Decision Making choice… maximizing utility framing effects Value • Round 1: Raise your hand if your middle name starts with the letter ‘M’ • Congratulations, you just won! • You are entitled to one of our prizes: – Prize A: $15 – Prize B: $ 10 • Which one do you choose? – Duh! – Prize A value > Price B value Expected value • Round 2: choose prize first • Winners will be decided based on the last digit of their SSN: – Prize C: $15 • if your SSN digit matches the number that comes out • for example, if ‘7’ comes out and your SSN ends in ‘7’ – Prize D: $ 10 • if your SSN digit is in the selected category (larger/smaller than 5) • For example, if ‘7’ comes out, and your SSN ends in ‘5’, ‘6’, 7, 8 or 9 • Which one do you choose to play? Please make your selection... 1. C 2. D 89% D C 11% Expected value • Obviously, you chose prize D. Why? • Expected value: – Prize C = $15 x .1 = $1.5 – Price D = $10 x .5 = $5.0 – EV = Value x Probability Expected Utility How desirable a bet is depends on: - Expected value (size of Payout x Probability ) - How much an individual values that payout (Saving a tree, $, etc.) - This provides a single scale for the goodness of any particular choice Utility: how happy or satisfied something makes you (how desirable something is) Utility theory: A Normative Theory of Choice • Describes how people should make decisions • In making a decision, you should: - Assess how worthy each outcome is to you (subjective utility) Assess how likely each outcome is Compute the expected utility of each possible option Compare those expected utilities Select the choice with largest expected utility Example: should you buy a lottery ticket? --Largest powerball jackpot ever = $195,000,000 !! --Probability of winning the powerball 1 in 10,000,000,000. --The expected value: .00000000001 x 195,000,000 = 2 lousy cents. Should you buy a ticket? Only if it costs 2c or less. Utility theory: Criticism • There are several problems with Utility theory: – Probability outcomes are often unknown • What is the probability that he will say ‘yes’ if I ask him out? – It’s tricky to assess the expected utility of future outcomes • How happy would I be to have chosen ‘Nova? – Lots of evidence that people do not reason this way Please make your selection... Option A. Winning $40 with probability .80 Option B. Getting $30 for sure Certainty Effect: People tend to prefer sure gains (risk averse for gains) 80% 20% Eva: $40 x .8 = $32 EVb: $30 x 1 = $30 Option A. Winning $40 with probability .80 Option B. Getting $30 for sure Certainty Effect - People’s tendency to be influenced by the manner in which choices are presented or framed. A. Winning $40 with probability .80 B. Winning $30 with probability 1.00 if both probabilities are cut in half: Choice A. Winning $40 with probability .40 Choice B. Winning $30 with probability .50 people pick this people pick this Certainty Effect: People tend to prefer sure gains (risk averse for gains) Framing effects: Positive Frame Students in right side of class will answer: Imagine that the US is preparing for the outbreak of an unusual tropical disease, which is expected to kill 600 people. Two alternative programs to combat the disease have been proposed. The estimates of the program’s effects are as follows: Program A: 200 people will be saved. Program B: 1/3 chance that 600 people will be saved. 2/3 chance that 0 people will be saved. Right side of the class, please make your selection... 1. Program A 2. Program B 83% B ra m Pr og Pr og ra m A 17% Negative Frame Students in right side of class will answer Imagine that the US is preparing for the outbreak of an unusual tropical disease, which is expected to kill 600 people. Two alternative programs to combat the disease have been proposed. The estimates of the program’s effects are as follows: Program C: 400 people will die. Program D: 1/3 chance that 0 people will die 2/3 chance that 600 people will die. left side of the class, please make your selection... 1. Program A 2. Program B 63% B ra m Pr og Pr og ra m A 38% Positive Frame Program A: Negative Frame Program C: 200 people will be saved. Program B: 400 people will die. Program D: 1/3 chance that 600 people will be saved. 2/3 chance that 0 people will be saved. 1/3 chance that 0 people will die 2/3 chance that 600 people will die. 80 80 60 60 40 40 20 20 0 0 A B 72% of subjects pick Program A when the problem is framed in terms of “lives saved.” With the positive frame, subjects are “risk averse.” C D Only 20% of subjects pick Program C when the problem is framed in terms of “deaths.” With the negative frame, subjects become “risk takers.” Donating money & saving lives Value of life saving • Each life is worth the same Series1 1 2 3 4 5 number of lives saved 6 • How much money would you give to save • Rokia • To save people from the village where Rokia lives A Hypothetical Value Function losses } } Value gains - “The pain of a loss is greater than the pleasure of a gain.” - “ small loses hurt (proportionally more) than big losses” Cash or Credit?? $1.30/gal 5 cent discount for cash... gains Discount seems negligible, people use credit card. $1.25/gal 5 cent charge for credit... Surcharge is outrageous… people pay cash. losses Framing effects are everywhere… What’s better? A basketball player who makes 75% of his free-throws, or one who misses 25% or his free-throws? Justification Effects: Another Departure from Expected Value Theory Imagine that you are planning a vacation in a warm spot over spring break. You have two options…The travel brochure give only a limited amount of information about the two options. Given the information available, which vacation spot would you prefer? Spot A: average weather average beaches medium quality hotel medium temperature water Spot B: lots of sunshine gorgeous beaches and coral reefs ultra-modern hotel very cold water very strong winds Imagine that you are planning a vacation in a warm spot over spring break. You have two options…but you can no longer retain your reservation for both. The travel brochure give only a limited amount of information about the two options. Given the information available, which reservation do you decide to cancel? Spot A: average weather average beaches medium quality hotel medium temperature water Spot B: lots of sunshine gorgeous beaches and coral reefs ultra-modern hotel very cold water very strong winds option A option B prefer 33% 67% cancel 52% 48% total 85% 115% - Option B has features that allow subjects to justify a good or bad rating. - Thus, subjects decide by referendum on option B - How the question is framed, - emphasizes the (very) positive aspects of option B, or - emphasizes the (very) negative aspects of option B Justification Effects: Last presidential election Kerry: Moderate on gay marriage Moderate on taxes Moderate on health insurance Unknown on Irak Moderate on Foreign Affairs Moderately religious Mixed message on abortion (personally opposes but Won’t legislate against it) Bush: Strongly opposed to gay marriage Strong ideas on taxes Strong ideas on health insurance Strong position on Irak Strong unilateralism Fervent religious Strongly oppose to abortion - Election was a referendum on the president - Both campaigns target Bush and try to frame him to their advantage - negative frame: anti-civil liberties, regressive taxes, mesianic, anti-choice - positive frame: moral values,tax relief, religious, pro-life Justification: living with your decisions • People make choices that they can justify to themselves (thus reducing regret) • Even if those choices are sometimes irrational • One last example: – you passed the exam -> you buy ticket to Hawaii (to celebrate) – You failed the exam -> you buy ticket to Hawaii (to cheer yourself up) – You don’t know whether you passed or you failed • Logically, you should buy the ticket, but • People are reluctant in this situation (no justification?) Summary • Utility theory fails to describe how people make decisions: – Frame effects – Influence of justifications (minimize regret) Other issues • Difficulty predicting future values – Wilson and Gilbert (on happiness) • Peak and end assessment of pain • Happiness (California) (Kahneman 1999) • • • • The focusing effect (or focusing illusion) is a cognitive bias that occurs when people place too much importance on one aspect of an event, causing an error in accurately predicting the utility of a future outcome. People focus on notable differences, excluding those that are less conspicuous, when making predictions about happiness or convenience. For example, when people were asked how much happier they believe Californians are compared to Midwesterners, Californians and Midwesterners both said Californians must be considerably happier, when, in fact, there was no difference between the actual happiness rating of Californians and Midwesterners. The bias lies in that most people asked focused on and overweighed the sunny weather and ostensible easy-going lifestyle of California and devalued and underrated other aspects of life and determinants of happiness, such as low crime rates and safety from natural disasters like earthquakes (both of which large parts of California lack).[1] A rise in income has only a small and transient effect on happiness and wellbeing, but people consistently overestimate this effect. Kahneman et al. proposed that this is a result of a focusing illusion, with people focusing on conventional measures of achievement rather than on everyday routine • Prospect theory wikipedia Utility theory: Summary • Each decision has associated costs and benefits. • Costs and benefits are, to certain extent, subjective • Most decisions carry certain amount of uncertainty or risk (probability that the expected outcome will occur) • expected utility = subjective utility of a particular outcome * probability of the outcome • Ideal decision makers should maximize expected utility that is, they should choose so to maximize benefits, and minimize costs Calculating Expected Value (Expected Utility) P = probability of a particular outcome (ranges from 0 to 1) V = value of a particular outcome (the cost or benefit associated with the outcome) Expected Value = P x V If multiple outcomes are possible given a particular decision, then the expected value of all possible outcomes is added up. Calculating Expected Value Suppose you get to choose between two different games of chance: (1) Winning $40 with probability .20 or (2) Winning $30 with probability .25 Which is the better choice? Calculating Expected Value (1) Winning $40 with probability .20 The expected value of choice 1 is .2 x $40 = $8 (2) Winning $30 with probability .25 The expected value of choice 2 is .25 x $30 = $7.50 Choice 1 has the higher expected value. Another way to think about expected value is as “the average outcome over the long run.” “Better Than Wall Street” Door 1 - Door 2 One doors hides $1,000 The other hides $0. Alternatively, you can take $500 instead. What do you want to do? – Door 1 – Door 2 – Take $500 for sure “Better Than Wall Street” If you chose the $500: - How much would the potential prize have to be to make you reconsider? - Risk premium • Option E: A 1/80 chance of winning $80 • Option F: $ 1 for sure • EVoptionE = $80 x 1/80 = 1 • EVoptionF = $1 x 1 = 1