement simply do not undo the consequences of federal prohibition . 1. Employment Currently, one of the biggest impediments to the legalization of marijuana in the states is the fact that those who test positive for marijuana can lose their employment even if their conduct is entirely consistent with state law. In laws. These consequences Colorado, both state n46 and federal courts n47 have held that Colorado's "lawful off-duty conduct" statute does not govern the consumption of marijuana. Because the possession of marijuana remains illegal under federal law, these courts have reasoned that consuming marijuana is not "lawful" conduct, even if it does not violate state law. Furthermore, the Colorado courts have concluded that an individual fired for testing positive for marijuana is ineligible for unemployment benefits under the same reasoning, 2. Probation/Parole Similarly, state courts have used marijuana's continuing illegality at the federal level to deny otherwise qualified criminal defendants probation or parole. n49 Because it is generally a standard condition of supervised release - either following a term of imprisonment or in even if that individual is a marijuana patient acting in compliance with state law. n48 lieu of one - that the defendant agree to commit no new offenses during the period of [*1119] release, n50 courts have held that a defendant's positive test for marijuana permits his re-arrest. Unless or until legislatures in marijuana states make explicit provision for marijuana use consistent with state law, n51 the federal prohibition will continue to cast 3. Public Services Generally A number of other public benefits, from public housing to student loans to government employment, are conditioned on the recipient's abstinence from illegal-drug use. For example, the federal a shadow over the availability of supervised release for those using marijuana either medically or recreationally. program that helps fund local public housing agencies (PHAs) forbids those agencies from admitting into public housing facilities families that include members who use marijuana. n52 While PHAs have the discretion not to evict residents who use medical marijuana, n53 that discretion does not extend to admitting marijuana users into public housing even where their use is compliant with state law. A single medical marijuana patient, in other words, can make an entire [*1120] family ineligible to receive public the continued prohibition of marijuana at the federal level leads to unsettled expectations , not just for those trying to housing, as long as marijuana remains illegal under federal law. 4. Conclusion This non-exhaustive list of examples of consequences makes clear that make a living in the marijuana industry but also for those who would take advantage of state laws permitting marijuana use. Deputy Attorney General Cole stated that federal policy is to let states achieve federal goals through the taxing and regulation of marijuana rather than state-level prohibition, but the criminality of marijuana at the federal level makes such experimentation essentially impossible in practice . The following Part proposes a cooperative federalism approach to marijuana regulation. If states that wish to opt out of the CSA are permitted to do so , if that law simply does not apply within those states, then they will truly be able to function as laboratories of ideas with regard to marijuana regulation and taxation. III. A Solution: Making the Second Cole Memo Law The second Cole memo is a cooperative step toward solving the apparent contradiction created when states legalize a drug that the federal government continues to prohibit. This concluding Part sketches a solution that I hope to I propose that Congress amend the CSA in a manner that allows states to opt out of its marijuana provisions. The federal government has already set forth the criteria to be used in determining whether a state is regulating marijuana in a manner consistent with federal priorities. Under this approach, Congress would authorize the Attorney General, or some other executive official, to certify that a state is regulating marijuana in a manner consistent with federal priorities . n55 Upon certification, the state's regulations would [*1121] become the sole regulations governing marijuana within that state. Those state provisions, rather than the CSA, would then apply to the manufacture, distribution, and use of marijuana. n56 While this approach might closely resemble the status quo in which states are allowed to experiment with marijuana legalization so long as they keep in mind and help achieve federal goals, it has one crucial difference. Under the current approach, states are allowed to experiment with marijuana law reform through an act of prosecutorial grace. Those using, selling, or manufacturing marijuana under state law are not subject to criminal prosecution simply because federal prosecutors have chosen not to prosecute them. This decision can be undone by yet another memo. A newly elected president may chart a new policy course or may invoke the wiggleroom written into the second Cole memo. Thus, those using or selling marijuana pursuant to state law could be arrested and prosecuted without any change in federal law . But more than that, the problem with the status quo is that marijuana possession, manufacture, and expand upon in a later article. n54 distribution remain illegal under the second Cole memo. Even if the government keeps its promise not to intervene in states that have enacted robust marijuana regulations, the continuance of federal marijuana prohibition has a profound effect in those states. Only by making marijuana truly legal in those states, by allowing qualified states to opt out of the CSA, can the [*1122] states truly be empowered to chart their own policy direction . CSA removal causes a shift to decentralized federalism which best promotes innovation Shechtman, 12 [Matthew, judicial law clerk for the United States Court of Appeals for the Fifth Circuit, Joint Authority? The Case for State-Based Marijuana Regulation Winter, Tennessee Journal of Law and Policy, http://trace.tennessee.edu/cgi/viewcontent.cgi?article=1135&context=tjlp] The origin of today's "War on Drugs" emanated from Richard Nixon's 1968 presidential campaign, where he cited growing drug use as the next great problem facing the nation.8 Just a few years later, the Nixon Administration created the federal Drug Enforcement Administration ("DEA") and increased the drug enforcement budget to nearly $800 million.9 Though Nixon was primarily concerned with the more potent and destructive heroin epidemic,10 marijuana use was easily subsumed into the United States' drug war following three decades of haphazardly implemented anti-marijuana criminal and tax laws." The "War on Drugs" fire was stoked once again by a republican presidential campaign in 1980.12 Backed by the powerful "parents' movement,"l 3 Ronald Reagan re- established the "War on Drugs" through the "Just Say No" campaign and increased the federal drugenforcement budget to nearly $6 billion within the next three years.14 The anti-drug establishment continued to escalate through the 1990s, enlisting almost $20 billion in federal anti-drug coffers by 1998.15 The 21st century has seen little retreat from the legalist regime of the past three decades as the political ante continues to intensify. A modern example is exemplified by the Bush Administration's National Drug Control Strategy, aimed at "healing America's drug users."l6 Most relevant to today's marijuana legalization debate is the Controlled Substances Act ("CSA"), which incorporates marijuana among its many listed illicit substances.' 7 Maximum penalties for marijuana possession, cultivation, and distribution range from one year to life in prison, with maximum fines from one thousand to eight million dollars depending on the amount of marijuana at issue and the circumstances underlying the conviction.'8 The CSA is undoubtedly one of the most salient consequences of current Supreme Court jurisprudence regarding Congress' interstate commerce power. Notably, the Court found in Gonzales v. Raich that Congress did not overstep its Constitutional authority by regulating the trade of illicit substances, including marijuana. 19 Relying on Wickard v. Fillburn2,0 the Court held that even purely intrastate cultivation and distribution of marijuana is subject to federal regulation under the interstate commerce clause-and hence constitutionally controlled under the CSA.21 Even before Supreme Court jurisprudence dramatically extended Congress' ability to regulate illicit substances in interstate commerce, several commentators decried a federal "monopoly" over drug policy. 22 Though the federal government has always possessed "an impressive array of tools to influence policymaking at lower levels of government," 2 3 recent developments in academia and state-based drug policies, suggest that state authority and policy innovation has established a solid footing in the marijuana law paradigm, ranging from medical-use licensing to decriminalization. While recognizing the federal government's oversight role in drug enforcement policy, this article ultimately argues for horizontal competition-at the expense of federal supremacy25-in marijuana policy for several reasons. First, it is not clear that the federal government has constitutional authority to mandate state drug policy. 2 6 Though preemption, through properly enacted federal law, plays an important role in drug enforcement, the federal government cannot require a state to enforce federal laws.27 Second, though the mere presence of federal enforcement undoubtedly affects state policymaking, the lack of federal enforcement resources strongly limits the feasibility of effective wide-scale federal enforcement. To be sure, drug laws are almost exclusively implemented and policed by state and local governments. As such, likelihood of vertical competition from the federal government is reduced.29 lastly, federal regulation is inefficient and burdensome , diminishing citizen autonomy, while hindering innovation and consumer choice.30 Regardless of the federal government's involvement in drug policy, current state innovation in marijuana legislation is undoubtedly significant. Presently, sixteen states as well as the District of Columbia have enacted legislation legalizing the possession, cultivation, and use of marijuana for the treatment of certain illnesses.3 1 Against this state regulatory backdrop loom the CSA and the potential for DEA and FBI enforcement. As previously mentioned, however, the federal government plays a very small role in the enforcement and prosecution of marijuana users, growers, and dispensaries-the United States Attorney only manages about one percent of all marijuana cases, leaving the rest to state enforcement. 3 2 Given that federal resources are unable to manage the overwhelming drug caseload, and that many states have already shown their unwillingness to cede power over drug regulation and enforcement, there is significant room for states to implement and experiment with new marijuana laws. With state experimentation comes the possibility for competition between states in the enactment of innovative marijuana regulatory schemes and legalization policies. This dynamic is known as jurisdictional competition, or more simply, the market for laws. 33 The basic premise of the jurisdictional competition paradigm is that governments compete to supply laws in order to support the influx of business and economic benefits, taxes, and citizenry. 3 4 This legal market concept has been applied most extensively in the corporate law context, focusing on Delaware's market dominance. The market concept has, however, found a receptive audience in the fields of environmental law, tax, bankruptcy, trusts, and family law.35 This article embarks on an analysis of the competitive framework over drug lawmaking authority and enforcement. While recognizing the historic dominance of federal authority in the field,36 it argues against the efficacy of federal authority and in favor of decentralized regulation over marijuana policy . Using alcohol regulation as a guiding example, this article argues for state authority over marijuana regulation, with localized enforcement and state discretion over local policymaking authority. Notwithstanding the ban on possession, cultivation, distribution, and use, there are a number of regulatory mechanisms states can implement outside of absolute illegality. For instance, states can institute penalty schemes, by varying sentencing guidelines or establishing statutory penalty frameworks that differentiate between misdemeanor and felony violations. 3 7 In addition, some states have employed alternative sentencing schemes, experimenting with drug treatment courts and probation dependent upon the successful completion of a rehabilitation program. Outside of varying penalties, states have an array of legalization options, ranging from 39 40 to marijuana licenses for medical use. Not to mention, several states have instituted decriminalization laws wherein possession and use is either legal or considered a misdemeanor, while distribution and 41 trafficking remains criminal. Enhanced forfeiture is also an interesting option for reform that has potential incentive effects not only for criminal possessors but for state coffers. laws currently stand, asset forfeiture "provides a significant incentive for state and local governments both to allocate substantial resources to drug enforcement and to cooperate with federal agencies."4 3 On the other hand, from a marijuana user's perspective, reform initiatives aimed at limiting state and federal ability to confiscate property in conjunction with drug seizures may be a considerable incentive to relocate.4 Given the myriad of potential decentralized alternatives for marijuana regulation, there is significant room for jurisdictional competition among state and municipal governments for citizens, businesses, tax revenues, and reduced violent crime. On the other hand, the drug debate is never quite so clear-cut; there are significant political45 and moral considerations-e.g. addiction, rehabilitation, and health care expenditures, as well as the potential for decreased economic productivity in the wake of potentially rampant drug abuse. Given the complex considerations involved, the next Part will introduce a new theory of decentralized marijuana regulation modeled partly after state alcohol regulation, while accounting for possible spillover effects, interest group influence, and political incentives unique to the market for marijuana. II. Invigorating the Market for Marijuana Laws - Embracing a Decentralized Role for Regulation With fundamentally different individual and political viewpoints in the marijuana debate, citizen autonomy should be at the forefront of the regulatory policymaking agenda, providing an avenue for increased individual choice and more efficient and innovative lawmaking. Accordingly, the core argument in this article promotes the redistribution of marijuana regulatory authority away from the federal government and into the hands of the states and local authorities. After first outlining the current regulatory framework, this Part argues for the rejection of federal control over marijuana policymaking. Noting the federal government's failure to account for state innovation and autonomy, the first section utilizes public choice theory to establish a state-based framework akin to alcohol regulation following the Twenty-First Amendment. The following section explains criticisms of such a position, but ultimately dispels these analyses in favor of the state as central decision-maker. The following section, however, points out, and expands upon, two well-founded critiques of consolidated state control so as to build on the decentralization framework; placing state and local politics at the forefront of the marijuana regulatory regime. A. Federal Involvement in current drug policy can best be described by the "Cooperative Federalism" framework. This regulatory depiction is "a combination of federal policy mandates and inducements (such as conditional grants) that require or provide strong financial incentives for states to implement the federal policy."4 6 National policy issues that are not only resource intensive, but also respond to Drug Policy Ironically, hypothetical state-to-state externalities further buoy the federally dominated regulatory regime.47 Sparked by states enacting reactive policies to a particular problem, the federal government responds at the behest of states and - 48 interest groups most invested in the issue. On one hand, states concerned about the capacity to fund these programs and the ability to successfully implement the program if other states do not conform push the federal government to enact a national program. On the other hand, federal politicians can garner the political support of vocal interest groups,50 while only paying for part of the overarching program. ' In the context of drug policy, "Cooperative Federalism" is illustrated by the pioneer states that first prohibited marijuana, and the resulting federal program, implemented through the CSA and the "War on Drugs." As the "Cooperative Federalism" framework predicts, the drug regulation dynamic balances "federal desires for control (and hence political support) and . . . engagement of state and local law enforcement in the war on drugs (and hence minimization of costs to the federal budget)."52 Extensive federal involvement, however, does not leave adequate room for state innovation in the drug policy arena. 5 3 Rather, this paradigm is only responsive to the dynamic wherein states and the federal government express views that are in agreement, or at the very least, that can be squared through political compromise. 5 4 As a result, states are left to either venture on their own, in defiance of federal policy initiatives, or maintain some complicity with the "War on Drugs." B. Federal Drug Regulation is Hampering the Marketfor MarijuanaPolicy Amidst the federal drug policy debate, there are abundant theories for optimal policymaking and response to population preferences. These theories are based on principles of federalism, public choice, and efficient competition, and range from strong federal control to variations of hybrid state-federal policymaking that either attempt to explain the current dynamic or argue for a shift in regulatory policy to better engender efficient drug policy. This article advocates for decentralized drug policymaking in an effort to promote democracy, autonomy, and efficiency. The federal government has instituted a "War on Drugs," stemming from political and moral opposition that predominantly began in the 1970s. Out of political necessity and increasing violence attributed to drug trafficking, the federal executive branch invested ever-increasin resources into drug regulation and enforcement. Rather than promoting uniformity, curing hypothetical negative externalities, or stemming drug-use, the federal drug regime led to divergent state drug policies56 and an Executive Order that retreats from the strictures of the CSA.57 This drug regime also confuses the citizenry and retail merchants as to how the federal government will react to marijuana use, possession, and distribution. In contrast to federal marijuana laws, alcohol policy covering use and distribution is largely left to the states. 60 it is relevant, if not absolutely necessary, to compare the maladies documented from alcohol prohibition in the 1920s in an effort to engender a new era of efficient and autonomous marijuana policymaking in the hands of state and local governments. 1.The Pitfalls of Prohibition The federal government has three basic positions it can take in response to a given state policy: active support, neutrality, or active discouragement. In the drug regulation arena, the federal government's traditional stance has been based almost entirely on how closely state policy resembles the "War on Drugs" paradigm. 6 2 In contrast, the federal government's role in the alcohol arena strongly supports state efforts at policymaking, 6 3 where the only inde endent roles for the federal government lie in labeling, taxation, and interstate distribution.6 6 Current United States alcohol policy is hardly surprising given Prohibition's sordid past. On January 16, 1920, the Eighteenth Amendment to the Constitution went into effect and prohibited "the manufacture, sale, or transportation of intoxicating liquors . . . for beverage purposes. . . ."67 Within a few short years, alcohol use once again became rampant, but was now unregulated, dangerous, and controlled by organized crime; prisons were overpopulated, and corruption in public officials was 68 unprecedented.68 Prohibition's failure is distinctly ironic, given its lofty social and public health goals. Indeed, the "noble experiment" as it came to be known, "was undertaken to reduce crime and corruption, solve social problems, reduce the tax burden created by prisons and poorhouses, and improve health and hygiene in America."69 These goals are similarly idealized by the CSA,70 which has been espoused as no less than the protector of the nation's health and public welfare.7 1 Ignoring the pitfalls of Prohibition and the social ills befalling blind adherence to rigid moral high ground not only ignores potential economic boons due to product taxation and retail sale, but also leaves "controlled" substances to be bartered for in the underground market, adulterated by drug dealers, and subject only to regulation 72 noble ideals pushed by Prohibitionists in an effort to rid through the criminal underworld. society of the social ills created by alcohol, the homicide rate increased by seventyeight percent during Prohibition, all other crimes increased by twenty-four percent, and arrests for drunkenness and disorderly conduct increased by forty-one percent.73 In essence, "[m]ore crimes were committed because [P]rohibition destroy[ed] legal jobs, create[ed] black-market violence, divert[ed] resources from enforcement of other laws, and greatly increase[d] the prices people ha[d] to pay for the prohibited goods."74 The analogy to marijuana is striking considering the enormous rate of violent crime attributed to drug trafficking, yet the exorbitant number of inmates in United States prisons are incarcerated as a result of simple drug possession7.5 2. A State-Based Solution to Federal Marijuana Prohibition In response to the historically apt analogy to Prohibition and the arguable shortcomings inherent in the current federal drug regime, some commentators argue for adoption of the "Constitutional Alternative."76 Finding support in basic public choice theory, supporters of the "Constitutional Alternative" argue for a basic reversion of authority to the states , wherein "the power to control the manufacture, distribution, and consumption of all psychoactives" would be under state control. Strongly resembling the current federal-state dynamic over alcohol distribution, this dynamic, however, would leave the regulation of interstate drug distribution to the federal government. 7 9 Rather than purporting to legalize marijuana distribution, this power-shift is "intended to provide states with greater autonomy by 'permitting the states to choose drug-control strategies more in line with the preferences and circumstances of their citizens."' 80 This state-based framework is supported by two overarching policy rationales: 1) citizen choice; and 2) policy innovation. 1 Decentralization would promote more autonomy among the United States population to choose the laws and regulations that fit their lifestyle preferences so that if a "resident of one state does not like the rules imposed by the majority there, he is free to move to a state whose laws better suit his preferences or circumstances." 82 For example, if a nation consisted of one hundred people, forty of whom want marijuana to be legalized and sixty who would opt to retain the status quo, the ban on marijuana possession will remain in place-as it is in the CSA-leaving forty citizens unhappy with the law.83f, however, the nation were divided into separate states, each with the power to enforce its own laws, then more citizens would be content with the nation's regulatory policy.84 For instance, if one state contains fifty residents who favor the status quo and ten residents who would opt for legalization, while another state contains ten residents favoring continued illegality, and thirty who would opt for legalization, then one state will opt to maintain marijuana's illegal status, while the other will opt for some form of legalization. Simple arithmetic provides that eighty of the nation's citizenry will be satisfied, while twenty are still unhappy with the policy. 8 6 Adding in the option for citizen mobility and minimal transactions costs, the net benefits could be even greater.87 Decentralization also promotes policy innovation where states with divergent political considerations experiment with new-and possibly more optimal- regulatory policy. In stark contrast, a purely unitary federal policy only gives the political process one shot to respond to social needs.89 As Justice Brandeis' famous dissent points out, "[i]t is one of the happy incidents of the federal system that a single courageous state may, if its citizens choose, serve as a laboratory; and try novel social and economic experiments without risk to the rest of the country." 90 The simplistic example above shows us how the policy innovation rationale easily fits into the public choice model wherein two states adopting different policies can adapt, amend, or reject their own policies in response to the consequences-both positive and negative-displayed by their peer state's policy choices.91 Policymakers should take heed; just as Prohibition failed to cure, and even exacerbated, the social ills it attempted to curtail, the federal reign over marijuana law could do the same; it has already created an enormous taxpayer burden while leading to increased violent crime and addiction. 9 2 Though federal legislators may lose the political soapbox federal regulation so conveniently provides, repeal of the CSA (as it relates to marijuana) will lead to the same benefits we saw following enactment of the Twenty-First Amendment:9 3 reduced corruption and organized crime, job creation, and invigorated addiction support programs. III. Spillover Effects and Negative Externalities: Evaluating the Criticisms of Consolidated State Control Commentators have not unanimously rejoiced at the prospect of bolstering state power in drug policymaking. Rejecting the "Constitutional Alternative" approach to United States drug policy, Michael O'Hear argues that the federal government must "adopt a clear, coherent policy towards state innovation"9 5 through the adoption of a theory of government control he labels the "Competitive Alternative." 96 O'Hear critiques the purely state-based policymaking approach, arguing that it may actually "reduce the degree of decentralization in national drug policy by consolidating state control, and . . . [producing] perverse incentives that warrant federal intervention."97 The first section to this Part outlines O'Hear's concerns with an outright reversion of federal power to state regulatory authority. The following section attempts to rebut O'Hear's most salient critiques by utilizing traditional theory in the field of jurisdictional competition. The next section follows with an analysis of the focal points of O'Hear's "Competitive Alternative," evaluating the federal media machine and asset forfeiture laws. Finally, this Part attempts to reconcile and incorporate some of O'Hear's most salient and practical points with this article's approach to state control over marijuana regulatory policy. . O'Hear'sCritique Perhaps counter-intuitively, O'Hear argues that carte blanche state control could lead to less local autonomy than under the "Cooperative Federalist" regime. This is so because much of the support for federal drug control goes directly to localities-e.g. monetary grants, referral for federal prosecution, and equitable sharing statutes that allow local enforcement to keep some of the proceeds of drug confiscations. 99 Local autonomy may be engendered due to federal prosecutorial incentives as well, where United States Attorneys are subject to political pressures and must address local needs. 00 At the very least, O'Hear argues that state regulatory control would not clearly do a better job of regulatory policymaking than the current regime by stating that, "[n]otwithstanding the benefits of decentralization, federal control may still be justified on the basis of 'Race to the Bottom' pressures or spillover effects."' 0' He argues that dominant state regulatory authority may create a "Race to the Bottom" market failure wherein states will create continually relaxed marijuana regulation laws in an effort to garner tax revenues from legalized sale and distribution.10 2 The critique further predicts that "spillover effects" may undermine the workability of such a decentralization framework because states that relax their drug policy may create problematic negative externalities in "neighboring get-tough states." 03 O'Hear points out that a significant part of the cost of marijuana lies in the risk and subterfuge involved in the illegal trafficking regime, which inflates the price.104 Consequently, when states legalize the process, prices will deflate, attracting potential users in neighboring states-states that maintain the illegality of marijuana use, possession, and distribution.'0 5 In response to the alleged failings of state regulatory dominance, O'Hear argues for implementation of his own "Competitive Alternative." Though still grounded in a presumption of decentralized policymaking, O'Hear additionally focuses on reducing federal distortion of drug policy information, increasing local political control over federal drug enforcement decisions, and increasing local law enforcement accountability.106 B. Counteringthe Critique Despite O'Hear's reasoned criticisms, state-based regulatory authority is in many ways hard to dispute. Moreover, hypothetical fears can be assuaged, and state- based authority validated, by analogy to the current alcohol regulation framework, which would take nothing more than repeal of the CSA as it relates to marijuana control. Further, the main argument for federalization -07and one recognized by O'Hearl 0 8-often lies in an attempt to curtail negative externalities and potential "races to the bottom" among states.109 It is unclear, however, that federal regulation would be the answer, even if these market failures existed. More relevant to this discussion is the uncertainty that state-based marijuana policy is likely to lead to the problems highlighted in O'Hear's critique. 1. Federal Regulation May Not be the Answer to a Race to the Bottom for Marijuana Laws As previously discussed, O'Hear points out the likelihood of a "Race to the Bottom," and potential spillover effects resulting from the decentralization of drug policy.' 10 A common solution to these state-based market failures is preemptive federal regulatory authority." Picking up, however, on Richard Revesz's work in the environmental market for laws, federal regulation is not alwa s the quick fix to market failure that it is presumed to be." The typical argument for federal authority is simple; where federal regulation preempts state policymaking in the field, states will no longer be able to engage in an inefficient policy battle with negative social utility." 3 Revesz used federal authority in environmental policy to rebut the preemption rationale: [Flederal can have adverse effects on other state programs. Such secondary effects must be considered in evaluating the desirability of federal environmental regulation. Most importantly, the presence of such effects suggests that federal regulation will not be able to eliminate the negative effects of interstate competition. Recall that the central tenet of race-to-the-bottom claims is that environmental standards competition will lead to the reduction of social welfare; the assertion that states enact suboptimally lax environmental standards is simply a consequence of this more basic problem. In the face of federal environmental regulation, however, states will continue to compete for industry by adjusting the incentive structure of other state programs. Federal regulation thus will not solve the prisoner's dilemma.114 Revesz simply points out that regulation and social welfare are not created in a vacuum. The government should, and does, regulate in a complex matrix of policies involving a number of different variables that all impact each other. To take one of the variables that suffers from market failure and impose a uniform federal standard upon it does not necessarily lead to increased social welfare on the whole. In essence, desirable regulation is too complex to achieve through piecemeal centralization; it is akin to plugging the dam with a federal forefinger while watching the wall fissure just out of reach. Unfortunately for federalism and state autonomy, the theoretical result from such an approach is complete centralization in the federal 115 government. So what is to be made of the environmentalmarijuana analogy? Revesz points to competing regulatory variables in the environmental arena, like workers' rights and corporate taxation, which are inevitably tied to industry location decisions.116 Thus, when several variables play into corporate decision-making, one state-based regulatory change is unlikely to provide the incentives necessary to propagate a "Race to the Bottom." A possible counterargument to the application of this analogy here may elucidate a number of distinctions in marijuana regulation. For example, political decisions in the environmental arena are often aimed at maintaining the status quo-keeping industry in place or simply combating more stringent environmental policies-while progressive marijuana regulation runs against the status quo. Thus, rather than Revesz's world of environmental regulations playing a small factor in business incentives, marijuana regulation may play out differently. To be sure, political inertia is undoubtedly an important consideration when confronting change. Here, however, it is less than certain that the pivotal "status quo" distinction makes a difference in the theoretical argument; or practically whether it creates a barrier at all. Rather, it seems that the anti-drug status quo is less of a political fallback and more of a public perception and interest group driver that would be balanced in a jurisdictional competition framework. In fact, it is more likely that the complexities of regulatory dynamics would be more robust in the market for marijuana than contemplated in Revesz's critique of federal oversight in the environmental arena. Comparing the market for marijuana laws to the environmental law patchwork, there are several apparent variables in a complex regulatory scheme that would play against a centralization argument. Simply speaking, one such variable lies in economic growth itself. Much like pollution, if a state is not allowed to provide for legal marijuana sales-and hence benefit from economic growth and taxes-the state may loosen standards in other areas to compensate. Further, drug tourism is not an unheard of phenomenon; it is seen internationally, as well as in states that allow for purchase without local citizenship." 7 Federalized drug prohibition could thus lead to overly lax enforcement in tourism related to other vice goods like gambling or prostitution. Furthermore, it is plausible that, given the extensive prison overpopulation and the overwhelming burden faced by enforcement authorities, policymakers will institute overly lenient penalties for non- drug crimes or prosecutors may simply not enforce crimes to the extent of the law. In sum, just as Revesz argues that federal oversight is an unwise option for corrective regulation in the environmental arena, preemptive regulation in marijuana regulation is similarly disjunctive. Even if a "Race to the Bottom" does exist for marijuana laws, federal oversight may lead to inefficient regulation in other economic areas, especially tourism, in addition to penal laws and their enforcement. 2. It is Not Clear that Jurisdictional Competition for Marijuana Laws Will Lead to a Race to the Bottom Among States The preceding discussion may be largely irrelevant, however, if marijuana policy is not conducive to "Race to the Bottom" or negative externality market failures. In fact, there are several reasons we would not expect to see these economic failures play out in the realm of marijuana policy. In the criminal justice arena, scholars focus extensively on the effects of penalties on crime displacement and jurisdictional infighting that may lead to inefficient collective-action problems. This market failure contemplates peer jurisdictions "spending increasingly high resources on their criminal justice system[s] simply to deflect crime to their neighbors.""8 Indeed, "in recent decades [states] have shown increasing awareness of the criminal justice policies of their sister states."1 9 Scholars utilizing this approach are apt to recognize the need for federal oversight to eliminate the state "race" to overly harsh criminal penalties.'20 As previously discussed, a similar argument has been heavily cited and remarked upon in the environmental field; noting the argument for federal regulation to circumvent a state-industrial "Race to the Bottom" over pollution standards. 12 1 The clearly established "Race to the Bottom" argument in other areas can certainly be applied to criminal justice standards, wherein criminals are assumed to be rational actors and will commit crimes in the jurisdictions where the costs associated with illegal activity are the lowest.122 When one state implements stricter criminal laws or penalties, it is posited that criminals will at least consider relocating to a jurisdiction with more lenient standards. 12 3 In the face of criminal displacement, recipient states that presumably do not want the social ills associated with more criminals among its populace will respond inkind and institute even harsher penalties in an effort to displace the criminal population within its borders.1 This established model, however, only reasonably applies to criminal activities with little to no societal benefits; for instance, violent crimes, sex crimes, and larceny. In contrast, regardless of the negative effects of drug-use itself, a large proportion of the negative societal consequences of criminal drug activity are due to the nature of illicitness itself. To be sure, while drug use may lead to community costs in the form of increased health care outlays, rehabilitation, and reduced economic productivity, the overwhelming demand for drugs creates an enormous underground market, by drug dealers, street gangs, organized crime syndicates, and drug cartels. Whereas government-sanctioned markets are transparent and regulated, underground "shadow economies"1 26 lead to regulation by the hand of distribution, the criminal underworld and organized crime syndicates. The end result is a drug trade that leads to overwhelming violence, not just in manufacturing countries, but also in developed countries, which fuel the demand for these illicit substances. 127 On one hand, federal regulation of drug markets has led to remarkable societal consequences in the form of crime and violence. On the other hand, criminal 125 policed justice theorists suggest a potential "Race to the Bottom," leading to overly harsh criminal penalties. It is not clear, however, that a "Race to the Bottom" will occur in the marijuana market. Empirics and logic suggest a successful and societally beneficial market for drug legalization.128 For example, in contrast to state exile of pedophiles and violent criminals, states stand to benefit from increased tax revenues,129 less violent crime,130 and significant economic growth by taking an already existing market aboveground.1 3 1 In order for the "Race to the Bottom" theory to attach, there must be negative externalities sufficiently realized to incentivize states to change their laws in an attempt to remedy those externalities. First, consider Teichman's theory of overly strict regulation to effectively exile criminals from within a jurisdiction. This is hardly a far-fetched theory. Rather, state and local policies regarding ex-convicts have shown just such an effort to exile criminals through bussing and relocation efforts. 13 2 Taking the next step, altering penal laws to move criminals to other jurisdictions is also plausible. However, this theory's application in the realm of marijuana laws is less than certain and seemingly far- fetched. The negative externalities associated with criminal activities seemingly stem mostly from violence and economic losses through theft. Though addiction, medical problems, homelessness and vagrancy undoubtedly contribute to the attacks against legalization, these factors exist whether marijuana is legal or illegal, as we have seen for decades. But if a jurisdiction legalizes marijuana, the violent crime variable will presumably be eliminated as the market moves out of the hands of organized crime and into retail outlets.' 33 The more relevant question is whether marijuana use will increase with legalization; and if it does, whether the negative impacts of citizen use will outweigh the benefits, such that the jurisdiction will seek to move users outside its boundaries. Even assuming that most of the populace will begin to use, or even abuse, marijuana, it does not necessarily follow that there will be far-reaching negative public impacts. Though it is certainly possible that worker productivity may decrease, while accidents, DUIs, and addiction rehabilitation needs increase. It is also necessary to consider moral stigma and negative externalities associated with interjurisdictional trafficking. 134 Policymakers must balance these negative implications with the possible benefits of taxation, reduced prison populations, increased citizen autonomy and happiness, and reduced violent crime through elimination of the drug underworld. In contrast to the unsavory criminal activities noted by Teichman, where the criminal element moves from one jurisdiction to another, unwanted by all, marijuana users and would-be distributors would bring both benefits and possible detriments to a jurisdiction, leaving state and local government to make the decisions jurisdictional competition theorists argue should be made by decentralized government in order to further efficient and innovative lawmaking. Even if Teichman's "Race to the Bottom" for overregulation does not apply to the market for marijuana laws, an argument could be made that the opposite may be trueunder-regulation incited by jurisdictions competing for tax revenues, drug tourism, and economic growth. But just as liquor laws faced the Teetotalers in the early 20th century, progressive drug policy faces a strong check through opposition in the religious right and parent advocacy groups, among many others. The marijuana policy battlefield offers a multitude of variables for policymakers to balance as they attempt to appease and attract a presumably mobile populace. As they have been in the federal regulatory framework, interest groups will be at the forefront of marijuana policymaking instituted by the states, with constituencies influenced by a variety of considerations including corporate, retail, and direct taxation; citizen autonomy and happiness; economic growth; and reduced crime and prison populations.135 Driving anti-marijuana legislation are various interest groups intent on entrenching the status quo. For example, the biggest contributors to Partnership for a Drug-Free America are the Prison Industrial Complex, Big Pharmaceutical, Big Tobacco, and the alcohol manufacturing industry.' 36 If under-regulation is the concerning factor in a "Race to the Bottom" analysis, these major interest groups will play a strong role in combating increasingly lenient marijuana policy. Considering a "Race to the Bottom" may end in overly restrictive or overly lenient lawmaking depending on the interests, the aforementioned competing interests should be robust enough to avoid a "race" in either direction. Given the extent of politically salient variables in play, state autonomy in policymaking would seem particularly apt in the context of marijuana policy. Indeed, principles of federalism suggest that states be able to choose the laws most applicable to the characteristics of the jurisdiction "thereby giving mobile citizens many different regulatory regimes from which to choose when selecting a place to live."l 37 Stepping outside the realm of theory, reality has similarly not played out the way an under-regulating "Race to the Bottom" would dictate. Only sixteen states138 have made progressive marijuana regulation in the face of the this article's proposed solution would remove the supposed federal barrier, possibly giving hesitant states the last push necessary to enter the "race" to legalization , a map of current current administration's tolerant Executive Order' 39 and general federal reliance on state enforcement.140 Though drug laws indicates that the impetus for progressive marijuana laws is likely more strongly tied to geographical ideologies and preferences than fear of the federal government's stance on drug laws.141 For instance, the most progressive laws tend to be on the West Coast: California, Nevada, Oregon, Washington, Hawaii, Alaska, Montana, and Colorado.14 2 In contrast, southern "bible belt" states have the strictest stance on marijuana with essentially zero- tolerance laws in Texas, Louisiana, Alabama, South Carolina, Georgia, Florida, Arkansas, Oklahoma, and Tennessee. 143 While hardly conclusive evidence of ideological preference influencing marijuana policymaking, the religious, tobacco, and prison industrial interest groups' stranglehold over the Southeast may well keep states in this region from entertaining progressive legalization laws, even if the federal government leaves the picture. This is not surprising given that analogous alcohol bans in counties and municipalities lie almost exclusively in the Southeast.'" Despite the uncertainty inherent in jurisdictional competition for marijuana laws, state autonomy seems to be the best alternative in an effort to achieve the greatest public welfare. In the absence of over-burdensome negative externalities and a race to overly strict or overly lax marijuana laws, the federal government's role should be limited to international traffic cop and interstate referee. Even if the aforementioned market failures do exist in a competitive framework for marijuana regulation, it is wholly unclear that the federal government's role as uniform legislator is the proper solution where states have other regulatory avenues to exploit in an effort to establish economic growth and constituent appeasement. Even Teichman concedes that "the U[nited] S[tates] government has a dismal track record when it comes to criminal justice, very often manifesting an irrational 'tou h on crime' attitude irrespective of legislative context."1 4 Prohibition's catastrophic failure should give policymakers keen background insight into marijuana's current federal regulatory future, opening the door for state and local authority with the repeal of the CSA's prohibition on marijuana use, possession, and distribution. C. The Competitive Alternative's Practical Concerns Though the market for marijuana policy likely includes the competing interests necessary to avoid the problems encountered in state-based market O'Hear nonetheless makes several salient suggestions for creating an efficient model for decentralization of marijuana policy and enforcement, regardless of the federal government's ultimate policymaking role. The "Competitive Alternative" first highlights federal policies and practices that distort the political debate over drug policy, hampering state and local efforts that conflict with the federal "War on Drugs." 46 Federal control inhibits state-based policy on a number of fronts. For instance, the federal marketing machine places an overwhelmingly negative spin on marijuana and progressive drug enforcement policy.14 7 This federal message stifles alternatives to the current status quo, including decriminalization or medical marijuana programs.148 In response, the "Competitive Alternative" posits that federal funds for advertising and marketing might be decentralized and turned over to the states to use at their discretion, or at the very least, with minimal federal funding conditions attached.14 9 In addition to revamping the federal media machine, O'Hear articulates a need for local oversight over federal enforcement.o50 This point harkens to the limited federal resources for drug policy implementation, yet acknowledges the overarching need for occasional federal enforcement and prosecution. O'Hear proposes a possible reform, requiring a local official, such as a District Attorney, to approve federal prosecutions within municipal boundaries so as to establish "systematic checks on federal 5 enforcement discretion."'1 While O'Hear maintains some federal control, he does not discount the need for local policymaking and enforcement. The "Competitive Alternative" keenly looks to the incentives driving municipal actors who forge drug O'Hear and the "Competitive Alternative" model. Highlighting the danger of spillover effects or a potential "Race to the Bottom," the "Competitive Alternative" calls for continued federal supremacy, with local control in the political and enforcement regimes, while systematically overhauling the federal media machine. In the end, there may be no perfect regulatory scheme, but if the past several decades of drug regulation have shown us anything, the United States fosters a vastly inefficient and over-budgeted federal drug regime imposed at the expense of state innovation. Recent state reforms have shown expansive state-based marijuana law reform and the federal government should respond in turn, ceding regulatory authority to the states and local governments. D. The Give and Take - Putting the Competitive Alternative to Work "[W]ithin our system of government, state control stands not as an endpoint on the decentralization spectrum, but as a midpoint between federal and local control."' 5 7 Indeed, O'Hear argues that the same tenets justifying decentralization to the states support further reversion to local governments.' 5 8 For example, citizen mobility is greater at the local level than across state lines and, rather than fifty state-level policy innovators, localities would provide tens of thousands of opportunities for experimentation.1 5 9 O'Hear's "Competitive Alternative" makes local authorities the gatekeepers to federal enforcement authority.160 Further, disassembling the federal media machine and eliminating the misaligned forfeiture laws are central propositions of the "Competitive Alternative."'61 While the previous section made the case for the "Constitutional Alternative," supporting a strong decentralization framework, this section analyzes the applicability of O'Hear's "Competitive Alternative" in an attempt to improve the state-based framework and respond to some of the likely shortcomings inherent in over- expansive decentralization. 1. Questioning the Localist Paradigm The "Competitive Alternative" pushes strongly for extensive decentralization, past the state level and on to local authorities, while maintaining a co-extensive federal regime.162 Local governments, however, lack the financial resources of states and have insufficient economies of scale to justify expensive enforcement mechanisms.163 In addition, while it is easier for criminals to cross municipality lines, local enforcement jurisdiction only extends to local boundaries.164 Most importantly, local governments rely on the state to provide an overarching criminal code and prison system. In O'Hear's defense, he does acknowledge these problems, and notes a possible solution of state funding, while allowing for local implementation at municipalities' discretion. 16 6 O'Hear argues that municipal decentralization accounts for local implementation instead of the state in the same way it does for state authority vis-A-vis the federal government; essentially the argument is that if some decentralization is good, then more is better.167 The consequences, however, of policymaking authority may not affect local governments in the same way they do state governments. Indeed, citizen autonomy is undoubtedly benefited by even more localized policymaking, increasing the policy choices of United States citizens from fifty states to tens of thousands of counties or municipalities. But the ultimate answer may lie in the incentives already encountered by the entrenchment and proliferation of the federal "War on Drugs" in the first place; policymakers seek to gain political clout with their constituencies while paying for as little of the program as possible.168 Just as federal legislators do not want to foot the bill for drug enforcement without the political windfall that comes with it, state legislators do not want to provide the implementation funds for policies that they may not agree with. Given that the states currently enforce the majority of marijuana violations, implement and fund the penal institutions, and would be the main beneficiaries of state corporate, sales, and direct drug taxes, the lawmaking authority and implementation should remain with the states, rather than localities that do not have the means to implement their own policy choices. This is not to say that states could not relinquish exclusive control, leaving authority with the local government, just that they would not be forced to do so, as O'Hear seems to argue. Just as the Twenty-First Amendment places plenary control in the hands of the states, repeal of the CSA's marijuana restrictions would leave authority and implementation solely to state discretion. While some states may pass policymaking authority down to localities, such an outcome would not be required, allowing state legislators to make the decision as to where state funds and the resulting political consequences go. It is also unclear why O'Hear posits the need for local authorities to serve as gatekeepers to federal enforcement authority' 69 as opposed to a purely state-based mechanism, removing the need for federal enforcement in intrastate marijuana policy. While the local-federal cooperative would put more power in the hands of local authorities, the "Competitive Alternative" uses a roundabout mechanism for empowering local politicians, while still supporting federal entrenchment. Indeed, rather than bolstering extensive bureaucracy and the resulting squabble between state and federal officials-not to mention the looming threat of federal bullying of local District Attorneys-an alternative would be for states and local governments to maintain concurrent enforcement authority, keepinf the federal government out of intrastate marijuana issues. In sum, O'Hear's localized enforcement regimes seem less responsive to the shortcomings of state-based regulatory authority, and more to amending some pitfalls in the federally dominated regulatory model. For instance, O'Hear argues for localization on one hand in making local law enforcement accountable to the local community, yet his framework notes that "local police would become answerable not only to federal law enforcement authorities, but also to local leaders who stand outside the law enforcement establishment."l 7 1 Rather than decentralization and the workability of a state-local dichotomy in incentivizing efficient enforcement allocation, the "Competitive Alternative" seemingly adapts the current federal framework by instituting a more localized federal regime, appeasing decentralization advocates while tiptoeing around the status quo. 2. Learning From the Competitive Alternative The "Competitive Alternative" make a good point about the perverse incentives generated by current forfeiture laws and articulates a very workable idea in the form of redirection to a state general fund. 17 2 Because municipal actors respond to drug policies at the ground level, forfeiture and sharing laws incentivize local enforcement personnel to over-enforce drug laws in an effort to boost local coffers with the proceeds from drug busts. Rather than redirecting all enforcement to the state, O'Hear smartly recognizes the ability to redirect assets to the state level.173 The "Competitive Alternative" also cogently points to the problems inherent in the federal framing of the drug issue to the American public.174 The federal propaganda machine and its "War on Drugs" distorts the issues surrounding marijuana legislation and pits reform groups against politicians responding to the federal anti-drug stance. O'Hear sensibly argues for federal advertising funding to be directed instead to state marketing budgets or to Congressional spending bills.s75 The importance of this directive, however, may be limited under a "Constitutional Alternative" framework, as the federal government plays such a limited role in marijuana enforcement that continued federal advertising spending would be unlikely. Unlike the alcohol regulatory context, however, there are still many other drugs that would fall under the guise of the CSA, maintaining the federal government's incentive to continue its campaign against illegal drugs. Thus, it does appear that some control over the federal media machine is necessary, and directing at least a portion of its funds as it relates to marijuana is imperative. In addition, stipulations as to the federal content and the overarching "War on Drugs" message would be essential to fostering state innovation and adoption of progressive marijuana policies. Ultimately, O'Hear's "Competitive Alternative" argument, while putting forth strong ideas for specific reforms, is seemingly unresponsive to any purported shortcomings of state-based regulatory authority. Instead of elucidating the decentralization regime he purports to stand behind, O'Hear makes adjustments to much of the federally entrenched framework we see in place today, without accounting for the reality, and necessity of, state innovation and competition in the market for marijuana. Nonetheless, O'Hear makes cogent points about the federal role in enforcement, incentives, and media content. Accordingly, this article recognizes the need to adopt reformed forfeiture laws, asset redirection, and redistributed government media funding so as to properly set the stage for state-based jurisdiction over marijuana laws. IV. A Final Concern Raised by Decentralization: The "Race to Nowhere" The previous Part set out to raise, and refute, some of the most salient concerns surrounding state consolidation of marijuana policy. Among the most prominent arguments against divergent state-based policymaking is the "Race to the Bottom" effect garnered by individualized competition for (or against) an identifiable social policy repercussion. As discussed previously, the variety of interests inherent in the market for marijuana do not lend it to a race to overly stringent or lenient regulation and increasingly inefficient outcomes inherent in one-upping neighboring states. Interestingly though, is the possibility not for a "Race to the Bottom," but simply to one extreme or the other, giving a jurisdiction an all-or-nothing choice, legalization or a complete ban. This Part will first explain a previously illegalization in an effort to avoid the criminal element entrenched in illegal drug distribution. B. Undercutting the Assumptions Necessary to Effectuate a "Race to Nowhere" Clearly, the aforementioned result is not optimal for a state that, all else being equal, chooses decriminalization, medical marijuana, or drug treatment programs over full legalization or a complete ban. Policymakers faced with an all or nothing choice will opt for the lesser of two evils, whatever that choice might be, but inefficient regardless. This hypothetical, however, rests on several assumptions, none of which can be fully realized in a world of bundled laws and complex regulatory frameworks. For the "Race to Nowhere" to occur there must be citizen mobility, full information, and unrealized benefits from the centrist choice. First, consider the ability and willingness of citizens to move from one jurisdiction to another based on the marijuana policies within the state. With more than fourteen million marijuana users in the United States, this is hardly a trifling variable.176 But of those fourteen million users, it is entirely unclear how many would choose to move based on the legality of their marijuana use when all they have ever known is a complete ban. Moreover, it is questionable how many would choose to relocate at the expense of families, jobs, and geographic ties. Assuming that many users choose to remain in a total-ban jurisdiction, State A, criminal distributors would have a market in both State A and State C, the intermediate, decriminalized, jurisdiction. Given this counterargument to full mobility, we can expect a viable criminal distribution market spread across both abolitionist and intermediate jurisdictions. One part of the hypothetical should remain true, however, in that the criminal element would remain displaced in State B, where distribution is legal, because the criminal distribution chain would be overwhelmed by regulated retail sales. Unlike mobility, full information is more likely to come to fruition in this hypothetical. With the overwhelming use of the Internet and the salience of the marijuana policy debate, both consumers and distributors are likely fully aware of the relevant policies in place. On the demand side, any consumer making a decision to move jurisdictions based on the marijuana policy is undoubtedly informed of the law when making such a decision. Even if not making a mobility decision based on another jurisdiction's marijuana laws, it seems likely that a drug user, accustomed to illicit substance use and avoiding enforcement, will be aware of current policy and upcoming changes to policy. On the supply side, just as we would expect a businessman to know the regulations and laws that apply to the business, drug dealers or legal dispensaries will know the law, how to avoid or comply with it, and surely be abreast of changes in policy. The true uncertainty in full information is more likely to be through the lens of the policymaker. A legislator faced with battling interest groups may be more informed on highly specific issues and less apprised of the indirect criminal costs associated with marijuana distribution and displacement from other jurisdictions. The costs and benefits of proposed intermediate policy is probably most difficult to project and account for in a hypothetical "Race to Nowhere." For such a race to occur, the hypothetical assumes that the benefits associated with a centrist marijuana policy choice would be outweighed by criminal activity within its borders based on the policy actions of State A and State B. However, given uncertain citizen mobility and possible criminal disbursement between State C and State B, the costs associated with such a choice may be limited. Further, state policymakers may not have full information on the consequences of their decisions relative to increased criminal distributor influx into the jurisdiction. Moreover, even if these two factors are fully realized, legislators may find that the benefits of an intermediate policy outweigh the costs of any criminal influx. For instance, reduced enforcement costs on minor possession may be redistributed to enforcement on distributors and trafficking or simply used for drug treatment. The intermediate policy itself may be focused on public health, instituting drug courts, or rehabilitation,'77 rather than turning a blind eye to addiction as many abolitionist states do, or simply promoting use as a legalization state does. The "Race to Nowhere" is likely not a foregone conclusion, albeit relying on several assumptions that are almost impossible to predict. Focusing on the analogy to alcohol regulation leads to the conclusion that the race is at least plausible, though limited. While states are free to implement their own alcohol policies, none has kept alcohol completely illegal; some states, however, maintained prohibition for several years following enactment of the Twenty-First Amendment. But some states do allow counties and municipalities to enact their own alcohol restrictions, and many have done so, opting for complete bans within county lines; restricted alcohol sales on certain days of the week; or requiring distribution through government suppliers. 7 9 While some of these limitations are less than a complete ban, and clearly not full legalization, neither are they akin to decriminalization where one side of the economic chain, consumption, is legalized and the other side, distribution, is criminal. Centrist alcohol ordinances, such as Sunday sales and government distribution, would not be expected to garner a bootlegging criminal element. Criminals are unlikely to move to take advantage of a one-day black market or to attempt to circumvent government distribution when consumers can easily accommodate the law and still consume alcohol. Liquor law regulation in this context has not progressed toward decriminalization or substance abuse programs in lieu of criminal punishment. Rather, alcohol policies reflect complete bans or legalization with retail restrictions. The alcohol analogy, though not perfectly aligned to marijuana regulation, seems to support a "Race to Nowhere." Even if a "Race to Nowhere" exists, the cure is not federal regulation. The Prohibition and its aftermath tells us that much. Beyond the alcohol regulatory analogy, the past generations of over-enforcement; billions of dollars of federal taxpayer money; seeming absence of a "Race to the Bottom" or substantial negative externalities; exceedingly high violent crime rates associated with illicit drugs; and unclear federal enforcement policy lead to the conclusion that decentralization is the best regulatory stance for marijuana laws. IV. Conclusion Currently, more than 24.8 million people are eligible to receive medical marijuana licenses under state laws, and approximately 730,000 people actually do.180 Medical marijuana markets exist in seven states: California, Colorado, Michigan, Montana, Oregon, Washington and New Mexico and five more will open this year in Arizona, Maine, New Jersey, Rhode Island and the District of Columbia.' Economically speaking, the marijuana marketplace is projected to more than double within the next five years.1 2 Outside of the capitalist retail market for marijuana, the question remains whether there is a viable market for innovative state laws. As addressed in Part II.A.- B., the federal regime over marijuana laws is hampering innovation and efficient policymaking, leaving overly harsh federal laws that go largely unenforced in practice and by Executive Order. State legislators and enforcement authorities are left in the dark, and United States citizens are faced with an unclear state-federal dichotomy by which distribution may be illegal but consumption is decriminalized. Even more striking, dispensary operators may be legally licensed by the state and yet subject to federal enforcement for violation of the Controlled Substances Act.183 Even outside the lack of clarity and poor suitability of federal authority, we should expect a fairly robust "market" for marijuana laws where there are competing interests, an informed and reactive populace, and a primed state-to-state competition for economic growth and citizenry.184 Further, as discussed in Part III.B, there does not seem to be reason to expect marijuana policies to be ill-suited for efficient competition, by promoting a "Race to the Bottom" 85 through imperfect information, negative externalities, or power inequalities between suppliers and consumers of laws. 86 In addition, federalization as a remedy to an unclear problem stifles innovation and experimentation, replacing jurisdictional competition with regulatory oversight and unwavering rules.' 8 7 Most simply, a given legal system would prefer state laws if the "market" has the ability to produce efficient laws and will not inflict market failures leading to overly stringent or lax regulation.'8 In the market for marijuana laws, one would expect to encounter less need for consistency, uniformity, and correction of market failure because jurisdictional "markets" in the drug trade will presumably be transparent and consumers will have relatively full information, while states will have appropriate incentives to optimize laws.' 89 The legalization, decriminalization, and medicalization of marijuana undoubtedly comprise a story in its early chapters. As states continue to adopt progressive marijuana laws, the legal marijuana industry continues to grow, and the executive branch ignores the strictures of the CSA, the structure of marijuana policy will begin to crystallize. Until then, United States citizens are at a crossroads of conflicting state and federal law and are waiting to see how the policymaking game will play out. Interest groups and lobbyists are no strangers to this game, pitting Big Tobacco, Big Pharma, the Prison Industrial Complex, and the Religious Right against a progressive populace and state legislators looking to fill their recession- ragged coffers while cutting back on drug-induced violence. The federal regulatory regime and the politically motivated and maintained "War on Drugs" costs American taxpayers billions of dollars a year in a seemingly fruitless attempt to rid the American populace of the social and moral hazards of drug use. Yet the social ills of marijuana use stem almost entirely from its illicitness, 90 inducing violent organized crime but causing fewer deaths each year than alcoholl91 or tobacco use;192 marijuana's addiction rate is also a mere pittance compared to nicotine addiction.' 9 3 The United States system of federalism is premised on extensive state autonomy, leading to experimentation and innovation in policymaking, concurrent with the citizenry's ability to choose the laws they want applied by locating in a jurisdiction with the bundle of laws they find most appealing. In accordance with this paradigm, we have already seen the bulwark of progressive marijuana laws enacted on the West Coast,194 and almost no innovation in the Southeast, seemingly in line with population ideologies in those respective locales.' 95 Cutting the federal government entirely out of marijuana regulation and enforcement is neither plausible, nor advisable. The drug trade is too international to limit federal involvement and states rely on federal enforcement where distribution and trafficking crosses state lines. Economies of scale also empower the federal government to utilize powerful resources in an effort to keep pace with well-funded drug syndicates. Further, federal legislators have too much at stake in the drug debate to let it go entirely. As seen in the alcohol regulatory scheme, we can expect to see Congress utilize its spending power to incentivize states to act in accordance with federal objectives.16 That being said, two central arguments from the "Competitive Alternative" give informed guidance to Congress, arguing to reign back on forfeiture laws and simultaneously cut spending on federal media campaigns against marijuana use.197 Ultimately, it seems the marijuana train has left the station and has the momentum necessary to establish its legitimacy in the United States. The million-dollar question then is how it will be regulated. From the standpoint of history and logic, state authority is the best vehicle for public welfare, citizen autonomy, and efficient regulation. AT: First The ballot is a referendum on the normative desirability of the 1ac’s strategy Moore, 99 [John prof @ Cambridge with Johan Muller, University of Cape Town “The Discourse of Voice and the Problem of Knowledge and Identity in the Sociology of Education,” British Journal of Sociology of Education 20 (2) p. 199-200] The pedagogic device (Bernstein, 1990) of voice discourse promotes a methodology in which the explication of a method's social location precludes the need to examine the content of its data as grounds for valid explanation. Who says it is what counts, not what is said. This approach favours an ethnography that claims to reveal the cultural specificity of the category--the 'voice' of membership. What is held to be the facts, to be the case, is only so-and can only be so-from a particular perspective. The world thus viewed is a patchwork of incommensurable and exclusive voices or standpoints. Through the process of sub-division, increasingly more particularised identity categories come into being, each claiming the unique specificity of its distinctive experience and the knowledge authorised by it. The consequence of the abolition of the knowledge boundary that follows from the epistemological theses of postmodernism is the increasing specialisation of social categories (see Maton, 1998). Maton describes this process of proliferation in terms of the way such 'knower' discourses, ... base their legitimation upon the privileged insight of a knower, and work at maintaining strong boundaries around their definition of this knowerthey celebrate difference where 'truth' is defined by the 'knower' or 'voice'. As each voice is brought into the choir, the category of the privileged 'knower' becomes smaller, each strongly bounded from one another, for each 'voice' has its own privileged and specialised knowledge. The client 'knower' group thus fragments, each fragment with its own representative ... The procession of the excluded thus becomes, in terms of the privileged 'knower', an accretion of adjectives, the 'hyphenation' which knower modes often proclaim as progress. In summary, with the emergence of each new category of knower, the categories of knowers become smaller, leading to proliferation and fragmentation within the knowledge formation. (ibid., p. 17) As Maton argues, this move promotes a fundamental change in the principle of legitimationfrom what is known (and how) to who knows it. The device that welds knowledge to standpoint, voice and experience, produces a result that is inherently unstable, because the anchor for the voice is an interior authenticity that can never be demonstrated, only claimed (Taylor, 1992; Siegel, 1997; Fuss, 1990, 1995). Since all such claims are power claims, the authenticity of the voice is constantly prone to a purifying challenge, 'If you do not believe it you are not one of us' (Hammersly & Gomm, 1997, para. 3.3) that gears down to ever more rarefied specialisations or iterations of the voice category; an unstoppable spiral that Bernstein (1997, p. 176) has referred to as the 'shrinking of the moral imagination [10]. As Bernstein puts it, 'The voice of a social category (academic discourse, gender subject, occupational subject) is constructed by the degree of specialisation of the discursive rules If categories of either agents or discourse are specialised, then each category necessarily has its own specific identity and its own specific boundaries. The speciality of each category is created, maintained and reproduced only if the relations between the categories of which a given category is a member are preserved. What is to be preserved? The regulating and legitimising the form of communication' (1990, p.23). insulation between the categories. It is the strength of the insulation that creates a space in which a category can become specific. If a category wishes to increase its specificity, it has to appropriate the means to produce the necessary insulation that is the prior condition to its appropriating specificity. (ibid.) Collection codes employ an organisation of knowledge to specialise categories of person, integrated codes employ an organisation of persons to specialise categories of knowledge (Bernstein, 1977, pp. 106-111). The instability of the social categories associated with voice discourse reflects the fact that there is no stable and agreed-upon way of constructing such categories. By their nature, they are always open to contestation and further fragmentation. In principle, there is no terminal point where 'identities' can finally come to rest. It is for this reason that this position can reappear so frequently across time and space within the intellectual field-the same move can be repeated endlessly under the disguise of 'difference'. In Bernstein's terms, the organisation of knowledge is, most significantly, a device for the regulation of consciousness. The pedagogic device is thus a symbolic ruler of consciousness in its selective creation, positioning and oppositioning of pedagogic subjects. It is the con- dition for the production, reproduction, and transformation of culture. The question is: whose ruler, what consciousness? (1990, p. 189) The relativistic challenge to epistemologically grounded strong classifications of knowledge removes the means whereby social categories and their relations can be strongly theorised and effectively researched in a form that is other than arbitrary and can be challenged by anyone choosing to assert an alternative perspective or standpoint. The opportunity cost of their framework is the AFF –the perms combinination solves Deudney 13 – (2013, Daniel, Associate Professor and Director of Undergraduate Studies in Political Science at Johns Hopkins University, “Mixed Ontology, Planetary Geopolitics, and Republican Greenpeace,” http://www.theory-talks.org/2013/11/theory-talk-60_9211.html) In many parts of both European and American IR and related areas, Postmodern and constructivist theories have significantly contributed to IR theorists by enhancing our appreciation of ideas, language, and identities in politics. As a response to the limits and blindnesses of certain types of rationalist, structuralist, and functional theories, this renewed interest in the ideational is an important advance. Unfortunately, both postmodernism and constructivism have been marked by a strong tendency to go too far in their emphasis of the ideational. Postmodernism and constructivism have also helped make theorists much more conscious of the implicit—and often severely limiting—ontological assumptions that underlay, inform, and bound their investigations. This is also a major contribution to the study of world politics in all its aspects. Unfortunately, this turn to ontology has also had intellectually limiting effects by going too far, in the search for a pure or nearly pure social ontology. With the growth in these two approaches, there has indeed been a decided decline in theorizing about the material. But elsewhere in the diverse world of theorizing about IR and the global, theorizing about the material never came anything close to disappearing or being eclipsed. For anyone thinking about the relationships between politics and nuclear weapons, space, and the environment , theorizing about the material has remained at the center, and it would be difficult to even conceive of how theorizing about the material could largely disappear . The recent ‘re-discovery of the material’ associated with various self-styled ‘new materialists’ is a welcome, if belated, re-discovery for postmodernists and constructivists. For most of the rest of us, the material had never been largely dropped out. A very visible example of the ways in which the decline in appropriate attention to the material, an excessive turn to the ideational, and the quest for a nearly pure social ontology, can lead theorizing astray is the core argument in Alexander Wendt’s main book, Social Theory of International Politics, one of the widely recognized landmarks of constructivist IR theory. The first part of the book advances a very carefully wrought and sophisticated argument for a nearly pure ideational social ontology. The material is explicitly displaced into a residue or rump of unimportance. But then, to the reader’s surprise, the material, in the form of ‘common fate’ produced by nuclear weapons, and climate change, reappears and is deployed to play a really crucial role in understanding ontologically incommensurate and very different realities are inescapable parts the human world. These ‘unlikes’ are inescapable parts of any argument, and must somehow be combined . There are a vast number of ways in which they can be combined, and on close examination, virtually all arguments in the social sciences are actually employing some version of a mixed ontology, however implicitly and under-acknowledged. But not all combinations are equally useful in addressing all questions. In my version of mixed ontology—which I call ‘practical contemporary change in world politics. My solution is to employ a mixed ontology. By this I mean that I think several naturalism’—human social agency is understood to be occurring ‘between two natures’: on the one hand the largely fixed nature of humans, and on the other the changing nature composed of the material world, a shifting amalgam of actual non-human material nature of geography and ecology, along with human artifacts and infrastructures. Within this frame, I posit as rooted in human biological nature, a set of ‘natural needs,’ most notably for security-from-violence and habitat services. Then I pose questions of functionality, by which I mean: which combinations of material practices, political structures, ideas and identities are needed to achieve these ends in different material contexts? Answering this question requires the formulation of various ‘historical materialist’ propositions, which in turn entails the systematic formulation of typologies and variation in both the These arguments are not centered on explaining what has or what will happen. Instead they are practical in the sense that they are attempting to answer the question of ‘what is to be done’ given the fixed ends and given changing material contexts. I think this is what advocates of arms control and environmental sustainability are actually doing when they claim that one set of material practices and their attendant political structures, identities and ideas must be replaced with another if basic human needs are to going to practices, structures and ideas, and in material contexts. continue to be meet in the contemporary planetary material situation created by the globalization of machine civilization on earth. Since this set of arguments is framed within a mixed ontology, ideas and identities are a vital part of the research agenda. Much of the energy of postmodern and many varieties of critical theory have focused on ‘deconstructing’ various identities and ideas. This critical activity has produced and continues to produce many insights of theorizing about politics. But I think there is an un-tapped potential for theorists who are interested in ideas and identities, and who want their work to make a positive contribution to practical problem-solving in the contemporary planetary human situation in what might be termed a ‘constructive constructivism’. This concerns a large practical theory agenda —and an urgent one at that, given the rapid increase in planetary problems —revolving around the task of figuring out which ideas and identities are appropriate for the planetary world, and in figuring out how they can be rapidly disseminated. Pro-cartel propaganda has flooded Mexico and is beginning to saturate America – correctives like the plan that accurately describe Mexican violence and its potential risks are crucial Guevara 13 [Journal of Strategic Security, Volume 6, Number 5 Fall 2013 Supplement: Ninth Annual, IAFIE Conference: Expanding the Frontiers of¶ Intelligence Education, Article 17, „Propaganda in Mexico’s Drug War,”¶ America Y. Guevara, ManTech International Corporation] As a result of governmental pressure, cartels evolved from criminal organizations to¶ organizations with capabilities to conduct intelligence, enforcement and propaganda¶ operations. This new level of sophistication has unprecedented and unidentified¶ outcomes. Mexican drug cartels have actively sought to transform the Mexican populace¶ with their intense forms of propaganda as they use violence, introduced the “narco”¶ concept, the narco-culture, narco-saints, intimidation tactics, and intent to control the¶ media . Their use of propaganda is also intended to create immense fear among rivaling¶ cartels and public/elected officials, defend their plazas, and provide a warning sign for¶ those who dare cross their path. The question arises: To what extent has Mexican drug¶ cartel propaganda become embedded in mainstream Mexico and what are the cartel’s¶ benefits for using these tactics?¶ Significance¶ The long-term consequences of cartel propaganda are still unknown. This new form of¶ criminality has the potential to threaten the United States homeland security as the narcolifestyle,¶ its messages and its violence spills over the borderland and into mainstream¶ society. Much to the intent of the cartels, a large degree of Mexican citizens have become¶ desensitized favorably to them due to their use of propaganda as their music, clothing, ¶ and religious aspects spread become embedded in Mexican mainstream society . As¶ acceptance of the cartels grows, so do their capabilities to recruit, glamorize the cartel¶ lifestyle, influence Mexican government measures as well as decrease the effectiveness¶ of government countermeasures. The fear of international spread is grand, as the border¶ region tends to contain a large number of Mexican immigrants who still maintain ties to¶ Mexico. Contact with the border nation-state is constant and difficult to limit. The spread¶ of this virus continues to spread we can soon find our society infected with its¶ consequences as only a wire fence physically limits the United States from Mexico. The¶ vulnerability is high as the constant flow of ideas and people are not limited by this¶ physical separation.¶ The Mexican drug cartels have blurred the lines between criminality, insurgency, and¶ terrorism further raising the national security importance of this topic. The cartels engage¶ in terrorist tactics to psychologically intimidate and manipulate rivals, journalist, and¶ government officials by using improvised explosive devices (IEDs), massive displays of¶ violence, narco-demonstrations and roadblocks. Cartels use insurgency tools by targeting¶ government officials through kidnapping or execution to produce a change in power¶ structure that better suits the cartels objectives further eroding the Mexican state.¶ Government officials are forced to act by the infamous phrase “plata o plomo”¶ demanding a decision between death or becoming a forced accomplice. The best¶ initiative is to further investigate the cartels’ propaganda campaigns, understand them and¶ keep a vigilant eye on their affects, especially in the borderland in order to prevent cartel¶ message infiltration. Ultimately, the relevance of propaganda to the United States¶ national security is that of preventing problem crossover by tracking the evolution of the¶ propaganda while the target demographic for said campaigns remains outside of the¶ United States. Outcomes matter, not intentions -- legalization is a good starting point Wilkinson 2013 (Will; Leveraging racism; Jun 11; www.economist.com/blogs/democracyinamerica/2013/06/marijuana-legalisation; kdf) This Bill Maher monologue, nominating marijuana legalisation as "the next gay marriage...the next obvious civil-rights issue that needs to fall", beautifully encapsulates the shifting tactics of savvy legalisation advocates. Mr Maher jokes openly (starting at about 2.20) about the sham, de facto legalisation brought about by California's medical-marijuana system, frankly suggesting that concern for the comfort and welfare of the sick and suffering was a pretext for people like him to acquire weed legally. He then goes on to profess solemnly his concern for "the three-quarters of a million people who are arrested for simple possession every year, and the fact that blacks are arrested at seven times the rate of whites, which is a subtle way to suppress the black vote, because 48 states limit voting rights for convicted felons". Marijuana prohibition: racist and undemocratic! You know what? It is outrageous. Legalisation supporters are going to get plenty of mileage out of this. Perhaps it will even push legalisation efforts past the intense moral objections of prohibitionists. But what about the shameless opportunism of privileged middle-class stoners (or rich ones, like Mr Maher) suddenly up in arms about the systemic racism of the American criminal-justice system? We should welcome it. We should cheer it, even if it begins in bad faith. Indignant exhortation only gets us so far. The best hope for justice is always an alliance with self-interest. It's unlikely that my legalisation activist friends would have come to care much about the cruelty of denying marijuana to the sick, but they came to care, genuinely and deeply. Once they saw the strategic sense of focusing first on the legalisation of medical marijuana, the needless suffering caused by prohibition truly engaged their empathy and compassion. Suddenly, tens of thousands of people too weak to fight for themselves had legions fighting sincerely on their behalf. The legalisation movement's strategic turn toward the racism of America's criminal-justice system is heartening for similar reasons. Institutionalised racism is America's great wickedness, and it remains braided through everyday American life, but its salience has faded for most. If the prospect of one day smoking a spliff with impunity is what it takes to get college kids outraged about the fact that the war on drugs turned out to be the second coming of Jim Crow, so be it. Sick people don't care why we came to want to help them. The unjustly jailed won't care why we came to set them free. We recognize the disparate impact that marijuana has on diferrent people – targeting solutions for reform doesn’t trade off with other solutions Jarecki 14 [08/02/14, Eugene Jarecki is a New York-based writer and film-maker. His Grierson, Emmy and Sundance-winning works include Why We Fight, The Trials of Henry Kissinger and The House I Live In, “As the marijuana economy takes off, let's not forget the casualties of the US war on drugs”, http://www.theguardian.com/commentisfree/2014/aug/03/marijuana-economy-casualties-us-war-on-drugs-eugene-jarecki] Throughout America's history, official and unofficial systems of racial oppression have arisen, been challenged, and then gone underground, shape-shifting themselves to return another day. In the modern era, as lawyer Michelle Alexander has argued in her book The New Jim Crow, the drug war stepped in to become the latest system . In 1971, as the gains of the civil rights movement for black Americans and other minorities might have seemed to usher America into a post-racial age, the drug war renewed the nation's commitment , however subtly, to the obstruction of black progress. Today as the marijuana economies in Colorado and Washington begin to take flight, Alexander noted the inescapable undertow of race that continues to haunt this moment of apparent progress at play: "Forty years of impoverished black kids getting prison time for selling weed, and their families and futures destroyed … Now, white men are planning to get rich doing precisely the same thing." Over those four decades, the war on drugs has failed abjectly in its stated mission – addressing a legitimate concern about rates of US addiction – but succeeded overwhelmingly in what would appear its de facto goals – making drug crime the primary preoccupation of law enforcement, flooding the courts with drug cases and overcrowding prisons with the world's largest population of inmates, more than 50% on drug-related charges. Taken together, these accomplishments have produced a system of mass incarceration that costs taxpayers an estimated $51bn a year, becoming one of the nation's leading employers. Within its walls, black Americans represent more than 50% of those sentenced for drug crimes, despite the fact that black people represent only 13% of the population and do not use drugs more or less than white people. A decade ago, when I began investigating the drug war in what would become my documentary The House I Live In, acquaintances were intrigued. They knew I was neither a drug user nor a dealer. They also knew that I was a comfortable white American, and thus highly unlikely to have been affected by the drug war personally. Inevitably, the question would arise about whether I was an advocate of marijuana legalisation, which had then become a primary focus for most reformers. I responded always with indignation, saying that I did not support legalising marijuana if that meant simply giving dreadlocked white snowboarders easier access to weed. Rather, I was concerned with the drug war's implications for poor and minority Americans, whose communities had been ravaged by the war's destructive machinery. I also saw a philosophic error in separating marijuana from other drugs. Part of what is assumed by advocates of the drug war is that the government has a legitimate role determining what substance an adult can choose to put in his or her body in the exercise of the right to life, liberty and the pursuit of happiness. Arguing that one drug should be legalised while others not seems to elide this question of public policy. And this elision is dangerous, first because it enables the country to avoid a deeper dialogue about the illegality of drugs per se and, second, because I feared it could let steam out of the debate about the drug war more broadly, reducing public pressure for its overhaul. Worse, I even feared that by going easy on weed we would tighten the screws on the rest, keeping the system and its predations intact . I've since changed my mind on the importance of marijuana as a target for reformers , owing to what I've learned about the role it plays in driving the cycle of personal, family and community destruction on which the war thrives . "Gateway drug" has been the term often used by drug warriors to suggest that, with one puff of a joint, a young person may find himself hurtling down a road to hard drugs. Despite this notion's popularity, it has little or no basis in science. Yet marijuana is a gateway drug for countless young Americans into a lifetime of involvement with the criminal justice system. For many, an arrest for possession at a young age can start a chain reaction that leads first to drastically reduced employability and then to a higher likelihood of becoming engaged in the underground economy of drug distribution, often the only job available. Once this happens, it becomes almost a fait accompli that that person will spend a serious portion of his life rotating in and out of the system. The numbers speak volumes . Of the 2.2 million prisoners serving in the US, nearly 25% were convicted of marijuana possession . Legalisation, were it retroactive, would dramatically reduce prisoner numbers while profoundly stemming the tide . The aff is the largest step towards ending institutional racism— Franklin and Title 2014 (Neill and Shaleen; 3 Reasons Marijuana Legalization in Colorado Is Good for People of Color; Jan 23; www.huffingtonpost.com/neillfranklin/marijuana-legalization-race-racism-minorities_b_4651456.html; kdf) For the first time, President Obama acknowledged this week that the prohibition of marijuana is unfairly enforced against AfricanAmericans and Latinos, and for that reason, he says, legalization in Colorado and Washington should go forward. Without explicitly endorsing the laws, he told the New Yorker, "it's important for [them] to go forward because it's important for society not to have a situation in which a large portion of people have at one time or another broken the law and only a select few get punished." As the president acknowledged, marijuana prohibition targets black and brown people (even though marijuana users are equally or more likely to be white). Ending prohibition through passing legalization laws, as Colorado and Washington have, will reduce this racial disparity. The war on drugs, as we all know, has led to mass criminalization and incarceration for people of color. The legalization of marijuana, which took effect for the first time in the country in Colorado on January 1, is one step toward ending that war. While the new law won't eradicate systemic racism in our criminal justice system completely, it is one of the most effective things we can do to address it. Here are three concrete ways that Colorado's law is good for people of color. 1. The new law means there will be no more arrests for marijuana possession in Colorado. Under Colorado's new law, residents 21 or older can produce, possess, use and sell up to an ounce of marijuana at a time. This change will have a real and measurable impact on people of color in Colorado, where the racial disparities in marijuana possession arrests have been reprehensible. In the last ten years, Colorado police arrested blacks for marijuana possession at more than three times the rate they arrested whites, even though whites used marijuana at higher rates. As noted by the NAACP in its endorsement of the legalization law, it's particularly bad in Denver, where almost one-third of the people arrested for private adult possession marijuana are black, though they make up only 11% of the population. These arrests can have devastating and long-lasting consequences. An arrest record can affect the ability to get a job, housing, student loans and public benefits. As law professor Michelle Alexander describes, people (largely black and brown) who acquire a criminal record simply for being caught with marijuana are relegated to a permanent second-class status. When we make marijuana legal, we stop those arrests from happening. 2. Unlike under decriminalization, the new law means there will be no more arrests for mere marijuana possession in Colorado, period. In the Jan. 6 article "#Breaking Black: Why Colorado's weed laws may backfire for black Americans," Goldie Taylor mistakenly suggests that Colorado's new legalization law may "further tip the scales in favor of a privileged class already largely safe from criminalization." Much of the stubborn "this-changes-nothing" belief about the new law stems from confusion between decriminalization and legalization. There is a profound difference between the hodgepodge of laws known collectively as "decriminalization" passed in several states over the past 30 years, and Colorado's unprecedented legalization law. Decriminalization usually refers to a change in the law which removes criminal but not civil penalties for marijuana possession, allowing police to issue civil fines (similar to speeding tickets), or require drug education or expensive treatment programs in lieu of being arrested. Because of the ambiguity in some states with decriminalization, cops still arrest users with small amounts of marijuana due to technicalities, such as having illegal paraphernalia, or for having marijuana in "public view" after asking them to empty their pockets. One only need look as far as the infamous stop-and-frisk law in New York, where marijuana is decriminalized, to see how these ambiguities might be abused to the detriment of people of color. In Colorado, however, the marijuana industry is now legal and above-ground. People therefore have a right to possess and use marijuana products, although as with alcohol, there are restrictions relating to things like age, driving, and public use. Police won't be able to racially profile by claiming they smelled marijuana or saw it in plain view. 3. We will reduce real problems associated with the illicit market. As marijuana users shift to making purchases at regulated stores, we'll start to see improvement in problems that were blamed on marijuana but are in fact consequences of its prohibition. The violence related to the street-corner drug trade will begin to fall as the illicit market is slowly replaced by well-guarded stores with cameras and security systems. And consumers will now know what they're getting; instead of buying whatever's in a baggie, they have the benefit of choosing from a wide variety of marijuana products at the price level and potency they desire. Goldie Taylor made the dubious claim that since marijuana prices were initially high in Colorado's new stores, the creation of a legal market won't affect the existing illicit market. But despite sensational headlines, prices for marijuana are just like anything else. They respond to levels of supply and demand. In the first couple weeks, prices were high because only a small fraction of marijuana businesses in Colorado opened, and what looked like every user in the state was in line to make a purchase on the day the historic law took effect. As the novelty-fueled demand levels off and the rest of the stores across the state begin to open, increasing supply, prices will drop. For their money, purchasers can conveniently buy a product they know is tested and unadulterated. And for those who don't want to buy at a store, Colorado residents over 21 are permitted to grow up to six marijuana plants at home. Make no mistake: communities of color, particularly young black men, continue to face injustice in the form of the drug war, and marijuana legalization has not fixed that. Even around marijuana laws alone, there is much more work to do. But the voters of Colorado deserve to be applauded for demanding an end to the thousands of racially disparate marijuana possession arrests of its citizens each year. 1ar AT: Follow On Their delay arguments take out the neg’s offense but not the aff— legalization is inevitable at the state level because of voter pressure, but federal inertia means only CSA removal solves Vitiello, 13 [MICHAEL VITIELLO* Joints or the Joint: Colorado and Washington Square Off Against the United States,Distinguished Professor of Law, University of the Pacific, McGeorge School of Law; University of Pennsylvania, J.D., 1974; Swarthmore College, B.A., 1969, ] The first brief moment when the federal government seemed ready to reevaluate its position on marijuana occurred during Jimmy Carter’s presidency. President Carter called for its decriminalization. Also during the Carter presidency, the government implemented a compassionate use program, allowing some seriously ill patients access to marijuana through a carefully controlled federal program.57 Begun during Richard Nixon’s presidency,58 the War on Drugs proliferated during Ronald Reagan’s presidency.59 Penalties were increased, often with mandatory minimum sentences.60 And those laws were enforced, often vigorously.61 Under federal drug laws, marijuana is categorized as a Schedule I drug, one for which there is no recognized medical benefit.62 The government has fought all efforts to reschedule marijuana. It fought early efforts of the National Organization for the Reform of Marijuana Laws (NORML) to do so. As I summarized elsewhere, Litigation dragged on between 1972 and 1992, with drug enforcement agencies using various procedural maneuvers to prevent a hearing on the issue. Despite an administrative law judge’s recommendation, the DEA administrator ruled against More recent efforts to reschedule marijuana have been met with similar resistance by the federal government. Protracted litigation has ended recently with a federal court of appeals again upholding the Drug Enforcement Agency’s (DEA) refusal to reschedule marijuana .64 During the 2008 presidential campaign, candidate Obama gave supporters of legalization of marijuana hope when he stated that he would stop raids on “legitimate” medical marijuana dispensaries.65 Shortly after the election, the Attorney General’s office issued a memo randum seemingly implementing that promise.66 Almost certainly, the government’s “softer” approach led to rapid expansion of dispensaries in states with existing medical marijuana laws67 and to passage of medical marijuana statutes elsewhere.68 That was then. But what followed seems like a U-turn in administration policy. Notably, in California, marijuana providers opened hundreds of dispensaries, often in central business locations.69 The Obama administration reacted forcefully. Under his administration, there have been more raids on marijuana dispensaries in California than there were under the Bush administration.70 Federal government agents have threatened landlords with forfeiture of their drug laws that heighten penalties when drug dealers sell drugs within proximity to schools.72 Finally, the Internal Revenue Service has pursued “legitimate” dispensaries. The IRS’s position is especially threatening to states’ hopes of raising tax revenues. Reagan-era legislation makes it unlawful for drug dealers to deduct ordinary business expenses, including salaries paid to staff.73 At least according to news reports, the IRS has targeted some of the most law-abiding dispensaries in California.74 That stance, if upheld by the courts,75 has a potentially perverse effect: dispensary owners most interested in complying with the law would be forced out of business, while those who are interested in using medical marijuana laws as a cover for drug trafficking may be able to remain in business. Some observers express little surprise in the Obama administration’s shift in its position.76 An outsider might conclude that the Obama administration discovered a reality of modern government: change is hard because of inertia resulting from entrenched vested interests of governmental agencies . Thus, the administration’s policy shift may have resulted from a conflict between Obama’s more tolerant position towards marijuana and officials in the Office of National Drug Policy, the DEA, and other law enforcement agencies.77 Unwilling to take on entrenched bureaucrats, especially after the 2010 election debacle, the administration simply folded. If that narrative is accurate, then at least for the next several years, talk of legalization of marijuana is wishful thinking . Using its full arsenal, the federal government can prevent Colorado and Washington from implementing their laws. At least as drug laws are written, state officials who participate in the state-authorized drug trade—for example, as employees providing marijuana—would be violating federal law. As the federal government has done in California, it can invoke various laws, including forfeiture laws and tax laws, to drive state-authorized drug sellers out of business. Again, continuing the same narrative, efforts to legalize marijuana create an existential crisis for agencies like the DEA: officials in those agencies will not go away without a fight. Viewed from that perspective, reports of the demise of marijuana laws are greatly exaggerated. We will concede this—2ac Schechtman in 2ac Shechtman 2012 (Matthew, “Joint Authority? The Case for State-Based Marijuana Regulation”, Tennessee Journal of Law & Policy Volume 8 | Issue 1 Article 4, http://trace.tennessee.edu/cgi/viewcontent.cgi?article=1135&context=tjlp) With fundamentally different individual and political viewpoints in the marijuana debate, citizen autonomy should be at the forefront of the regulatory policymaking agenda, providing an avenue for increased individual choice and more efficient and innovative lawmaking. Accordingly, the core argument in this article promotes the redistribution of marijuana regulatory authority away from the federal government and into the hands of the states and local authorities. After first outlining the current regulatory framework, this Part argues for the rejection of federal control over marijuana policymaking. Noting the federal government's failure to account for state innovation and autonomy, the first section utilizes public choice theory to establish a state-based framework akin to alcohol regulation following the Twenty-First Amendment. The following section explains criticisms of such a position, but ultimately dispels these analyses in favor of the state as central decision-maker. The following section, however, points out, and expands upon, two well-founded critiques of consolidated state control so as to build on the decentralization framework; placing state and local politics at the forefront of the marijuana regulatory regime. Federalism externally turns and outweighs case EPSTEIN and LOYOLA 2014 (RICHARD, Laurence A. Tisch Professor of Law at New York University, the Peter and Kirsten Bedford Senior Fellow at the Hoover Institution, and the James Parker Hall Distinguished Service Professor of Law (emeritus) at the University of Chicago and MARIO, senior fellow at the Texas Public Policy Foundation, “Saving Federalism”, National Affairs, ISSUE NUMBER 20 ~ SUMMER 2014, http://www.nationalaffairs.com/publications/detail/saving-federalism) It is particularly vital to disentangle the operations of state and federal governments. It is one thing for the federal government to locate a research institute at a state university or manage multiple federal, state, and local agencies in response to a disaster. It is quite another to systematically integrate the finances of governments with separate taxing authorities. As Michael Greve convincingly argues in his 2012 book, The Upside Down Constitution, the intermingling of state and federal finances has led to a disastrous and unsustainable fiscal dysfunction across the whole government. The money Washington sends to the states is not "assistance"; it is rent for the use of state agencies as field offices of the federal government, in transactions that contain a strong element of coercion. Much the same is true for cooperative regulatory programs under "conditional preemption." The separation of state and federal government is every bit as vital as the separation of powers within government, and given the much greater disparities in bargaining power, judicial policing of that troubled boundary is as indispensable for long-term national prosperity as for federalism itself.2