UPTC School of Education Course: Epistemology Passage 1, August 12, 2001 The Human Paradox Fernando Silva, UPTC Guildernstern: “My Lord, we were sent for.” Hamlet: I will tell you why, so shall my anticipation prevent your discovery, and your secrecy to the King and Queeen moult no feather. I have of late,-but wherefore I know not- lost all my mirth, forgone all custom of exercises; and indeed it goes so heavily with my disposition, that this goodly frame, the earth, seems to me a sterile promontory; this most excellent canopy, the air, look, you, this o’erhanging firmament, this majestical roof fretted with golden fire, why, it appeareth no other thing to me than a foul and pestilent congregation of vapours. What a piece of work is a man! How noble in reason, how infinite in faculties! in form and moving, how express and admirable! in action, how like an angel! in apprehension, how like a god! the beauty of the world! the paragon of animals, and yet, to me, what is this quintessence of dust? Man delights not me ... Shakespeare in Hamlet, Prince of Denmark Man is a weird abortion of nature, an uglyish creature without the fiery color of the butterfly, or the glossy coat of a bear, or the graceful shape of a bird. He canters along with an ungainly, two-legged gait that makes him slow and vulnerable as compared with the big cats, and features a size that makes him no rival to the bigger mammals. He has released himself of the responsibilities of every other creature in the food chain: while alive he is the preferred food of no predator. In fact, he has become his own sole predator, killing his kin not for food, but for spite. Over and above that, he remains the most voracious predator of nature, destroying everything in his reach for no other purpose than his own pleasure. He has an unduly long prenatal stage, longer only in the very big mammals, and unlike any other animal an abnormally long dependent period between birth and adulthood: both the insect and the whale calf, at either end of the scale size, are born with full control of their members and ready to survive in a hostile world. Man, on the contrary, struggles through a lengthy childhood and a traumatic adolescence, and at times in his old age and deathbed, is still a child, unable to cope with reality. And yet, he calls himself Creation’s King, the Masterpiece of Paradise. What makes him think so? Two minor things: one a bodily feature, the other, a spiritual glint. Like the primates, he has an opposing thumb. All other creatures are limited to their jaws, like a tiger, or their extremities, like the spider, or even its whole body, like a snake, to catch another creature, and they do so only to feed or mate. Man uses this little accident of his upper extremities to turn every object of his surroundings into an extension of himself: he learned to hurl stones and arrows, and later bullets, to dishearten enemies or to fell prey much bigger than himself, and he can deftly climb up a tree to flee from a threatening predator. He can cover himself with the warm skins of furry animals by stitching their hides into garments, and build a lodging to protect himself from weather and foe. Finally, unlike any other animal, he can put together subtle elements like kindling and heat to build himself a fire for protection, warmth and company. And unlike any other creature, or at least we think so, he thinks. In truth we do not really know whether any other creature in the universe can claim this strange ability of thought, presumably residing in the brain, but we know that none other shares the even stranger ability to share his thoughts with his kin through articulate language. Language itself is an abortion. While every sense has its own organ, speech , like sex, must usurp the organs of other functions as if both were of little or no importance: the lungs, pharinx and nose are meant for breathing and making noise, but man has made of them a resonating box to refine the noises into linguistic sounds. The mouth and tongue are meant for feeding, and man has imposed on them the task of further modelling the sound to produce words, and thereby thoughts. Even the brain, that mysterious organ that seems to set the limit between spirit and matter, used to be a mere coordinator of bodily organs in lower animals, but man has turned into a powerful engine of thought and language. However, the urge to mean is by no means an exclusively human endowment. Every creature from the most simple living organism, such as the sponge or protozoid, must impose itself on other members of its kin and on its environment to carry out two basic functions: to feed and grow as an individual, and to reproduce and survive as a species. This impulsive behaviour of all living organism to move outwards is the deepest origin of human language. But once again, man uses it for new and surprising purposes: to coo and to deceive, to entice and to reject, to manipulate and to rebel. In brief, to think. To think? Is not then speech the result of thought? Isn't it, perhaps, the other way around, so that thought is the child of speech? A child is born with the ability to think, but he really only thinks after he has developed the ability to speak, or more broadly, to use language. We cannot really think without language (Wittgenstein). We can bring to our mind the shapes of nameless objects, much like we can perceive objects that we cannot fully discern, and therefore cannot fully name. Even so, when this happens, we quickly impose language on these unlikely shapes, the language of form and color and likeness. We say, or think, “this or that is something like a shapeless sack” or “it is big and heavy”. However, beyond perceiving or remembering un-nameable objects, we cannot grasp them in any way without the use of language, as if language were the opposing thumb of the mind. Thinking is strictly propositional, and advanced thinking is only possible with an advanced command of language. Hence, while most people thing that language is the child of thought, some are tempted to believe the opposite, that thought is the child of language. Halliday proposes that every failure of a child at school is really a language failure. Thought, then, or rather language, is the second item that makes man a creature with a higher destiny. And this brings around a paradox. A creature with such high calling should stand well above all others in nobility and rank, but oft enough he betrays this calling. How should we then perceive this strange creature? Like the spiritual being that can bring himself to the threshold of the gods? Or like the “quintessence of dust”, the lowly scoundrel that kan kill his own kin for no apparent reason, an orphanly abortion of nature, deceivingly clad in spirituality? Which of the two we choose depends on mood. To Hamlet, in his despair of having uncovered the murder of his father at the hands of his uncle and mother, man is the latter: a hopeless creature capable of the most hideous baseness. To the poet in a lighter mood, paraphrased by Hamlet in the first lines of his paradox, man is nature’s most enlightened product, a mighty piece of work. But in the line of paradox, man is both. To Hamlet, Guilderstern and Rosencrantz, standing before him, are an incarnation of the paradox: first his long-time friends, and now come to him, by order of his mother and uncle, to become his murderers. However, notwithstanding his biological limitations, man is best perceived in his higher bidding. The human side of man (as opposed to his merely biological side), is a result of his ability to think, a result, in turn, of his ability to speak. Thought is merely a re-elaboration of experience. We can think beyond what we know, but only in terms of the things we know: every creature of our imagination has the limbs of the creatures of our experience, and we code this knowledge in terms of “internal speech” (Wittgenstein). From a different angle, everything in the human side of man has a single purpose, to enable human action, defining said “human action” as that kind of move that transcends biological intention. We cannot act in the absence of knowledge, and we know and learn in order to act. Truth, or knowledge, is anything that we can act upon. The opposite of truth is not falsehood, or ignorance, but irrelevance. Conversely, in a way, all “truths” are lies because they are necessarily incomplete renditions of reality, and as such, untrue. Thus the object of intellect is not certainty, which can never occur, but the adoption of a healthy measure of skepticism to the extent that we can act upon it safely without pretending it to be absolute truth. Language reflects this paradox. Whereas a classic view of language, as analysed y Wittgenstein in a passage of St. Augustin, is usually taken to be univocally meaningful and dependable, pragmatical analysis shows it to be equivocal and undependable: we rarely say what we mean, we rarely mean what we say. Language is merely a well-intended attempt to tell others of what we think we know, but turning this intention into a fully unequivocal statement implies such complexities, that in the end we end up saying only a fraction of what we would have to say to make it unequivocal. Grice sets this paradox in the context of a “cooperative principle”: when we say something we give it our best shot, and we can only hope that what we say will be adequately interpreted by a cooperative interlocutor. Even so, the hearer may decide to twist my proposition and make it say a totally different thing. Thus a given proposition said by a speaker is only as true as the hearer wants to make it, first because the speaker is limited by the context (he may say more or less than needed, he may be intentionally telling lies, he may be saying it the wrong way, and he may be speaking of something that is not relevant), and then, because language is inherently inaccurate. Hence it will always be up to the hearer to decide how much credit he gives to the utterances of the speaker. This being true it goes without saying that, if language is the vehicle of knowledge, knowledge is at best an approximation. Halliday, Explorations in the Functions of Language. London. Arnold, 1972 Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations. London, Basil Blackwell, 1958 Shakespeare, Hamlet, King of Denmark. of nature an uglyish creature without the fiery color of the butterfly the glossy coat of a bear the graceful shape of a bird with an ungainly, two-legged gait as compared with the big cats The noun phrase a size to the bigger mammals. of the responsibilities of every other creature in the food chain the preferred food of no predator In fact his own sole predator (not) for food (but) for spite the most voracious predator of nature in his reach for no other purpose his own pleasure an unduly long prenatal stage in the very big mammals unlike any other animal an abnormally long dependent period between birth and adulthood the insect and the whale calf at either end of the scale size with full control of their members in a hostile world on the contrary through a lengthy childhood (and) a traumatic adolescence at times in his old age and deathbed a child to cope with reality The sentence He calls himself Creation’s King, the Masterpiece of Paradise. Two minor things make him so: one a bodily feature, the other, a spiritual glint. he has an opposing thumb like the primates. All other creatures are limited and and to their jaws, like a tiger, or their full extremities, like the spider, or even its whole body, like a snake, to catch another creature, so only to fight, feed or mate. they do Man uses this little accident of his upper extremities to turn every object of his surroundings into an extension of himself: he can hurl he can deftly climb He can cover stones and arrows, and later bullets, to dishearten enemies or to fell prey much bigger than himself, up a tree to flee from a threatening predator. himself with the warm skins of furry animals by stitching their hides into garments, and build a lodging to protect himself from weather and foe. Finally, unlike any other animal, he can put together subtle elements like kindling and heat to build himself a fire for protection, warmth and company. And unlike any other creature, or at least we think so, he thinks. In truth we do not really know whether any other creature in the universe can claim this strange ability of thought, presumably residing in the brain, but we know that none other shares the even stranger ability to share his thoughts with his kin through articulate language. Language itself is an abortion. While every sense has its own organ, speech , like sex, must usurp the organs of other functions as if both were of little or no importance: the lungs, pharinx and nose are meant for breathing, but man (like other animals) has made of them a bellows to push air through the system to make noise, and the system into a resonating box to refine the noises into sound. The mouth and tongue are meant for feeding, and man has imposed on them the task of further modelling the sound to produce words, and thereby thoughts. Even the brain, that mysterious organ that seems to set the limit between spirit and matter, used to be a mere coordinator of bodily organs in lower animals, but man has turned into a powerful engine of thought and language. However, the urge to mean is by no means an exclusively human endowment. Every creature from the most simple living organism, such as the sponge or protozoid, must impose itself on other members of its kin and on its environment to carry out two basic functions: to feed and grow as an individual, and to reproduce and survive as a species. This impulsive behaviour of all living organism to move outwards is the deepest origin of human language. But once again, man uses it for new and surprising purposes: to coo and to deceive, to entice and to reject, to manipulate and to rebel. In brief, to think. To think? Is not then speech the result of thought? Perhaps it is the other way around, and thought is the child of speech. A child is born with the ability to think, but he really only thinks after he has developed the ability to speak, or more broadly, to use language. We cannot really think without language (Wittgenstein). We can bring to our mind the shapes of nameless objects, much like we can perceive objects that we cannot fully discern, and therefore cannot fully name. Even so, when this happens, we quickly impose language on these unlikely shapes, the language of form and color and likeness. We say, or think, “this or that is something like a shapeless sack” or “it is big and heavy”. However, beyond perceiving or remembering un-nameable objects, we cannot grasp them in any way without the use of language, as if language were the opposing thumb of the mind. Thinking is strictly propositional, and advanced thinking is only possible with an advanced command of language. Hence we are tempted to believe that thought is the child of language, and not the other way around. Halliday proposes that every failure of a child at school is really a language failure. Thought, then, or rather language, is the second item that makes man a creature with a higher destiny.