WNDI 2011 Ecofeminism K 1 ***ECOFEMINISM K*** ***ECOFEMINISM K*** ................................................................................................................................ 1 1NC ................................................................................................................................................................ 3 1NC (1/3) ................................................................................................................................................... 4 1NC (2/3) ................................................................................................................................................... 5 1NC (3/3) ................................................................................................................................................... 6 Links .............................................................................................................................................................. 7 Foreign Policy ............................................................................................................................................ 8 Hegemony ................................................................................................................................................. 9 Nuclear War ............................................................................................................................................ 10 Omission ................................................................................................................................................. 11 Post Modernism ...................................................................................................................................... 12 Science .................................................................................................................................................... 13 Science .................................................................................................................................................... 14 Sovereignty ............................................................................................................................................. 15 Space Exploration.................................................................................................................................... 16 Space Exploration.................................................................................................................................... 17 Space Tourism ......................................................................................................................................... 18 Treaties ................................................................................................................................................... 19 Impacts........................................................................................................................................................ 20 Borders .................................................................................................................................................... 21 Oppression .............................................................................................................................................. 22 Environment ........................................................................................................................................... 23 Colonialism .............................................................................................................................................. 24 Racism ..................................................................................................................................................... 25 Hidden Violence ...................................................................................................................................... 26 Outweighs ............................................................................................................................................... 27 Alternative .................................................................................................................................................. 28 Ecofeminism Key ..................................................................................................................................... 29 Ecofeminism Key ..................................................................................................................................... 30 Ecofeminism Key ..................................................................................................................................... 31 Ecofeminism Key ..................................................................................................................................... 32 WNDI 2011 Ecofeminism K 2 Ecofeminism Key ..................................................................................................................................... 33 Ecofeminism Key ..................................................................................................................................... 34 Ecofeminism Key ..................................................................................................................................... 36 Feminism Key .......................................................................................................................................... 37 Narratives................................................................................................................................................ 38 Narratives................................................................................................................................................ 39 Narratives................................................................................................................................................ 40 Answers ....................................................................................................................................................... 41 Framework .............................................................................................................................................. 42 Framework .............................................................................................................................................. 43 Framework .............................................................................................................................................. 44 Framework .............................................................................................................................................. 46 Framework .............................................................................................................................................. 47 Framework .............................................................................................................................................. 48 Framework .............................................................................................................................................. 49 Perm ........................................................................................................................................................ 50 Perm ........................................................................................................................................................ 51 Perm ........................................................................................................................................................ 52 Perm ........................................................................................................................................................ 53 Essentialism............................................................................................................................................. 54 Essentialism............................................................................................................................................. 55 Essentialism............................................................................................................................................. 56 Essentialism............................................................................................................................................. 58 Essentialism............................................................................................................................................. 59 A2: You don’t go far enough ................................................................................................................... 61 A2: You prioritize nature ......................................................................................................................... 62 WNDI 2011 Ecofeminism K 3 1NC WNDI 2011 Ecofeminism K 4 1NC (1/3) Space exploration prioritizes masculinity over femininity Joseph & Lewis, 86 [Gloria I. & Jill. Common Differences: Conflicts in Black and White Feminist Perspectives, 1986. Pg. 131-132.] American society in reality never made family survival a priority. The priorities were private and corporate interests, not the daily-life needs of people surviving on the wages for their labor. Industrial production and technological development produced outer space exploration and a multi-billion-dollar nuclear armament industry and military complex in a society where millions have little or no access to adequate health care and the infant mortality rate is still shockingly high. The institutional framework and the organization of daily life into polarized areas of paid labor versus family nurturance and survival, along with ideas of competition, possessiveness, and individualism, placed "the family" in the crossfire of exploitation, authority, and power. Images and notions of femininity (embodying fragility, dependency, obedience, and passivity) versus masculinity (embodying strength, authority, autonomy, and activity) flowered in and around the daily reality of most women's lives, which both confirmed and contradicted them. Sdf WNDI 2011 Ecofeminism K 5 1NC (2/3) Domination of nature justifies the domination of others based on race, class, and gender because it strips subjectivity Plumwood, 93 [Val: Australian Research Council Fellow at the Australian National University. Feminism and the Mastery of Nature. Pg. 4] Thus it is also exclusion from the master category of reason which in liberation struggles provides and explains the conceptual links between different categories of domination, and links the domination of humans to the domination of nature. The category of nature is a field of multiple exclusion and control, not only of nonhumans, but of various groups of humans and aspects of human life which are cast as nature. Thus racism, colonialism and sexism have drawn their conceptual strength from casting sexual, racial and ethnic difference as closer to the animal and the body construed as a sphere of inferiority, as a lesser form of humanity lacking the full measure of rationality or culture. As Vandana Shiva points out (1989, 1991). It Is not only women's labour which traditionally gets subsumed 'by definition' into nature, but the labour of colonised non-western, non-white people also. The connections between these forms of domination in the west are thus partly the result of chance and of specific historical evolution, and partly formed from a necessity inherent in the dynamic and logic of domination between self and other, reason and nature. To be defined as 'nature' in this context is to be defined as passive, as non-agent and non-subject, as the 'environment' or invisible background conditions against which the 'foreground' achievements of reason or culture (provided typically by the white, western, male expert or entrepreneur) take place. It is to be defined as a terra nullius, a resource empty of its own purposes or meanings, and hence available to be annexed for the purposes of those supposedly identified with reason or intellect, and to be conceived and moulded in relation to these purposes. It means being seen as part of a sharply separate, even alien lower realm, whose domination is simply 'natural', flowing from nature itself and the nature(s) of things. Such treatment, standard in the west for nature since at least the Enlightenment, has since that time been opposed and officially condemned for humans (while all the while normalised for marginalised groups such as women and the colonised). WNDI 2011 Ecofeminism K 6 1NC (3/3) Alternative: Reject the 1AC in favor of ecofeminism Must reevaulate humanity within feminism or else an infrastructure of domination will always reappear Plumwood, 93 [Val: Australian Research Council Fellow at the Australian National University. Feminism and the Mastery of Nature. Pg. 22-23] The framework of assumptions in which the human/nature contrast has been formed in the west is one not only of feminine connectedness with and passivity towards nature, but also and complementarity one of exclusion and domination of the sphere "of nature by a white, largely male elite, which I shall call the master model. But the assumptions in the master model are not seen as such, because this model is taken for granted as simply a human model, while the feminine is seen as a deviation from it. Hence to simply repudiate the old tradition of feminine connection with nature, and to put nothing in its place, usually amounts to the implicit endorsing of an alternative master model of the human, and of human relations to nature, and to female absorption into this model. It does not yield, as it might seem to do at first, a gender-neutral position; unless the question of relation to nature is explicitly put up for consideration and renegotiation, it is already settled—and settled in an unsatisfactory way—by the dominant western model of humanity into which women will be fitted. This is a model of domination and transcendence of nature, in which freedom and virtue are construed in terms of control over, and distance from, the sphere of nature, necessity and the feminine. The critique of the domination of nature developed by environmental thinkers in the last twenty years has shown, I think, that there are excellent reasons to be critical of this model of human/nature relations. Unless there is some critical re-evaluation of this master model in the area of relations to nature, the old female/nature connection will be replaced by the dominant model of human distance from and transcendence and control of nature. Critical examination of the question then has to have an important place on the feminist agenda if this highly problematic model of the human and of human relations to nature is not to triumph by default. If the model of what it is to be human involves the exclusion of the feminine, then only a shallow feminism could rest content with affirming the 'full humanity of women without challenging this model. WNDI 2011 Ecofeminism K 7 Links WNDI 2011 Ecofeminism K 8 Foreign Policy US foreign policy is militarized and masculine Enloe, 04 [Cynthia: professor at Clark University, The Curious Feminist: Searching for Women in a New Age of Empire, p. 122-124] The militarization of any country’s foreign policy can be measured by monitoring the extent to which its policy: is influenced by the views of Defense Department decisionmakers and / or senior military officers, flows from civilian officials’ own presumption that the military needs to carry exceptional weight, assigns the military a leading role in implementing the nation’s foreign policy, and treats military security and national security as if they were synonymous. Employing these criteria, one has to conclude that U.S. foreign policy today is militarized. A feminist analysis can help reveal why U.S. foreign policy has become so militarized— and at what costs. Since 1980, due to the growth of the women’s movement, it has become almost commonplace in many domestic U.S. policy circles to ask: “Will this proposed solution have disproportionately negative impacts on girls and women?” and “Does this policy option derive from unspoken assumptions about men’s employment, men’s health, or men’s supposed abilities?” Notable strides have been made in domestic policy arenas, even if there is still a long way to go before such intelligent questioning produces equally smart policy outcomes. By contrast, in foreign policy, progress toward a more sophisticated— realistic— understanding of the causes and costs of policy options has been sluggish. In the 1970s and 1980s women activists and feminist analysis did help drive popular protests against U.S. wars in Southeast Asia and Central America. Yet, generally, U.S. foreign policy has been tightly controlled by the president and Congress, limiting a genuinely public debate. Stalling progress toward bringing feminist analyses into foreign policy decision-making processes has been the conventionally naive belief that international affairs— trade, immigration, hightech weapons sales— have nothing to do with gender. They do. Feminist foreign policy analysis is not naive. It derives from a systematic, eyes-wide-open curiosity, posing questions that nonfeminists too often imagine are irrelevant or find awkward to ask. For starters: Are any of the key actors motivated in part by a desire to appear “manly” in the eyes of their own principal allies or adversaries? What are the consequences? Which policy’s option will bring women to the negotiating table? Does the alleged reasonableness of any foreign policy choice rest on the unexamined assumption that women’s issues in the target country can be addressed “later,” that it is men’s anxieties that must be dealt with immediately? WNDI 2011 Ecofeminism K 9 Hegemony Hegemony rests upon negation/patriarchy. Awareness of negation key to overcoming hierarchic structure of hegemony Agnew & Corbridge, 95 [John & Stuart. Mastering Space: Hegemony, Territory and International Political Economy, 1995. Pg. 212-213] Metaphorically, Hegel’s model of lordship and bondage is the frame of reference in which conventional understandings of international political economy operate. But it is not the essential equality of the selves that has received most attention. Rather, it has been the assumed naturalness of an enduring hierarchy. In a world of competitive states, or a competitive world economy a ‘singular’ appropriation of power and wealth is taken as a natural feature of a world in which individual states/persons/firms objectify everything that they see as other, and where they view other states/persons/firms as little more than obstacles in their path.There is a point of connection here between this conception of the mastering of others-elsewhere implicit in the logics of previous geopolitical discourse and practice and a feminist reading of Hegel’s dialectic. From this point of view, to accept the unchanging polarity of man and woman in the lordship-bondage relation is to succumb to a structure of male domination. Hegemony can be seen as resting in both cases as much upon negation as upon positive recognition for its dynamic force. And, ‘The more negation can be inscribed in silence, the more binding it will be, for the explicit denigration of women [or others] constitutes an act of naming that permits differing views about the strength of the tie between name and thing, between sign and referent’ (Fox-Genovese 1991, 237). Awareness of this negation, therefore, is the first step out of the polarity upon which coercive hierarchy relies for its material and discursive power. WNDI 2011 Ecofeminism K 10 Nuclear War Fear of threats to existence such as nuclear war justify oppression of women and land Collard '89 [Andree: Professor at Brandeis University. Rape of the Wild. Pg. 46] However my purpose is not to understand hunters but to situate hunting in the culture that spawned it. Hunting is the modus operandi of patriarchal societies on all levels of life – to support one level is to support them all. However innocuous the language may sound – we hunt everything from houses to jobs to heads – it reveals a cultural mentality so accustomed to predation that it horrifies only when it threatens to kill us all, as in the case of nuclear weapons. Underlying all this hunting is a mechanism that identifies/names the prey, stalks it, competes for it, and is intent on getting the first shot at it. This is blatantly done when the prey is named woman, 34 animal, or land but it extends to whatever phobia happens to seize and obsess a nation, whether this be another nation or a race other than that of power holding groups. WNDI 2011 Ecofeminism K 11 Omission Leaving animals out of discussions of violence undermines anti-violence agendas Deckha ‘10 (Maneesha: Associate Professor at the University of Victoria Faculty of Law. “It’s time to abandon the idea of ‘human’ rights,” The Scavenger, December 13, 2010.) Yet, the discourse around (hu)man violence against animals is muted in mainstream debates about violence, vulnerability and exploitation in general. More common is a concern with violence against humans and how to eliminate it and make humans less vulnerable. This theorizing largely proceeds through affirmations of the inviolability or sanctity of human life and human dignity, establishing what it means to be human through articulation of what it means to be animal. The humanist paradigm of anti-violence discourse thus does not typically examine the human/nonhuman boundary, but often fortifies it. The failure to address this boundary and its creation and maintenance of the figure of the subhuman undermines anti-violence agendas. WNDI 2011 Ecofeminism K 12 Post Modernism Postmodernism dissolves accountability and autonomy of feminism Webster, 00 [Fiona: Co-editor of Asia-Pacific Review. “The Politics of Sex and Gender: Benhabib and Butler Debate Subjectivity,” Hypatia, 15.1, 2000.] Benhabib claims that the critique of identity categories raised by postmodern theory gives rise to an "identity crisis" for feminism. She is by no means alone in making such a claim. 2 She argues that this identity crisis "may eliminate not only the specificity of feminist theory but place in question the very emancipatory ideals of the women's movement altogether" (Benhabib 1995a, 20). Her argument is based on the claim that, in its strong form, postmodern theory promotes a dissolution of the subject which in turn dissolves the concepts of intentionality, accountability, self-reflexivity and autonomy (1995a, 20). Postmodern theory has debilitating implications for feminism precisely because the ideal of the autonomous, self-directing subject is replaced with a fractured, opaque self (1992, 16). Given that women's sense of self is already fragile, that their history has been written by others and that they have not been able to fully control their lives, Benhabib claims that this fractured, opaque self of postmodern theory can only provide women with a more fragmented and fragile vision of themselves and their future (1992, 16). As such, it is a particularly damaging account of subjectivity and one which does not further the emancipatory objectives of the feminist movement. The norms of autonomy, choice, and self-determination in the legal, moral, and political arenas are vital, Benhabib claims, for women's struggles to be successfully voiced and acted upon (1992, 16). Indeed, she claims that the project of female emancipation is unthinkable without recourse to a regulative principle on agency, autonomy, and selfhood (1995a, 21). WNDI 2011 Ecofeminism K 13 Science Science comes from a standpoint regardless of how much you can claim otherwise. This pushed women into a categorization that allows them to be the target of masculine violence. Harding, 04 [Sandra: an American philosopher of feminist and postcolonial theory, epistemology, research methodology and philosophy of science. Hypatia vol. 19, no. 1, 29-32] The women’s movement needed knowledge that was for women. Women had long been the object of others’ knowledge projects. Yet the research disciplines and public policy that depended upon them permitted no conceptual frameworks in which women as a group became the subjects or authors of knowledge; the implied “speakers” of scientific sentences were never women.7 Such subjects were supposed to be generic humans, which meant men, or even, as Donna Haraway famously put the point, God: science was to perform the “God trick” of speaking authoritatively about everything in the world from no particular social location or human perspective at all (Haraway 1989). Yet feminists pointed out how the conceptual frameworks of the disciplines and of public policy never achieved such a transcultural perspective; they clearly represented easily identifiable social interests and concerns, and these were rarely women’s. Worse, these conceptual frameworks often represented interests counter to those of women. This particular kind of cultural specificity ensured systematic ignorance and error not only about women’s lives but also about men’s lives, in all their diversity, and about how any particular society’s gender relations worked. In the dominant accounts it remained mysterious through which processes women’s life choices became so restricted, albeit in different ways in different classes, races, sexualities, cultures, and historical eras. How did it come about that violence against women in every class and race in modern Western societies—usually committed by men from within their own social groups that women were supposed to be able to trust—was persistently interpreted by legal systems as women “asking for it” and “deviant men” doing it? How did it occur that a double day of work, one unpaid, was regarded as normal and desirable for women but not for men? How come women who were going through such expectable biological life-events as menstruation, birthing, or menopause were treated by the medical profession as if they were ill? What social processes made reasonable the belief that women made no contributions to human evolution? WNDI 2011 Ecofeminism K 14 Science Science has subjective elements Talshir, 04 [Gayil. “The role of environmentalism: From The Silent Spring to The Silent Revolution,” Liberal Democracy and Environmentalism: The End of Environmentalism?” Marcel Wissenburg & Yoram Levy, 2004. Pg. 14-15] This attitude, nevertheless, ignores the fact that scientific knowledge is contested and that in order for environmental problems to be addressed politically they have to compete with other issues on the limited public agenda, economic resources and political concerns. Thus, the nature of environmental issues is different from that of other social subjects, but ecological problems inevitably become subjected to representation. Unfortunately, environmental changes could hardly be noticed without scientific research on the one hand, and political awareness on the other. While ecological problems have an ontological dimension, the epistemology of ecology is crucial for grasping these problems and handling them. The politicization process of environmental problems, despite the naive call for realism, begins in the science of ecology. WNDI 2011 Ecofeminism K 15 Sovereignty Nature exists as bare life under sovereignty Hudson ‘8 (Laura. “The Political Animal: Species-Being and Bare Life,” Mediations, 23.2, Spring 2008.) The rise of environmentalism, deep ecology, and animal rights can be seen as effects of this inability of law, or the Law, to distance the “natural world” as a state outside itself. Natural objects reappear within the political realm not as political actors but as markers of bare life. Sovereignty, in seeking to establish a political life separate from the state of nature, produces both political life as the life proper to the citizen (the “good life”) and bare life, which occupies a space in between bios and zoē, evacuated of meaning. The state of nature is not separate from political life but a state that exists alongside political life, as a necessary corollary of its existence. Political life is alienation from an imagined state of nature that we cannot access as human beings because it appears only in shadow form as bare life. The state of exception is that which defines which lives lack value, which lives can be killed without being either murdered or sacrificed. Agamben’s examples of the inextricable link between political and bare life focus on the limit cases of humanity rather than the ideal, providing an analysis of precisely the cases that prove problematic in Ferry’s liberal humanism. The exception, as that which proves the rule, cannot be avoided. It is necessary to look to the figure of the refugee, the body of the “overcomatose” or the severely mentally impaired, and, under the Third Reich, the life of the Jew to see how the law fails in the task Ferry sets for it. These cases demonstrate the zone of indistinction that Agamben elaborates as the zone of “life that does not deserve to live.” The refugee demonstrates the necessity of a link between nation and subject; refugees are no longer citizens and, as such, lack a claim to political rights: “In the system of the nation-state, the so-called sacred and inalienable rights of man show themselves to lack every protection and reality at the moment in which they can no longer take the form of rights belonging to citizens of a state.”15 Confronted with the figure of the refugee, human rights are faced with their hidden ground in national origin, where, as Agamben notes, the key term is birth: men are born free, invoking the natural codes from which law was to separate us. This freedom is, in actuality, a function of citizenship and incorporation in the nation-state rather than a fact of being human: “citizenship names the new status of life as origin and ground of sovereignty and, therefore, literally identifies … les membres du souverain, ‘the members of the sovereign.’”16 This makes the link between that which is proper to the nation and that which is proper to the citizen the determinant of the zone of sacred life: those who do not fulfill the role of the citizen are no longer guaranteed protection or participation in political life, their so-called human rights void in the absence of national identity. The refugee or refugees as a group have a claim only to bare life, to being kept alive, but have no political voice with which to demand the rights of the citizen. Agamben, while noting the same trend toward politicizing natural life that concerns Ferry, demonstrates that this politicization is already contained within the structure of politics itself. This corresponds to the position of animals in human society: the exemplar of the limit case, they have always existed in the state of exception that founds the political. There is thus a connection between the plight of the refugee and that of the animal: neither participates directly in the political, though both are absolutely subject to political decisions in which they have no voice. The establishment of a realm outside the political, where lives have no value and thus may be killed, is marked by the difference between the human and the animal. WNDI 2011 Ecofeminism K 16 Space Exploration Space exploration reflects a mentality of violence and domination Collard '89 [Andree: Professor at Brandeis University. Rape of the Wild. Pg. 39-40] The solution, then, is to make ‘the best’ of a bad situation. Lorenz suggests ‘dangerous undertakings, like polar expeditions and, above all, the exploration of space’ in which nations could fight each other in hard and dangerous competition without engendering national or political hatred’. 22 Such solutions reflect the mentality of violence and domination that are so much a part of a rapist culture. They are instances of rape of the wild where nature again is objectified, probed, used, and brought under control of man’s futile attempt to redirect his ‘aggression’ to ‘better’ ends. Of course, these theorists do not consider such attempts as futile. They construe what is actually violence as progress, and continued violation of the integrity of being as achievement. In this sense, ethologist Richard Dawkins believes that ‘modern man’ has outgrown his prehistoric past and has the ability to modify not only his environment but his genetically programmed behavior. 23 Now that ‘we’ have acquired enough knowledge of ourselves, ‘we’ can control those destructive traits that brought us to the brink of extinction. And yet, looking at the direction of science, reading about men’s futuristic visions, we see more and more control exercised by fewer and fewer individuals over the many, through cybernetics, mood and ‘achievements’, together with the nuclear and chemical threats to the environment, the robotisation of work, the desensitization to life, the chemicalisation of foodstuffs, the proliferation of iatrogenic diseases, the extinction of animals and plant species, the increasing rigidity of the political structure, the impoverishment of imaginative life – all give reason to think that if this represents the optimum in human evolution, the hunters who are shaping are insane. WNDI 2011 Ecofeminism K 17 Space Exploration Expansion without reflecting upon the relationship between environmental destruction, technology and speciesism will inevitably result in the problems that cause us to need to get off the rock, and we’ll destroy those planets too. Kochi & Ordan, 08 [Tarik: Queen’s University; Noam: Bar Ilan University. “An Argument for the Global Suicide of Humanity,” borderlands, 7.3, 2008.] In 2006 on an Internet forum called Yahoo! Answers a question was posted which read: “In a world that is in chaos politically, socially and environmentally, how can the human race sustain another 100 years?” The question was asked by prominent physicist Stephen Hawking (Hawking, 2007a). While Hawking claimed not to know ‘the solution’ he did suggest something of an answer (Hawking, 2007b). For Hawking the only way for the human race to survive in the future is to develop the technologies that would allow humans to colonise other planets in space beyond our own solar system. While Hawking’s claim walks a path often trodden by science fiction, his suggestion is not untypical of the way humans have historically responded to social, material and environmental pressures and crises. By coupling an imagination of a new world or a better place with the production and harnessing of new technologies, humans have for a long time left old habitats and have created a home in others. The history of our species, homo sapiens, is marked by population movement aided by technological innovation: when life becomes too precarious in one habitat, members of the species take a risk and move to a new one. Along with his call for us to go forward and colonise other planets, Hawking does list a number of the human actions which have made this seem necessary. [1] What is at issue, however, is his failure to reflect upon the relationship between environmental destruction, scientific faith in the powers of technology and the attitude of speciesism. That is, it must be asked whether population movement really is the answer. After all, Hawking’s suggestion to colonise other planets does little to address the central problem of human action which has destroyed, and continues to destroy, our habitat on the earth. While the notion of cosmic colonisation places faith in the saviour of humanity by technology as a solution, it lacks a crucial moment of reflection upon the manner in which human action and human technology has been and continues to be profoundly destructive. Indeed, the colonisation of other planets would in no way solve the problem of environmental destruction; rather, it would merely introduce this problem into a new habitat. The destruction of one planetary habitat is enough – we should not naively endorse the future destruction of others. Hawking’s approach to environmental catastrophe is an example of a certain modern faith in technological and social progress. One version of such an approach goes as follows: As our knowledge of the world and ourselves increases humans are able to create forms of technology and social organisation that act upon the world and change it for our benefit. However, just as there are many theories of ‘progress’ [2] there are also many modes of reflection upon the role of human action and its relationship to negative or destructive consequences. The version of progress enunciated in Hawking’s story of cosmic colonisation presents a view whereby the solution to the negative consequences of technological action is to create new forms of technology, new forms of action. New action and innovation solve the dilemmas and consequences of previous action. Indeed, the very act of moving away, or rather evacuating, an ecologically devastated Earth is an example at hand. Such an approach involves a moment of reflection – previous errors and consequences are examined and taken into account and efforts are made to make things better. The idea of a better future informs reflection, technological innovation and action. WNDI 2011 Ecofeminism K 18 Space Tourism Tourism assumes a gaze and mobility – must be reflexive to standpoint Phillimore & Goodson, 04 [Jenny & Lisa. “From Ontology, Epistemology and Methodology to the Field Reference,” Qualitative Reasearch in Tourism: Ontologies, Epistemologies and Methodologies, 2004. Pg 127] Indeed there is a sense in which both mobility and sight are deemed to be prerequisites for engaging with tourism as conventionally constructed by the leisure and tourism industry and leisure and tourism studies. This emphasis on mobility to sites and ability to see sights is evident in the research of many leisure and tourism scholars. Urry, for example, has focused on 'touring cultures' and the 'tourist gaze' signifying the importance of sight and mobility within tourism. It is clear that tourism studies and tourism research can benefit from engaging with the sorts of debates initiated through and by standpoint epistemologies. To do so would require tourism studies and research to look through varied different standpoint 'spectacles' (that is, take 'post'-standpoint perspectives) at phenomena under examination. The tourism researcher examining the impact of tourism on particular destinations would benefit considerably from asking pertinent questions about the lived experiences of local marginalised or minority groups, their environment and how they interrelate. 5 This suggests that tourism researchers need to engage minority groups collaboratively in their research and to take a reflexive approach to their research, critically reflecting upon their own gender identities, ethnicity, nationality, and so forth. WNDI 2011 Ecofeminism K 19 Treaties Treaties become a masculine contest in order to appear manly within their own culture Enloe, 04 [Cynthia: professor at Clark University, The Curious Feminist: Searching for Women in a New Age of Empire, p. 122-124] However, when Defense Department officials have weighed in on a given policy question, Congress and the administration have shied away from feminist analyses. Consequently, the U.S. government either has invested energy in watering down new international treaties designed to roll back militarism, or has refused outright to ratify such agreements as, for instance, the treaty to ban land mines, the UN convention acknowledging the rights of children in war, and the treaty establishing the International Criminal Court (the first permanent international war crimes tribunal). In each instance, it has been the Pentagon’s ability to persuade civilian officials that the military’s own goals would be compromised— its desire to maintain land mines in South Korea, its desire to recruit those under age eighteen, and its prioritizing the protection of American soldiers stationed abroad when they are charged with criminal acts— that has carried the day in Washington. Civilian representatives’ repeated privileging of military concerns over other important U.S. international goals is due in part to the nervousness that many male civilian executive and congressional officeholders feel when confronted with military resistance. This is not about hormones. It is about the male politician’s angst over not appearing “manly.” This, in turn, is about American political culture. WNDI 2011 Ecofeminism K 20 Impacts WNDI 2011 Ecofeminism K 21 Borders Control over ecological resources create a history that determines control over land Goldman & Schurman, 00 [Michael and Rachel A: Professors at University of Minnesota. "Closing the 'Great Divide': New Social Theory on Society and Nature. Annual Review of Sociology, Vol. 26. p. 569] Along the first of these lines, Rocheleau and Ross (1995) analyze the roles of trees as “tools and text.” They show how different social groups in the Dominican Republic utilized the Acacia tree, as well as ideas about Acacia trees, in their efforts to establish claims to land and other productive resources. Similarly, Donald Moore’s (1996) work on environmental struggles in Zimbabwe emphasizes the symbolic aspects of peasant land claims. Drawing on Antonio Gramsci and Raymond Williams, Moore contends that symbolic struggles effect material transformation, and that “cultural meanings are constitutive forces, that is, shapers of history, and not simply reflections of a material base” Moore, pg. 127). A number of scholars have interrogated the gendered nature of struggles over meaning (e.g. Carney 1996, Bassett 1999, Rocheleau &Ross 1995), showing, for instance, how men and women mobilize differing cultural understandings to justify their claims over particular resources. The inspiration for many of these analyses of ideology, symbolism, and the cultural construction of meaning was Nancy Peluso’s (1992) pioneering study of the struggle between the Indonesian State and forest dwellers over the Indonesian teak forests. Building on the works of E.P. Thompson and James Scott on Cultures of resistance, Peluso shows how the Indonesian State sought to maintain control of the forests through a certain conception of property rights and an ideology of criminality, and how forest dwellers challenged those conceptions by engaging in “criminal behavior” and developing a counterdiscourse on what is a fair, legal, and legitimate use of the forest. WNDI 2011 Ecofeminism K 22 Oppression Domination over nature justifies exploitation Birke, 94 [Linda: Biologist and Women's Studies Professor @ University of Warwick. Feminism, Animals and Science: The Naming of the Shrew. Pg. 11] Another area in which we might make more connections between our theorizing about science and other politics and social movements concerns environmental issues, and there has been a surge of interest in ecofeminism in recent years. How western culture constructs its relationship to nature is, as many critics have argued, deeply problematic. It focuses on notions of dominance over and exploitation of nature that are causing widespread environmental havoc (Shiva 1989; Cox 1993). ‘Nature’ in this context of dominance is partly non-human nature – the other species of animals, the plants, the microorganisms, the geological structures of our earth – but it is also significantly much of humanity. Western imperialism and global exploitation assumes that it can appropriate nature’s resources without significant consequence; those resources may be other peoples, or they may be directly affected by western destruction of their local environment. It is in that vein, that, for example, the Women’s Environmental Network in Britain has investigated the chocolate industry, which not only destroys the environment but also has repercussions on human lives. WNDI 2011 Ecofeminism K 23 Environment Patriarchial Domination is the Cause for Environmental Domination Mack-Canty, 04 (Colleen, NSWA Journal, Volume: 16 No. 3, Fall, Pg 171, AMC) Feminists who take the historical and causal approach to explain the interconnected subjugations of women, other suppressed people, and nature, suggest that the ubiquitousness of androcentrism with its accompanying phenomenon, the patriarchal domination of women and nature, is the source of environmental degradation. Riane Eisler (1988) and Carolyn Merchant (1980) are examples of feminists who present varying accounts of this approach. They explain how and approximately when societies that previously had been living essentially in concord with nature and with each other became subjugated by patriarchal domination. Societies, in these accounts, then become disharmonious in their relationships. WNDI 2011 Ecofeminism K 24 Colonialism Speciesism justifies colonialism more than racism Kochi & Ordan ‘8 (Tarik: Queen’s University; Noam: Bar Ilan University. “An Argument for the Global Suicide of Humanity,” borderlands, 7.3, 2008.) One dominant presumption that underlies many modern scientific and political attitudes towards technology and creative human action is that of ‘speciesism’, which can itself be called a ‘human-centric’ view or attitude. The term ‘speciesism’, coined by psychologist Richard D. Ryder and later elaborated into a comprehensive ethics by Peter Singer (1975), refers to the attitude by which humans value their species above both non-human animals and plant life. Quite typically humans conceive non-human animals and plant life as something which might simply be used for their benefit. Indeed, this conception can be traced back to, among others, Augustine (1998, p.33). While many modern, ‘enlightened’ humans generally abhor racism, believe in the equality of all humans, condemn slavery and find cannibalism and human sacrifice repugnant, many still think and act in ways that are profoundly ‘speciesist’. Most individuals may not even be conscious that they hold such an attitude, or many would simply assume that their attitude falls within the ‘natural order of things’. Such an attitude thus resides deeply within modern human ethical customs and rationales and plays a profound role in the way in which humans interact with their environment. The possibility of the destruction of our habitable environment on earth through global warming and Hawking’s suggestion that we respond by colonising other planets forces us to ask a serious question about how we value human life in relation to our environment. The use of the term ‘colonisation’ is significant here as it draws to mind the recent history of the colonisation of much of the globe by white, European peoples. Such actions were often justified by valuing European civilisation higher than civilisations of non-white peoples, especially that of indigenous peoples. For scholars such as Edward Said (1978), however, the practice of colonialism is intimately bound up with racism. That is, colonisation is often justified, legitimated and driven by a view in which the right to possess territory and govern human life is grounded upon an assumption of racial superiority. If we were to colonise other planets, what form of ‘racism’ would underlie our actions? What higher value would we place upon human life, upon the human race, at the expense of other forms of life which would justify our taking over a new habitat and altering it to suit our prosperity and desired living conditions? WNDI 2011 Ecofeminism K 25 Racism Species thinking creates racial demarcations. The reason violence happens after the othering process is because people are dehumanized Deckha ‘10 (Maneesha: Associate Professor at the University of Victoria Faculty of Law. “It’s time to abandon the idea of ‘human’ rights,” The Scavenger, December 13, 2010.) One of her primary arguments is that race thinking, which she defines as “the denial of a common bond of humanity between people of European descent and those who are not”, is “a defining feature of the world order” today as in the past. In other words, it is the “species thinking” that helps to create the racial demarcation. As Razack notes with respect to the specific logic infusing the camps, they “are not simply contemporary excesses born of the west’s current quest for security, but instead represent a more ominous, permanent arrangement of who is and is not a part of the human community”. Once placed outside the “human” zone by race thinking, the detainees may be handled lawlessly and thus with violence that is legitimated at all times. Racialization is not enough and does not complete their Othering experience. Rather, they must be dehumanized for the larger public to accept the violence against them and the increasing “culture of exception” which sustains these human bodily exclusions . Although nonhumans are not the focus of Razack’s work, the centrality of the subhuman to the logic of the camps and racial and sexual violence contained therein is also clearly illustrated in her specific examples. In the course of her analysis, to determine the import of race thinking in enabling violence, Razack quotes a newspaper story that describes the background mentality of Private Lynndie England, the white female soldier made notorious by images of her holding onto imprisoned and naked Iraqi men with a leash around their necks. The story itself quotes a resident from England’s hometown who says the following about the sensibilities of individuals from their town: To the country boys here, if you’re a different nationality, a different race, you’re sub-human. That’s the way that girls like Lynndie England are raised. Tormenting Iraqis, in her mind, would be no different from shooting a turkey. Every season here you’re hunting something. Over there they’re hunting Iraqis. Razack extracts this quote to illustrate how “race overdetermined what went on”, but it may also be observed that species “overdetermined what went on”. Race has a formative function, to be sure, but it works in conjunction with species difference to enable the violence at Abu Ghraib and other camps. Dehumanization promotes racialization, which further entrenches both identities. It is an intertwined logic of race, sex, culture and species that lays the foundation for the violence. WNDI 2011 Ecofeminism K 26 Hidden Violence Violence against nature is hidden in order to make it acceptable Deckha ‘10 [Maneesha: Associate Professor at the University of Victoria Faculty of Law. “It’s time to abandon the idea of ‘human’ rights,” The Scavenger, December 13, 2010.] According to Richard Bulliet, professor of history at Columbia University, part of what characterizes postdomestic society in the United States is the invisibility of violence against animals. Contrary to the seemingly insatiable appetite for animal blood sports several centuries ago, postdomestic sensibilities against this type of bloodletting have become the norm due to an aversion to viewing animal slaughter despite the acceptance of slaughterhouses and the knowledge of the hidden and routine violence against animals that occurs there. Postdomestic societies brutalize animals, but hide the brutality. Thus, anti-cruelty laws cover these blood sports today, but not much else beyond basic sustenance and shelter. “Cruelty” typically only extends to protection from “unnecessary” suffering and excludes all forms of current or “postdomestic” institutionalized violence against animals. It is not that postdomestic societies are any less violent than predomestic ones. Rather, only the “excessive” violence against animals, i.e., that which is not related to any culturally mainstream profitable or recreational practice, is outlawed while a multiplicity of institutional violence venues are kept hidden or filtered from full view. This approach to animal “protection” is compatible within a legal regime that classifies all nonhuman beings as property rather than persons and is premised on a species divide that is foundational for western cultures in general. Statutes outlawing cruelty co-exist with the slaughterhouse. It is a mistake though to assume that the slaughterhouse is an “animal rights” issue of no consequence to humans beyond the working conditions for the slaughterhouse workers. WNDI 2011 Ecofeminism K 27 Outweighs The most pervasive kind of violence is violence against nature Deckha ‘10 [Maneesha: Associate Professor at the University of Victoria Faculty of Law. “It’s time to abandon the idea of ‘human’ rights,” The Scavenger, December 13, 2010.] One of the most violent places imaginable is the modern day slaughterhouse. The rate of killing inside is swift and of unprecedented proportions. In the United States alone, around 9.5 billion animals are killed per year. To put that in perspective, that amounts to 250 cows per hour and 266 chickens per second. This figure does not account for all slaughter of animals for food in the United States, merely the extent of killing of land farm animals. The overwhelming number are born, raised, and killed for consumption making the violence against farm animals the most pervasive form of institutionalized violence against animals. These statistics also fail to capture the suffering animals endure while in the slaughterhouse, where they are raised for slaughter. Violence against animals is central to how we perform violence against each other Deckha ‘10 [Maneesha: Associate Professor at the University of Victoria Faculty of Law. “It’s time to abandon the idea of ‘human’ rights,” The Scavenger, December 13, 2010.] While the intersection of race and gender is often acknowledged in understanding the etiology of justificatory narratives for war, the presence of species distinctions and the importance of the subhuman are less appreciated. Yet, the race (and gender) thinking that animates Razack’s argument in normalizing violence for detainees (and others) is also centrally sustained by the subhuman figure. As Charles Patterson notes with respect to multiple forms of exploitation: Throughout the history of our ascent to dominance as the master species, our victimization of animals has served as the model and foundation for our victimization of each other. The study of human history reveals the pattern: first, humans exploit and slaughter animals; then, they treat other people like animas and do the same to them. Patterson emphasizes how the human/animal hierarchy and our ideas about animals and animality are foundational for intra-human hierarchies and the violence they promote. The routine violence against beings designated subhuman serves as both a justification and blueprint for violence against humans. For example, in discussing the specific dynamics of the Nazi camps, Patterson further notes how techniques to make the killing of detainees resemble the slaughter of animals were deliberately implemented in order to make the killing seem more palatable and benign. That the detainees were made naked and kept crowded in the gas chambers facilitated their animalization and, in turn, their death at the hands of other humans who were already culturally familiar and comfortable with killing animals in this way. WNDI 2011 Ecofeminism K 28 Alternative WNDI 2011 Ecofeminism K 29 Ecofeminism Key The only way to overcome competition over scarce resources is ecofeminism Gaard, 93 [Greta Claire: Associate Professor of Humanities, Fairhaven College at Western Washington University. Ecofeminism: Women, Animals, Nature. Pg. 2-3] It is now common knowledge that rights-based ethics (most characteristic of dominant-culture men, although women may share this view as well) evolve from a sense of self as separate, existing within a society of individuals who must be protected from each other in competing for scarce resources. In contrast, Gilligan describes a different approach, more common to women, in which "the moral problem arises from conflicting responsibilities rather than from competing rights and requires for its resolution a mode of thinking that is contextual and narrative rather than formal and abstract. This conception of morality as concerned with the activity of care centers moral development around the understanding of responsibility and relationships, just as the conception of morality as fairness ties moral development to the understanding of rights and rules." 4 Similarly, Karen Warren's "Toward an Ecofeminist Ethic" describes eight boundary conditions of a feminist ethic; that is, conditions within which ethical decision making may be seen as feminist. These conditions include coherence within a given historical and conceptual framework, an understanding of feminism as striving to end all systems of oppression, a pluralistic structure, and an inclusive and contextual framework that values and emphasizes humans in relationships, denies abstract individualism, and provides a guide to action. The analyses of Gilligan and Warren indicate that ecofeminism, which asserts the fundamental interconnectedness of all life, offers an appropriate foundation for an ecological ethical theory for women and men who do not operate on the basis of a self/other disjunction. WNDI 2011 Ecofeminism K 30 Ecofeminism Key Any attempt at liberation requires investigation into oppression of women and nature Gaard, 93 [Greta Claire: Associate Professor of Humanities, Fairhaven College at Western Washington University. Ecofeminism: Women, Animals, Nature. Pg. 1-2] Ecofeminism is a theory that has evolved from various fields of feminist inquiry and activism: peace movements, labor movements, women's health care, and the anti-nuclear, environmental, and animal liberation movements. Drawing on the insights of ecology, feminism, and socialism, ecofeminism's basic premise is that the ideology which authorizes oppressions such as those based on race, class, gender, sexuality, physical abilities, and species is the same ideology which sanctions the oppression of nature. Ecofeminism calls for an end to all oppressions, arguing that no attempt to liberate women for any other oppressed group will be successful without an equal attempt to liberate nature. Its theoretical base is a sense of self most commonly expressed by women and various other nondominant groups - a self that is interconnected with all life. In their analyses of oppression, socialists, animal liberationists, ecologists, and feminists each distinguish between privileged and oppressed groups, where the privileged are upper- or middle-class, human, technologically and industrially "developed," male, and the oppressed are poor or working-class, nonhuman animal, "undeveloped" nature, and female, respectively. Ecofeminism describes the framework that authorizes these forms of oppression as patriarchy, an ideology whose fundamental self/ other distinction is based on a sense of self that is separate, atomistic. WNDI 2011 Ecofeminism K 31 Ecofeminism Key Feminism recognizes the privilege of the scientization of society and its objectification of women and nature Goldman & Schurman, 00 [Michael and Rachel A: Professors at University of Minnesota. "Closing the 'Great Divide': New Social Theory on Society and Nature. Annual Review of Sociology, Vol. 26p. 571572] Some find the origins of universalized oppression of women and nature rooted in the Enlightenment and the (Western) scientization of society, with its consequent objectification of nature as the formal object of dispassionate (read: male, scientific) inquiry (Merchant 1980, 1992; Shiva 1989; Mies & Shiva 1993). Others are less convinced by this macrostructural rigidity, yet maintain a strong critique of dominant scientific practices and related oppressive effects for objects of science, such as nature, and for subjects excluded from the scientific professions, such as (until recently) women (Haraway 1991, 1997b; Martin 1994; Ginsburg & Rapp 1995; Downey & Dumit 1997). Nonetheless, the shared project of destabilizing common myths around what is nature, culture, and biology, is yielding some of the most fruitful scholarly work in social theory today. Two substantive areas stand out: gender and the environment, particularly in developing countries; and biotechnology and the politics of the body (human and nonhuman). These areas overlap and cross-pollinate intellectually, with scholars borrowing from and contributing to each other’s work. Through multiple lenses, feminists walk the tightrope of explicating what biological/ecological traits are meaningful for whom, and which are used as weapons. For example, an assumed promise of late capitalism is that we humans all have the potential of transcending the biological limits of nature: to produce food without soil, prolong human life with techno-surrogate body parts, and consume more than the earth can sustain. Environmental feminists recognize that the promise of limitless consumption exists, but only for the most privileged, for whom “[the] limits are borne by others, including the earth itself” (Mellor 1997, p. 190). They contend that biology does matter and, moreover, that it is a contested zone in which constructed gender, race, class, nationality, and species differences have significant consequences. In contrast to the notion of transcendence, which underlies Enlightenment thought on society’s relationship to nature, environmental feminists theorize social-natural relations in terms of ecological embeddedness and biological embodiment(Mellor 1997, Salleh 1997). This alternative perspective is associated with the idea of immanence, or a reflexive awareness of one’s position in nature. WNDI 2011 Ecofeminism K 32 Ecofeminism Key Ecofeminism’s deconstructive methods key to solve psychotic avoidance of sexism Gaard, 93 [Greta Claire: Associate Professor of Humanities, Fairhaven College at Western Washington University. Ecofeminism: Women, Animals, Nature. Pg. 42-43] Radical environmentalists find much common ground with regard to the sort of societies they would like to live in. However, ecofeminism. Differs from Manstream theory when it comes to strategy, or how to get there. The Liberalist and Leftist (non-Marxist) approaches in green thought call for changing people's values through reason, education and/or spirituality in order to bring about social change but deny the significance of sex and gender in personal motivation. Put more emphatically by Sharon Doubiago: "Because of sexism, because of the psychotic avoidance of the issue at all costs, ecologists have failed to grasp the fact that at the core of our suicidal mission is the psychological issue of gender, the oldest war, the war of the sexes." S1 A strategy based on denial is insufficient to achieve social change. Ecofeminist strategy, in contrast, suggests that a deconstructive process is also necessary. Ecofeminists would defuse the ideological and psychological pressures upon the masculine ego that fuel the abuse of power. Manstream green strategy, on the other hand, often fails to deal with problems of politics-as-usual, liberalism, mysticism, identification, power seeking and sexism, and co-optation. In the discussion below, I focus on the Liberalist position, but some points apply to Leftists as well. Again, "Liberalist" refers to strategies for social change that begin from the individual - it is not to be confused with liberal ideology. History proves that domination is not inevitable. Feminism solves conflict. Kheel, 08 (Marti: writer and activist in the areas of animal liberation, environmental ethics and ecofeminism. Nature Ethics: An Ecofeminist Perspective. Pg. 209) One goal of placing the exploitation of women and nature in historical context is to provide a basis of hope for change in existing attitudes. If domination has historical roots, the argument for its inevitability is called into question. Ecofeminists thus delve beneath surface actions and ideas to challenge the prevailing assumptions about human nature that underlie modern Western society. While most theorists in the modern Western ethical tradition presume the inevitability of egoistic impulses and then offer abstract principles and constructs to control them, for many ecofeminists the overridingethical question is, rather, how and why compassion and moral conduct toward nature have failed to be sustained. Philosopher Alison Jaggar speculates on what would occur if liberals were to rethink their assumptions about human nature: “Instead of community and cooperation being taken as phenomena whose existence and even possibility is puzzling, and sometimes even regarded as impossible, the existence of egoism, competitiveness and conflict would themselves become puzzling and problematic.”5 WNDI 2011 Ecofeminism K 33 Ecofeminism Key Only ecofeminism takes the extra step to relinquish “inherent” human power over nature Gaard, 93 [Greta Claire: Associate Professor of Humanities, Fairhaven College at Western Washington University. Ecofeminism: Women, Animals, Nature. Pg. 133-134] Seen in this light, ecofeminism, rather than being a poor relation of the feminist and ecology movements, is a synthesis, the sibling connection between that which is fundamental to both movements. The ideology of ecofeminism demands opposition to domination in all its forms,20 and a rejection of the notion that any part of the world, human or nonhuman, exists solely for the use and pleasure of any other part. This is a deceptively simple-sounding assertion; but if you contemplate it for a moment, you will realize that it has the entire weight of the Western cultural tradition against it. Until the last two decades, even the most radical environmentalists accepted the idea of human superiority over nature; they urged only that we be responsible, that we not abuse our rights to shape nature to human ends.31 Ecofeminism goes further, and relinquishes all claims to inherent human powerover.32 Problems of nature and humanity must be considered by feminists because it intersects with other forms of oppression Plumwood, 93 [Val: Australian Research Council Fellow at the Australian National University. Feminism and the Mastery of Nature. Pg. 26] The key concepts of rationality (or mentality) and nature then create crucial links between the human and the masculine, so that to problematise masculinity and rationality is at the same time to problematise the human and, with it, the relation of the human to the contrasted non-human sphere. As we shall see, however, these concepts also form links to other areas of exclusion, for it is not just any kind of masculinity which is usually involved here, but a particular kind which is formed in the context of class and race as well as gender domination (which I have called the master model). The western rationalist ideals of the human embody norms not only of gender exclusion but of race, class and species exclusion. The view that women’s humanity is unproblematic mistakenly takes the concept of the human to be unproblematic and fails to observe these biases and exclusions. This connection is then another reason why the issue of the traditional connection of women and nature cannot simply be ignored, why the problems raised must be considered by feminists. WNDI 2011 Ecofeminism K 34 Ecofeminism Key Ecology can only prevail under a feminist framework because of its recognition of interconnectedness of oppression Plumwood, 93 (Val: Australian Research Council Fellow at the Australian National University. Feminism and the Mastery of Nature. Pg. 17) If social ecology fails to reconcile the critiques because it cannot understand that human relations to non-humans are as political as human relations to other humans, deep ecology as articulated here also suppresses the potential for an adequate political understanding of its theme of human/nature domination, although it achieves this suppression of the political by a different route. Thus dominant forms of deep ecology choose for their core concept of analysis the notion of identification, understood as an individual psychic act rather than a political practice, yielding a theory which emphasises personal transformation and ignores social structure. The dominant account is both individualist_(failing to provide a framework for change which can look beyond the individual) and psychologistic (neglecting factors beyond psychology). A similarly apolitical understanding is given to its core concept of ecological selfhood; here the account, while drawing extensive connections with various eastern religious positions, seems to go out of its way to ignore the substantial links which could fruitfully be made with feminist accounts of the self and with feminist theory (Warren 1990; Cheney1987; 19 89). :The result, as largue -in chapters 6 and 7, is a psychology .of - . : .••• incorporation, not a psychology, of mutuality. Fox suggests that selfishness in the form of excessive personal attachment, which he conflates with psychological egoism, is the fundamental cause of 'possessiyeness, greed, exploitation, war and ecological destruction' (Fox 1990:262). An analysis which exhorts us to consider nature by transcending the egoism of personal attachment matches in its depth of political insight the sort of social analysis which exhorts us to resolve problems of social inequality through acts of individual unselfishness. Such an analysis also uncritically assumes an account of personal attachment as antithetical to moral life which has increasingly and deservingly come under attack recently, especially from feminists (chapter 7). This form of deep ecology makes a good religious or spiritual garnish for a main political recipe which eschews radical critique and treats green politics in terms of a warmed-over 'green' liberalism. Deep ecology, like social ecology, fails in its current form to present a coherent liberatory perspective (Elkins 1989). Given these points it seems that both deep ecology and social ecology, as they are currently articulated, are unsuitable for providing the basis for an adequate green theory. Social ecology stresses environmental problems as social problems, arising from the domination of human by human, but has little sensitivity to the domination of nonhuman nature, while deep ecology has chosen a theoretical base which allows its connection with various religious and personal change traditions but blocks its connection to the critiques of human oppression. It seems then that an ecologically orientated feminism is the most promising current candidate for providing a theoretical base adequate to encompass and integrate the liberatory concerns of the green movement. The domination of women is of course central to the feminist understanding of domination, but is also a well-theorised model which can illuminate many other kinds of domination, since the oppressed are often both feminized and naturalized. The ecological feminism of writers such as Rosemary Radford Ruether has always stressed the links between the domination of women, of other human groups and of nature.10 ‘An ecological ethic’, she writes, ‘must always be an ethic of ecojustice that recognizes the interconnection of social domination and the domination of nature’ (1989: 149). WNDI 2011 Ecofeminism K 35 Ecological feminism provides an excellent framework for the exploration of such interconnections. I attempt her to provide some of the philosophical basis for such an account. WNDI 2011 Ecofeminism K 36 Ecofeminism Key Ecofeminism is more accessible than other kinds of feminism Alaimo, 94 [Stacy. “Cyborg and Ecofeminist Interventions: Challenges for an Environmental Feminism. Feminist Studies,20.1, 1994.] The social organization, communicative actions, and "personality" of animals makes blurring boundaries between people and animals much easier than crossing the broader human-nature divide.23 How should an ecologically conscious feminism engage nature? Ecofeminism, as Carolyn Merchant explains, valorizes both women and nature: "The radical form of ecofeminism is a response to the perception that women and nature have been mutually associated and devalued in western culture and that both can be elevated and liberated through direct political action."24 Parallel to the way Luce Irigaray reverses the values of traditional femalemale oppositions, ecofeminism recognizes that women and nature have long been linked in Western systems of thought, and instead of trying to break the ties that many would argue keep women oppressed, ecofeminists reaffirm them in order to fight for both women and nature. They accept the ideological terrain, complete with its Victorian throwbacks of woman as nurturer. Even when ecofeminists strive toward a nonessentialist connection between women and nature, they still describe women primarily as mothers and homemakers: "Women who are responsible for their children's well-being are often more mindful of the long-term costs of quick-fix solutions. Through the social experience of caretaking and nurturing, women become attentive to the signs of distress in their communities that might threaten their households."25 Despite its shortcomings from a poststructuralist feminist perspective, ecofeminism would seem a productive oppositional discourse for contemporary U.S. culture. In Ynestra King's words (paraphrased by Judith Plant), it is a "strand of feminist thought that, indeed, was not interested in an equal share of the same old carcinogenic pie."26 Ecofeminism's conception of ordinary "female" activities and experiences as the basis of planet saving could attract women who feel left behind by what they perceive as a feminist movement that is only concerned with women achieving "successful careers." The potential for ecofeminism to attract women who define themselves in traditional roles could benefit both the environmental and feminist movements. WNDI 2011 Ecofeminism K 37 Feminism Key We shouldn’t put up with the oppression of women. The negative supports a more violent form of politics to keep women in place. As long as these hierarchies remain unquestioned politics is useless. Need to prioritize the oppressed in discussions Ellison ’96 [Marvin Mahan. Erotic Justice: A Liberating Ethic of Sexuality, 1996. Pg. 9-10] An ethic of sexuality must realistically assess what poor women, women of color, and other disenfranchised people are up against in this culture. The fact that many women "put up with" abuse and degradation tells us volumes, if we can hear, not about any purported female desperation to seek "love" at any cost, but rather about the devastating absence of justice and well-being in most women's lives and in the lives of their children. Those lacking social power stay in dehumanizing, often lifethreatening situations not because of personal inadequacies but because there are few, if any, social alternatives that justify taking the risks of leaving an abusive but familiar situation, especially because men typically escalate their violence to keep "their" women in place. 9 Liberalism's moral guidance about sex and family life will never be useful if it leaves unquestioned the power hierarchies of husband over wife, parent over child, white over black, able-bodied over disabled, and so forth, or if it naturalizes these relationships as beneficial to all parties. "The best theorizing about justice," feminist philosopher Susan Moller Okin writes, "is not some abstract 'view from nowhere,' but proceeds from the carefully attentive consideration of everyone's point of view."10 The strength of Okin's statement is that she insists that moral reason is concretely situated, but her claim, as it stands, is not strong enough to make a real difference in a stratified, conflicted world of power inequities. From a postliberal perspective, theorizing about sexual injustice must proceed by listening to and giving priority to those who are subjected to sexual oppression and who manage against all odds to resist its indignities. Listening can become justicebearing only as the conversation is recentered and democratized. The voices of socially powerful, privileged people need to be heard, but their voices must no longer monopolize the discussion. Moral traditions can correct past distortions and become more humanizing, but only if we pay special attention to the voices and moral wisdom of women, gay/lesbian/bisexual people, survivors of sexual violence, and others without social status and power. By incorporating these voices from the margins, the liberal theological tradition can also be transformed. Perspectives from "the underside" enrich the ethical analysis, as well as stretch the vision of the moral good. The feminist and gay liberation movements, especially as they maintain a strong commitment to race and class diversity, are shaking the foundations by their insistence on a reordering of social power toward equality, including all sexual relations. Transformative moral wisdom emerges from the collective insights of social movements as they seek, over time, to reconstruct power dynamics and renew cultural traditions. Religious communities, whether they recognize it or not, are indebted to the feminist and womanist movements and to the gay/lesbian/bisexual liberation movement for keeping alive a vision of justice within personal life. The impetus for rethinking the sexual system is coming not from established insiders but from social justice movements on the margins. WNDI 2011 Ecofeminism K 38 Narratives Narratives provide alternative forms of knowledge for ecofeminism Gaard, 93 [Greta Claire: Associate Professor.of Humanities, Fairhaven College at Western Washington University. Ecofeminism: Women, Animals, Nature. Pg. 129-130] Many ecofeminists therefore find greater satisfaction in stories of the past that acknowledge the intangible, the magical. And many of us want more from history than a cautionary reminder of what we already know. We want inspiration and alternative ways of knowing. For that reason we sometimes turn to more admittedly conjectural histories than those which purport to portray the past "objectively", gleaning knowledge from reports of archeological findings, oral traditions, remnants of earlier cultures, intuitive readings of myth and ritual, and sheer speculation. Particularly popular in this respect are histories of matriarchal or matrifocal cultures in which women enjoyed positions of equality or superiority vis—vis men, and nature was seen as a collaborator or benefactor, not as a foe to conquer. 2s In the past ten years, there has been an abundance of work in this area, both scholarly and popular, and it seems to have attracted a wide following. Within the academy, such histories are of course suspect, since they rest heavily on icons portraying women and animals as deities or symbols of fertility and abundance, and tend to ignore the fact that female idolization/idealization seems quite able to coexist with actual low status (see the chapter by Stephanie Lahar in this volume). But this is no reason to dismiss them. All history is conjectural and subjective; complete pictures are virtually impossible. The value of speculative histories is that they offer a sense of possibility, a sense that what might have been might also yet be. And because they draw on myth and ritual, they offer models of consciousness that help us to create cosmologies and rituals for our own time. WNDI 2011 Ecofeminism K 39 Narratives Narratives create alternate histories for ecofeminism Vance, 95 [Linda. "Sexist Words, Speciesist Roots" Animals and Women: Feminist Theoretical Explorations by Carol J. Adams & Josephine Donovan, Pg. 176-177] Storytelling is by definition an act done in community. When I tell you, or my students, or my friends the story of the frog pond, or stories like it, I am engaging in a form of ethical discourse, modeling, as it were, my beliefs about human/nature relationships. Mv stories shape others' stories; their stories shape mine. Imagine, then, the power of conscious narrative, of myths and tales intentionally constructed and repeated that would inform and instruct us in "proper" attitudes toward nature. This is not so different from the type of storytelling that has emerged from feminism over the past twenty years. We have told each other our stories, have discerned the patterns that emerge from them, have chosen the patterns that seem best suited to a liberated future, and have repeated those again and again, with appropriate modifications and variations, until a relatively clear "feminist ethos" of caring, relationship, compassion, and attentiveness has been called into existence. It is no wonder, then, that ecofeminists would advocate a similar approach to the creation of a new environmental ethos. For Karen Warren, first-person narratives can "give voice to a felt sensitivity often lacking in traditional ethical discourse, namely, a sensitivity to conceiving of oneself as fundamentally 'in relationship with' others"; they can express "a variety of ethical attitudes and behaviors often overlooked or underplayed in mainstream Western ethics"; and thev can suggest "what counts as an appropriate solution to an ethical situation" ( 135 - 36J. These consciously chosen narratives, Jim Cheney suggests, rightfully extend out to include "not just the human community but also the land, one's community in a larger sense." What we want, he says, ; ...is language that grows out of experience and articulates it, language intermediate between self, culture, and world, their intersection, carrying knowledge of both, knowledge charged with valuation^and instruction. This is language in which, in Paul Shepard's.words, "the clues to the meaning of life [are] embodied in natural things, where everyday life [is] inextricable from spiritual significance and encounter." (Nature and the Theorizing of Difference, 9) WNDI 2011 Ecofeminism K 40 Narratives Stories about ecological limits solve Vance '95 [Linda. "Sexist Words, Speciesist Roots" Animals and Women: Feminist Theoretical Explorations by Carol J. Adams & Josephine Donovan. Pg. 179-180] Similarly, it is inappropriate to craft narratives that present the world as an unlimited storehouse of resources awaiting human use, or which posit human ingenuity as the single driving force behind change, or which, for that matter, extol the virtues of human manipulation of the natural world. The tale of human progress, whether strictly linear or dialectically unfolding, has outlived its usefulness, if indeed it ever had any. And while declensionist narratives may seem too overwhelming, too fatalistic, or too much a manipulative stage setting for salvation fantasies, it does us no good to avoid the unpleasant truth: there are ecological limits. So let's tell the stories of dammed and polluted rivers, disappeared ecosystems and species, plains and prairies and tundra ravaged by inappropriate agriculture and grazing, forests leveled for exports, the unnecessary slaughter of millions of animals. But at the same time, let's also tell the stories about how we could live in harmony with the rest of nature. Our narratives could remind us of the integrity and complexity of the natural world, and the need to embrace limits with joy and humility. They could be models of ecologically responsible and respectful interactions, both among animals and between humans and animals. They could inspire us to see beauty and feel delight in natural forces. None of these stories require that we ignore "the facts," or turn away from elements of the natural world that seem harsh or cruel, like predation, or starvation, or natural disaster, or competition. Our narratives about nature, about animals, about ourselves — all must ultimately be judged by their credibility; we must therefore tell stories that are as accurate as we can make them. WNDI 2011 Ecofeminism K 41 Answers WNDI 2011 Ecofeminism K 42 Framework Policy Making doesn’t change the minds of people because it doesn’t exist in a vacuum. Our approach avoids this “politics as usual” approach and is key to retooling politics outside of Patriarchy and Humanism Gaard, 93 [Greta Claire: Associate Professor of Humanities, Fairhaven College at Western Washington University. Ecofeminism: Women, Animals, Nature. Pg. 43-44] This Liberalist strategy contains vestiges of the dominant liberal political and economic paradigm that, it says, contributes to the environmental problem. Mainstream liberals assume that simply changing people's values will lead to different voting and behavior patterns. Their reasoning is this: values make people prefer certain lifestyle or political alternatives; therefore, political change can be achieved bv persuading others to adopt one's own beliefs. This logic is perfectly reasonable - but only in a vacuum unaffected by the media, corporate advertising, a liberal orthodoxy. Patriarchal social conditioning, linguistic patterns, and so on. This is because mainstream liberal philosophy is premised on an image of Man as an autonomous individual, separate from His context. Many Liberalist greens eschew liberalism, yet share its context-free logic, which does not acknowledge the full extent to which our mental processes and values are shaped by the superstructure and infrastructure of our social institutions. Thus, although many Manstream green writers are themselves political activists, the approach is essentially "politics as usual" because it relies ultimately on traditional pressure Politics and "numbers" for radical change. They are essentially only advocating public pressure for better goals and policies. However, corporate power is above governments and largely dictates who gets elected and what they do. The Liberalist strategy does not undermine the props or address the emotional "needs" of the powerful. There is a certain irony in a position that recognizes that the competitive global economic system creates environmental problems but then proposes a solution that is essentially market-based, reiving on consumers to change their values and lifestyles. This is analogous to approaching the drug problem by persuading people to "just say no," when we are dealing with something that is profitable precisely because it operates outside the market. The resource extraction and pollution industries do not pay the replacement costs of public resources. Like the illegal drug business, they are lucrative because they do not pay the real costs and they create markets. Likewise, the Green consumer/voter-based strategy encourages us to place a kind of moral responsibility on the victim, distracting attention from the profiteers. ^Although people demand goods, they do not, for example, demand that these goods be made with new toxic materials and processes that merely replace natural ones. People have not actually been given these kinds of choices. Recent events illustrate that educating consumers is less urgent than retooling our technocratic, political, and corporate decisionmaking arenas. Consumers would surely not object, for instance, if their creature comforts were provided via solar energy. In fact, public enthusiasm for recycling centers, environmentally friendly products, and recycled paper has outstripped the supply, yet recycling centers have had to close in Australia. Industry has not been buying the material simply because, in our distorted economy, live trees are cheaper than used ones. This phenomenon is a function of power relations that shape institutions, laws, and economic and planning methods, and only partly a function of chauvinism toward other animals. WNDI 2011 Ecofeminism K 43 Framework Policy-making leads to the destruction of the environment for the sake of economic growth Gaard, 93 [Greta Claire: Associate Professor of Humanities, Fairhaven College at Western Washington University. Ecofeminism: Women, Animals, Nature. Pg. 14] The other superficial ground for optimism is the burgeoning number of environmental professionals whose role is to advise government and industry. Environmental specialists are multiplying in all professions, and we now have “environmental” economists, scientists, administrators, lawyers, and planners promoting marginal reforms. The decision-making methodologies these professions use, however, are heavily influenced by concepts derived from the mainstream liberal paradigm and are biased against the preservation of species and ecosystems. For example, because they are geared to analyzing the costs and benefits of development alternatives, they balance off public needs to meet private wants over the long term. Even more fundamentally, an instrumentalist and anthropocentric ethic – whereby human and natural “resources” are construed to have value to the extent that they can be used for human purposes – is endemic to the technocratic methodologies, decision-making processes, and regulatory schemes. This ethic is a natural outgrowth of a “power complex” that is so deeply ingrained in the modern psyche that planners and decision makers who consider themselves environmentally aware continue to make decisions that facilitate the exponential destruction of the nonhuman environment by incremental trade-offs of environmental quality for economic growth. Feminist approaches expand debate in useful ways Simson ‘5 (Rosalind S. “Feminine Thinking” Social Theory and Practice. Vol 31. 2005) 2. Feminine Thinking, Knowledge, and Rationality The examples cited above are strong evidence that, contrary to the historically popular belief that feminine thinking is ill-suited to intellectual pursuits, feminine ways of thinking in fact expand the domain of rational thought and human knowledge beyond the bounds mapped out by masculine approaches. These examples, moreover, are but the tip of the iceberg. In the last fifteen or so years, feminine ways of thinking have been applied to an everexpanding variety of areas: law, corporate management, pedagogy, nursing, international relations, and many others. (34) Of course, reasonable people may disagree about the persuasiveness of specific claims made by Gilligan, Noddings, McClintock, Oakley, and the many others who use feminine approaches, but there should be consensus that in general these approaches expand debate in useful ways. Feminine types of thinking suggest new topics for investigation, alternative methods for gathering evidence, additional hypotheses for consideration, and further factors to take into account in deciding whether hypotheses have been confirmed. WNDI 2011 Ecofeminism K 44 Framework Naturalized notions of politics are imbued with calculation/rationality, and eliminates localized perspectives. Bad for environment. Goldman & Schurman, 00 [Michael and Rachel A: Professors at University of Minnesota. "Closing the 'Great Divide': New Social Theory on Society and Nature. Annual Review of Sociology, Vol. 26. p. 576-577] Whereas some look at the production of scientific knowledge from the perspective of political interests (e.g. Tyalor & Buttel 1992), others take a different approach by considering how particular culturalsocial values become naturalized and diffused beyond the intentions of any particular interests (Mackenzie 1995; Escobar 1995; Luke 1997; Goldman 1998, 200; Darier 1999). These scholars deploy a Foucauldian analysis of power/knowledge (Foucault 1980, Burchell et all 1991) for which exercises of power and the accumulation of (environmental) knowledge are co-constitutive, producing power relations and scientific discourses that rare intentional yet nonsubjective. These power/knowledge relations are imbued with calculation, rationality, and a productive influence on global norms of ecological and social governance (i.e. what constitutes the eco-rational citizen or state). Hence, we find globalizing discourses of environmentalism, reproduced by nonstate international institutions—e.g. NGO, intergovernmental, and scientific networks—that energetically push to establish universalizing norms, behaviors, and procedures to regulate the security of the environment. These power/knowledge incursions elide heterogeneity and conflict and instead represent the world as rational, consensual, and easily molded for sustainability. For example, tools such as environmental impact assessments and green cost-benefit analyses are now commonly used by public and private agencies around the world, and they are, in fact, often requirements for governments seeking international debt relief and financial support from institutions such as the World Bank and the International Monetary Fund. Yet despite their practice in vastly different settings (e.g. Laos, Lesotho, or Lithuania), environmental impact assessments and cost-benefit analyses rarely reflect localized cultural forms and norms, but, rather, newly contrived universal norms and models of sustainability, resource valuation and degradation. These kinds of questions this knowledge/power literature asks include the following: What specific micro-technologies of power do these new methodologies and sciences engender? What perspectives, issues, and questions get disguised, buried, or eliminated (i.e. subjugated knowledges) in the production and circulation of these universal scientific tools and models (i.e. elite knowledge)? Scholars working from this perspective have begun to theorize naturesociety relations in Foucauldian terms of biopolitics and biopower (Dean 1994, Burchell et al 1991). For example, Arturo Escobar’s (1995) analysis of development discourse deconstructs the concept of sustainable development as deployed in the South by Northern-based institutions. Playing with Carolyn Merchant’s trenchant analysis of the Enlightenment, Escobar argues that these institutions have brought about the semiotic “death of nature” and replaced it with the “rise of the environment,” a discursive strategy rooted in the destructive processes of post-World War II development and the proliferation of new governing strategies of nature. Everything in nature that is useful for increased industrial production falls under the rubric of the environment; all else disappears. Moreover, localized forms of knowledge become useful only in as much as they serve the new disciplinary mechanisms of local “participation” and global integration. The new scientific discourses of economism and ecologism coalesce under new regimes of power that, Escobar concludes, do more to undermine ecological-social WNDI 2011 Ecofeminism K 45 balances around the world than to sustain them. Studying the changing agrarian landscape in rural India, Akhil Gupta (1998) argues that new technological innovations in biotechnology, intellectual property rights, and bioengineered seeds and food products are factors in the respatialization of sovereignty, that is, who controls what farmers can grow on what land and the reconfiguration of socio-ecological relations. Gupta contends that new global environmental regulations emanating from the 1992 Rio Earth Summit and other global accords have given birth to new technologies of government unhitched from the nation-state and found in the realm of transnationality (cf Ong 1999). In his work on the World Bank, Michael Goldman (2000) uses the term eco-governmentality to denote the rapid diffusion of power/knowledge technologies that simultaneously operate on the levels of the individual, society, and the state. These practices are at the center of new political battles over what counts as nature and environmental problems and what constitutes an eco-rational citizen. According to these scholars, this type of green knowledge production has become prolific, controversial, and hegemonic. Its “ways of seeing” have poured through the arteries of popular, political, and economic networks that have as their mission the accumulation of knowledge for the control of nature’s value. It is a process that frames current discourses of sustainability, and disguises the engines of capitalist expansion as liberalizing and rational. In short the production of green knowledge should be understood as internal to, and constitutive of, new and existing exercise of power. WNDI 2011 Ecofeminism K 46 Framework Environmentalism is more about reshaping politics than working within it Wissenburg & Yoram ‘4 (Liberal Democracy and Environmentalism: The End of Environmentalism?” Marcel Wissenburg & Yoram Levy, 2004. Pg. 4) Environmentalism is traditionally not only concerned with the capability of existing political arrangements and institutions to successfully address the environmental challenge. It also entails or suggests a different conception of the good society. In addition to solving environmental problems, environmentalism is also, maybe even primarily, concerned with an analysis of the nature of such problems. In addition to a concern with acting effectively within a given political institutional context, environmentalism is also engaged in redefining and reshaping that context. And in addition to its concern with institutional design, environmentalism is also engaged in specifying and defining the environmental goals those institutions should promote, goals like the preservation of a self-sustaining nature or natural biodiversity. In other words, prior to its instrumental dimension environmentalism has a normative and moral dimension determining the way in which the whole environmental issue makes sense to us - if at all. It is with regard to this dimension that we ask whether environmentalism has come to an end. The empirical approach cannot answer this question, since, by its very nature, it treats the normative and moral dimension as a given. Nature is political Talshir ‘4 (Gayil. “The role of environmentalism: From The Silent Spring to The Silent Revolution,” Liberal Democracy and Environmentalism: The End of Environmentalism?” Marcel Wissenburg & Yoram Levy, 2004. Pg. 23) Furthermore, the environment was instrumental in challenging the boundary of the political as the environment was, par excellence, the non-political issue. The Enlightenment ethos of progress, dependent on the exploitation of nature and advancement of science and technology, was rarely challenged before on these grounds. Nature was never a subject in the moral or political sense. The realization that natural problems are political, that economic growth - advocated by left and right alike - encroaches upon Earth's limited resources, and that national systems can hardly address ecological issues, challenged the underlying assumption concerning the political arena. WNDI 2011 Ecofeminism K 47 Framework Need an entirely reconceived notion of politics – Current one is super destructive Talshir ‘4 (Gayil. “The role of environmentalism: From The Silent Spring to The Silent Revolution,” Liberal Democracy and Environmentalism: The End of Environmentalism?” Marcel Wissenburg & Yoram Levy, 2004. Pg. 18) The third option I want to pursue here is the linkage between environmentalism and 'new politics' - the argument that environmental politics is not merely about the preservation of nature, but entails a different conception of what politics is, and how political research should be conducted. For environmental exploitation has always been an integral aspect of human activities in the world, a natural part, as it were, of people's way of life. Indeed, the radical transformations in demographic, geographical and socio-economic patterns, maturing in the late nineteenth century, led the western industrialized nations to rely heavily on global natural resources for their rapid growth. World resources were gradually incorporated into one central pool of capital, managed largely through international market mechanisms, resulting in a rapid depletion of resources on a world-wide scale. It took recovery from two world wars for relatively affluent and stable advanced industrial democracies to settle into the bipolarity of the cold war, a balance of power which set in motion environmental problems, leading to their introduction onto the political agenda. By far the most profound experience that led environmental awareness to take root in western societies was the real prospect for a global destruction through nuclear war. The current fear of the use of weapons of mass destruction being used on innocent populations is the most recent appearance of the same basic worries. The culmination of global threat and personal anxiety in the name of national interest led to a popular realization that a thorough assessment of environmental issues is fundamental for a humane future. Nuclear war, the disposal of nuclear waste, atomic, biological and chemical (ABC) weapons, an accelerated arms race and the threat of the development of weapons of mass destruction comprise, however, only the tip of the iceberg of environmental problems threatening to overwhelm the global village. WNDI 2011 Ecofeminism K 48 Framework Standards for objectivity and rationality within a community for the insiders without alternative perspectives means that that neutrality can’t ever be achieved and discriminates against those who are already oppressed within that system Harding ‘6 [Sandra: teaches philosophy in the Graduate School of Education and Information Studies at UCLA. “Two Influential Theories of Ignorance and Philosophy’s Interests in Ignoring Them,” Hypatia, 21.3, 2006.] Feminist standpoint theorists identify the epistemological underdevelopment of mainstream epistemologies and philosophies of science as well as of the popular and disciplinary conceptual frameworks through which they gain widespread influence.5 These arguments are now familiar, though often misunderstood. Prevailing standards for objectivity, rationality, and good method, as well as for appropriate topics for scientific inquiry, are constituted in ways that make them oblivious to their own limitations. Scientific standards and forms of social rule, of governance, co-constitute each other. Paradoxically, even tragically for the dominant philosophies of science, research that rigorously obeys disciplinary methodological rules for meeting these standards will be unable to satisfy them. For example, "the scientific community" simultaneously directs scientific research to identify all social elements of a research project, yet also tells the researcher there is no need to seek criticisms and perceptions from outside its "consensus." Attempts to achieve value neutrality by repeating observations across disciplinarily legitimated observers, whether individuals or research teams, block the possibility of recognizing cultural and political values and interests that are both shared by all such observers and tend to become visible [End Page 24] only from "outside" the groups of whoever counts as disciplinarily legitimated observers (Harding 1993, 2003). Feminist standpoint theorists have made this kind of argument explicit; it appears also in the writings of other social justice movements. Values and interests such as androcentrism, white supremacy, Eurocentrism, heteronormativity, and ableism have highly shaped what have been regarded as the very best, most highly confirmed theories in the disciplines. They were able to do so because they were widely shared across the disciplines and among dominant groups in the surrounding social order. Consequently, such research discriminates against those already oppressed and devalued. WNDI 2011 Ecofeminism K 49 Framework Fiat bad - imagining total inclusivity is good so long as you don’t make it concrete, otherwise it becomes exclusionary. This is especially true for a feminist politics. Vasterling ’99 [Veronica: Associate Professor at the Department of Philosophy and the Center of Women Studies of the University of Nijmegen, the Netherlands. “Butler’s Sophisticated Constructivism: A Critical Assessment,” Hypatia, 14.3, 1999.] Butler nevertheless offers radical inclusivity as a positive political ideal. But she does this in the context of a critical political diagnosis of the world we live in: a world in which hegemonic conventions determine who is to count as a subject and who is not. In this context, to strive for total inclusivity means to strive for a radical democratic world, that is, a world no longer regulated by hegemonic conventions, in which everyone is entitled to the status of subject. Yet, even though hers is a positive political ideal, Butler is wary of presenting radical democracy simply as an achievable goal. To become an achievable goal, the ideal of radical democracy has to be translated in a political program or movement: the abstract, as it were, empty universality of total inclusivity is translated into a concrete, meaningful universality, such as the concrete universality of human rights. Though inevitable if the ideal is to be effective, the translation has its price for it cannot fail to be exclusionary and contestable. If radical democracy is simply taken as an achievable goal, ideal and translation get conflated. What gets lost in the conflation is the irreducible and critical distance between abstract and concrete universality, between the idea(l) of total inclusivity and its inevitably exclusionary and contestable translation. Because of the lack of critical distance the translation becomes self-evident, uncontestable, in short, hegemonic, and the violence of its exclusions will be ignored, be excused, or most likely, remain invisible. In other words, without the critical distance between ideal and translation, the ideal [End Page 34] of radical democracy, like any other ideal of a perfect world, may turn into its opposite. 19 To prevent the conflation of ideal and translation, radical democracy should be taken not as an achievable goal but as a regulatory idea in the Kantian sense. As such it enjoins us both to act as if total inclusivity is realizable in the future and, at the same time, to contest here and now any (violent) exclusions effected in its name. Feminist politics can draw a valuable lesson from the general argument concerning radical inclusivity. In so far as feminist politics invokes the category of "women," it seems to face a dilemma. On the one hand, it cannot but rely on this category if it is to have a basis for solidarity and empowerment. On the other hand, not even the most politically correct, multiculturalist specification of identities can fulfill the promise of inclusivity this category holds out. On the contrary, if anything, politically correct identity politics evokes rather than assuages recriminations of exclusion and lack of recognition. Instead of empowerment and solidarity, a "politicing of identity" (Butler 1993, 117) is the result. We are confronted with the dilemma of either giving up the category of "women" and hence the basis of feminist politics or resigning ourselves to proto-totalitarian identity politics. However, if we take the category of "woman" as a regulative idea(l) rather than an actual representation of all women, the dilemma is resolved. This means that we have "to learn a double movement: to invoke the category and, hence, provisionally to institute an identity and at the same time to open the category as a site of permanent political contest" (Butler 1993, 222). Only if we do not forget that the idea of total inclusivity is not realizable as such and hence that the category of "women" is permanently open to different interpretations, can the invocation of this category enable solidarity and empower feminist politics. WNDI 2011 Ecofeminism K 50 Perm Ecological degradation is inevitable under the existing legal system Gaard, 93 [Greta Claire: Associate Professor of Humanities, Fairhaven College at Western Washington University. Ecofeminism: Women, Animals, Nature. Pg. 13] Radical green philosophy is premised on the conviction that the sources of the environmental crisis are deeply rooted, in modern culture, and therefore fundamental social transformation is necessary if we are to preserve life on earth in any meaningful sense. This follows from the realization that we cannot rely on patchwork reforms through more appropriate economics, technology, and regulation, or better policies gained through green electoral politics. Our public choice mechanisms and technocratic methods are inherently biased against environmental preservation and conflict prevention. 1 Therefore, the gradual attrition, degradation, and biological impoverishment of the natural environment are inevitable under the existing system. To save a wilderness area is to hold a finger in a bursting dam: it only buys time. Working within the system can’t change our relationship to the environment Gaard, 93 [Greta Claire: Associate Professor of Humanities, Fairhaven College at Western Washington University. Ecofeminism: Women, Animals, Nature. Pg. 14-15] Thus, while it is important to work for electoral success, environmental consciousness, better policies, and more scientific research, these cannot change the deeply rooted behavior patterns and structural relationships that led to the environmental crisis in the first place. Nor can these change the nature of the decision-making methods and processes that support business as usual. If we value life, then we must transform the cultural and institutional infrastructure 3_— our frameworks of thinking, relating, and acting. The question is, how do we get from here to there? This is where green philosophies divide. WNDI 2011 Ecofeminism K 51 Perm Cooption in the political process is inevitable Gaard, 93 [Greta Claire: Associate Professor of Humanities, Fairhaven College at Western Washington University. Ecofeminism: Women, Animals, Nature. Pg. 14] There is another problem with political "success." Pressure politics is a matter of power, and while power attracts new talent, it also can divide and corrupt. We are beginning to see this in the green movement in Australia. Many "nouveau greens" seeking positions in the public arena lack a deep analysis or an ethical commitment sufficient to prevent the compromise of principles or a latent agenda of personal power. The process of cooptation has begun: a pluralist environmental movement is gradually being transformed into a structure of corporatist representation and mediation. 2 The legitimation of environmental interests by incorporation into existing decisionmaking structures, as has happened with the labor movement, cannot resolve the underlying psychological and behavioral causes of environmental or social conflict. Your narrative is not a good narrative Vance, 95 [Linda. "Sexist Words, Speciesist Roots" Animals and Women: Feminist Theoretical Explorations by Carol J. Adams & Josephine Donovan. Pg. 178-179] I think we must learn to be discriminating about narrative, at least the narrative that we put forward as what Cheney calls "ethical vernacular" ( Postmodern Environmental Ethics, 134). It is always true that narrative may offer insights into the psychology of the storyteller, or the worldview of the culture from which she speaks, and in that sense all narrative has value. But insights alone do not make it good narrative. Good narrative — that is, narrative that can form the basis of an ethic that recognizes both individual and general others — requires more. If we are to propose the creation of intentional narratives, myths to live by, we must also establish criteria by which to judge them. The kind of narratives we want, I think, should satisfy four criteria: (1) they should be ecologically appropriate to a given time and place: (2) they should be ethically appropriate in that time and place; (3) they should give voice to those whose stories are being told; and (4) they should make us care. I'll expand on each of these criteria separately. WNDI 2011 Ecofeminism K 52 Perm Law doesn’t solve Deckha ‘10 (Maneesha: Associate Professor at the University of Victoria Faculty of Law. “It’s time to abandon the idea of ‘human’ rights,” The Scavenger, December 13, 2010.) One of the organizing narratives of western thought and the institutions it has shaped is humanism and the idea that human beings are at the core of the social and cultural order. The cultural critique humanism has endured, by way of academic theory and social movements, has focused on the failure of its promise of universal equal treatment and dignity for all human beings. To address this failing, a rehabilitative approach to humanism is usually adopted with advocates seeking to undo humanism’s exclusions by expanding its ambit and transporting vulnerable human groups from “subhuman” to “human” status. Law has responded by including more and more humans under the coveted category of “personhood”. Yet, the logic of the human/subhuman binary typically survives this critique with the dependence of the coveted human status on the subhuman (and the vulnerabilities it enables) going unnoticed. Violence against animals is legitimated by the very law that “protects” them Deckha ‘10 (Maneesha: Associate Professor at the University of Victoria Faculty of Law. “It’s time to abandon the idea of ‘human’ rights,” The Scavenger, December 13, 2010.) All of this infliction on animal bodies is perceived as legitimate violence because of the nonhuman status of the species involved. The law buttresses this cultural acceptance. Animals are the property of corporate and human owners; theirs is a near universal status in western legal systems, which facilitates their instrumental use and exploitation for human ends. Due to the humanist parameters of our typical framings of violence, when we do think of violence against animals, it is only certain forms of violence that enter the realm of legal sanction. The protection that animals receive in western common law systems extends to protection from “cruelty”. Yet, “cruelty” only covers a fraction of the violent activities against animals and even then is designed to protect owners’ property interests, rather than recognize any inherent interests of animals themselves. WNDI 2011 Ecofeminism K 53 Perm Must recognize the way humans have altered the environment – can’t be through policy Talshir ‘4 (Gayil. “The role of environmentalism: From The Silent Spring to The Silent Revolution,” Liberal Democracy and Environmentalism: The End of Environmentalism?” Marcel Wissenburg & Yoram Levy, 2004. Pg. 13-14) Human society has always lived off the environment, changed and influenced it. Clearly, environmental changes have to be considered as dangerous or endangering in order for them to qualify as ecological problems. They can threaten either natural ecosystems, or human health or quality of life. The process of realization itself is not an ecological but a social one. The very problematization of certain phenomena - the extinction of species, the disappearance of wilderness, rising levels of carbon dioxide, the greenhouse effect - is predicated on empirical changes which the environment underwent. Recognizing the role of man-made influences on the environment is fundamental for developing environmental awareness. Actual ecological processes underlie environmental consciousness; natural reality is mediated through scientific and social discourse. Moulding environmental knowledge is relevant to this discussion, but, crucially, the actual condition of nature is a constituent part of it. Several things should be noted at this level. The first is that some ecological problems are not immediately apparent: one cannot always actually see water, air or soil pollution; the process by which acid rain produced in Britain, say, finds its way to Norway is not easy to understand; or that global warming influences the sea level and that coastal cities might be flooded. In other words, grasping ecological problems and their possible effects already requires complicated and abstract thinking. Second, ecological processes are gradual and take a long time - they are therefore difficult to assess vis-à-vis urgent economic needs (for example, even if a factory produces polluting substances which might cause lung cancer in its employees in ten years time, the workers would still be reluctant to lose their jobs and be unemployed today because of possible consequences in the long run). Third, politically, the discourses of interests and representation are foreign to ecological issues. Ecological problems rarely speak for themselves - they need to be explained and therefore require second-order representation (Talshir 1997). WNDI 2011 Ecofeminism K 54 Essentialism Ecofeminism affirms cultural diversity, violence against women is a universal in patriarchal societies Gaard, 93 [Greta Claire: Associate Professor of Humanities, Fairhaven College at Western Washington University. Ecofeminism: Women, Animals, Nature. Pg. 21] The misunderstanding that ecofeminism is dualistic probably derives from the ecofeminist suggestion that alternatives to Patriarchy are possible, as evidenced in women's and tribal cultures. That is, some mistakenly construe ecofeminism as conceiving of women as a "homogeneous whole" (in opposition to men) without making adequate distinctions between different races, nationalities, classes, and so on. This, of course, would run counter to the affirmation of cultural diversity by ecofeminists -- and by most greens, for that matter. The notion that women could have some similarities in experience and consciousness across national and class boundaries, due to certain shared conditions, is especially troublesome to those who reduce social problems to the existence of classes. 18 This is ironic, as the idea that workers in different industries, cultures, or nations could have a similar consciousness is essential to a class-based analysis. 19 The reality is that men of all classes use and take for granted power over women within their class, workplace, political party, or family structure, even --or especially— when power in the public arena is denied to those men. This is evidenced by the fact that violence toward women is fairly universal in Patriarchal societies and does not differ significantly across class boundaries. Your claim that ecofeminism is essentialist is a construct of patriarchy Gaard, 93 [Greta Claire: Associate Professor of Humanities, Fairhaven College at Western Washington University. Ecofeminism: Women, Animals, Nature. Pg. 22-23] The major attack against ecofeminism, however, has been that it allegedly claims that women possess an essential nature -- a biological connection or a spiritual affinity with nature that men do not. 21 While perhaps some women believe this, it is not a concept relevant to ecofeminism as such. In the first place, "essentialism" would be inconsistent with the logic of ecofeminism, let alone mainstream ecology. After all, as Ynestra King and others have explained, since all life is interconnected, one group of persons cannot be closer to nature. 22 The assertion of "difference" is based on the historical socialization and oppression of women, not biologism. If gender is shaped by culture, ideology/and history, and how one experiences nature is culturally mediated, then gender conditioning would tend to shape our experience of nature. Of course, the diversity of women and their experience is certainly not denied by ecofeminists. In fact, this diversity is celebrated and seen as a cause for optimism: diversity is vital in the effort to bring about social change. The accusation that ecofeminism is essentialist, I believe, results from a Patriarchal wav of thinking. That is, it presupposes the legitimacy of the Patriarchal construct that sees nature as separate from culture. As Joan Griscom explains, "The question itself is flawed. Only the nature/history split allows us even to formulate the question of whether women are closer to nature than men. The very idea of one group of persons being 'closer to nature' than another is a 'construct of culture.' " 23 WNDI 2011 Ecofeminism K 55 Essentialism Ignoring biological determinism renders the body useless Birke, 95 [Lynda: Biologist and Women's Studies Professor @ University of Warwick. "Sexist Words, Speciesist Roots" Animals and Women: Feminist Theoretical Explorations by Carol J. Adams & Josephine Donovan. Pg. 17] Partly, too, setting humans apart from other animals has been implicitly part of our opposition to biological determinism. In doing so, we have objected to the ways in which biologically determinist arguments have been used to justify women's oppression; we have also emphasized the myriad ways in which gender can be seen to be socially and culturally constructed. Yet this emphasis on social construction has its drawbacks. For example, it has left little space for bodies and their functions: it is almost as if our bodies were not part of our selves. Instead, the body becomes "a blank page for social inscriptions including those of biological discourse" (Haraway 1991, 197). Emphasizing social construction has also cut us off from the rest of the animal kingdom, thus reinforcing the view that humans are hot animals. In criticizing biological determinism, feminists have objected to the idea that human behavior and capabilities are the product of some underlying biological urge. We have also objected to the ready extrapolation from animals to humans, which is characteristic of so much biological determinism. WNDI 2011 Ecofeminism K 56 Essentialism Feminine and masculine apply more to ideas than people. Erasing the category of feminine makes the conditions that create oppression invisible Simson ‘5 (Rosalind S. “Feminine Thinking” Social Theory and Practice. Vol 31. 2005) Despite the considerations just discussed, some feminists have been loath to endorse the concept of feminine thinking because they are suspicious of sex-correlated categories. Although, as I noted earlier, there is no serious debate about whether all women think in feminine ways or about whether all feminine thinkers think exactly alike, some writers worry that simply using the label "feminine" serves to overemphasize similarities and underemphasize differences among groups of women and invariably takes Western, white, middle-class, heterosexual women as the standard for all. (48) In addition, several authors have pointed out overlap between thinking styles that are labeled "feminine" and those generally characteristic of people of color and of people in various non-Western cultures. Calling a way of thinking "feminine," these authors caution, may obscure reasons other than sex or gender that may be responsible for the kinds of thinking common among non-white and nonwestern women. (49) Moreover, it may falsely suggest that it is somehow possible to separate out aspects of women's thinking that may be the result of sex and gender from aspects that may be due to racial, cultural, or other influences. One response to these various concerns is to find a label for the modes of thinking that I have called "feminine" that could apply equally well to the thinking of nonWesterners and any others who might be found to think similarly. Some writers have taken this approach, substituting for "feminine" the terms "relational" or "connected" and substituting for "masculine" the terms "separate" or "abstract." (50) A different response is to eschew labels altogether. This approach seeks simply to detail, but not to categorize, the spectrum of thinking styles that result when the wide array of influences on thought patterns intersect. (51) On the whole, I am quite sympathetic to these concerns about categorization. It is certainly true that the research subjects used to study modes of thinking have disproportionately been privileged, Western, and white. I also acknowledge that the many formative influences on thinking interact with one another, and so the aspects of people's thinking that can be attributed to sex and gender cannot be separated out from aspects attributable to racial, cultural, and other factors. As I indicated earlier, furthermore, I believe that the adjectives "feminine" and "masculine" are best understood as applying directly to types of thinking and only indirectly to people. And lastly, I recognize that the contributions that different thinking styles make to human knowledge can be appreciated independently of any sex or gender associations they might have. Nevertheless, for several reasons, I am reluctant--at least at the present time--to adopt either of the approaches described above and essentially give up on the category of feminine thinking. First, the empirical studies that suggest the existence of sex-correlated differences in thinking have hardly been limited to privileged Western whites. Various of the studies that I cited in section 1.a took care to include people of differing classes, races, and ethnicities among their research subjects. (52) In addition, some of the studies that suggest that women tend to think femininely have focused on people of color--for example, the respective analyses that I discussed earlier by Patricia Hill Collins and Jane Duran of African-American women and Chicanas in the American Southwest. Moreover, these are not isolated examples. For instance, in a study of poor and working-class inner city U.S. public high school students of varying cultural backgrounds, psychologist Niobe Way concluded that although WNDI 2011 Ecofeminism K 57 these girls and boys had equally strong desires for intimate, supportive friendships, the girls were generally more likely than the boys actually to find and maintain such friendships. (53) Similarly, in a study of identity development in the adolescent children of black Caribbean immigrants in New York City, sociologist Mary Waters found that boys were more likely than girls to make dichotomous choices between an American identity and an ethnic identity, whereas girls were more likely than boys to be bicultural--that is, to see the boundaries between American and ethnic identities as "fluid and permeable." (54) And lastly, in a study of thinking styles in eight societies around the globe, Jane Duran detailed the lingering effects of strong cross-cultural tendencies, particularly among peoples with long traditions of written language, to exclude women from the kinds of abstract religious and philosophical theorizing that traditionally has been one of the hallmarks of masculine thinking. (55) The suggestion that women in general tend to think femininely does not imply that the thinking of all subgroups of women falls within the cluster concept of feminine thinking. Nor does it imply that all feminine thinking is produced by the same confluence of factors. A great deal of research is yet to be done-particularly research by investigators from a broad range of backgrounds that compares the thinking styles of females and males in non-Western cultures. Further study may make clear the scope and limitations of the notion of feminine thinking and conceivably might reveal that the idea of feminine thinking, even as a cluster concept, is fundamentally flawed. My point here is that, at present, the claim that there is a significant correlation between sex and modes of thinking, though hardly conclusively established, does have notable multicultural support. Perhaps I might be more inclined to urge waiting for more evidence before using the concept of feminine thinking if the alternatives outlined above were more appealing. Both, however, have substantial drawbacks. On the one hand, I resist substituting terms like "connected" and "separate" for "feminine" and "masculine" because, as I have already suggested and explain further below, I believe that people's tendencies to think in particular ways is due at least in part to their societal situations. By decontextualizing and treating as abstract sets of traits that most likely arose in very situated ways, these terms encourage one to overlook the social significance of different modes of thought. Moreover, by grouping "feminine," "non-Western," and other thinking styles under one general label, these terms serve to obscure ways in which these thinking styles may differ from one another. On the other hand, my difficulty with rejecting categorizations and instead treating every intersection of formative factors as distinctive is that it makes unavailable to feminists various strategies for improving the situations of many women. If there are in fact observable tendencies in women's thinking, then as I argued earlier, women in general stand to benefit from the recognition that this is so. Moreover, as history suggests, overlooking these tendencies can operate to the detriment of large numbers of women. (56) Finally, in response to concerns that the label "feminine" may blind theorists to the influences of race, culture, and other factors on women's thinking, I underline that I am not suggesting that "feminine" is the only classificatory category that can or should be used. I have focused on "feminine thinking" as a category because, as I have argued, I believe that it provides a useful lens for achieving various insights that are important for epistemology and for social justice. Other classificatory categories can no doubt be used to similar advantage. For example, it may well be a source of equal, if not greater insights, to examine the thinking styles of African-American women in terms of the category "African-American modes of thought" and of the intersectional category, "feminine African-American thinking." Using multiple classificatory categories to analyze thinking styles seems to me to offer the best means of identifying and understanding the significance of differences and similarities among modes of thinking. (57) WNDI 2011 Ecofeminism K 58 Essentialism Preconceived notions of what human, animality or objects close off what any of those things actually are Soffer, 96 [Gail. “Heidegger, Humanism and the Destruction of History,” The Review of Metaphysics, 49.3, 1996.] Yet as commonplace as its association with Heidegger has become, the equation of humanism with essentialism is not to be found in Heidegger's central statement on the subject, the "Letter on Humanism." Indeed, nowhere does Heidegger reject the view that man has an essence. To the contrary, his criticism of humanism is always that it has incorrectly or "metaphysically" determined the essence of man; that it conceives of man as animal rationale, and hence on the basis of a preconceived notion of `nature' or `animality' or `objects'. His claim is that such preconceptions close off the question of the relation between human existence and Being, thereby blinding us to the true human essence.(3) Heidegger himself is clearly concerned to provide a glimpse of this true essence, and it is for this reason that he faults humanism for not determining the essence of man "high enough." Thus the entire debate surrounding the early Heidegger's alleged humanism or anti-humanism presupposes an equation of humanism with essentialism which is not Heideggerian, but Sartrean or MarxianAlthusserian.(4) Butler agrees, have to use the categorical term “woman” to resignify it Webster ’00 [Fiona: Co-editor of Asia-Pacific Review. “The Politics of Sex and Gender: Benhabib and Butler Debate Subjectivity,” Hypatia, 15.1, 2000.] The curious point to note, however, concerning Butler's contribution to this issue is the sense in which she ultimately confesses the imperative, in the reality of political life, "to set norms, to affirm aspirations, to articulate the possibilities of a more fully democratic and participatory political life" (1995c, 129). Indeed, she suggests, for example, the strategic and political importance of retaining the category of "women," a category which she has brought into question, in order to make particular political claims (1993, 222; 1995b, 49). Whenever this is necessary, she argues, we must simply be aware that such categories are not fixed or determinate but always sites of contest (1993, 221; 1995b, 50). She therefore wants to claim that in problematizing that category she does not want to prevent it from being used in order to serve particular ends, but rather to open it up to the possibility of resignification and transformation. Indeed, for Butler, the problematic character of the category ultimately enables such resignification and transformation. WNDI 2011 Ecofeminism K 59 Essentialism The redefinition of the term “woman” is where agency is derived from Webster ’00 [Fiona: Co-editor of Asia-Pacific Review. “The Politics of Sex and Gender: Benhabib and Butler Debate Subjectivity,” Hypatia, 15.1, 2000.] How can we understand Butler's critique of identity categories and her critique [End Page 9] of identity politics in relation to this ultimate appeal to the norms and requirements of the political arena? Butler provides very little material which directly addresses the programmatic implications of her critique of identity categories. 9 Indeed, part of the difficulty we have in assessing her work is working out precisely what her programmatic vision for a feminist politics might be, given the theoretical imperatives which guide her work. 10 Nevertheless, given the criticisms which such theorists as Benhabib raise against her work, it seems imperative that we question what possible direction a feminist politics would take on the basis of the various critiques she makes of identity categories and identity-based politics. Does Butler, as Susan Hekman claims, ultimately give up the basis for a feminist politics (Hekman 1995a, 156)? To address this question, let us return here to some claims Butler does explicitly make concerning the strategies we might employ as feminists addressing the concerns of "women" in the political arena. Despite being insistently critical of the descriptive force of the category "women," Butler endorses strategic use of that category to serve particular political ends. She claims that "to understand 'women' as a permanent site of contest, or as a feminist site of antagonistic struggle, is to presume that there can be no closure on the category and that, for politically significant reasons, there ought never to be. That the category can never be descriptive is the very condition of its political efficacy" (1993, 221). As in the case of her account of agency, we can see here the sense in which Butler understands categorical instability to give rise to political efficacy. That is, insofar as the category "women" is always open, always a site of contest, the possibilities for transformation and resignification, both within that very category and in its deployment in the political arena, are never-ending. 11 Butler's claims here are critically informed both by her theory of performativity and by her analysis of Slavoj Zizek's analysis of political signifiers as "empty signs which come to bear phantasmatic investment of various kinds" (Butler 1993, 191). Butler claims that understanding the category of "women" as a political signifier in this way affirms the sense in which that signifier unifies the category it seeks to represent and, simultaneously, constitutes that very category. The performative power of the political signifier therefore lies in "enacting that which it names" (1995a, 150; 1995c, 134). The critical force of the political signifier consists in its failure, ultimately, to fully or comprehensively describe or represent that which it names. It is precisely this open-ended character, this inability to ever fully establish or describe the identity to which it refers which, Butler claims, constitutes the possibility of an "expansive re-articulation" (1993, 218) of that identity. So, in summary, the performative character of the signifier is the very condition of its agency. "Agency" is therefore located by Butler in the performative character of the political signifier. It is not an attribute or "power" of subjects, through which they assert control or "authorship" over action or signification. Indeed, Butler [End Page 10] is highly critical of an account of agency which implies that the subject is somehow the exclusive "origin" or "owner" of action or signification (1993, 227). The subject, for Butler, is constituted in and by a signifier (such as "woman"), where "'to be constituted' means 'to be compelled to cite or repeat or mime' the signifier itself" (1993, 220). Agency is located in this very action of at once being brought into being by and repeating or miming the signifier it-self. 12 Possibilities for "agency," and therefore for change and transformation, lie in the very activity of WNDI 2011 Ecofeminism K 60 repetition and identification. Furthermore, such activity is not, for Butler, entered into deliberately or voluntarily but rather is a process which subjects are compelled to enter into insofar as they are constituted in and through relations of power in society. WNDI 2011 Ecofeminism K 61 A2: You don’t go far enough Ideas about what Nature should be are what lead to ecological destruction and fascism. Hudson ‘8 (Laura. “The Political Animal: Species-Being and Bare Life,” Mediations, 23.2, Spring 2008.) Seeing Nature as essentially innocent, deep ecology suggests that humanity is an evolutionary mistake, “a fatal disease of nature” that must be contained.5 Deep ecology argues that nature is in need of salvation or recuperation from the insatiable drives of the human world that infect nature’s body like a cancer. But this presupposes that the natural world is whole and complete prior to the introduction of human beings as an alien, destructive force. Nature becomes a romantic illusion when we forget the role that human beings play in shaping the world, or forget that we are a part of the natural world as well as apart from it. Any attempt to “return to nature” is doomed: our concepts concerning the natural world necessarily reflect the social relations of the time when they emerge. We cannot separate the concept of Nature from the social form in which it functions. Nature exists as an “outside” to the modern world because culture and society exist as the claustrophobic “inside”: Nature is not a static object but a dynamic category whose meaning has evolved in intercourse with human beings. The necessity of saving Nature only makes sense in the midst of a period of ecological destruction that threatens not the natural world, which will continue in some form regardless of what we do, but rather our ideas about what the natural world should be. Nor can our ideas about nature be separated from our ideas about human nature. Any time a desire to save the earth, or save the animals, is asserted, what is truly to be saved is our version of the earth, or our concept of the animals, both of which are deeply implicated in our ideas about ourselves. It is because humanity begins to seem like a disease or pathogen that the natural world becomes increasingly innocent and idealized. It is our own salvation, our own human world, our own tainted innocence we want to redeem through projecting it onto the natural world. If we follow deep ecology to its logical conclusion, the salvation of Nature would be best accomplished by the removal of the corrupting force of human beings: “if humans are the problem, then killing most of them would be the solution.”6 Indeed, some of the deepest green of deep ecologists invoke the imagery of the “population bomb” and argue for limiting or massively reducing human population, demonstrating the irony that the salvation of humanity seems to require the destruction or restriction of a large number of its members. The confusion of deep ecology seems to end up either, as Ferry argues, invoking a thinly veiled fascism where an enlightened few dictate the tenets of appropriate interaction with the natural world, including the potential depopulation of the earth, or emptying itself of any content through according intrinsic value to everything “natural,” making the weighing of decisions or options against one another murky at best. The very idea of intrinsic value depends on concepts of value inculcated by capitalism, even if only in a reactionary way. In valuing the concrete, material world where everything is invested with intrinsic value, deep ecology challenges the abstraction of capitalism where value is only produced through the system of exchange. Yet, if everything has intrinsic, natural value, then what reason is there to value one form of life over another? Why bother trying to save humanity at all? WNDI 2011 Ecofeminism K 62 A2: You prioritize nature The choice between humanists, speciesists, and eco-fascists is a false one and should be rejected Kochi & Ordan, 08 [Tarik: Queen’s University; Noam: Bar Ilan University. “An Argument for the Global Suicide of Humanity,” borderlands, 7.3, 2008.] Finally, it is important to note that such a standpoint need not fall into a version of green or ecofascism that considers other forms of life more important than the lives of humans. Such a position merely replicates in reverse the speciesism of modern humanist thought. Any choice between the eco-fascist and the humanist, colonial-speciesist is thus a forced choice and is, in reality, a non-choice that should be rejected. The point of proposing the idea of the global suicide of humanity is rather to help identify the way in which we differentially value different forms of life and guide our moral actions by rigidly adhered to standards of life-value. Hence the idea of global suicide, through its radicalism, challenges an ideological or culturally dominant idea of life-value. Further, through confronting humanist ethics with its own violence against the non-human, the idea of global suicide opens up a space for dialectical reflection in which the utopian ideals of both modern humanist and anti-humanist ethics may be comprehended in relation to each other. One possibility of this conflict is the production of a differing standpoint from which to understand the subject and the scope of moral action.