The Constitution and the International Order Outline Prof. Feldman Spring 2009 Ethan Kent CONST. & INT’L ORDER OUTLINE Chapter 1 – Constitution and Empire 5 § 1.01 – Summary of Cases & Materials ................................................................................................................5 [A] – Somersett’s Case, 98 Eng. Rep. 510 (K.B. 1772) ........................................................................................5 [B] – Scott v. Sandford, 60 U.S. 393 (1856)..........................................................................................................5 [C] – Downes v. Bidwell, 182 U.S. 244 (1901) .....................................................................................................5 [D] – Johnson v. Eisentrager, 339 U.S. 763 (1950) ...............................................................................................5 [E] – Ahrens v. Clark, 335 US. 188 (1948) ...........................................................................................................5 [F] – Reid v. Covert, 354 U.S. 1 (1957) ................................................................................................................6 [G] – United States v. Verdugo-Urquidez, 494 U.S. 259 (1990) ...........................................................................6 [H] – Rasul v. Bush, 542 U.S. 466 (2004) .............................................................................................................6 [I] – Boumediene v. Bush, 128 S.Ct. 2229 (2008).................................................................................................7 § 1.02 – Important Themes .....................................................................................................................................7 [A] – Lawyers’ Special Skills ................................................................................................................................7 [B] – The History and Origins of the Writ of Habeas Corpus ...............................................................................8 [C] – Sovereignty...................................................................................................................................................8 [D] – Natural Law..................................................................................................................................................9 [E] – The Tension between Limited Powers and Empire ......................................................................................9 [G] – Guantanamo’s Rationale ............................................................................................................................ 10 [H] – Ideology and the Justices............................................................................................................................ 10 [I] – SCOTUS Justices: A Soap Opera ................................................................................................................ 11 [J] – Constitutional Rights without Remedies? ................................................................................................... 12 Chapter 2 – International Law? 13 § 2.01 – Summary of Cases & Materials .............................................................................................................. 13 [A] – The Schooner Exchange v. McFaddon, 11 U.S. 116 (1812) ...................................................................... 13 [B] – United States v. Schooner Peggy, 5 U.S. 103 (1801) ................................................................................. 13 [C] – The Antelope, 23 U.S. 66 (1825) ............................................................................................................... 13 [D] – Vattel, The Law of Nations (1758, English edition of 1854) lv–lxvi ......................................................... 13 [E] – Joseph Story, “Law of Nations,” in Encyclopedia Americana vol. ix (1843) 141–49 ................................ 13 [F] – Brown v. United States, 12 U.S. 110 (1814) ............................................................................................... 13 [G] – Foster v. Neilson, 27 U.S. 253 (1829) ........................................................................................................ 14 [H] – United States v. Percheman, 32 U.S. 51 (1833) ......................................................................................... 14 [I] – The Paquete Habana, 175 U.S. 677 (1900) .................................................................................................. 14 [J] – Filartiga v. Pena-Irala, 630 F.2d 876 (2d Cir. 1980) ................................................................................... 14 [K] – Tel Oren v. Libyan Arab Republic, 726 F.2d 774 (D.C. Cir. 1984) ........................................................... 15 [L] – Kadic v. Karadzic, 70 F.3d 232 (2d Cir. 1996)........................................................................................... 15 [M] – Louis Henkin, International Law as Law in the United States, 82 Mich. L. Rev. 1555 (1984) ................. 15 [N] – Bradley & Goldsmith, Customary International Law as Federal Common Law: A Critique of the Modern Position, 110 Harv. L. Rev. 815 (1997) ............................................................................................................... 15 [O] – Sosa v. Alvarez-Machain, 542 U.S. 692 (2004) ......................................................................................... 15 § 2.02 – Important Themes ................................................................................................................................... 16 [A] – The Law of Nations, the Law of Nature, and Individuals .......................................................................... 16 [B] – Treaties ....................................................................................................................................................... 16 [C] – Who / What is the U.S. Sovereign? ............................................................................................................ 16 [D] – Sources of Customary International Law ................................................................................................... 17 [E] – CIL as U.S. law........................................................................................................................................... 17 [F] – Act of State & Political Question Doctrines ............................................................................................... 18 [G] – The Alien Tort Statute Today..................................................................................................................... 18 [H] – The Blackstone Three ................................................................................................................................ 18 [I] – The Relationship Between our Constitution and the International Order .................................................... 18 Chapter 3 – Torture: An Interlude 20 § 3.01 – Summary of Cases & Materials .............................................................................................................. 20 [A] – Geneva Conventions, Common Article III ................................................................................................. 20 [B] – Memo from Jay Bybee to Alberto Gonzales (Aug. 1, 2002) ...................................................................... 20 2 [C] – McCain Torture Act ................................................................................................................................... 20 [D] – Congressional testimony—Gonzalez, Mukasey, and Holder ..................................................................... 20 [E] – Committee against Torture, Israel High Court Case ................................................................................... 20 § 3.02 – Important Themes ................................................................................................................................... 20 [A] – Attorney Responsibilities ........................................................................................................................... 20 [B] – What is Torture? ......................................................................................................................................... 21 [C] – Unitary Executive ....................................................................................................................................... 21 [D] – What’s Do the Senate Confirmation Hearings Tell Us About Torture? ..................................................... 22 [E] – Authorization v. Avoidance of Liability ..................................................................................................... 22 Chapter 4 – War and Exception 23 § 4.01 – Summary of Cases & Materials .............................................................................................................. 23 [A] – The Lieber Code: Excerpts ......................................................................................................................... 23 [B] – Letter from Abraham Lincoln to Sen. Albert G. Hodges (Apr. 4, 1864) .................................................... 23 [C] – Abraham Lincoln, Message to Congress in Special Session (July 4, 1861) ............................................... 23 [D] – Letter from Abraham Lincoln to Erastus Corning and Others (June 12, 1863) ......................................... 23 [E] – Ex parte Merryman, 17 F. Cas. 144 (C.C.D. Md. 1861) ............................................................................. 23 [F] – Ex parte Milligan, 71 U.S. (4 Wall.) 2 (1866) ............................................................................................ 23 [G] – Carl Schmitt, Political Theology: Four Chapters on the Concept of Sovereignty 12–13 (George Schwab, trans. 1985) .......................................................................................................................................................... 24 [H] – Korematsu v. United States, 323 U.S. 214 (1944) ..................................................................................... 24 [I] – Ex parte Endo, 323 U.S. 283 (1944) ............................................................................................................ 24 [J] – Ex Parte Quirin, 317 U.S. 1 (1942) ............................................................................................................. 24 [K] – In re Yamashita, 327 U.S. 1 (1946) ............................................................................................................ 25 [L] – Hirota v. MacArthur, 338 U.S. 197 (1949) ................................................................................................. 25 [M] – Hamdi v. Rumsfeld, 542 U.S. 507 (2004) ................................................................................................. 25 [N] – Hamdan v. Rumsfeld, 548 U.S. 557 (2006) ............................................................................................... 26 [O] – Padilla v. Hanft, 432 F.3d 582 (4th Cir. 2005) ........................................................................................... 26 § 4.02 – Important Themes ................................................................................................................................... 26 [A] – The Tests of a Constitution ........................................................................................................................ 27 [B] – War = Necessity?........................................................................................................................................ 27 [C] – Sharp Wars ................................................................................................................................................. 27 [D] – Habeas as Guardian of the Rule of Law ..................................................................................................... 27 [E] – A Schmittian Analysis of U.S. Exception ................................................................................................... 27 [F] – Do it But Don’t Bring it into Court ............................................................................................................. 28 [G] – Habeas Jurisprudence: Jurisdiction v. Substance ....................................................................................... 28 [H] – The Geneva Convention ............................................................................................................................. 28 Chapter 5 – Who Obeys What? The States and International Law 29 § 5.01 – Summary of Cases & Materials .............................................................................................................. 29 [A] – Missouri v. Holland, 252 U.S. 416 (1920) ................................................................................................. 29 [B] – Reid v. Covert, 354 U.S. 1, 16-18 (1957) ................................................................................................... 29 [C] – Convention on Consular Relations (Apr. 24, 1963) – Article 36 ............................................................... 29 [D] – State Department Materials on VCCR Compliance: Flow Chart and Booklet ........................................... 29 [E] – LaGrand Case (F.R.G. v. U.S.), 2001 I.C.J. 466 (June 27) ......................................................................... 29 [F] – In the Case Concerning Avena and Other Mexican Nationals (Mex. v. U.S.), 2004 I.C.J. 128 (Mar. 31). 30 [G] – George W. Bush, Memorandum for the Attorney General (Feb. 28, 2005) ............................................... 30 [H] – Sanchez-Llamas v. Oregon & Bustillo v. Johnson, 548 U.S. 331 (2006) .................................................. 30 [I] – Medellin v. Texas 120 S. Ct. 1346 (2008) .................................................................................................. 30 § 5.02 – Important Themes ................................................................................................................................... 31 [A] – Federal and State Power and Treaties ........................................................................................................ 31 [B] – Comity and Timid Courts ........................................................................................................................... 31 [C] – The Supreme Court as (Exclusive?) Interpreter of Treaties ....................................................................... 32 [D] – Treaties, Unsettled? .................................................................................................................................... 32 [D] – The Political Implications of Self-Execution (Now and Then) .................................................................. 32 [E] – Anthony Kennedy v. Everyone Else ........................................................................................................... 32 3 Chapter 6 – The Constitution in International Markets / Rights and International Norms 33 § 6.01 – Summary of Cases & Materials .............................................................................................................. 33 [A] – Charles A. Beard, An Economic Interpretation of the Constitution Of The United States (1913) ............. 33 [B] – Robert A. McGuire, To Form A More Perfect Union: A New Economic Interpretation of the United States Constitution (2003) ................................................................................................................................... 33 [C] – McCulloch v. Maryland, 17 U.S. 316 (1819), 401-25 ................................................................................ 33 [D] – Legal Tender Cases: Hepburn v. Griswold, 75 U.S. 603 (1870); Knox v. Lee & Parker v. Davis, 79 U.S. 457 (1871) ........................................................................................................................................................... 33 [E] – Gold Clause Cases: Norman v. Baltimore & Ohio Railroad Co., 294 U.S. 240; Nortz v. United States, 294 U.S. 317; Perry v. United States, 294 U.S. 330 (all 1935). ................................................................................. 34 [F] – Loewen Group Inc. v. United States (International Ctr. for Resolution of Disputes 2003) ........................ 34 [G] – Roper v. Simmons, 543 U.S. 551 (2005) ................................................................................................... 35 [H] – Lawrence v. Texas, 539 U.S. 558 (2003) ................................................................................................... 35 [I] – Transcript of Discussion Between U.S. Supreme Court Justices Antonin Scalia and Stephen Breyer, Jan. 13, 2005 ............................................................................................................................................................... 35 [J] – Ruth Bader Ginsburg, Looking Beyond Our Borders: The Value of a Comparative Perspective in Constitutional Adjudication, 40 Idaho L. Rev. 1 (2003) ..................................................................................... 35 § 6.02 – Important Themes ................................................................................................................................... 35 [A] – Mad Libs: _____ is the most important _____ in _____. ........................................................................... 35 [B] – What’s This Necessity Thing, Anyway? .................................................................................................... 35 [C] – Creditors ..................................................................................................................................................... 36 [D] – Arguments about Citing Foreign Sources = Proxy War ............................................................................. 36 4 Chapter 1 – Constitution and Empire § 1.01 – Summary of Cases & Materials [A] – Somersett’s Case, 98 Eng. Rep. 510 (K.B. 1772) Description: James Somersett, a slave, was taken to England from Jamaica by his owner Charles Stewart. People claiming to be Somersett’s godparents petitioned the King’s Bench for a writ of habeas corpus. The court ordered Somersett’s release. Holding (Mansfield): Because slavery is “[s]o high an act of dominion,” it could be lawful only if authorized by positive law; because it is not, slavery is unlawful in England (although not the colonies). [B] – Scott v. Sandford, 60 U.S. 393 (1856) Description: Scott was a slave held at times in the Wisconsin Territory (now Minnesota), a free territory under the Missouri Compromise. He argued that having been held in a free territory meant he had become free. The Court dismissed for lack of subject matter jurisdiction. Holding (Taney): (1) The framers did not intend that blacks be citizens of any state or of the United States and therefore Article III does not allow them to bring suit; federal courts have no jurisdiction to hear such cases. (2) The Missouri Compromise was unconstitutional because the federal government could only administer territories as a trustee pending incorporation into the U.S. as a state; a provision forbidding slavery was not a power enumerated to Congress and it would work unconstitutional takings under the Fifth Amendment. [C] – Downes v. Bidwell, 182 U.S. 244 (1901) Description: New York was charging duties on merchandise imported from Puerto Rico following Puerto Rico’s becoming a U.S. territory after the Spanish-American War (as authorized by the Foraker Act). Downes, importer of goods, argued that Art. I, §§ 8 and 9 forbade duties for imports from U.S. territories. The Court affirmed the lower court’s judgment for Bidwell, holding the Foraker Act constitutional. Holding (Brown): The Constitution does not necessarily apply in territories, it only protects the states that formed the union; Congress can tailor what provisions apply to territories as the necessity of empire dictates. Dissent (Harlan): The U.S. has a government of enumerated powers, whose authority derives from the Constitution; Congress therefore cannot dispense with constitutional requirements when they are inconvenient or in cases of necessity. [D] – Johnson v. Eisentrager, 339 U.S. 763 (1950) Description: Twenty-one German nationals held in Landsberg Prison, Germany, were convicted of war crimes for continuing to assist the Japanese following Germany’s surrender. The Germans petitioned the U.S. government for a writ of habeas corpus to review their conviction by military tribunal. The Supreme Court reversed the D.C. Cir., reinstating the dismissal for lack of subject matter jurisdiction by the D.D.C. Holding (Jackson): There is no statutory jurisdiction for federal courts to hear habeas petitions filed by aliens who have never been in the U.S. (see Ahrens v. Clark) and the Constitution does not require the U.S. to extend procedural protections to aliens (see Downes v. Bidwell). Dissent (Black): U.S. courts should be able to hear habeas cases anywhere the U.S. “imprisons any person in any land we govern”; the location of the imprisonment should not be controlling when it comes to a person challenging his detention. Id. at 798. [E] – Ahrens v. Clark, 335 US. 188 (1948) 5 Description: Habeas petitioners are a group of 120 Germans held at Ellis Island who filed their petitions in the D.D.C. against Attorney General Clark. The federal habeas statute, 28 U.S.C. § 455 says district courts are competent to grant habeas “within their respective jurisdictions.” The Germans argue that the D.D.C. is proper because the “jailer” is the A.G. The Supreme Court affirmed the dismissal for want of subject matter jurisdiction. Holding (Douglas): The statute conferring habeas jurisdiction, 28 U.S.C. § 455, requires that the petitioner be within the jurisdiction of the court to which he petitions for the writ. Dissent (Rutledge): A court with jurisdiction over the jailer should have jurisdiction to hear the petition because the writ has always been viewed as a command to the jailer and because where a petitioner is not within any U.S. jurisdiction he will be without redress for illegal imprisonment. [F] – Reid v. Covert, 354 U.S. 1 (1957) Description: Defendants Covert and Kinsella each allegedly murdered her husband while on military bases abroad. The women were convicted of murder by court martial, jurisdiction per the U.C.M.J. The defendants petitioned for the writ of habeas corpus in federal district court. The Court ordered the women released from military custody. Holding (Black plurality): “The United States is entirely a creature of the Constitution[; i]ts power and authority have no other source”; thus “the Constitution in its entirety” applies to the civilian spouses of military personnel deployed abroad, and because courts martial do not meet the requirements of Art. III, § 2 and the Fifth and Sixth Amendments, they cannot constitutionally exercise jurisdiction over civilians. Id. at 6–7, 18. The Insular Cases don’t apply because (1) this case concerns U.S. citizens and (2) the continuing vitality of the Insular Cases is up in the air. Concurrence (Harlan): The Insular Cases are still vital, but counsel us “that the particular local setting, the practical necessities, and the possible alternatives are relevant to a question of judgment” respecting what constitutional protections apply; here the circumstances require application of the Constitution. Id. at 75. [G] – United States v. Verdugo-Urquidez, 494 U.S. 259 (1990) Description: Verdugo-Urquidez was suspected of leading a drug gang that smuggled marijuana into the U.S. and was wanted in connection with the murder of a D.E.A. agent. The Mexican authorities allowed D.E.A. agents to search the defendant’s property in Mexico. Defendant claims the search violated the Fourth Amendment, which he asserts applied to any search conducted by the U.S. government. Holding (Rehnquist): Constitutional protections do not apply to all acts the U.S. undertakes abroad as the Insular Cases, Eisentrager, and the history and text of the Fourth Amendment demonstrate; Reid is distinguishable as concerning U.S. citizens and is a plurality opinion with narrower concurrences. Dissent (Brennan): “If we expect aliens to obey our laws, aliens should be able to expect that we will obey our Constitution when we investigate, prosecute, and punish them . . . by placing respondent among those governed by federal criminal laws and investigation him for violations of those laws, the Government has made him a part of our community for purposes of the Fourth Amendment.” Id. at 284, 286. [H] – Rasul v. Bush, 542 U.S. 466 (2004) Description: Fourteen foreign nationals detained in the U.S. facility in Guantanamo Bay, Cuba, brought habeas petitions through next friends in D.D.C. D.D.C. dismissed for want of subject matter jurisdiction, citing Eisentrager; D.C. Cir. affirmed. Supreme Court reversed. Holding (Stevens): The statute giving federal courts jurisdiction to hear habeas petitions, 28 U.S.C. § 2441, allows the exercise of jurisdiction where the custodians are within the court’s jurisdiction. The jurisdictional holding in Eisentrager relied upon Ahrens; Ahrens was overruled by Braden v. 30th Judicial Circuit Court, 410 U.S. 484, 502 (1973); thus, Eisentrager no longer controls with respect to the habeas statute. 6 Concurrence (Kennedy): Eisentrager is concerned with separation of powers and “requires an initial inquiry into the general circumstances of the detention to determine whether the Court has the authority to entertain the petition . . . there are circumstances in which the courts maintain the power and the responsibility to protect persons from unlawful detention even where military affairs are implicated.” Id. at 487. The facts here include de facto sovereignty over Guantanamo and indefinite detention; thus, here (but not in all habeas cases where a custodian is within the court’s jurisdiction) the court has jurisdiction. Dissent (Scalia): Eisentrager is directly on-point and was not overruled until right now; the court should not disrupt such important precedent in a time of war. Ahrens expressly reserved the question of whether the habeas statute applied to those detained abroad. Eisentrager was a statutory holding (contrary to the majority’s view here) and answered the statutory question itself; thus, Eisentrager doesn’t rely on Ahrens. Braden did not overrule Ahrens: “Braden stands . . . only [for] the proposition . . . [concerning] custody in multiple jurisdictions within the United States . . . . Outside that class of cases, Braden did not question the general rule of Ahrens.” Id. at 495. [I] – Boumediene v. Bush, 128 S.Ct. 2229 (2008) Description: After the decision in Rasul, Congress passed 28 U.S.C. § 2241(e), which superseded the statutory holding in Rasul. A group of alien detainees then brought a habeas petition to challenge their detention, arguing that 28 U.S.C. § 2441(e) violates the Suspension Clause, Art. I, § 9, Cl. 2. Holding (Kennedy): U.S. courts have jurisdiction to hear the petitioners’ habeas petitions because the Detainee Treatment Act provides an inadequate substitute procedure for habeas corpus and therefore works a suspension of the writ inconsistent with the Suspension Clause. 28 U.S.C. § 2441(e) is unconstitutional. Federal courts should hear habeas petitions only if there is undue delay in the military procedures or the military procedures are exhausted. The Suspension Clause protections reach the detainees because Guantanamo is de facto U.S. territory and because Eisentrager, Reid, and the Insular Cases indicate the Constitution follows the flag based on practical considerations. Guantanamo is de facto U.S. territory; to hold otherwise allows the political branches the “power to switch the Constitution on or off at will . . . leading to a regime in which Congress and the President, not this Court, say ‘what the law is.’” Id. at 2259. The Suspension Clause reaches the detainees, thus the suitability of the replacement procedure can be evaluated. The procedure here is insufficient, so it is unconstitutional. Concurrence (Souter): Rasul basically did the work; this opinion only extends the reasoning to the constitutional question. Additionally, the dissents ignore how long these detainees have been held (six years). Dissent (Roberts): The procedures are an adequate safeguard—the Court has stepped in too early without letting the military procedures (which are based on Hamdi v. Rumsfeld) run their course, so they have no basis to determine that the procedures are inadequate. Dissent (Scalia): Eisentrager controls and “held beyond any doubt [] that the Constitution does not ensure habeas for aliens held by the United States in areas over which our Government is not sovereign”; occupied Germany was no less under de facto U.S. control than Guantanamo. Id. at 2298–99. The reasoning from Rasul can’t do the work here because it was about the applicability of a statute and this is a constitutional holding (contra Souter). The cases from the Insular Cases through Verdugo-Urquidez stand for aliens having no substantive rights under the Constitution. This is about aggrandizing the judicial branch. § 1.02 – Important Themes [A] – Lawyers’ Special Skills [1] – The Lawyer’s Question Prof. Feldman (and Prof. Issacharoff) argues that “The Lawyer’s Question” is ‘Who should decide?’—this is what distinguishes lawyers from other professions. This question is implied by the law’s focus on procedure, the distinction between law and fact, arguments respecting institutional competency, and other uniquely legal issues. 7 [2] – “Artificial Reasoning” Natural law was believed to relate to reason, and “reason . . . meant the artificial reason of common lawyers, that is, the expert ability to reason dialectically in Aristotelian fashion and to ‘find out the truth by argument and disputation.’ Sir Edward Coke, chief justice of the Court of Common Pleas and later of the King’s Bench, famously argued that such ‘artificial reasoning’ was what distinguished the professional expertise of the common lawyer from the mere opinion of the sovereign. Not by chance, Coke was dismissed from the bench by James I in 1616, and later, as a member of Parliament, played an important role in the ongoing struggle concerning the prerogatives of the Crown.” Victoria Ann Kahn & Lorna Hutson, Rhetoric and Law in Early Modern Europe 11 (2001). [B] – The History and Origins of the Writ of Habeas Corpus Note: this history is excerpted from Habeas corpus, http://en.wikipedia.org/w/index.php?title=Habeas_corpus (last visited Mar. 25, 2009). “Blackstone cites the first recorded usage of habeas corpus ad subjiciendum in 1305, during the reign of King Edward I. . . . [¶] The procedure for the issuing of writs of habeas corpus was first codified by the Habeas Corpus Act 1679, following judicial rulings which had restricted the effectiveness of the writ. A previous act had been passed in 1640 to overturn a ruling that the command of the King was a sufficient answer to a petition of habeas corpus. “Then, as now, the writ of habeas corpus was issued by a superior court in the name of the Sovereign, and commanded the addressee (a lower court, sheriff, or private subject) to produce the prisoner before the Royal courts of law. A habeas corpus petition could be made by the prisoner himself or by a third party on his behalf and, as a result of the Habeas Corpus Acts, could be made regardless of whether the court was in session, by presenting the petition to a judge. [¶] Since the 18th century the writ has also been used in cases of unlawful detention by private individuals, most famously in Somersett's Case . . . . [¶] The privilege of habeas corpus has been suspended or restricted several times during English history, most recently during the 18th and 19th centuries.” In the U.S., “The writ of habeas corpus ad subjiciendum is a civil, not criminal, ex parte proceeding in which a court inquires as to the legitimacy of a prisoner's custody. Typically, habeas corpus proceedings are to determine whether the court which imposed sentence on the defendant had jurisdiction and authority to do so, or whether the defendant's sentence has expired. Habeas corpus is also used as a legal avenue to challenge other types of custody such as pretrial detention or detention by the United States Bureau of Immigration and Customs Enforcement pursuant to a deportation proceeding.” [C] – Sovereignty Under natural law, sovereignty was thought to arise from the people. In the U.S., there are arguments that the people are sovereign. See, e.g., Scott, 60 U.S. at 404 (“The words ‘people of the United States’ . . . describe the political body who, according to our republican institutions, form the sovereignty, and who hold the power and conduct the Government through their representatives”). Others argue that the Congress is sovereign. An assertion that the President can seize property upon the declaration of war “must assume for its basis . . . a rule which acts directly upon the thing itself by its own force, and not through the sovereign power.” Brown v. United States, 12 U.S. at 128 (see §2.01[F], infra). This assumes the executive is not sovereign, and because it is Congress that would authorize this power, Justice Marshall at least suggests that Congress is the sovereign. Story in his dissent in Brown suggests that sovereignty is split between the President and Congress, at least during wartime. “There is no act of the legislature defining the powers, objects or mode of warfare: by what rule, then, must [the President] be governed? I think the only rational answer is by the law of nations as applied to a state of war. Whatever act is legitimate, whatever act is approved by the law, or hostilities among civilized nations, such he may, in his discretion, adopt and exercise; for with him the sovereignty of the nation rests as to the execution of the laws. Id. at 149. 8 Finally, under Schmitt’s view, he who declares the exception is the sovereign. There is also a distinction between de facto and de jure sovereignty. “When we have stated that sovereignty is a political question, we have referred not to sovereignty in the general, colloquial sense, meaning the exercise of dominion or power, but sovereignty in the narrow, legal sense of the term, meaning a claim of right. Indeed, it is not altogether uncommon for a territory to be under the de jure sovereignty of one nation, while under the [de facto] sovereignty[] of another.” Boumediene, 128 S.Ct. at 2252–53 (citations omitted). [D] – Natural Law Natural law stands opposed to positive law, and is law derived from nature that is therefore the same for everyone, everywhere. Natural law forms an important part of the basis of the common law system. In this regard, legal positivism and realism stand opposed to a natural law view of the common law. “[T]here is no [transcendental] body of law. The fallacy and illusion that I think exist consist in supposing that there is this outside thing to be found. Law is a word used with different meanings, but law in the sense in which courts speak of it today does not exist without some definite authority behind it. Black & White Taxicab & Transfer Co. v. Brown & Yellow Taxicab & Transfer Co., 276 U.S. 518, 533 (1928) (Holmes, J., dissenting). Holmes’ positivist streak traces to thirty years earlier, when he wrote “I think it desirable . . . to point out and dispel a confusion between morality and law, which sometimes rises to the height of conscious theory, and more often and indeed constantly is making trouble in detail with-out reaching the point of consciousness. You can see very plainly that a bad man has as much reason as a good one for wishing to avoid an encounter with the public force, and therefore you can see the practical importance of the distinction between morality and law. A man who cares nothing for an ethical rule which is believed and practised by his neighbors is likely nevertheless to care a good deal to avoid being made to pay money, and will want to keep out of jail if he can.” Oliver Wendell Holmes, The Path of the Law, 10 Harv. L. Rev. 457, 459 (1896–97). Courts have also distinguished between “natural rights” and “remedial rights.” “We suggest, without intending to decide, that there may be a distinction between certain natural rights, enforced in the Constitution by prohibitions against interference with them, and what may be termed artificial or remedial rights, which are peculiar to our own system of jurisprudence. Of the former class are the rights to one's own religious opinion and to a public expression of them, or, as sometimes said, to worship God according to the dictates of one's own conscience; the right to personal liberty and individual property; to freedom of speech and of the press; to free access to courts of justice, to due process of law and to an equal protection of the laws; to immunities from unreasonable searches and seizures, as well as cruel and unusual punishments; and to such other immunities as are indispensable to a free government. Of the latter class are the rights to citizenship, to suffrage, and to the particular methods of procedure pointed out in the Constitution . . . .” Downes, 182 U.S. at 282–83. [E] – The Tension between Limited Powers and Empire [1] – Does the Constitution Follow the Flag? Scott was a “perhaps the most profoundly anti-colonial opinion in the U.S. reporters,” according to Prof. Feldman: “[T]he power of Congress over the person or property of a citizen can never be a mere discretionary power under our Constitution and form of Government. The powers of the Government and the rights and privileges of the citizen are regulated and plainly defined by the Constitution itself. And when the Territory becomes a part of the United States, the Federal Government enters into possession . . . limited by the Constitution, from which it derives its own existence, and by virtue of which alone it continues to exist and act as a Government and sovereignty. It has no power of any kind beyond it; and it cannot, when it enters a Territory of the United States, put off its character, and assume discretionary or despotic powers which the 9 Constitution has denied to it. It cannot create for itself a new character separated from the citizens of the United States . . . and the Federal Government can exercise no power . . . beyond what that instrument confers, nor lawfully deny any right which it has reserved.” Scott, 60 U.S. at 449–450. In contrast, at the time it was decided, Downes appeared to hold that no particular constitutional rights necessarily applied in U.S. territories. Id. at 283–87. In Eisentrager, Jackson writing for the majority and Black in dissent each cited Downes for different propositions. The majority asserted that with respect to the application of constitutional protections abroad, “[n]o decision of this Court supports such a view. Cf. Downes v. Bidwell, 182 U.S. 244.” Eisentrager, 339 U.S. at 784–85. The dissent applies the case differently: “If our country decides to occupy conquered territory either temporarily or permanently . . . [p]robably no one would suggest, and certainly I would not, that this nation either must or should attempt to apply every constitutional provision of the Bill of Rights in controlling temporarily occupied countries. But that does not mean that the Constitution is wholly inapplicable in foreign territories that we occupy and govern. See Downes v. Bidwell, 182 U.S. 244.” Eisentrager, 339 U.S. at 796–97. However, in light of Boumediene, the holding of the Insular Cases is something more like the Downes dissent. That is, the U.S. government is one of limited powers that cannot exercise authority over territories it controls except in keeping with the Constitution. [2] – Necessity & Empire The Downes court wrote that “the power to acquire territory by treaty implies not only the power to govern such territory, but to prescribe upon what terms the United States will receive its inhabitants, and what their status shall be in what Chief Justice Marshall termed the ‘American Empire.’ There seems to be no middle ground between this position and the doctrine that if their inhabitants do not become, immediately upon annexation, citizens . . . . If such be their status, the consequences will be extremely serious. Indeed, it is doubtful if Congress would ever assent to the annexation of territory upon the condition that its inhabitants, however foreign they may be to our habits, traditions and modes of life, shall become at once citizens of the United States.” 182 U.S. at 279–80. This implies that creating an empire carries with it a necessity rationale that can be used to override limitations on government power. [G] – Guantanamo’s Rationale To put the line of cases from this section together, Guantanamo was based upon Eisentrager and therefore Ahrens, plus the Insular Cases. The Bush administration realized that Guantanamo, like Landsberg Prison in Germany, was under the control of the U.S. but was de jure Cuban territory. This situation was thought analogous to the status of Landsberg Prison in Eisentrager and so the administration believed that the Eisentrager reasoning would apply to the Guantanamo detainees: provided that they were not U.S. citizens and had never been within the U.S., the detainees would have no habeas rights. Even if Guantanamo was taken to be U.S. territory, the Bush administration still had an out. Under Downes, the administration thought that no constitutional protections necessarily applied in U.S. territories. There was thus a two-part theory: (1) The Guantanamo detainees have no rights under the U.S. Constitution, see Downes. (2) Even if they do, they can’t petition for habeas to vindicate those rights, see Eisentrager. [H] – Ideology and the Justices [1] – Strict Construction and Pragmatism There has been an interesting shift in the styles of statutory construction / constitutional interpretation and the politics that perspective has served. Today we’re used to the textual originalism of Scalia and Thomas as 10 representing the right wing of the Court. However, it was at one time a liberal jurisprudence. Through the 19th and much of the 20th century, originalism was rights-expanding and anti-colonial. In contrast, pragmatic / necessitybased / “Grand Style” jurisprudence was facilitative of government authority and imperial. Chief Justice Taney in Scott wrote an opinion that was disgraceful and bigoted, but was in another sense “profoundly anti-colonial.” It was so because it sought to limit governmental authority to the powers enumerated in the Constitution. This would hobble the ability of the U.S. to hold territories abroad. This strain of though would appear in (the elder) Harlan’s Downes dissent, which sought to bind the government to the Constitution when acting abroad. It turned up in the Black (and Douglas(???) – he wrote Ahrens) dissent in Eisentrager (and earlier in Rutledge’s dissent in Ahrens). Black wrote the plurality opinion in Reid, again arguing that the U.S. was bound by the Constitution. In contradistinction, the majority in Downes had to undermine Scott and rely on a pragmatic, necessity-based argument to justify American colonialism. Similarly, Jackson, writing for the majority in Eisentrager, noted the impracticability of allowing detainees to challenge military commanders in the field as an important consideration in denying habeas rights to detainees. In Reid, the unanimous court split into two ideological camps: Black, writing the plurality opinion, questioned the continuing vitality of the Insular Cases. (He might have cited Scott, except for the whole nasty business of his having been a Klan member.) Harlan (the younger) and Frankfurter, concurring separately, grounded their votes more narrowly, arguing that the Insular Cases were still applicable but must be based upon an instrumental, due process-like determination of what rights extend under what circumstances. By the time the Court heard Verdugo-Urquidez, the interpretive methods of liberal and conservative Justices had more or less flipped. Rehnquist, writing for the majority and opposing limits to the government’s authority to act abroad based his arguments upon text and precedent. In contrast, Brenan, joined by Marshall, argued from concepts of fairness, reciprocity, and the rule of law. [2] – The Role of the Courts The current tension between Justices Scalia and Kennedy has its roots in Plato and Aristotle. Plato favored “the law of men”—a case-by-case, pragmatic approach to the law. Aristotle preferred “the rule of law,” because he believed that there was no guarantee of a philosopher king upon whom society can rely always to rule justly. This tension plays out in Boumediene. Scalia wrote, “[w]hat drives today’s decision is . . . an inflated notion of judicial supremacy. . . . Our power ‘to say what the law is’ is circumscribed by the limits of our statutorily and constitutionally conferred jurisdiction.” Id. at 2302–03. Kennedy appears to view the Court’s “saying what the law is” as both necessary and expansive. Kennedy was troubled by the political branches avoiding judicial review through jurisdictional slight of hand. “Our basic charter cannot be contracted away like this. The Constitution grants Congress and the President the power to acquire, dispose of, and govern territory, not the power to decide when and where its terms apply. . . . To hold the political branches have the power to switch the Constitution on or off at will . . . would permit a striking anomaly in our tripartite system of government, leading to a regime in which Congress and the President, not this Court, say ‘what the law is.’” Id. at 2259. Scalia reframes Kennedy’s concern as not tolerating “areas in which the legal determinations of the other branches will be (shudder!) supreme.” Id. at 2303. Chief Justice Marshall was also a proponent of a powerful judiciary—indeed, he articulated the principle of judicial review in Marbury v. Madison. A similar tension occurs in Foster v. Neilson, 27 U.S. 253 (1829) (see Ch. 2, infra). There, a treaty was held not to be self-executing. This implies that facially self-executing treaties may nevertheless be subject to judicial review, which implies that even a “self-executing” treaty may be self-executing only after a court passes on it. [I] – SCOTUS Justices: A Soap Opera 11 Prof. Feldman outlined a few interesting anecdotes about various Justices. First, Justice Jackson and Justice Black hated each other with intensity unequalled in the Court’s history. Jackson believed that Black’s decisions were motivated by personal preferences. See Wikipedia, Robert H. Jackson, http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Robert_H._Jackson (as of Apr. 30, 2009, 20:41 GMT). The animosity deepened when Black refused to recuse himself from Jewell Ridge, a case involving a former law partner of Black’s. Id. Jackson also believed Roosevelt would appoint him Chief Justice, but Truman instead appointed Vinson to avoid entanglement in the Black / Jackson feud; Jackson sent several wires from Nuremberg. Id. Justice Douglas was aligned with the Black faction, and his “concurrence” in Hirota might be seen as a dig at Jackson and Truman. In 1940, Roosevelt’s running mate Henry Wallace corresponded with a strange “guru”; when the Republicans threatened to expose him, the Democrats arranged a truce by agreeing not to release information of Republican candidate’s Wendell Willkie’s extramarital affair. In the 1944 election, Roosevelt sought to replace Wallace and passed over Douglas for Truman (at the behest of the Democratic party). In 1948, Douglas campaigned briefly for the nomination but withdrew; then Truman offered for Douglas to be his running mate, which Douglas refused. See Wikipedia, William O. Douglas, http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/William_O._Douglas (optional description here) (as of Apr. 30, 2009, 21:08 GMT). Justice Black had been a member of the Ku Klux Klan while running for Senate in Alabama. Justice Scalia was long irked by Justice O’Connor, whom he viewed as mushy minded and unprincipled. However, after O’Connor left the Court and Justice Kennedy became the swing vote (and tacked left), Scalia realized that O’Connor was a pretty swell lady, all things considered. Scalia realized that although he was probably smarter, a better writer, more principled, and all-around a more capable Justice than Kennedy, he would nevertheless be relegated to writing “numerous fiery dissents and concurrences and a few idiosyncratic majority opinions, while Kennedy will be remembered as the most important liberal Justice in the late-20th and early-21st centuries.” [J] – Constitutional Rights without Remedies? While legal realists and other legal philosophies consider a right without a remedy as no right at all, there are numerous examples of such rights in the cases. In the habeas cases the absence of jurisdiction precludes the right to challenge detention. In the cases involving the V.C.C.R., see Ch. 5, infra, the Court presently holds that failure to comply with that treaty is a violation of international law that carries with it no remedy. 12 Chapter 2 – International Law? § 2.01 – Summary of Cases & Materials [A] – The Schooner Exchange v. McFaddon, 11 U.S. 116 (1812) Description: French warship shows up in Philadelphia port. McFaddon (and Greetham) claim it’s their ship (converted to a warship) and that Napoleon stole it at sea. Court dismisses case for lack of jurisdiction. Holding (Marshall): U.S. courts cannot hear cases concerning a warship belonging to foreign sovereigns operating in U.S. waters because such a ship would enter only under an implied waiver of U.S. jurisdiction, and while this waiver might be rescinded, this must be done expressly by the government. [B] – United States v. Schooner Peggy, 5 U.S. 103 (1801) Description: The U.S. captured the Schooner Peggy. After a judgment by the Circuit Court but before the Supreme Court decision, the U.S. signed a treaty with France pertaining to “[p]roperty captured, and not yet definitively condemned . . . .” Government wants the booty, original owners maintain that the treaty is effective and that the property was not definitively condemned so long as the case was on appeal. Original owners win. Holding (Marshall): Where a treaty comes into force that affects the rights of the litigants, a court of appeals will apply the treaty the same as any law changed law. [C] – The Antelope, 23 U.S. 66 (1825) Description: Privateer ship carrying stolen slaves was captured by the U.S. Several parties claimed the slaves: the original owners (Spain and Portugal), the Antelope’s captain, the U.S. captain who captured her, and the U.S. Spain and Portugal get their slaves back. Holding (Marshall): The slave trade is not prohibited by the law of nations because it is still customary in many nations; thus, in applying international law, U.S. courts are bound to recognize the slave trade as lawful among countries practicing it. [D] – Vattel, The Law of Nations (1758, English edition of 1854) lv–lxvi Recognizes the law of nations as law appertaining to the relations between one nation-state and another (i.e., not individual). Argues “the law of Nations is originally no other than the law of Nature applied to Nations.” Id. at lvi. Claims that one nation cannot enforce the law of nations as against another: “Nations being free and independent, though the conduct of one of them be illegal and condemnable by the laws of conscience, the others are bound to acquiesce in it, when it does not infringe upon their perfect rights.” Id. at lix (cf. The Antelope). [E] – Joseph Story, “Law of Nations,” in Encyclopedia Americana vol. ix (1843) 141–49 Story begins with Vattel, argues that the law of nations, in addition to concerning relations between states (external law of nations, a.k.a. international law) also concerns the relation between the sovereign and the people (internal law of nations, a.k.a. the public law of state). Story then lists a series of principles concerning each of the internal and external law of nations. [F] – Brown v. United States, 12 U.S. 110 (1814) Description: U.S. government seizes British property after War of 1812 begins. Owner challenges condemnation, arguing that the declaration of war by itself does not authorize the executive to seize enemy property found on U.S. soil. Brown gets the property back. 13 Holding (Marshall): The declaration of war, by itself, does not authorize the executive to seize property found on U.S. soil at the beginning of war; that power would arise only from express authorization by Congress, either in the declaration of war itself or in a subsequent action. (One additional argument: “war,” Art. I, § 8, Cl. 11, may be definable only with reference to the law of nations.) Dissent (Story): The President may take any action that Congress has not forbade and that is consonant with the law of nations in conducting a war; thus, he may (subject to obloquy) seize the property because this is recognized by the law of nations. “By the constitution, the executive is charged with the faithful execution of the laws; and the language of the act declaring war authorizes him to carry it into effect. In what manner, and to what extent, shall be carry it into effect? What are the legitimate objects of the warfare which he is to wage? There is no act of the legislature defining the powers, objects or mode of warfare: by what rule, then, must he be governed? I think the only rational answer is by the law of nations as applied to a state of war.” Id. at 149. [G] – Foster v. Neilson, 27 U.S. 253 (1829) Description: Both parties claim a tract of land in Louisiana. Foster was granted the land by the Spanish governor, Neilson claims that the land transferred to France (then the U.S.) before the grant to Foster. This turns on whether the Treaty of St. Ildefonso is self-executing. Neilson keeps the land because the treaty was not self-executing. Holding (Marshall): In the U.S. (unlike other countries), treaties can be self-executing – provided the language of the treaty makes this clear; otherwise, treaties are contracts for the legislature subsequently to pass laws. [H] – United States v. Percheman, 32 U.S. 51 (1833) Description: Percheman claims title to 2,000 acres granted by the Spanish Governor, covered by the treaty of St. Ildefonso. Court this time (unlike Foster v. Neilson, supra) looks at Spanish language version of the treaty, this time holds that the treaty is self-executing. Holding (Marshall): The treaty of St. Ildefonso actually is self-executing. [I] – The Paquete Habana, 175 U.S. 677 (1900) Description: Two Cuban coastal fishing vessels are at sea as the Spanish-American war begins. The U.S. captures the ships as prizes of war. Original owners sue. SCOTUS rules for original owners. Holding (Gray): The President is bound by customary international law (absent an act by Congress) because “[i]nternational law is part of our law, and must be ascertained and administered by the courts . . . .” Id. at 700. The sources of international law include “the customs and usages of civilized nations; and, as evidence of these, to the works of jurists and commentators . . . not for the speculations of their authors concerning what the law ought to be, but for trustworthy evidence of what the law really is.” Id. Dissent (Fuller): Our holding in Brown v. United States forbids customary international law to act directly and not through the sovereign; thus, the President is not bound by international law. [J] – Filartiga v. Pena-Irala, 630 F.2d 876 (2d Cir. 1980) Description: Plaintiff Filatritga’s son was allegedly tortured to death by Pena, acting in an official capacity while in Paraguay. Both parties happen to be in the U.S., Filartiga sues under the Alien Tort Statute, 28 U.S.C. § 1350, which states “The district courts shall have original jurisdiction of any civil action by an alien for a tort only, committed in violation of the law of nations or a treaty of the United States.” Supreme Court reverses dismissal for lack of subject matter jurisdiction. Holding (Kaufman): Torture, when committed by a person acting under color of state authority, is a violation of the law of nations (as shown by commentators and U.N. resolutions). 14 [K] – Tel Oren v. Libyan Arab Republic, 726 F.2d 774 (D.C. Cir. 1984) Description: Plaintiffs were survivors of (mostly) Israeli citizens murdered during an attack on a civilian bus. The D.D.C. dismissed for lack of subject matter jurisdiction. The D.C. Cir. upholds the dismissal in a per curiam decision with each of the three judges concurring separately. Concurrence (Edwards): The law of nations does not apply to individuals not acting under color of state authority except with a few crimes, e.g. piracy – torture and terrorism are not in this category. Concurrence (Bork): The Alien Tort Statute creates jurisdiction but not a cause of action for torts in violation of international law; causes of action are probably available only for Blackstone’s enumerated offenses: piracy, crimes involving ambassadors, and violations of safe-conducts. [L] – Kadic v. Karadzic, 70 F.3d 232 (2d Cir. 1996) Description: Plaintiffs were subject to brutal treatment by Karadzic, the President of a Bosnian-Serb republic inside Bosnia-Herzegovina known as Srpska and mostly unrecognized by other nations. Karadzic was served inside the U.S. and plaintiffs assert jurisdiction under the Alien Tort Statute for acts of torture, genocide, and war crimes. Karadzic argues that he was not a state actor (as his state is unrecognized) and that he cannot as an individual violate the law of nations. Second Circuit reverses dismissal by S.D.N.Y. with respect to genocide and war crimes. Holding (Newman): Individuals can violate the law of nations; Filartiga didn’t reach this question and Edwards recognized in Tel-Oren that piracy violates the law of nations. The community of nations is unified against both genocide and war crimes, but not torture—thus, an individual can violate the law of nations by committing genocide or war crimes. [M] – Louis Henkin, International Law as Law in the United States, 82 Mich. L. Rev. 1555 (1984) Argues that customary international law is self-executing federal law in the U.S. [N] – Bradley & Goldsmith, Customary International Law as Federal Common Law: A Critique of the Modern Position, 110 Harv. L. Rev. 815 (1997) Argues that customary international law is not part of U.S. law and the courts cannot apply it without authorization from the political branches. [O] – Sosa v. Alvarez-Machain, 542 U.S. 692 (2004) Description: Alvarez was alleged to have assisted in the torture-murder of a D.E.A. agent in Mexico. The U.S. collaborated with a group of Mexican nationals, including Sosa, to have Alvarez abducted and transported into the U.S. Alvarez was tried and acquitted. Subsequently, he brought a tort suit against Sosa for the kidnapping. The Supreme Court ruled that the ATS did not allow a cause of action on these facts. Holding (Souter): “[T]he statute is in terms only jurisdictional, [but] we think that at the time of enactment the jurisdiction enabled federal courts to hear claims in a very limited category defined by the law of nations and recognized at common law.” Id. at 712. “[F]ederal courts should not recognize private claims under federal common law for violations of any international law norm with less definite content and acceptance among civilized nations than the historical paradigms familiar when § 1350 was enacted. . . . And the determination whether a norm is sufficiently definite to support a cause of action should (and, indeed, inevitably must) involve an element of judgment about the practical consequences of making that cause available to litigants in the federal courts.” Id. at 731–33. Concurrence (Scalia): “I would subtract [the majority’s] reservation of a discretionary power in the Federal Judiciary to create causes of action for the enforcement of international-law-based norms.” Id. at 739. This implies 15 that “the consensus of states on any subject[] can be used by a private citizen to control a sovereign’s treatment of its own citizens within its own territory.” Id. at 749–50. § 2.02 – Important Themes [A] – The Law of Nations, the Law of Nature, and Individuals Story argues that “the law of Nations is originally no other than the law of Nature applied to Nations.” Id. at lvi. This reflects a conception of law that legal positivism and Erie would repudiate. Thus, as indicated by Tel-Oren, Sosa, etc, this conception fails to address the question of authority. Judge Edwards wrote, “the individual’s status in international law has been in flux . . . . Through the 18th century and into the 19th, writers and jurists believed that rules of international law bound individuals as well as states. . . . In the 19th century, the view emerged that states alone were subjects of international law, and they alone were able to assert rights and be held to duties devolved from the law of nations. Under that view – which became firmly entrenched both in doctrine and in practice . . . individual rights existed only as rights of the state . . . and could be asserted, defended or withdrawn by the state. . . . [¶] In this century, once again writers have argued that both the rights and duties of international law should be applied to private parties. Tel-Oren v. Libyan Arab Republic, 726 F.2d 774, 794 (D.C. Cir. 1984). The transition in the 19th century appears to coincide with a shift from the term “law of nations” to the term “international law,” notes Feldman. See Story, supra, at 141. [B] – Treaties [1] – Generally Treaties relate both to U.S. law and the Constitution. Treaties create U.S. law, either upon ratification (if selfexecuting) or upon Congress passing laws to enact the treaty. The Constitution gives the executive and Senate the authority and procedure by which to ratify a treaty. U.S. Const., Art. II, § 2, Cl. 2. Because the treaty is law, it preempts state law via the supremacy clause. Also, a treaty inconsistent with existing U.S. law is sufficient to supersede that law. Treaties exist simultaneously as positive international law, private law between the U.S. and foreign citizens, and public law. The U.S. has to follow treaties unless it definitively withdraws (divorce is okay but no cheating). There are some strategic aspects in the Constitution’s treaty procedures. First, the President need not gain approval from the House of Representatives for a treaty. This may imply that the framers did not want to place international affairs in the control of the most politically accountable branch. Second, the President does not have plenipotentiary powers when negotiating treaties. Thus, on the one hand he has some rhetorical strength in approaching the Senate (“I’ve already gotten them to agree to this treaty and I’ve given my word…”) while at the same time having the ability to raise the Senate as a heavy in negotiating the most favorable deal for the U.S. possible. [2] – Self execution Treaties may be self-executing in the U.S. This is unusual among nations, most of which treat all treaties as contracts for the legislature to take subsequent action. See Foster, 27 U.S. at 314. A treaty is self-executing if it is clear from its language: “Our constitution declares a treaty to be the law of the land. It is, consequently, to be regarded in courts of justice as equivalent to an act of the legislature, whenever it operates of itself without the aid of any legislative provision.” Id. See § 1.02[H][2], supra, regarding judicial intervention in self-executing treaties. See ch. 5, infra, for the modern changes to self-execution in the wake of Sanchez-Llamas and Medellin. [C] – Who / What is the U.S. Sovereign? 16 See § 1.02[F], supra. [D] – Sources of Customary International Law Justice Marshall in the Paquete Habana gives opinio juris as the source for customary international law. “[W]here there is no treaty, and no controlling executive or legislative act or judicial decision, resort must be had to the customs and usages of civilized nations; and, as evidence of these, to the works of jurists and commentators, who by years of labor, research and experience, have made themselves peculiarly well acquainted with the subjects of which they treat. Such works are resorted to by judicial tribunals, not for the speculations of their authors concerning what the law ought to be, but for trustworthy evidence of what the law really is.” Id. at 700. This creates a problem in distinguishing between descriptive and normative pronouncements by the jurists and commentators. Cf. Restatement (Second) Torts § 402A (a “Restatement” of the law that essentially invented the field of strict products liability). [E] – CIL as U.S. law [1] – Pre-Erie The most important line of the Supreme Court’s international law jurisprudence, written by Marshall, appears in the Paquete Habana, 175 U.S. at 700: “International law is our law.” This pronouncement gave explicit recognition to an assumption guiding earlier decision; cf. The Antelope, The Schooner Exchange, and Brown. Story’s dissent in the Paquete Habana maintained that the President was not bound by international law unless Congress enacted a statute that reflected the principle of international law. While “the law of nations” does not appear in the supremacy clause or Art. III, the federal courts could exercise common law authority So the law stood until Mr. Tompkins went for a stroll next to a railroad track. [2] – Erie and International Law Post-Erie, some scholars argue that customary international law is and should be part of U.S. federal law. See, e.g., Louis Henkin, International Law as Law in the United States, 82 Mich. L. Rev. 1555, 1559–60 (1984); Philip C. Jessup, The Doctrine of Erie Railroad v. Tompkins Applied to International Law, 33 Am. J. Intl. L. 740 (1939) (“[W]hatever the specific grounds for disposing of any individual case, any attempt to extend the doctrine of the Tompkins case to international law should be repudiated by the Supreme Court”). Henkin argues that in Banco Nacional de Cuba v. Sabbatino, 376 U.S. 398 (1964), the Supreme Court circumvented Erie. Henkin, supra at 1560. The Sabbatino court wrote, “It seems fair to assume that the Court did not have rules like the act of state doctrine in mind when it decided Erie R.[R.] Co. v. Tompkins. Soon thereafter, Professor Philip C. Jessup, now a judge of the International Court of Justice, recognized the potential dangers were Erie extended to legal problems affecting international relations. He cautioned that rules of international law should not be left to divergent and perhaps parochial state interpretations. His basic rationale is equally applicable to the act of state doctrine.” Id. at 425. Because the Supreme Court affirmed the act of state doctrine, the Court must also accept Prof. Jessup’s pronouncement, the reasoning goes. Henkin argues that the judiciary’s power to apply customary international law arises from the framers’ assumption that it was binding, and the phrase “laws of the United States” in both the supremacy clause and Article III. Henkin, supra at 1566. Critics of this position argue that customary international law was based upon general common law, not post-Erie federal common law. Curtis A. Bradley & Jack L. Goldsmith, Customary International Law as Federal Common Law: A Critique of the Modern Position, 110 Harv. L. Rev. 815, 849 (1997). Erie declared that “[t]here is no federal general common law,” 304 U.S. at 78. 17 Thus, “Erie requires federal courts to identify the sovereign source for every rule of decision. Because the appropriate ‘sovereigns’ under the U.S. Constitution are the federal government and the states, all law applied by federal courts must be either federal law or state law. After Erie, then, a federal court can no longer apply CIL in the absence of some domestic authorization to do so, as it could under the regime of general common law.” Bradley & Goldsmith, supra at 852–53. The critics point out that customary international law is not mentioned in the supremacy clause or Article III, and that Congress has never incorporated it by statute. Id. at 856–57. One additional argument for pro-customary international law scholars may be to suggest that Erie has been misinterpreted. See generally Craig Green, Repressing Erie’s Myth, 96 Cal. L. Rev. 595 (2008). Behind the rhetoric, Feldman notes that “customary international law is part of the liberal plot.” International law tends to be “wildly progressive,” and because the Paquete Habana and other cases would tap the work of those writing professedly on the law (i.e., law professors), the liberal academy loves it. [F] – Act of State & Political Question Doctrines The political question and act of state doctrine are both principles rooted in the separation of powers. Each recognizes that the political branches are more competent than the courts to handle certain issues. “The act of state doctrine in its traditional formulation precludes the courts from inquiring into the validity of the public acts a recognized foreign sovereign power committed within its own territory.” Sabbatino, 376 U.S. at 401. “Prominent on the surface of any case held to involve a political question is found a textually demonstrable constitutional commitment of the issue to a coordinate political department; or a lack of judicially discoverable and manageable standards for resolving it; or the impossibility of deciding without an initial policy determination of a kind clearly for nonjudicial discretion; or the impossibility of a court's undertaking independent resolution without expressing lack of the respect due coordinate branches of government; or an unusual need for unquestioning adherence to a political decision already made; or the potentiality of embarrassment from multifarious pronouncements by various departments on one question.” Baker v. Carr, 369 U.S. 186, 217 (1962). Prof. Feldman argues that the political question doctrine is likely done with Bush v. Gore, 531 U.S. 98 (2000). [G] – The Alien Tort Statute Today After the decision in Sosa, both sides seem to claim (limited) victory. Fans of customary international law say that the Court could have shut the door on the Alien Tort Statute after Erie but didn’t. They also point to Scalia’s dissent, which claims that the majority has created “discretion” in the federal courts to create new causes of action. See Sosa, 542 U.S. at 749–50. Critics of customary international law in the U.S. point out that Alvarez lost the case, and that the majority’s requirement that the alleged violations of international law be as definite as the Blackstone three functionally mean that causes of action under the Alien Tort Statute are few and far between. [H] – The Blackstone Three As described in the line of cases concerning the Alien Tort Statute, Blackstone listed three specific offenses that individuals could commit in violation of the law of nations. Souter described “a sphere in which . . . rules binding individuals for the benefit of other individuals overlapped with the norms of state relationships. Blackstone referred to it when he mentioned three specific offenses against the law of nations addressed by the criminal law of England: violation of safe conducts, infringement of the rights of ambassadors, and piracy. An assault against an ambassador, for example, impinged upon the sovereignty of the foreign nation and if not adequately redressed could rise to an issue of war.” Sosa, 542 U.S. at 715 (citations omitted). [I] – The Relationship Between our Constitution and the International Order 18 In brief summary, the relationship between our Constitution and the International Order is as follows. First, customary international law may be part of our law. When federal courts had carte blanche to develop a common law, there was no question of authority. With Erie, however, federal courts may no longer be able to develop a general common law. Thus, the authority to integrate customary international law into U.S. law is in doubt. The Alien Tort Statute appears to give federal courts statutory authority to hear claims, at least tort claims. However, Sosa holds that the Alien Tort Statute does not create a cause of action and instead is only jurisdictional. While the Torture Victim Protection Act provides a cause of action in some circumstances, see Sosa, 542 U.S. at 728, the precise contours of what claims state a cause of action remain murky. 19 Chapter 3 – Torture: An Interlude § 3.01 – Summary of Cases & Materials [A] – Geneva Conventions, Common Article III Common Art. III binds a contracting party, fighting in a war “occurring in the territory of one of the High Contracting Parties,” to apply certain provisions including refraining from torture. [B] – Memo from Jay Bybee to Alberto Gonzales (Aug. 1, 2002) A Office of Legal Counsel memo prepared for the CIA and OGA to discuss what types of interrogation techniques the Agencies could undertake. It began by discussing the meaning of torture within 18 U.S.C. §§ 2340–2340A and defined it as only severe pain or suffering, either physical or mental. It then compared the statute to U.N. conventions and U.S., European, and Israeli judicial interpretations of the word “torture.” It concluded by contemplating what defenses may be available, including both self-defense and necessity. [C] – McCain Torture Act Appears to prohibit “inhuman and degrading treatment.” However, it may be what Prof. Feldman characterized as a “fake statute” because it refers to the standards of the Fifth, Eight, and Fourteenth Amendments, and therefore may be exactly equivalent to Regan’s “understanding” with respect to the Convention Against Torture. See Bybee Memo p. 187. [D] – Congressional testimony—Gonzalez, Mukasey, and Holder Senators were concerned with torture, specifically waterboarding. All three nominees succeeded in answering questions clearly, refusing to speculate or interpret the meaning of torture. This may have been both to keep the door open for future use of enhanced techniques and also to avoid statements that might lead to previous acts being prosecuted. [E] – Committee against Torture, Israel High Court Case Description: The Public Committee Against Torture in Israel brought suit to stop the General Security Service (GSS) from engaging in techniques that the Committee argues are torture: violently shaking prisoners, the “Shabach” position (prisoner with arms handcuffed awkwardly behind a low, forward-leaning chair, hooded, loud music played), tight handcuffs, and the “Frog Crouch” (prisoner forced to lean against wall on tiptoes and held up by fingertips). The Court ruled that the GSS cannot authorize the methods although a necessity defense is possible if a GSS interrogator employs the methods. Holding (Barak): “The power to interrogate granted to the GSS investigator is the same power the law bestows upon the ordinary police investigator . . . [his] duty . . . is to conduct the interrogation according to the law, . . . subject to the same restriction applicable to police interrogators”; this law does not allow torture. Id. at 29, ¶ 32. The necessity defense cannot be used prospectively to authorize (i.e., render non-criminal) torture, only retrospectively as a defense to a crime. § 3.02 – Important Themes [A] – Attorney Responsibilities [1] – Responsibility for Everything You Write or Sign Prof. Feldman points out that as a lawyer, you must be prepared to take responsibility both for everything you write and everything you sign. For example, the “Bybee Memo” was in fact likely written by John Yoo. Bybee signed 20 the memo and would likely have had his career ruined but for his lifetime appointment to the bench before its release. John Yoo is now a professor at the U.C. Berkeley School of Law and his critics have attempted to force him out. Marty Lederman, Convictions: Yoo, Tenure, and the Academy, Slate, April 11, 2008, http://www.slate.com/blogs/blogs/convictions/archive/2008/04/11/yoo-tenure-and-the-academy.aspx. [2] – Lawyers as Ethicists Prof. Feldman argues that there has been a shift in how lawyers view their job. Until a decade or two ago, lawyers saw their role as providing advice and counsel not only in answering detailed legal questions but more generally as offering a perspective on the individual, corporation, or government entity’s overall operations. This included both technical and ethical guidance. Part of a lawyer’s appeal, then, was her ability to give prudent advice over the long term. In the last decade or two, however, lawyers have become more commodified, hired for short-term work, and focused on smaller details of the enterprise in which they work. For these reasons, lawyers are less likely to give ethical advice or put their feet down when their clients’ behavior crosses an ethical line. This, says Feldman, is unfortunate and we (i.e., HLS students / lawyers of tomorrow) should resist this trend. [B] – What is Torture? Most definitions involve “severe pain.” The Bybee memo took this much further, requiring “pain that is difficult to endure. Physical pain amounting to torture must be equivalent in intensity to the pain accompanying serious physical injury, such as organ failure, impairment of bodily function, or even death. For purely mental pin or suffering to amount to torture . . . it must result in significant psychological harm of significant duration, e.g., lasting for months or even years. We conclude that the mental harm also must result from one of the predicate acts listed . . . .” Id. at 172. This definition has since been repudiated. It is less clear precisely to what limits the U.S. will go today. [C] – Unitary Executive Taken from Wikipedia, Unitary executive theory, http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Unitary_executive_theory (as of May. 2, 2009, 14:31 GMT). The Vesting Clause of Article II provides that “[t]he executive Power [of the United States] shall be vested in a President of the United States of America.” Proponents of the unitary executive theory argue that this language, along with the Take Care Clause (“The President shall take care that the laws be faithfully executed . . .”), creates a "hierarchical, unified executive department under the direct control of the President.” The general principle that the President controls the entire executive branch was originally rather innocuous, but extreme forms of the theory have developed. John Dean explains: “In its most extreme form, unitary executive theory can mean that neither Congress nor the federal courts can tell the President what to do or how to do it, particularly regarding national security matters.” According to law professors Lawrence Lessig and Cass Sunstein, "No one denies that in some sense the framers created a unitary executive; the question is in what sense. Let us distinguish between a strong and a weak version.” In either its strong or weak form, the theory would limit the power of Congress to divest the President of control of the executive branch. The "strongly unitary" theory posits stricter limits on Congress than the "weakly unitary" theory. . . . Proponents of a strongly unitary theory argue that the President possesses all of the executive power and can therefore control subordinate officers and agencies of the executive branch. This implies that the power of Congress to remove executive agencies or officers from Presidential control is limited. Thus, under the 21 strongly unitary executive theory, independent agencies and counsels are unconstitutional to the extent that they exercise discretionary executive power not controlled by the President. [D] – What’s Do the Senate Confirmation Hearings Tell Us About Torture? Prof. Feldman suggested that if you were to organize from scratch a system of government that simultaneously could publicly oppose and privately allow torture, you would want to have everyone go to the same schools (e.g., Lieberman and Mukasey in the same small section at Yale). You would want elected officials to project the image of deep disagreement and spirited debate to satisfy an ideologically divided polity, but it wouldn’t hurt if they remained cordial, either for show or in reality (e.g., old “Iron Pants”). You would want confirmation hearings to function somewhat dysfunctionally, with the subjects able to dodge the questions and those asking to be making predetermined rhetorical points rather than conducting a cross-examination. If this is what we have with the confirmation hearings, does this represent “complexly developed, organized hypocrisy” in Feldman’s words? If so, is this bad? Is it acceptable if torture keeps us safer? [E] – Authorization v. Avoidance of Liability The necessity-as-authorization argument, raised both in the Bybee Memo and the Israeli case, underscores two possible approaches to necessity as enabling torture or other unlawful activity. An argument can be made that it is best to keep torture illegal for the purposes of propriety and international reputation, but to torture when necessary and then absolve the torturers of liability. Thus, one might oppose torture entirely and structure the law to prohibit and not forgive those who torture of “necessity.” Alternatively, one may forbid torture but, given the right circumstances, forgive torturers. Finally, one may authorize torture. The ex ante use of the necessity defense conflates the latter two theories. It might be best, if one favors torture, to keep one’s mouth shut about any form of ex ante authorization. See § 2.02 [D], supra; cf. § 4.02[F], infra. 22 Chapter 4 – War and Exception § 4.01 – Summary of Cases & Materials [A] – The Lieber Code: Excerpts The Lieber Code is a military order that seeks to have Union combatants comport themselves within certain standards of military conduct (jus in bello). The Code had little effect on the conduct of the Civil War, but was influential in subsequent thinking about the law of war. [B] – Letter from Abraham Lincoln to Sen. Albert G. Hodges (Apr. 4, 1864) Letter justifying the Emancipation Proclamation, which was likely unconstitutional. Lincoln comes fairly close to admitting that this is so: “I felt that measures, otherwise unconstitutional, might become lawful, by becoming indispensable to the preservation of the constitution, through the preservation of the nation. Right or wrong, I assumed this ground, and now avow it.” Id. at 1. [C] – Abraham Lincoln, Message to Congress in Special Session (July 4, 1861) Lincoln had suspended the writ of habeas corpus on his own authority and argued for his interpretation that this power lay with the executive. He also justified his decision on grounds of necessity, arguing that he cold not be expected to allow all other laws to go unexecuted simply to preserve the writ. Finally, he argued that the states are sovereign only through membership in the U.S., and that they therefore had no authority to secede, especially since it was likely that the majority of U.S. citizens would prefer to remain united. [D] – Letter from Abraham Lincoln to Erastus Corning and Others (June 12, 1863) Lincoln argued in favor of preventive arrests and against resolutions of a public meeting held in Albany. He argued that he had authority to suspend the writ even in non-rebel territory because the Constitution did not distinguish between rebel and non-rebel territory. He also asserted that it was preferable to arrest agitators before they succeeded in persuading desertions rather than executing soldiers who deserted. [E] – Ex parte Merryman, 17 F. Cas. 144 (C.C.D. Md. 1861) Description: Merryman lived in Maryland, was snatched up by an armed force claiming to act under orders from General Keim but without lawful authority. General Keim claims that he was authorized by the President to suspend the writ of habeas corpus. Justice Taney, riding circuit, ordered the President to take measures to “cause the civil process of the United States to be respected and enforced.” Id. at 153. Holding (Taney): The President does not have the power to suspend the writ of habeas corpus; this power lies with the Congress. [F] – Ex parte Milligan, 71 U.S. (4 Wall.) 2 (1866) Description: Milligan was arrested pursuant to an order by General Hovey (on charges related to assisting the Confederacy), tried before a military commission, and sentenced to hang. Subsequently, the Cir. Ct. Ind. empanelled a grand jury, which declined to indict. Milligan then petitioned the Cir. Ct. Ind. for the writ of habeas corpus, and the court certified questions regarding his imprisonment to the Supreme Court. The Supreme Court Holding (Davis): A military commission cannot exercise jurisdiction over a civilian U.S. citizen in a place where the civil courts are open—the Constitution provides the government “all the powers . . . necessary to preserve its existence,” so no suspension of constitutionally protected rights (e.g., Fifth Amendment) need occur. Id. at 121, 123. 23 [G] – Carl Schmitt, Political Theology: Four Chapters on the Concept of Sovereignty 12–13 (George Schwab, trans. 1985) Advances the theory that he who decides upon the state of exception is the sovereign. Thus, by Schmitt’s reasoning, Lincoln became the sovereign (and forever rendered the President sovereign, at least until someone else declares the state of exception) when he suspended the writ of habeas corpus and otherwise suspended constitutional rights. [H] – Korematsu v. United States, 323 U.S. 214 (1944) Description: Korematsu was a U.S. citizen convicted of violating 18 U.S.C. § 97a, a statute criminalizing violation of military exclusion orders. The government did not contest Korematsu’s loyalty. The military, under the aegis of Executive Order 9066, ordered persons of Japanese ancestry to leave certain military areas considered to require special protection. Subsequent to exclusion, many of the excluded Japanese-Americans were taken to assembly centers, then held in detention centers. Korematsu was arrested without before entering the assembly or detention centers. The Supreme Court upheld the conviction. Holding (Roberts): A person who does not comply with the military exclusion order excluding persons of Japanese ancestry can be prosecuted criminally, because the order was made out of reasonable military necessity (not racial prejudice), pursuant to an Executive Order, and its violation was made criminal by Congress; the petitioner was never in an assembly or detention center, so we cannot pass upon those programs. Concurrence (Frankfurter): War power is the “power to wage war successfully”; Justice Jackson should refrain from suggesting that the order was unconstitutional but should be tolerated and not brought before the courts, because this “suffuse[s] a part of the Constitution with an atmosphere of unconstitutionality.” Id. at 224–25. Military necessity is what makes the actions constitutional. Dissent (Roberts): We can’t separate the components of this program, so the detainment is properly before us; this “is the case of convicting a citizen as a punishment for not submitting to imprisonment in a concentration camp, based . . . solely [on] . . . his ancestry, without evidence or inquiry concerning his loyalty . . . . I need hardly labor the conclusion that his Constitutional rights have been violated.” Id. at 226. Dissent (Murphy): This “plea of military necessity in the absence of martial law ought not to be approved. Such exclusion goes over the very brink of constitutional power and falls into the ugly abyss of racism.” Id. at 233 (internal quotation marks omitted). There is no reliable evidence of Japanese-Americans posing any danger and we can’t defer to the military for sociological considerations. Dissent (Jackson): The military may undertake actions that violate the constitution—these actions may even be correct. However, the court cannot place its imprimatur on unconstitutional actions; otherwise the “principle then lies about like a loaded weapon ready for the hand of any authority that can bring forward a plausible claim of an urgent need.” Id. at 246. [I] – Ex parte Endo, 323 U.S. 283 (1944) Description: Endo was evacuated from her home in Sacramento and held in the Tule Lake War Relocation Center. She filed a petition for the writ of habeas corpus in the N.D. Cal. which was denied; appealed to the 9th Cir., affirmed, appealed to the Supreme Court. The Supreme Court reversed and ordered Endo freed. Holding (Douglas): A concededly loyal Japanese-American citizen cannot be detained as part of a program of detentions based only upon ancestry because although Congress and the executive have broad war powers, laws abridging civil liberties must be constructed strictly with respect to their purposes; the goal of preventing sabotage and espionage cannot reasonably permit detaining a loyal citizen. [J] – Ex Parte Quirin, 317 U.S. 1 (1942) 24 Description: A group of Germans, including one who was a U.S. citizen, came ashore in N.Y. and Fla. as part of Operation Pastorius in order to carry out acts of sabotage. They were tried by a military commission and sentenced to death; the Supreme Court allowed an appeal in special term from a petition for the writ of habeas corpus by the district court. The Supreme Court affirmed the judgment of the lower court, and six of the eight were executed just over a week later (the remaining two received life sentences). The full opinion was released months after the executions occurred. “The case was not this Court’s finest hour.” Hamdi v. Rumsfeld, 542 U.S. 507, 569 (2004) (Scalia, J., dissenting). Holding (Stone): The Constitution allows enemy combatants charged with crimes against the law of war to be tried by a military commission, irrespective of citizenship; the right to trial by jury applies only to offenses for which the common law allowed jury trial prior to the framing—this does not include war crimes. Ex Parte Milligan is inapplicable because Milligan was not an enemy combatant. [K] – In re Yamashita, 327 U.S. 1 (1946) Description: After the conclusion of WWII, the U.S. reoccupied the Philippines. The Japanese had killed 100,000 Filipino civilians in the Manila Massacre, and General Tomoyuki Yamashita was blamed—it is disputed as to whether he had command authority. Prof. Feldman suggests that the U.S. was motivated politically to try and execute Yamashita hastily in order to placate the Filipinos as they were being reoccupied by the U.S. Yamashita was tried before a military tribunal, convicted of war crimes and sentenced to death. Yamashita petitioned the Supreme Court of the Philippines for a writ of habeas corpus, which was denied; he appealed the denial to the U.S. Supreme Court, which affirmed the denial. He was hanged 2-1/2 weeks after the Court’s decision. Holding (Stone): Properly constituted military commissions can try enemy combatants for war crimes committed during wartime even after the cessation of hostilities. (Probably not good law anymore says Feldman.) Dissent (Murphy): Yamashita should have been afforded Fifth Amendment protections—constitutional protections should not be ignored except under extreme circumstances; this is dangerous for us in the future. Dissent (Rutledge): Yamashita is a scapegoat; we don’t hang Generals after we win. “This long-held attachment [to due process] marks the great divide between our enemies and ourselves. Theirs was a philosophy of universal force. Ours is one of universal law, albeit imperfectly made flesh of our system and so dwelling among us. Every departure weakens the tradition, whether it touches the high or the low, the powerful or the weak, the triumphant or the conquered. If we need not or cannot be magnanimous, we can keep our own law on the plane from which it has not descended hitherto and to which the defeated foes’ never rose.” Id. at 42. [L] – Hirota v. MacArthur, 338 U.S. 197 (1949) Description: Hirota and two others convicted by a military tribunal in Japan. They petitioned the Supreme Court for habeas corpus; the Court determined it did not have authority to hear the cases because the military commission was not a tribunal of the U.S. Hirota and one of the other defendants were hanged; the third spent four years in prison. The judgment was per curiam; Justice Douglas wrote a bizarre concurring opinion more than six months later. This outcome of this case was important for Justice Jackson because he had been prosecutor at Nuremberg, and if the Supreme Court held otherwise, it would undermine the legitimacy of the tribunal. Concurrence (Douglas): Although on these facts the Supreme Court does not have jurisdiction, it is not the case that international tribunals are beyond U.S. authority; so long as the U.S. has authority over the custodian, habeas corpus can be effective. [M] – Hamdi v. Rumsfeld, 542 U.S. 507 (2004) Description: Yaser Hamdi, a U.S. citizen, was captured by the Afghan Northern Alliance and turned over to U.S. forces who detained him in Guantanamo Bay, then transferred to a naval brig in Norfolk, Va. Hamdi’s father petitioned as next friend for a writ of habeas corpus under 28 U.S.C. § 2241 in E.D. Va. The district court ordered a public defender appointed and given access to Hamdi. The Fourth Circuit reversed this order. The district court 25 then ordered the government to produce evidence, which the government appealed and the Fourth Circuit reversed, holding that separation of powers precluded the courts from interfering in this area. Certiorari was granted, and the Supreme Court vacated the Fourth Circuit’s judgment and remanded. Scalia’s dissent is dramatic and famous, although Feldman suggests that it might be designed to force Congress’ hand to suspend the writ of habeas corpus, and this might explain why Souter and Ginsburg didn’t join. Plurality Holding (O’Connor, Rehnquist, Kennedy, and Breyer): The President has the power under the Authorization for the Use of Military Force (the Court did not reach the question of authority under Art. II) to detain enemy combatants even if they are U.S. citizens; however, they must be afforded process consistent with the principles articulated in Matthews v. Eldridge, 424 U.S. 319 (1976). Concurrence (Souter and Ginsburg): Argues that the Non-Detention Act prevents the President from detaining combatants except with express Congressional authorization (which the A.U.M.F. does not provide); joins the plurality for practical reasons: it’s disposition comes closest to the concurring Justices’ preferred resolution. Dissent (Scalia and Stevens): In the absence of the suspension of the writ of habeas corpus, the U.S. must either charge Hamdi with a crime or release him. Dissent (Thomas): The President has Art. II powers to detain enemy combatants; there is no process due. [N] – Hamdan v. Rumsfeld, 548 U.S. 557 (2006) Description: Salim Ahmed Hamdan, allegedly Osama Bin Laden’s driver, was captured by militia forces and turned over to U.S. forces in Afghanistan. He was held in Guantanamo, and after a year without specific charge was accused of the Kafkaesque “conspiracy to commit offenses triable by military commission.” Id. at 566 (internal punctuation changed). Hamdan petitioned the D.D.C. for a writ of habeas corpus which it granted. The D.C. Cir. reversed. The Supreme Court granted certiorari, reversed the D.C. Cir. and remanded to the trial court. The Supreme Court had jurisdiction because the case was pending before Congress amended 28 U.S.C. § 2441, the federal habeas statute (which would have precluded jurisdiction, but was subsequently overruled, as applied, in Boumediene). Holding (Stevens): The military commission was unlawful because 10 U.S.C. § 821 allows military commissions to try persons who either violate a statute or the law of war; the petitioner is not alleged to have violated any statute so the law of war applies. Because the Geneva Conventions are part of the law of war, Art. 3—requiring trials to be held by a “regularly constituted court”—applies. Military commissions are not regularly constituted courts. Plurality (Stevens, not joined by Kennedy): The law of war also allows the detainee to be present. Dissent (Thomas): The Geneva Convention doesn’t apply because its phrase “armed conflict not of an international character . . .” is ambiguous but the President’s interpretation of the phrase is entitled to deference; even if it applies the claim is not ripe and the commission is regularly constituted and sufficient. Dissent (Alito): This is a regularly constituted court under U.S. domestic law. [O] – Padilla v. Hanft, 432 F.3d 582 (4th Cir. 2005) Description: José Padilla, a U.S. citizen, was arrested in Chicago’s O’Hare airport returning from the Middle East, first as a material witness, then as an enemy combatant. The Fourth Circuit had previously held that the President had the authority to detain enemy combatants. The government petitioned the Fourth Circuit either to transfer Padilla from military custody in S.C. to civilian custody in Fla. or to withdraw its earlier opinion. The Fourth Circuit believed that the government was doing this in order to avoid the Supreme Court, and denied the motion. The Supreme Court subsequently granted the government’s motion for release from military custody and denied certiorari pending further proceedings. Hanft v. Padilla, 546 U.S. 1084 (2006). § 4.02 – Important Themes 26 [A] – The Tests of a Constitution Professor Feldman describes two ways by which to evaluate a constitution. First, does it provide justice? Second, does it hold the country together? Prof. Feldman argues that the U.S. Constitution as framed in 1787 failed both tests. As to the first question, the pre-13th Amendment Constitution permitted slavery. As to the second, Lincoln believed it necessary to exceed his constitutional authority to hold the country together during the Civil War. [B] – War = Necessity? Some view war itself as creating a justification of necessity. In his Korematsu concurrence, Justice Frankfurter cited Chief Justice Hughes’ line that “the war power of the Government is ‘the power to wage war successfully.’” Korematsu, 323 U.S. at 224. A fuller quote from Hughes is that “the framers of the Constitution ‘ did not contrive a spectacle of imposing impotency’ . . . the Constitution g[ives] to the Government the power to wage war [and] ‘the power to wage war is the power to wage it successfully.’ ” War Power Ample, Hughes Declares, N.Y. Times, Sept. 6, 1917, at A1, available at http://www.nytimes.com/ (search “War Power Ample”). Lincoln’s letters also indicate a view that war implies necessity; see in particular his letter to Erastus Corning. Finally, war as necessity permeates the Bybee Memo and the Confirmation Hearing materials. [C] – Sharp Wars “The more vigorously wars are pursued the better it is for humanity. Sharp wars are brief.” Lieber Code, ¶ 29. This relates to a strain of thought traceable to Carl von Clausewitz, On War (1832). Clausewitz noted that war tends to escalate. On War, http://en.wikipedia.org/w/index.php?title=On_War (last visited Mar. 25, 2009) [hereinafter Wikipedia, On War]. This theory laid the groundwork for “total war,” a class of warfare that mobilizes all resources and lessens or eliminates the distinctions between combatants and civilians. Total war, http://en.wikipedia.org/w/index.php?title=Total_war (last visited Mar. 25, 2009) [hereinafter Wikepedia, Total war]. Clausewitz’ most famous line is “War is not merely a political act, but also a real political instrument, a continuation of political commerce, a carrying out of the same by other means.” Lieber and Clausewitz also both discuss a prime goal of war as the return to peace. There is a tension between the theory of total war and other values reflected in the Lieber Code; see, e.g. Id. at ¶¶ 21 & 25. [D] – Habeas as Guardian of the Rule of Law In his Message to Congress in Special Session, Lincoln asked, “are all the laws, but one, to go unexecuted, and the government itself go to pieces, lest that one be violated?” Prof. Feldman points out that is disingenuous, for if the writ of habeas corpus is suspended, there can be no vindication of any other law. Thus, while Lincoln would suggest that he continued to enforce other laws, without habeas this is a dubious claim. The history of the writ supports this objection. The writ was instrumental in placing the sovereign within the law rather than outside the law. [E] – A Schmittian Analysis of U.S. Exception According to Schmitt’s theory, Lincoln seized the nations sovereignty and placed it within the executive branch by declaring exception. It is colorable under this theory that in Korematsu, under rubric of Jackson’s dissent, the military became the sovereign. This is because Jackson accepted the idea that the military might act 27 unconstitutionally but properly as necessity dictates. This seems to suggest it lies with the military to declare a state of exception, and by Schmitt’s reasoning, the military became the executive upon exercising this authority (judicial review notwithstanding). [F] – Do it But Don’t Bring it into Court Jackson’s dissent in Korematsu seems to suggest that the military can operate unconstitutionally but correctly if necessity so requires. However, Jackson couldn’t uphold unconstitutional policies. This implies that Jackson could approve of the military’s conduct so long as it does not come before the court. There’s a similar implication in Eisentrager and the cases that follow: the Court appears not to want the question of military authority / necessity before it. This is also comparable to necessity as authorization contrasted with necessity as defense—the court cannot approve of torture ex ante but perhaps can excuse it ex post. See §3.02[E], supra. A somewhat analogous situation makes Steven’s arguments in Hamdan unlikely and bold: if the Geneva Convention, Common Article III applies to Al Qaeda, Bush administration officials might be guilty of a war crime for torturing detainees. This may explain why Mukasey during his confirmation hearing distinguished the procedural aspects of Hamdan from the substantive ones—he implies that the Supreme Court never reached the question of whether the Geneva Convention’s protection against torture applies. [G] – Habeas Jurisprudence: Jurisdiction v. Substance Rasul and Hamdi were handed down the same week. Rasul was a statutory holding regarding habeas jurisdiction. Hamdi concerned both the power to detain and the process due to a detainee. Boumediene opened the door for detainees to challenge their detention even after Congress amended the habeas statute. [H] – The Geneva Convention Eisentrager appears to hold that the Geneva Convention is not self-executing. See Hamdan, 548 U.S. at 627. Stevens makes the argument in Hamdan (mirroring an argument by Souter in his Hamdi concurrence) that if the government invokes international law as its authority for conducting military commissions, it is bound by international law in conducting itself. Because the Geneva Convention is part of international law, even if it’s not self-executing, it is incorporated into the military’s conduct that relies for its authority upon international law (you can’t “pick and choose”). This, says Feldman, is “profound” if correct, because it’s yet another mechanism for getting International law into our law—common law, various statutes (including the Alien Tort Statute), and now the U.C.M.J., which references international law as a basis for military tribunal jurisdiction. (Note, this could also be argued to be implied by the word “war” in the Constitution.) 28 Chapter 5 – Who Obeys What? The States and International Law § 5.01 – Summary of Cases & Materials [A] – Missouri v. Holland, 252 U.S. 416 (1920) Summary: The U.S. entered into the Migratory Bird Treaty Act, which affected Missouri’s rights with respect to the birds within the state. Congress had previously passed an act, ruled unconstitutional under the Tenth Amendment, that regulated the killing of migratory birds. Missouri appealed the dismissal of its challenge to the treaty to the Supreme Court which affirmed the dismissal. Holding (Holmes): With respect to rights reserved to the States, the treaty-making power is not limited to what may be done by an unaided act of Congress, and the supremacy clause (Art. VI, ¶ 2) gives treaties superiority over conflicting state law. [B] – Reid v. Covert, 354 U.S. 1, 16-18 (1957) Summary: See § 1.01[F], supra. The petitioner argued that the treaty between the U.S. and Great Britain allowed the U.S. military courts to exercise jurisdiction of the dependents of U.S. servicepersons. The Supreme Court answered that the U.S. did not have the power to do this. Plurality Holding (Black): “[N]o agreement with a foreign nation can confer power on the Congress, or on any other branch of Government, which is free from the restraints of the Constitution.” Id. at 16. [C] – Convention on Consular Relations (Apr. 24, 1963) – Article 36 Summary: Purport to confer the rights to “a foreign national ‘arrested’ or ‘detained in any other manner’ (1) to have, on his ‘reques[t],’ the ‘consular post’ ‘inform[ed]’ of that arrest or detention; (2) to have forwarded ‘without delay’ any ‘communication addressed to the consular post’; and (3) to be ‘inform[ed] . . . without delay’ of those two ‘rights.’” Sanchez-Llamas v. Oregon, 548 U.S. 331, 373 (2006) (Breyer, J., dissenting). Art. 36 of the V.C.C.R. would play an important role in several subsequent cases, turning on the issue of interpretation and enforceability of judgments pursuant to the V.C.C.R. [D] – State Department Materials on VCCR Compliance: Flow Chart and Booklet Summary: A document distributed to local law enforcement agencies providing information about how those agencies can comply with the requirements of the V.C.C.R. [E] – LaGrand Case (F.R.G. v. U.S.), 2001 I.C.J. 466 (June 27) Summary: Arizona arrested two brothers, both German citizens for felony murder and bank robbery, tried them, and sentenced them to death. Germany was informed much later and after the procedural default rule had barred future collateral challenges to their death sentences. Their consulate was not informed of their arrest, and Art. 36 of the V.C.C.R. required their consulate be informed. One of the brothers was executed. The government of Germany filed an action in the International Court of Justice, which issued a provisional order requiring the U.S. government to do everything within its power to prevent the second brother’s execution pending disposition of the case before the I.C.J. The Solicitor General advised the Supreme Court that the I.C.J.’s order had no legal effect, and the Supreme Court did not intervene. The Arizona Governor, contrary to the advice of the clemency board, allowed the execution to proceed, and the second brother was executed. Germany amended its complaint to submit (1) the U.S. violated the LaGrands’ and Germany’s rights under the V.C.C.R.; (2) the U.S. violated Art. 36, ¶ 2; (3) the U.S. violated its international legal obligations by violating the I.C.J. order; and (4) the U.S. must be required to assure Germany of future compliance with U.S. obligations under the V.C.C.R. The I.C.J. upheld Germany’s submissions, and noted that the U.S. must provide a procedure for the resolution of V.C.C.R. violations. 29 [F] – In the Case Concerning Avena and Other Mexican Nationals (Mex. v. U.S.), 2004 I.C.J. 128 (Mar. 31). Description: “In 2003, Mexico filed suit in the I.C.J. on behalf of 54 Mexican nationals on death row in the United States and obtained provisional remedies against execution of the named inmates prior to the conclusion of the proceedings. . . . The United States characterized this as an effort to obtain a prohibition on capital punishment for Mexican nationals. In the suit, Mexico sought annulment of the convictions without a showing of prejudice; a return to the status quo ante; and application of the exclusionary rule to confessions taken in violation of the order. The world court held that the United States had violated the convention as to 51 of the original 54 individuals named in the suit. The I.C.J. interpreted the Vienna Convention requirement that the suspect be notified of his consular rights without delay, deciding that this phrase did not require notification prior to interrogation in every case, but rather prompt notification under the circumstances. . . . The I.C.J. also reiterated in Avena that procedurally defaulted review did not give full effect to the treaty provisions, and held that clemency proceedings did not provide the requisite review and reconsideration either. The courts remedy was to order United States courts to fully examine the claims of those named in the judgment, insisting that full weight be given to the treaty violations in any review process. The Court did not, however, order annulment of the convictions and declined to declare the treaty notification provision a basic human right.” John M. Castellano, Castellano on Medellin v. Texas, 2008 Emerging Issues 3095 (citations omitted). [G] – George W. Bush, Memorandum for the Attorney General (Feb. 28, 2005) Description: Bush wrote the Attorney General that the U.S. “will discharge its international obligations under . . . Avena . . . by having State courts give effect to the decision in accordance with general principles of comity . . . .” [H] – Sanchez-Llamas v. Oregon & Bustillo v. Johnson, 548 U.S. 331 (2006) Description: After the I.C.J.’s judgments in LaGrand and Avena and after Bush’s letter, Moises Sanchez-Llamas and Mario Bustillo were separately arrested for attempted murder and other felonies. The prisoners were not among those listed in Avena. Neither was informed of the right to consular notification. Both appeal their denial of state writs of habeas corpus. The Supreme Court affirmed the decisions of the state supreme courts. Holding (Roberts): The V.C.C.R. does not require an exclusionary rule if the notice provisions of Art. 36 are violated. The interpretation of U.S. treaties lies with the U.S. courts, so the I.C.J.’s interpretation of the V.C.C.R. is not binding on the U.S. Dissent (Breyer): The V.C.C.R. creates individual rights; sometimes state procedural default rules must yield, under the supremacy clause, to treaty obligations including the I.C.J.’s judgment; sometimes an exclusionary rule is the appropriate remedy to V.C.C.R. violations. [I] – Medellin v. Texas 120 S. Ct. 1346 (2008) Description: Jose Ernesto Medellin, a Mexican national, was convicted of participating in the gang rape and murder of two girls, aged 14 and 16. Medellin was among the prisoners listed in Avena. After dismissal of several other of his collateral challenges, the Supreme Court granted certiorari to review the dismissal of his state habeas challenge by the Texas Ct. Crim. App. The Supreme Court affirmed the dismissal and Medellin was executed in 2008. Holding (Roberts): Although they create an international law obligation, I.C.J. judgments are not self-executing in the U.S. The I.C.J., which has jurisdiction under the V.C.C.R.’s optional protocol—to which the U.S. was a signatory—does not have the authority to bind the U.S. to its judgments because the United Nations Charter, Art. 94, provides that the sole enforcement mechanism for I.C.J. judgments is referral to the U.N. Security Council. The President’s memo has no effect because he does not have the authority to cause an international obligation to become self-executing under separation of powers principles. 30 Dissent (Breyer): Self-execution cannot be determined from the text of a treaty because self-execution is a U.S. concept; instead, treaties must be read from a purposive approach. The President may have the power to require the enforcement of the judgment because of something like political necessity, although Breyer would rather not reach this question and doesn’t provide a definitive answer. § 5.02 – Important Themes [A] – Federal and State Power and Treaties “The powers not delegated to the United States by the Constitution, nor prohibited by it to the States, are reserved to the States respectively, or to the people.” U.S. Const. amend. X. One conception of state’s rights is that the colonies become sovereign states at the time of the framing. If this is so, the 10th Amendment merely confirmed what was already true. If instead the Constitution was adopted by “we the people” in the sense of the United States, the 10th Amendment serves as a necessary protection for the states. Holmes confronted this in Missouri v. Holland. “[W]hen we are dealing with words that also are a constituent act, like the Constitution of the United States, we must realize that they have called into life a being the development of which could not have been foreseen completely by the most gifted of its begetters. It was enough for them to realize or to hope that they had created an organism; it has taken a century and has cost their successors much sweat and blood to prove that they created a nation. The case before us must be considered in the light of our whole experience and not merely in that of what was said a hundred years ago. The treaty in question does not contravene any prohibitory words to be found in the Constitution. The only question is whether it is forbidden by some invisible radiation from the general terms of the Tenth Amendment. We must consider what this country has become in deciding what that Amendment has reserved.” 252 U.S. at 433–34. Whatever the relation between the states and federal government before the Civil War, Holmes seems to believe the federal government has the upper hand afterwards. “It is obvious that there may be matters of the sharpest exigency for the national well being that an act of Congress could not deal with but that a treaty followed by such an act could, and it is not lightly to be assumed that, in matters requiring national action, a power which must belong to and somewhere reside in every civilized government is not to be found.” Id. at 433 (internal quotation marks omitted). “This Constitution, and the Laws of the United States which shall be made in Pursuance thereof; and all Treaties made, or which shall be made, under the Authority of the United States, shall be the supreme Law of the Land . . . .” U.S. Const. art. VI, § 2. Holmes suggests that the text implies that the laws of the United States must be made in pursuance of the Constitution, whereas treaties needn’t be. In reply, Black argues in Reid that “the reason treaties were not limited to those made in ‘pursuance’ of the Constitution was so that agreements made by the United States under the Articles of Confederation, including the important peace treaties which concluded the Revolutionary War, would remain in effect. It would be manifestly contrary to the objectives of those who created the Constitution, as well as those who were responsible for the Bill of Rights – let alone alien to our entire constitutional history and tradition – to construe Article VI as permitting the United States to exercise power under an international agreement without observing constitutional prohibitions. In effect, such construction would permit amendment of that document in a manner not sanctioned by Article V. The prohibitions of the Constitution were designed to apply to all branches of the National Government and they cannot be nullified by the Executive or by the Executive and the Senate combined.” 354 U.S. at 16–17. A counterargument to this point is that the verb tense is future: “shall be made.” This seems a poor explanation for backwards looking provisions. A better argument might be that this is bad draftsmanship. [B] – Comity and Timid Courts Black’s defines comity as “The recognition and respect that a court of one state or jurisdiction shows to another state or jurisdiction in giving effect to the other's laws and political decisions.” International courts in particular find themselves in a strange position of position of trying simultaneously to act as courts (i.e., decisively and authoritatively) but without pushing the limits of the acceptability of their judgments. The ICJ in LaGrand and 31 Avena tread somewhat softly in an absolute sense (although pretty forcefully for the ICJ) in ordering only that the U.S. review its procedures, not that the procedural default rule was unconstitutional. This worry was borne out: the U.S. withdrew from the Optional Protocol. A similar thread would show up in the ICSID’s resolution of Loewen. See §6.01[F], infra. [C] – The Supreme Court as (Exclusive?) Interpreter of Treaties In Sanchez-Llamas, the Court wrote that “[n]othing in the structure or purpose of the ICJ suggests that its interpretations were intended to be conclusive on our courts. . . . Any interpretation of law the ICJ renders in the course of resolving particular disputes is thus not binding precedent even as to the ICJ itself; there is accordingly little reason to think that such interpretations were intended to be controlling on our courts.” 548 U.S. at 354–55. Because the I.C.J. is envisioned by the V.C.C.R. to be the body that explicates the treaty’s meaning, the Supreme Court must assume that the Supreme Court and not the I.C.J. is the final arbiter of the meaning of the treaty itself (and not just of how the U.S. will apply the treaty). If this is so, while the lower courts may have been entitled to consider the I.C.J.’s explication of the V.C.C.R. (as persuasive authority) prior to the Supreme Court’s weighing in on it; perhaps the supremacy clause now precludes this advisory information now that the Supreme Court has interpreted the V.C.C.R. If, e.g., the procedural default rule is statutory in a state, the state court might have been able to rely on the authority of the I.C.J.’s judgment before Sanchez-Llamas, now they can’t. [D] – Treaties, Unsettled? Breyer, dissenting in Medellin, worries “the majority’s very different approach has seriously negative practical implications. The United States has entered into at least 70 treaties that contain provisions for ICJ dispute settlement similar to the Protocol before us. . . . [T]he consequence is to undermine longstanding efforts in those treaties to create an effective international system for interpreting and applying many, often commercial, self-executing treaty provisions. I thus doubt that the majority is right when it says, ‘We do not suggest that treaties can never afford binding domestic effect to international tribunal judgments.’ In respect to the 70 treaties that currently refer disputes to the ICJ’s binding adjudicatory authority, some multilateral, some bilateral, that is just what the majority has done.” 128 S. Ct. at 1387–88 (citations removed). [D] – The Political Implications of Self-Execution (Now and Then) When Foster and Percheman were decided, few treaties created obligations respecting international tribunals. Thus, the worst that could be said in terms of democracy deficit problems with treaties is that they bypassed the political branches of the U.S. Now, with treaties that require adjudication before international tribunals, the President and Senate can work to put the resolution of U.S. disputes in the hands of foreigners. [E] – Anthony Kennedy v. Everyone Else The court more or less flips in its decisions in Boumediene and Medellin. Only Anthony Kennedy votes with the majority both times (more or less—the Court split 6-3 in Medellin, but Stevens concurrence seems almost more sympathetic to the dissent). Kennedy would likely claim that the liberals and conservatives are simply being political and that he is being consistent by standing always with the Supreme Court as the arbiter of what the law is. The other justices might say that Anthony Kennedy is a hack lawyer who is on the Court only because he was personal friends with Reagan, but has gone all mushy and he is just splitting the difference politically. 32 Chapter 6 – The Constitution in International Markets / Rights and International Norms § 6.01 – Summary of Cases & Materials [A] – Charles A. Beard, An Economic Interpretation of the Constitution Of The United States (1913) Description: Argues that by examining the correspondence of the framers and the Federalist, it’s clear that the Constitution is an economic document designed to satisfy economic interests. “It was an economic document drawn with superb skill by men whose property interests were immediately at stake; and as such it appealed directly and unerringly to identical interests in the country at large.” Id. at 188. The framers were wealthy as bondholders and sought to reign in the power and revolutionary spirit of farmers and planters; Beard argued in later works that farmers and debtors would win out over the capitalists by 1800. See Wikipedia, An Economic Interpretation of the Constitution of the United States, http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/An_Economic_Interpretation_of_the_Constitution_of_the_United_States (as of Apr. 30, 2009, 11:55 GMT). The book was the most important work on the Constitution for several decades following its publication, until it was discredited in the 1950s. While its conclusions are not entirely accurate, the works discrediting Beard were based on economic models with insufficiently sophisticated regression analysis. Nevertheless, it has largely dropped out of view in modern curricula. [B] – Robert A. McGuire, To Form A More Perfect Union: A New Economic Interpretation of the United States Constitution (2003) McGuire argues that although Beard’s interpretation fell out of favor and is not entirely correct with its focus on “personalty” and “realty,” it is correct that the framers were motivated by self-interest. He undertakes an economic study of demographic factors of the framers and state ratifying conventions (which offered more robust than the data on the framers: 1400 or 1500 people compared to 51) comparing this data to how each voted (public choice theory). “The findings indicate voting patterns that can be said to generally support an economic interpretation of the Constitution because personal and constituent economic interests affected voting on particular issues primarily when those interests were more likely to be advanced by the outcome. . . . [T]he statistical findings . . . indicate that a delegate’s occupation, assets, and wealth did significantly influence his vote during the drafting and ratification of the Constitution.” Id. at 91, 209. [C] – McCulloch v. Maryland, 17 U.S. 316 (1819), 401-25 Description: Maryland attempted to tax the Second Bank of the United States. Maryland sued James McCulloch, a cashier at the bank, for issuing currency not stamped in the manner required by Md. law. The Md. appellate courts affirmed the decision, and McCulloch appealed to the Supreme Court. The Supreme Court struck down the Md. law. Holding (Marshall): U.S. states are bound by acts of Congress that are neither specifically enumerated nor forbidden, provided that Congress’s end is legitimate within the scope of the Constitution and its means are appropriate and plainly adopted to that end. [D] – Legal Tender Cases: Hepburn v. Griswold, 75 U.S. 603 (1870); Knox v. Lee & Parker v. Davis, 79 U.S. 457 (1871) Description: Hepburn held that Congress could not make notes legal tender to satisfy contracts entered into before the legislation (Legal Tender Act of 1862) because the notes were not of the same value and thus violated the due process clause of the Fifth Amendment. The dissenters noted that military necessity in paying for the Civil War gave Congress this power. They were “very frank” said Feldman, because they recognized they weren’t clearly correct on constitutional grounds, but noted that there was clear necessity. 33 The Legal Tender Cases overruled Hepburn, holding that the obligation a contract creates is simply to pay the debt, although expectations might include gold coins. Therefore Legal Tender Act applied even to preexisting contracts, because it did not impair contracts, and in any event the 5th Amendment does not cognize this sort of regulation as a taking. Bradley’s dissent is particularly interesting as it explains necessity in a Hobbesian way. See § 6.02[B], infra. [E] – Gold Clause Cases: Norman v. Baltimore & Ohio Railroad Co., 294 U.S. 240; Nortz v. United States, 294 U.S. 317; Perry v. United States, 294 U.S. 330 (all 1935). Description: Immediately after President Roosevelt took office, Congress passed the Emergency Banking Act and E.O. 6102, requiring all gold be remitted to the government in exchange for paper money. Later followed a “joint resolution canceling all gold clauses in public and private contracts, stating such clauses interfered with the Congress's power to regulate U.S. currency.” Wikipedia, Gold Clause Cases, http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Gold_Clause_Cases (as of Apr. 30, 2009, 12:28 GMT). Norman held that necessity and the power of Congress to create rules affecting commerce made the gold clause limitations constitutional. Responding to the argument that vested gold clauses in contracts were a property right that Congress had destroyed without compensation, the Court wrote that contracts cannot “fetter the constitutional authority of the Congress” and that the ubiquity of gold clauses thwarts a legitimate congressional objective. Id. at 307, 312. The dissenters argued that the government was bound by its limited and enumerated powers, and that the majority’s holding was part of a nefarious plan that would allow the government simply to print money. The government was avoiding its obligations in violation of the Fifth Amendment, including its obligations to bondholders abroad. Nortz involved a holder of a Treasury gold certificate, and argued that he was entitled to the weight of gold the certificate promised, which was worth more than the face value of the certificate due to higher gold prices. Perry involved a similar situation with a bond promising payment in gold coin. The Emergency Banking Act prevented both parties from private ownership of the gold the instruments they held promised; the Court in both cases held that there was no Fifth Amendment violation because neither claimant was entitled to the gold and therefore had no claim that he had been deprived of its value. [F] – Loewen Group Inc. v. United States (International Ctr. for Resolution of Disputes 2003) Description: A dispute between a funeral home company in Canada (Loewen) and one in Miss. (O’Keefe) led to a jury trial in Miss. in which the jury awarded O’Keefe $500 million. The award was outrageous and followed from a trial rife with appeals to race, class, and national identity. In order to appeal Loewen would have to post bond of 125% of the judgment. After several interim measures, the appeals court refused to provide any relief from this requirement or further stay execution of the judgment pending an appeal. Loewen was forced to settle with O’Keefe. Loewen brought a claim before the ICSID, alleging discrimination in violation of provision of NAFTA. Subsequently, Lowewen moved most of its operations to the U.S., leaving behind a shell company whose only asset was this claim. The court noted that the Miss. court’s behavior was beyond the pale, but ruled that the while Loewen’s failure to exhaust his appeals was the ostensible reason for dismissal. The fact that the company is in the U.S. was also an important reason for dismissal. Lurking behind the scenes may be the ICSID’s fear of putting its foot down and leading the U.S. to back out of NAFTA. See Id. at 70, ¶ 242. The court discussed that while “[r]ights of action under private law arise from personal obligations . . . NAFTA claims have quite a different character, stemming from a corner of public international law in which, by treaty, the power of States under the law to take international measures for the correction of wrongs done to its nationals has been replaced by an ad hoc definition of certain kinds of wrong, coupled with specialist means of compensation.” Id. at 67, ¶ 233. 34 [G] – Roper v. Simmons, 543 U.S. 551 (2005) Description: A 17 year old sentenced to death challenged his conviction under the Eighth Amendment, and after the Mo. Supreme Court struck down his conviction, certiorari was granted. In affirming the Mo. Supreme Court, Justice Kennedy cited a variety of international sources. Holding (Kennedy): The Eighth Amendment forbids imposing the death penalty juvenile offenders under 18. [H] – Lawrence v. Texas, 539 U.S. 558 (2003) Description: Two men were convicted of violating Texas’s anti-sodomy law. On appeal to the Supreme Court, Justice Kennedy cited to international law in overruling Bowers v. Hardwick and ruled that the Texas law was unconstitutional. Holding (Kennedy): Anti-sodomy laws violate the due process clause. [I] – Transcript of Discussion Between U.S. Supreme Court Justices Antonin Scalia and Stephen Breyer, Jan. 13, 2005 Breyer likes talking about international law in his opinions. Scalia does not like this (especially when Kennedy does it). [J] – Ruth Bader Ginsburg, Looking Beyond Our Borders: The Value of a Comparative Perspective in Constitutional Adjudication, 40 Idaho L. Rev. 1 (2003) Ginsburg likes looking at international law in her opinions. § 6.02 – Important Themes [A] – Mad Libs: _____ is the most important _____ in _____. “International law is part of our law” is the most important line in the U.S. Reports about international law. Dred Scott is the most profoundly anti-colonial opinion in the U.S. Reports. McCulloch v. Maryland is the most important constitutional decision in Supreme Court history. Missouri v. Holland is the most important treaty power case in Supreme Court history. The Bank of the United States was the most important political issue in the first 30 years of the U.S. [B] – What’s This Necessity Thing, Anyway? “But the creditor interest will lose some of its gold! Is gold the one thing needful? Is it worse for the creditor to lose a little by depreciation than everything by the bankruptcy of his debtor? Nay, is it worse than to lose everything by the subversion of the government? What is it that protects him in the accumulation and possession of his wealth? Is it not the government and its laws? And can he not consent to trust that government for a brief period until it shall have vindicated its right to exist? All property and all rights, even those of liberty and life, are held subject to the fundamental condition of being liable to be impaired by providential calamities and national vicissitudes.” The Legal Tender Cases, 79 U.S. at 564 (Bradley, J., dissenting). On this view, but for the government, one would have nothing—no property, no rights, no life. As Feldman put it “you can talk about your rights as much as you want, it won’t do any good and then they’ll eat you.” If this is true, the government can legitimately justify literally anything so long as it’s born of true necessity. 35 [C] – Creditors One can argue for economic necessity along the following lines: if the government must borrow money to function, one of its most (perhaps its very most) critical role is to protect creditors. It must do this two ways: first, by solving a collective action problem; second, by using its nonpolitical branches to prevent the majority of debtors from abrogating their obligations (tyranny of debtors). The bailout is the most recent demonstration of the thoroughness with which economic necessity is accepted. While it might be the case that the bailout is unconstitutional, the Supreme Court would never rule this way and would in fact likely not even grant certiorari on a case challenging the bailout. The Supreme Court functioned primarily as a protector of property interests until the Legal Tender Cases. This would prove to be but a blip, however, as the Lochner Era would lead to renewed property protection. However, the New Deal Court would shift its focus to protecting liberty. One explanation is that the creditors became more sophisticated and could rely on capturing political branches and structuring the law so as never to reach the courts or having positive law on their side rather than relying on the courts to protect them. [D] – Arguments about Citing Foreign Sources = Proxy War It is difficult to explain what international law means to those who haven’t made a close study of it. Thus, it seems that the debate over the proper place of international law in the U.S. is being fought out as the debate between Justices Kennedy and Scalia, for example. This is a much-altered debate, but contains many of the important threads of the fuller controversy. 36