Cognitive-Functional Linguistics – Some Basic Tenets I Rolf Theil Bergen, June 19, 2006 – More juice! Nothing could seem less remarkable than a one-year-old child requesting More juice! But the remarkable fact is that even this baby utterance differs from the communicative activities of other animal species in a number of fundamental ways. June 19, 2006 RT/CFL/I 2 – Doggie gone! Nothing could seem less remarkable than a one-year-old child commenting Doggie gone! But the remarkable fact is that no other animals make disinterested comments to one another about missing dogs. June 19, 2006 RT/CFL/I 3 The most astounding fact From an ethological perspective, perhaps the most astounding fact is that about 80 percent of all Homo sapiens cannot understand these simple utterances at all. Whereas the individuals of all nonhuman species can communicate effectively with all of their conspecifics, human beings can communicate effectively only with other persons who have grown up in their same linguistic community. June 19, 2006 RT/CFL/I 4 Language learning Whatever may be the reasons for this unique, indeed bizarre, situation, one immediate outcome is that, unlike most other animal species, human beings cannot be born with any specific set of communicative behaviors. Yound children must learn the set of linguistic conventions used by those around them, which for any given language consists of tens of thousands, or perhaps even hundred of thousands, of individual words, expressions, and constructions. June 19, 2006 RT/CFL/I 5 Flexibility The human species is biologically prepared for this prodigious task in ways that individuals of other species are not. But this preparation cannot be too specific, as human children must be flexible enough to learn not only all of the different words and conventional expressions but also all of the different types of abstract constructional patterns that these languages have grammaticized historically. June 19, 2006 RT/CFL/I 6 Many years It thus takes many years of daily interaction with mature language users for children to attain adult-like skills. This is a longer period of learning with more things to be learned – by many orders of magnitude – than is required of any other species on the planet. June 19, 2006 RT/CFL/I 7 The Innateness Hypothesis Our ability to speak and understand a natural language results from – and is made possible by – a richly struc-tured and biologically determined capacity specific both to our species and to this domain. […] the language faculty is a part of human biology, tied up with the architecture of the human brain, and distinct in part from other cognitive faculties. June 19, 2006 P. 216 in S. R. Anderson and D. Lightfoot (2002): RT/CFL/I The Language Organ. Linguistics as Cognitive Physiology.8 The Language Organ The path of development which we observe suggests that the growth of language results from a specific in-nate capacity rather than emerging on a purely inductive basis from observation of the language around us. The mature system incorporates properties that could not have been learned from observation or any plausibly available teaching. Anderson & Lightfoot (2002: 2) June 19, 2006 RT/CFL/I 9 Arguments for the Innateness Hypothesis Speed of Acquisition Language is acquired in a remarkably short period, which would not be possible if humans did not have an innate language faculty. Poverty of Data The grammar acquired by children is much more complex than one should expect on the basis of the language data the children is exposed to from people around them. Language Universals Languages resemble each other in structural features that are not necessary properties of a language. These universal structural properties must be explained on the basis of June 19, 2006 RT/CFL/I 10 innate knowledge. Arguments against innateness I Speed of Acquisition In order to assess this argument, we need to know what it means to acquire language in «a remarkably short period», and this information has never been supplied. Poverty of Data This statement about the poverty of data, which was done years before anyone had done serious research on the nature of the speech addressed to children, has not been supported by later research. Language Universals The number of language universals is not that impressive, and not large enough to justify the postulation of an innate language faculty. Geoffrey Sampson (2005): The ‘Language Instinct’ Debate. June 19, 2006 RT/CFL/I 11 Arguments against innateness II Speed of Acquisition It thus takes many years of daily interaction with mature language users for children to attain adult-like skills. This is a longer period of learning with more things to be learned – by many orders of magnitude – than is required of any other species on the planet. Poverty of Data The principles and structures whose existence it is difficult to explain without universal grammar (such Chomskian things as the subjacency constraints, the empty category principle, and the binding principles) are theory-internal affairs and simply do not exist in usage-based theories of language. Language Universals Virtually all linguists … involved in the detailed analysis of individual languages cross-linguistically … agree that there are very few … specific grammatical categories and constructions … present in all languages. Michael Tomasello (2003): Constructing a Language. A Usage-Based Theory of Language Acquisition. June 19, 2006 RT/CFL/I 12 Language Universals Of course there are language universals. It is just that they are not universals of form – … not particular kinds of linguistic symbols or grammatical categories or syntactic constructions – but rather … universals of communication and cognition and human physiology. Because all languages are used by human beings with similar social lives, all peoples have the need to solve in their languages certain kinds of communicative tasks … Michael Tomasello (2003): Constructing a Language. June 19, 2006 RT/CFL/I 13 The Cognitive-Functionalist Linguists – Who are they? June 19, 2006 RT/CFL/I 14 Joan L. Bybee (1945–) An active and productive scholar, in particular within the fields of phonology, morphology, typology and psycholinguistics. Recently, she was elected President of the Linguistic Society of America. In 1985, her book Morphology: a study of the relation between meaning and form became a great source of inspiration for linguists at the University of Oslo, and her work contributed greatly to the establishment of a Cognitive Linguistics group there – a group that has steadily grown to become a meeting place for new students, research fellows and visiting scholars. June 19, 2006 RT/CFL/I 15 Ronald W. Langacker (1942–) Develops the central ideas of Cognitive Grammar in his two-volume Foundations of Cognitive Grammar (1987, 1991), which became a major departure point for the emerging field of Cognitive Linguistics. Cognitive Grammar treats human languages as consisting solely of semantic units, phonological units, and symbolic units (conventional pairings of phonological and semantic units). Cognitive Grammar extends the notion of symbolic units to the grammar of languages. Langacker further assumes that linguistic structures are motivated by general cognitive processes. June 19, 2006 RT/CFL/I 16 George P. Lakoff (1941–) The author of Moral Politics: How Liberals and Conservatives Think, 2nd Ed., (2002). He is also the author of Women, Fire, and Dangerous Things: What Categories Reveal About The Mind (1987) and co-author of Metaphors We Live By (1980), More Than Cool Reason (1989), Philosophy in the Flesh: The Embodied Mind and Its Challenge To The Western Tradition (1999), Where Mathematics Comes From: How the Embodied Mind Brings Mathematics Into Being (2000) and, most recently, Don't Think of an Elephant: Know Your Values, Frame the Debate (2004). June 19, 2006 RT/CFL/I 17 Leonard Talmy A professor of linguistics and philosophy at the University at Buffalo in New York. In Toward a Cognitive Semantics (2000), Talmy basically defines the field of cognitive semantics. He approaches the question of how language organizes conceptual material both at a general level and by analyzing a crucial set of particular conceptual domains: space and time, motion and location, causation and force interaction, and attention and viewpoint. Talmy maintains that these are among the most fundamental parameters by which language structures conception. June 19, 2006 RT/CFL/I 18 Adele E. Goldberg Professor of Linguistics at Princeton University. Her research interests include argument structure, constructionist approaches to language, language acquisition, categorization, and the role of information structure in syntax. Books: Constructions: A Construction Grammar Approach to Argument Structure (1995); Constructions at Work. The Nature of Generalization in Language (2006). June 19, 2006 RT/CFL/I 19 William Croft William Croft is a professor of linguistics at the University of New Mexico, from January 2006; earlier at the University of Manchester. Books: Cognitive Linguistics (2004) with D. A. Cruse; Radical Construction Grammar: Syntactic theory in typological perspective (2001); Explaining Language Change (2001); Typology and Universals, 2nd ed. (2003; 1st ed. 1990); June 19, 2006 RT/CFL/I 20 Cognitive-Functional Linguistics – What’s that? 1. 2. 3. 4. The Cognitive Commitment The Generalization Commitment The Functionalist Commitment The Embodied Mind June 19, 2006 RT/CFL/I 21 1. The Cognitive Commitment Language and linguistic organization should reflect general cognitive principles. Principles of linguistic structure should reflect what is known about human cognition from other disciplines Accordingly, cognitive linguistics rejects the modular theory of mind. June 19, 2006 RT/CFL/I 22 The Modular Theory of Mind The human mind is organized into distinct ‘encapsulated’ modules of knowledge. One of these is the language module. Linguistic structure and organization are markedly distinct from other aspects of cognition. June 19, 2006 RT/CFL/I 23 2. The Generalization Commitment Identify common structural principles that hold across phonology, semantics, pragmatics, morphology, syntax, and other aspects of language. Language is not divided into separate modules. June 19, 2006 RT/CFL/I 24 The Modular Theory of Language Language is divided into distinct subsystems or modules – e.g. the phonology module, the syntax module, and the semantics module. These modules are organized in significantly divergent ways, on the basis of different kinds of primitives. June 19, 2006 RT/CFL/I 25 3. The Functional Commitment The Usage-Based Thesis: Language structure emerges from language use. Language use is integral to our knowledge of language, our ‘mental grammar’. The distinction between competence and performance is rejected. June 19, 2006 RT/CFL/I 26 Competence and Performance Competence: Knowledge of language. Performance: Use of language. Competence determines performance. Performance does not influence competence. Performance can be affected by language-external factors – tiredness, distraction, intoxication – and often fails to adequately reflect competence. June 19, 2006 RT/CFL/I 27 The Cognitive Commitment and its Implications for a Linguistic Theory Principles of linguistic structure should reflect what is known about human cognition from other disciplines. Central aspects of this knowledge about human cognition is represented by six basic psychological terms – presented on the following slides. June 19, 2006 RT/CFL/I 28 Six Basic Psychological Terms Entrenchment (innprenting) Abstraction (abstraksjon) Comparison (samanlikning) Composition (komposisjon) Association (assosiasjon) Embodiment (kroppsleggjering) June 19, 2006 RT/CFL/I 29 ENTRENCHMENT NORWEGIAN: INNPRENTING The occurrence of psychological events leaves some kind of trace that facilitates their reoccurrence. Through repetition, even a highly complex event can coalesce into a well-rehearsed routine that is easily elicited and reliably executed. It equals “routinization”, “automatization” and “habit formation”. June 19, 2006 RT/CFL/I 30 Entrenchment: Unit NORWEGIAN: EINING When a complex structure comes to be manipulated as a “pre-packaged” assembly, no longer requiring conscious attention to its parts or their arrangement, it has the status of a unit. Examples: Writing your signature Shifting gear Saying How do you do? June 19, 2006 RT/CFL/I 31 ABSTRACTION The emergence of a structure through reinforcement of the commonality inherent in multiple experiences. By its very nature, this abstractive process ”filters out” those facets of the individual experiences which do not recur. June 19, 2006 RT/CFL/I 32 Abstraction: Schematization NORWEGIAN: SKJEMATISERING Schematization is a special case of abstraction. It involves our capacity to operate at varying levels of ”granularity” or ”resolution”. June 19, 2006 RT/CFL/I 33 An Example of Schematization The visual image of a person seen at a distance versus The visual image of a person seen close up June 19, 2006 RT/CFL/I 34 Another Example of Schematization A buffalo herd versus individual buffalos June 19, 2006 RT/CFL/I 35 Other Examples of Schematization The structure of a sonnet versus the structure of an individual sonnet. The meaning of animal versus the meaning of dog. A consonant versus [p]. June 19, 2006 RT/CFL/I 36 Abstraction: Schema and Instance A schema is an ‘abstract’ or ‘coarsegrained’ representation vis-à-vis its more fully specified instances. The instances elaborate the schema in contrasting ways. A solid arrow represents the relationship between a schema and an instance: A → B means ‘B instantiates / elaborates A’ June 19, 2006 RT/CFL/I 37 Schema and Instances First example SCHEMA Animal INSTANCE Dog June 19, 2006 INSTANCE Cat RT/CFL/I INSTANCE Cow 38 Schema and Instances Second example SCHEMA Vowel INSTANCE [i] June 19, 2006 INSTANCE [a] RT/CFL/I INSTANCE [u] 39 COMPARISON Fundamental to cognition is the ability to compare two structures and detect any discrepancy between them. Comparison involves an inherent asymmetry: one structure functions as a standard of comparison, the other as its target. June 19, 2006 RT/CFL/I 40 Comparison (by Americans) Standard: USA Target: Turkey The standard is familiar and well entrenched The target is unfamiliar June 19, 2006 RT/CFL/I 41 Comparison: Categorization Categorization is a special case of comparison: the standard represents an established unit and the target (at least originally) is novel. When there is no discrepancy between standard and target, there is an instantiation relationship between them: A → B. When there is a discrepancy between them, there is an extension relationship between them: A⇢ B. June 19, 2006 RT/CFL/I 42 Categorization: Trees oak oak instantiation oak birch extension June 19, 2006 RT/CFL/I 43 Categorization: Face Recognition Suzanne Kemmer as a good instance of Suzanne Kemmer. June 19, 2006 Suzanne Kemmer as a poor instance of Sydney Lamb. RT/CFL/I 44 COMPOSITION The combination of simpler structures to yield a more complex structure. It involves the integration of two or more component structures to form a composite structure. June 19, 2006 RT/CFL/I 45 The Buddhist Monk 佛 June 19, 2006 A Buddhist Monk begins at dawn one day walking up a mountain, reaches the top at sunset, meditates at the top for several days until one dawn when he begins to walk back to the foot of the mountain, which he reaches at sunset. Make no assumptions about his starting or stopping or about his pace during his trip. Riddle: Is there a place on the path that the monk occupies at the same hour of the day on the two separate journeys? RT/CFL/I 46 Arthur Koestler This is the amazing riddle that Arthur Koestler presents in The Act of Creation. […] Imagine that the monk is taking both ways on the same day. There must be a place where he meets himself, and that place is the one we are looking for. Its existence solves the riddle. Fauconnier & Turner (2002): The Way We Think. June 19, 2006 RT/CFL/I 47 ASSOCIATION The well-known phenomenon in which one kind of experience is able to evoke another. The smell of bananas always reminds me of my week in hospital in 1952. I always had bananas on my night table. June 19, 2006 RT/CFL/I 48 Association The particular kind of association that concerns us is symbolization: The association of conceptualization with the mental representations of observable entities such us sounds, gestures, and written marks. June 19, 2006 RT/CFL/I 49 Association: The Symbolic Unit An established symbolic relationship – a symbolic unit – is conveniently given as [ [ A ] / [ a ] ], where upper and lower case stand respectively for a conceptualization and a symbolizing structure. The slash ( / ) stands for the symbolization relationship. June 19, 2006 RT/CFL/I 50 The Bipolar Symbolic Structure [ [ TREE ] / [tɹiː] ] A symbolic structure is bipolar. The conceptualization is the semantic pole. The symbolizing structure is the pole. RT/CFL/I June phonological 19, 2006 51 EMBODIMENT NORWEGIAN: LEKAMLEGGJERING, KROPPSLEGGJERING Experience is embodied: We have a species-specific view of the world due to the unique nature of our physical bodies. In other words, our construal of reality is likely to be mediated in large measure by the nature of our bodies. The human mind – and therefore language – cannot be investigated in isolation from human embodiment. June 19, 2006 RT/CFL/I 52 Mind/Body Dualism Since René Descartes (1596– 1650) developed the idea that mind and body are distinct entities, there has been a common assumption within philo-sophy that the mind can be studied without recourse to the body, and hence without recourse to embodiment. June 19, 2006 RT/CFL/I 53 The Rationalist Approach In modern linguistics this rationalist approach has been most evident in formal approaches such as the Generative Grammar developed by Noam Chomsky (1928–) and formal approaches to semantics, such as the framework developed by Richard Montague (1930– 1971). It is argued that language can be studied as a formal system, without taking into account the nature of June 19, 2006 bodies RT/CFL/I human or human experience. 54 Embodiment: Image Schemas NORWEGIAN: BILETSKJEMA [image: (mentalt) bilete] One way in which embodied experience manifests itself at the cognitive level is in terms of image schemas: ”A recurring dynamic pattern of our perceptual interactions and motor programs that gives coherence to our experience”. (M. Johnson 1987: xiv.) June 19, 2006 RT/CFL/I 55 Image Schemas Human bodily movement, manipulation of objects, and perceptual interactions involve recurring patterns without which our experience would be chaotic and incomprehensible. I call these patterns ‘image schemas’, because they function primarily as abstract structures of images. Johnson (1987: xix) June 19, 2006 RT/CFL/I 56 More on image schemas IMAGE The term ‘image’ is equivalent to the use of this term in psychology, where imagistic experience relates to and derives from our experience of the external world. Another term for this type of experience is sensory experience. June 19, 2006 SCHEMA The term ‘schema’ tells us that image schemas are not rich or detailed concepts, but rather abstract concepts consisting of patterns emerging from repeated instances of embodied experience. RT/CFL/I 57 A Selective List of Image Schemas ‘Most of the more important’ (Johnson 1987: 126) CONTAINER BALANCE COMPULSION BLOCKAGE COUNTERFORCE RESTRAINT REMOVAL ENABLEMENT ATTRACTION MASS-COUNT PATH LINK CENTRE-PERIPHERY CYCLE NEAR-FAR SCALE PART-WHOLE MERGING SPLITTING FULL-EMPTY MATCHING SUPERPOSITION ITERATION CONTACT PROCESS SURFACE OBJECT COLLECTION June 19, 2006 RT/CFL/I 58 CFL – Basic Tenets End of Part I June 19, 2006 RT/CFL/I 59