A2 Religious Studies: Developments (Paper 3) Philosophy of Religion. Atheism and Unbelief. Atheists or unbelievers can be defined as people who believe one or more of the following statements to be true: That there are no supernatural agents: God, gods or even demons or the devil. Also, that there are no abstractions of God intended to replace him: e.g. Paul Tillich’s ‘The Ground of all Being.’ That there are no miracles: no interventions in the natural order of things by supernatural agents. That there is no life after death. In his book ‘Varieties of Unbelief’ J.C.A. Gaskin argues that there are 5 types of ‘unbelief’. He avoids using the word atheism, as atheism he argues has negative connotations and has been used as a term of abuse in the past. In Ancient Greece, atheism was seen as a criminal offence and impiety was occasionally punished: Socrates for example, was forced to take hi sown like by drinking hemlock. However, Ancient Greek society did permit a variety of ideas and prosecutions were rare. Throughout the Christian era, atheism has been severely punished and up until comparatively recently, it was not easy to hold or profess atheist beliefs and get away with it. Anything that contradicted the teaching of the Christian Church was suppressed and individuals that professed these views were often executed. In 448 CE, copies of Porphyry’s book ‘Against the Christians’ were burned and at the end of the Sixteenth Century, Giordano Bruno was repeatedly tortured and burned alive by the Holy Inquisition of the Catholic Church for expressing ideas that contradicted Church teaching. The five types of unbelief that Gaskin points out are: 1. Materialism; this is the belief that there is no supernatural realm; nothing beyond the physical world that we can see. We will use Bertrand Russell to explore this. 2. Skepticism; this is the belief that any knowledge of the gods or of God is not attainable by humans. We will use A.J. Ayer to explore this. 3. Critical unbelief; this is the belief that theism is incoherent, that it does not make sense as an argument. We will Use Baron d’Holbach to explore this. 4. Social unbelief; this is the belief that religion causes more harm than good. It is expounded very clearly in the present day by Richard Dawkins, who likens religion to a virus. We will use Karl Marx to explore it. 5. Naturalistic explanations for belief; this is the belief that there is a natural explanation for the source of religious belief (i.e. that it doesn’t come from God and is not revealed.) We will use Sigmund Freud to explore this. It is important to remember that most atheists will argue against belief in God from a number of perspectives to strengthen their arguments. For example, David Hume, Bertrand Russell and Richard Dawkins all produce systematic critiques of religious belief that attack it from a variety of angles. Richard Dawkins for example, in his book ‘The God Delusion’, argues from materialism, critical unbelief and social unbelief. A2 Religious Studies: Developments (Paper 3) Philosophy of Religion. Materialist unbelief: Bertrand Russell (1872-1970). Materialism is the belief that everything that exists is either matter, or the result of matter, that humans create divinities out of their deepest longings and aspirations. There are a number of philosophers who have adopted this position through the ages: Epicurus, Hobbes and others. We are going to look at arguments from Bertrand Russell; a Twentieth Century philosopher to examine the materialist position. Russell refutes two beliefs central to religion: the belief in a creator God and belief in the afterlife. In ‘Why I am not a Christian’, Russell dismisses belief in Christianity on a number of grounds; one of the arguments that he puts forward is a materialist one. Russell begins his argument, by refuting some of the traditional arguments for the existence of God: the Cosmological, Teleological and Moral Arguments. In his dismissal of the Cosmological Argument, Russell writes the following: ‘There is no reason why the world could not have come into being without a cause; nor, on the other hand, is there any reason why it should not have always existed. There is no reason to suppose that the world had any beginning at all. The idea that things have a beginning is really due to the poverty of our imagination.’ Russell is arguing either that everything must have a cause, or it must not. If everything has a cause, then God too must have a cause. If everything does not need a cause, then the world or the universe does not necessarily need a cause. Russell’s claim is that the material evidence for the existence of God (e.g. the universe, or design in the universe) does not necessarily point to the existence of God. He also points to the incoherence of the Design Arguments (that the design is somehow flawed) and the Moral Arguments (by using the Euthyphro dilemma and indicating that there must be a standard of right and wrong independent of God). Russell goes on to argue that it is in fact fear that is the cause of religious belief: ‘fear is the basis of the whole thing – fear of the mysterious, fear of defeat, fear of death.’ Russell argues that materialism and scientific knowledge can help us to overcome this fear and superstition: ‘Science can help us to get over this craven fear in which mankind has lived for so many generations. Science can teach us, and I think our own hearts can teach us, no longer to look around for imaginary supports, no longer to invent allies in the sky, but rather to look to our own efforts here below to make this world a fit place to live in.’ Even though Russell argues that materially speaking it is impossible to conclude that God exists, he also admits that it is not possible to disprove God’s existence using materialist arguments: ‘I do not pretend to be able to prove that there is no God. I equally cannot prove that Satan is fiction. The Christian God may exist; so may the Gods of Olympus, or of Ancient Egypt, or of Babylon. But no one of these hypotheses is more probable than any A2 Religious Studies: Developments (Paper 3) Philosophy of Religion. other: they lie outside the region of even probable knowledge, and therefore there is no reason to consider any of them.’ Philosophically speaking this is a sound argument and a shrewd move. Russell, whilst he admits that the material evidence does not in fact point to God, has to admit that there is no way of proving the non-existence of God (see A.J. Ayer below). This is something that Richard Dawkins does not do. In ‘The God Delusion’, Dawkins tries to show that ‘the God hypothesis’ is false. He argues that the material evidence for God’s existence is faulty and that people believe in God because they want to as a result of emotional immaturity: ‘It is time to face up to the important role that God plays in consoling us; and the humanitarian challenge, if he does not exist, to put something in his place. Many people who concede that God probably doesn’t exist, and that he is not necessary for morality, still come back with what they regard as a trump card: the alleged psychological or emotional need for a god. If you take religion away, people truculently ask, what are you going to put in its place? What have you to offer the dying patients, the weeping bereaved, the lonely Eleanor Rigbys for whom God is their only friend?’ Dawkins dismisses belief in God and argues that the only reason people hang on to it, is because it offers us consolation in the face of a cruel world. Elsewhere in ‘Unweaving the Rainbow’ Dawkins has supported his materialist argument by showing that things thought mysterious in the past can now be explained by science. Where people had once thought that certain events had mysterious or supernatural causes, science can now give a clear explanation of why these events take place. In Chapter 6 for example, he takes on the subject of astrology and writes a scathing critique of it, labelling it ‘meaningless pap’ amongst other things. He adds later: ‘We can get outside the universe. I mean in the sense of putting a model of the universe inside our skulls. Not a superstitious, small-minded, parochial model filled with spirits and hobgoblins, astrology and magic, glittering with fake crocks of gold where the rainbow ends.’ Although Bertrand Russell was unwilling to conclude that God does not exist, he did not shy away from concluding that belief in life after death was incoherent. For Russell, mind is produced by matter and people believe in life after death because they are afraid of death and are afraid of not existing any longer. In ‘What I Believe’, Russell begins by arguing that everything that makes up the universe is material. A human being is material. Our thoughts depend upon ‘tracks’ (synaptic connections) and chemical reactions in the brain; it would be possible to turn an intelligent man into an idiot simply by reducing the amount of iodine in his blood: ‘mental phenomena seem to be bound up with material structure.’ Russell goes on to state that ‘God and immortality…find no support in science.’ ‘I believe that when I die I shall rot, and nothing of my ego will survive. I am not young and I love life. But I should scorn to shiver with terror at the thought of annihilation. Happiness is nonetheless true happiness because it must come to an end, nor do thought A2 Religious Studies: Developments (Paper 3) Philosophy of Religion. and love lose their value because they are not everlasting…Undoubtedly we are part of nature, which has produced our desires, our hopes and fears, in accordance with laws which the physicist is beginning to discover. In this sense we are part of nature, we are subordinated to nature, the outcome of natural laws and their victims in the long run.’ Skeptical Unbelief: A.J. (‘Freddy’) Ayer. In 1936, A.J. Ayer published a book entitled ‘Language, Truth and Logic.’ In this book, amongst other things, Ayer set out a skeptical view of belief in God. The skeptical view holds that we cannot achieve any factual or full knowledge of God. The main reason for this is that we are finite and God is infinite and as Hobbes claimed in Leviathan: ‘Whatsoever we imagine, is finite. Therefore there is no idea, or conception of any thing we call infinite. No man can have in his mind an image of infinite magnitude.’ In Chapter 6 of his book, Ayer writes: ‘It is now generally admitted, at any rate by philosophers, that the existence of a being having the attributes which define the God of any non-animistic religion cannot be demonstratively proved.’ It is important to note at this stage that Ayer does not claim that this God does not exist, he is arguing that the existence cannot be proved, as we do not have the tools to do so. Ayer claimed that there were only two types of proof that have any meaning: analytic and synthetic. An analytic proof is one which is logically true, where the premises necessitate the conclusion. For example: P1: P2: C: Socrates is a man; All men are mortal; Socrates is mortal. This is an analytic proof, as by definition it has to be true. Other types of analytically true statements are: 2+2=4, or ‘blue is a colour.’ We do not have to look outside these statements to verify their truth. A synthetic proof is a proof that is grounded in fact. In order for a synthetic statement to be true, we need to provide empirical information to support it. For example: P1: P2: C: Socrates is mortal; All men are mortal; Socrates is a man. This argument is not true by definition. We would have to look at Socrates to verify that he was a man, because he could be a badger, a goat or a threetoed sloth. Other examples of synthetic statements are: ‘it’s raining outside’, ‘the Eiffel Tower is in Paris’, or ‘my hair is brown.’ I need to rely upon my A2 Religious Studies: Developments (Paper 3) Philosophy of Religion. senses to verify that these statements are true, whereas with analytic statements, I do not need them, they are true by definition. Ayer argued that the statement ‘God exists’ cannot be proved analytically or synthetically and is therefore a meaningless and unprovable statement: ‘…if the existence of such a god were probable, then the proposition that he existed would be an empirical hypothesis. And in that case it would be possible to deduce from it, and other empirical hypotheses, certain experiential propositions which were not deducible from those hypotheses alone. But in fact, this is not possible.’ ‘…to say that “God exists” is to make a metaphysical utterance which cannot be either true or false. And by the same criterion, no sentence which purports to describe the nature of a transcendent god can possess any literal significance.’ It is again important to recognise that Ayer does not say that it is impossible to claim that God exists, he claims that it is impossible to meaningfully state both that God does exist and that God does not exist. This is why people like Richard Dawkins and Bertrand Russell do not say “God does not exist” because they are aware that it is philosophically unsound to do so. Ayer argues that the word ‘God’ is wrongly used. Religious people use ‘God’ as a proper noun i.e. as a name of an existing thing or person. Ayer argues that for a noun to work, it must correspond to a real thing that the senses can experience. For example, the noun ‘chair’ corresponds to pieces of wood, plastic and metal that we can comfortably sit on. Not so with ‘God’ as the word God does not correspond to an empirically verifiable reality (i.e. something we could touch, taste, see, hear or smell.) ‘The mere existence of the noun is enough to foster the illusion that there is a real, or at any rate a possible entity corresponding to it. It is only when we enquire what God’s attributes are that we discover that “God” in this usage is not a genuine name.’ Ayer goes on to dismiss life after death, religious experiences and the antagonism between religion and science. The following quotations illustrate this: ‘But to say that there is something imperceptible inside a man, which is his soul or his real self, and that it goes on living after he is dead, is to make a metaphysical assertion which has no more factual content that the assertion that there is a transcendent God.’ ‘But the mystic, so far from producing propositions which are empirically verified, is unable to produce any intelligible propositions at all. And therefore we say that his intuition has not revealed to him any facts. It is no use his saying that he has apprehended facts but is unable to express them. For we know that if he really had acquired any information, he would be able to express it.’ ‘Since the religious utterances of the theist are not genuine propositions at all, they cannot stand in any logical relation to the propositions of science.’ A2 Religious Studies: Developments (Paper 3) Philosophy of Religion. Critical Unbelief: Baron d’Holbach (1723-1789) Baron d’Holbach was part of the French atheist movement of the Eighteenth Century which helped to lead to the establishment of a non-religious republic in France in 1789. Whilst there was a group of philosophers in France at the time, such as Voltaire, who were keen to argue against the influence of the Church, but maintain belief in God, there were others such as d’Holbach who wanted to sweep away belief in God altogether, claiming that belief was the result of misguided human imagination. Critical unbelief is the view that theism is an incoherent system of beliefs and critical unbelievers attempt to show that belief in God is based upon flawed arguments. The most recent critical atheist is Richard Dawkins who has attempted to systematically undermine belief in God. In his ‘The System of Nature’, D’Holbach attempted to show that religious belief was incoherent on the following grounds: 1. 2. 3. 4. 5. God was created by humans; An infinite being cannot relate to a finite being; God allows evil to exist; The revealed word of God is incoherent; God takes sides and is not impartial. 1. God was created by humans. D’Holbach argued that humans have a tendency to believe that what they are not capable of fully understanding is much more noble than things that we can understand. It is this belief, d’Holbach argues, that gave rise to belief in God: ‘These prejudices in man for the marvellous, appear to have been the source that gave birth to those wonderful, unintelligible qualities with which theology clothed the sovereign of the world.’ Humans, fully aware of their own inadequacies, created a God who was exempt from all of those failings, who was absolutely perfect in every way. Like Dawkins and Russell after him, d’Holbach argued that it was fear that led us to create this supernatural superbeing. 2. An infinite being cannot relate to a finite being. But, according to d’Holbach, this infinite being caused a problem. By making all the attributes of God perfect, we had put God out of our reach. D’Holbach argued that sensing this problem, the Church re-clothed God with human qualities. However, d’Holbach argued that this was a mistake: ‘[The Church] did not see that a God who was immaterial, destitute of corporeal organs, was neither able to think nor to act as material beings, whose peculiar organizations render them susceptible of the qualities, the feelings, the will, the virtues that are found in A2 Religious Studies: Developments (Paper 3) Philosophy of Religion. them. The necessity it felt to assimilate God to his worshippers, to make an affinity between them, made it pass over without consideration these palpable contradictions.’ D’Holbach argued that the Church was trying to force together two things that did not belong together: the finite and the infinite. He argued further that the Church claimed that humans could have a relationship with God, when this was impossible: if God was immutable and perfect as the Church argued, how could humans have a relationship with God as a relationship necessarily involves change; give and take? D’Holbach also argued that it would be impossible for us to emulate divine, perfect qualities such as goodness, wisdom and justice as these qualities are perfect in God, but we cannot experience God. They might be present in humans, but human justice is surely different from divine justice. 3. God allows evil to exist. D’Holbach begins his discussion of this, by mentioning the religious belief that evil and suffering are the just punishment from God for human sin. He attempts to refute this by arguing that if this is the case, then humans can inflict harm upon God. To offend someone presupposes a relationship with them: if humans offend God by sinning, then they have harmed God. If however, the finite can have no effect upon the infinite, how can this be possible? ‘To offend anyone is to diminish the sum of his happiness; it is to afflict him, to deprive him of something, to make him experience a painful sensation. How is it possible man can operate on the well-being of the omnipotent sovereign of nature, whose happiness is unalterable?’ D’Holbach continues by arguing that God is a tyrant; that God dispenses pain and pleasure according to whim: the innocent suffer and bad people escape unscathed. For d’Holbach, the presence of evil in the world makes God’s attributes of justice and goodness incoherent. 4. The revealed word of God is incoherent. D’Holbach argues that the fact that God has revealed certain truths necessary for human happiness over time, implies that God has been happy for us to exist unhappily without them before their revelation. Take the 10 Commandments for example, which outlaw murder, theft and adultery. Presumably, according to d’Holbach, God was content for some time for these things to continue prior to revealing that he was not. D’Holbach also argues that religious scriptures contain irrational language and stories of God’s iniquity and cruelty to whomever was not on his side. This is inconsistent with the perfect attributes of wisdom, justice and goodness. ‘This granted, all revelation is contrary to the notions they give us of the justice or of the goodness of a God, who they tell us is immutable, and who, without having occasion to reveal himself, or to make himself known to them by miracles, could easily convince and instruct men, and inspire them with those ideas which he desires.’ 5. God takes sides and is not impartial. A2 Religious Studies: Developments (Paper 3) Philosophy of Religion. This last part of d’Holbach’s critique of belief in God argues that God is a being who quite clearly takes sides and protects some from suffering in order to leave others to the cruelty of nature. Throughout, d’Holbach has attempted to show that it is incoherent to believe in the God that is promoted by the Church. Unlike Voltaire however, he was not content to hold belief in deism; that God created the world and left it to its own devices. D’Holbach wanted to remove all belief in God. Karl Marx and Social Unbelief. Karl Marx was a philosopher and social theorist and is one of the most influential thinkers to have ever existed. Marx was a materialist: he believed that every aspect of human life is determined by social and economic factors; material and social need determines the way that we live our lives and the values that we hold. Before you spend any time thinking about Marx, it is important to try to forget many of the things you have heard about him and about Marxism and Communism. Communism does not agree with Capitalism and as a result, Communism has been given a bit of a bad name over the last century. What Marx wanted to achieve. Marx was thinking and writing during the 19th Century. It was during this period of time that the Industrial Revolution was really taking hold in Europe. Huge cities were emerging in which people were working, some as young as 8 or 9 years old, in appalling conditions, for long hours, for very little pay. All around him, in the ‘developed’ world, Marx saw people who were oppressed, exploited and alienated. Marx wanted this to stop. Alienation. Marx was not the first philosopher to be concerned with alienation. Alienation is when one is separated from something of one’s own e.g. one can be alienated from one’s family, friends, possessions or in Marx’s view, one’s humanity i.e. the things that make us human. Marx believed that there were certain things that alienate humans from their human nature. He believed that once these were removed (by a Communist revolution) humans would be free from oppression and alienation. The things he wished to remove were: Personal property Capitalism (exploiting the skills of others to make money for an individual) Individual ownership of the means of production: factories/machines, but also intellectual production such as education State religion Idealism in philosophy (he was a materialist). Marx and Religion. A2 Religious Studies: Developments (Paper 3) Philosophy of Religion. Marx famously wrote of religion: ‘Religious distress is at the same time the expression of real distress and also the protest against real distress. Religion is the sigh of the oppressed creature, the heart of a heartless world, just as it is the spirit of spiritless conditions. It is the opium of the people.’ Marx saw religion as an indication that something else was wrong (the sigh of the oppressed creature) which he believed to be capitalism and the capitalist state. He worried that Christianity, with its emphasis on hard work and heavenly rewards in an afterlife, contributed to the continuation of oppression and was a distraction from the need for revolution. He saw it as a painkiller (opium). Marx believed that the idea of God is a human attempt to cope with the harshness of human life and the pain resulting from social and economic deprivation. Many people falsely believe that Marx wished to abolish religion full stop; he did not. (‘We no longer regard religion as the cause, but only as the manifestation of secular narrowness’) Marx believed that many people were no longer connected to the real world in which they lived and that anything which distracted people from the real world had to be abolished because it prevented humans from being free. Marx wanted to get rid of religion in the following circumstances: 1. When religion is promoted by the state: states must be secular (nonreligious); 2. When religion is an illusion or distraction from the conditions of oppression; 3. When religion prevents humans from being humans: e.g. when people feel that Jesus Christ or God have achieved things in their lives, when really it is the people themselves who have achieved this (projection). Marx was of the opinion that once society was reformed and people were freed from oppression, once people saw each other as fellow human beings, not as means to another end, once this happened religion would take care of itself and if it survived would be a true reflection of human nature. Any religious feelings would have nothing to do with the heavens, but would become Humanism or Socialism. Projection. Projection was an idea that Marx adopted from a man called Ludwig Feuerbach. Feuerbach believed that humans had created religion and God by selecting all the positive human attributes, magnifying them into perfections and worshipping them as a god. (‘Jesus Christ is the intermediary to whom man transfers the burden of all his divinity.’) God is therefore a projection of human virtues. For many at the time, this was the decisive proof that God does not exist. Marx disagreed with Feuerbach on many other things, but saw this theory as a way to start clawing back to humans the attributes that were rightfully theirs, which had been taken away and given to God: most A2 Religious Studies: Developments (Paper 3) Philosophy of Religion. religions teach that everything we have comes from God and that it is to Him that we owe our thanks. Sigmund Freud and Naturalistic Unbelief. Naturalistic unbelief is the view that religious belief is false because its origins can be explained. It is argued by those who hold this view, that if we can explain why religious belief arose or was invented in the first place, we can show it to be false. Many people have argued that religion arose to meet the needs of social groups: for example, that the idea of God was invented to coerce people to behave in particular ways through threats of supernatural violence or eternal punishment for sin. Others have argues that it arose out of a misunderstanding of the way that the elements worked e.g. that rain was operated by supernatural forces that humans had to appease. One person who has argued towards naturalistic unbelief was Sigmund Freud. Sigmund Freud is often referred to as the father of psychoanalysis, which is the discipline in psychology of trying to establish the cause(s) of neurosis and to resolve them. Freud was interested in the way religion developed in primitive society and felt that if we could work this development out, it might help to explain modern psychological problems. Freud’s work on religion underwent a long process of development, largely due to the criticisms levelled at his work and his need to revise and develop his arguments. His work can be split into two main areas, the first being based on his book Totem and Taboo and his later work, The Future of an Illusion. Totem and Taboo. Freud wrote ‘Totem and Taboo’ in 1917. He wrote after a long succession of academics had made visits to ‘primitive’ civilizations to study the habits of ‘natives’ and ‘savages’ (their terms!). People like J.G. Frazer, McLellan and Robertson Smith had done research into the significance of totems and Freud believed that the totem held significance for understanding religious belief. Freud believed that there must be a motive behind religious beliefs i.e. a reason why people hold them in the first place and believed that ancient societies held the key to solving this problem. ‘One day the brothers who had been driven out [by their father] came together, killed and devoured their father and so made an end of the patriarchal [father led] horde…Cannibal savages as they were, it goes without saying that they devoured their victim as well as killing him. The totem meal, which is perhaps mankind’s earliest festival, would thus be a repetition and commemoration of this memorable and criminal deed, which was the beginning of so many things – of social organization, of moral restrictions and of religion.’ Totem and Taboo A2 Religious Studies: Developments (Paper 3) Philosophy of Religion. A totem is a species of animal or more rarely, a type of plant. Members of a clan were forbidden from killing the totem animal except for during an annual ritual, where all the male members of the clan were expected to take part in the ritual killing of the totem animal. The death of the animal was at first mourned, then a celebration took place afterwards. In return, the clan expected protection from the totem animal and also help in sickness. Freud wondered where the practice of totemism began and suggested the story above. He believed this to be the case as totemic religion had two prohibitions: 1. Murder was forbidden and 2. It was forbidden to have sex with anyone else in the clan. Freud thought that these prohibitions came from somewhere and suggested the guilt felt by the young males who had murdered their father. As a way of making the feeling of guilt easier, they created the totem animal to represent their father and then made the two prohibitions. The prohibition of incest came because of the reason for the boys murdering their father in the first place; because the father kept all the females to himself and the boys wanted them. After they had killed their father, they made the feeling of guilt easier by giving up their claim to these women. Freud believed this to be the origin of religion (although he later denied this). The totem eventually became what we understand to be God today; a father figure who protects and a religious system that prohibits us from doing things we really wish or desire to do. He also believed that the guilt associated with this first murder was passed on to all humans. He found evidence of this in something called the Oedipus complex; a desire he thought young men have to kill their father and take his place with their mother. However, this is very problematic. Whilst a great deal of what Freud says about how religion has developed makes perfect sense, there are a number of problems with Totem and Taboo. Primarily, there is no evidence that this murder ever took place. Freud has suggested a reason for the existence of totemic religion, the reasons why we see God as a father figure and the existence of rules against murder and incest existing in the most primitive societies; he has looked at a state of affairs now and tried to establish a past reason for this current state of affairs. As such then, he may be guilty of the genetic fallacy. Also, to claim that all religious feeling results from problems with man’s relationship with his father, severely underestimates the complex ideas people may have about God. The Future of an Illusion. Freud wrote ‘The Future of an Illusion’ in 1927. In this book, he claimed that religion is an illusion based upon wish-fulfilment. He saw that life is hard and causes a great deal of unhappiness in humans. He also believed that religion offers a sense of protection from this unhappiness. The wishes he thought humans wanted fulfilled were as follows: To be able to predict the behaviour of other humans and guarantee that they will do us no harm. A2 Religious Studies: Developments (Paper 3) Philosophy of Religion. To be able to master and control the cruelty and destructiveness of nature. To be able to not fear death. To know what fate has in store for us. To have otherwise inexplicable events explained for us. To be rewarded for good and have evildoers punished. To always have a father to protect, as in childhood. Freud believed that humans had created religion and the gods to fulfil these wishes. The gods, Freud thought, had three main tasks: 1. They must remove the terrors of nature 2. They must make the cruelty of fate easy to bear and help humans understand it, especially in death 3. They must reward humans for the struggle of life with other humans and provide a morality. Freud therefore believed that religion was a creation by humans to give a psychological sense of protection. He suggested that this need for protection was a feeling that originated in childhood and at that time was fulfilled by the father. It is for this reason that God is like a father; he offers protection but is also an individual to be feared. He also argued that divine revelation was an illusion and used to strengthen the claims of religion. Freud also tried to show that it is irrational to hold religious beliefs (not that the beliefs themselves are irrational). This is known as an ad hominem critique, one that criticises the believers believing, not the belief itself. He wrote that we are told to have religious beliefs for three reasons: 1. We should believe because our ancestors did 2. We have proof of these beliefs handed down from these times (Bible etc.) 3. It is forbidden to raise the question of their authenticity at all. He dismissed them as follows. Reason 3 should make us suspicious if we are forbidden from questioning. Reason 1 is poor as our ancestors were more ignorant than us and may have been mistaken; they did believe the earth to be flat after all. Reason 2 is also poor as the Bible is full of contradictions and cannot be trusted. Freud argued that religion is an illusion created by human wishes or desires. He argued that illusions are not errors but a skewed perception of reality arising from a desire for something to be so and used the example of Christopher Columbus’ who believed he had discovered India, when in fact he had found America. Freud in effect claimed that religious need is the product of an unhealthy mind. If a person is basically fulfilled by life, they would have no need of the sense of protection offered by religion. ‘We know approximately at what periods and by what kind of men religious doctrines were created. If in addition we discover the motives that led to this, our attitude to the problem of religion will undergo a marked displacement. We shall tell ourselves that it would be very nice if there were a God who created the world and was a benevolent A2 Religious Studies: Developments (Paper 3) Philosophy of Religion. Providence, and if there were a moral order in the universe and an afterlife; but it is a very striking fact that all this is exactly as we are bound to wish it to be.’ The Future of an Illusion Problems. Freud’s starting point for his criticism of religion is the Oedipus complex, which he established from psychoanalytical observations. He therefore projects a problem observed in a few patients onto humankind as a whole. There is no proof of his connection between totemism/religion and the murder of an imagined father and the feelings of guilt that went with this. Paul Ricouer has pointed out that psychoanalysis involves how religious beliefs work, not whether or not they are true. R.S. Lee has argued that psychoanalysis can be used to help believers discover subconscious motivations for belief and allow them to arrive at a better understanding of faith. Life is not just about enduring misery and many people take part in religion for different reasons than Freud suggested. Freud basically tricks people into doubting their own sanity; he claims that for someone to need religion, they must have a defective relationship with their father. Freud would have known little or nothing of Buddhism, a religion which does not claim belief in a father-like God and aims to create mental stability through meditation and correct living.