Lea Ypi (LSE) 1st draft Who is exploited? The moral dilemmas of guestworker programmes It is often argued that guestworkers are exploited, and that unfair advantage is taken from their vulnerable position in host societies. This paper assesses the accuracy of this claim by examining three different theories of exploitation: a domination theory, an egalitarian theory and a sufficientarian theory. It argues that neither the defenders of these theories nor their critics manage to capture what is normatively problematic about guestworker programmes. Analysing their shortcomings shows that guestworker programmes exploit workers taken collectively (as a class) rather than distributively (as individuals divided by state-boundaries). The paper concludes by examining the remedial principles to which a similar perspective gives rise and by outlining their political implications. 1. Introduction: workers and guests A worker is someone who exchanges his labour for money. A guest worker is someone who exchanges his labour for money, as a guest. A guestworker therefore belongs, at the same time, to two distinguishable but related sets: the set of workers, who typically exchange their labour for money, and the set of migrant workers, who exchange their labour for money for a specified amount of time and in a foreign labour market. It is often said that guestworkers are exploited and that unfair advantage is taken from the (allegedly) vulnerable position of foreign workers in domestic labour markets (for some relevant discussions (see (Attas 2000; Carens 2008; Lenard and Straehle forthcoming; Mayer 2005; Ottonelli and Torresi 2010; Stilz 2010; Walzer 1983) for discussions)). But are guestworkers exploited in virtue of being workers or of being guests or both or neither? 1 The answer to these questions depends in part on the kind of moral baseline upon which we choose to focus in trying to capture the wrong of exploitation. If we link that wrong to the occurrence of domination we might think that guestworkers are exploited because they are guests rather than citizens (or permanent residents). Deprived of a significant (even if not full) range of political and social rights that normally protect citizens and permanent residents from the failures of the market and the whims of employers, they can easily be manipulated and taken unfair advantage of. Let us call this “the domination theory of exploitation”. Alternatively, if we think an agent is exploited whenever an unequal distribution of benefits systematically follows relatively equal amounts of effort for relatively similar tasks performed, we might say that a guestworker is exploited both because he is a worker and because he is a guest. As a worker, his labour is undervalued. As a guest, his labour is undervalued compared to that of workers operating in similar market conditions. Call this the “egalitarian theory of exploitation”. Finally, guestworkers might be considered exploited because they operate in a market that fails to reward their labour with sufficient access to primary resources. If prospective temporary workers are on the verge of starvation and accept employment offers just because they couldn’t afford to reject them, they are vulnerable to being taking unfair advantage of. We might call this “the sufficientarian account of exploitation”. This paper argues that neither the domination account nor the egalitarian account nor the sufficientarian account fully capture why guestworkers are exploited. To illustrate the wrong of exploitation, we should focus on workers taken collectively as a class rather than distributively as citizens belonging to different countries. The exploitation of guestworkers is, I shall argue, a result of the collective unfreedom of workers taken together, not of guestworkers considered as a special category deserving particular normative attention. The relevant question to ask when reflecting on the moral dilemmas of guestworkers is not whether guestworkers are exploited but whether guestworker programmes are exploitative. This paper claims that they are. The exploitative nature of guestworker programmes is manifest in the way labour markets operate in a global sphere, in the way states and private employers interact with each 2 other, and in the way the global distribution of labour negatively affects guestworkers and domestic workers alike (even if not in equal measure). Viewed thus, guestworker programmes make for a curious object of enquiry. Rather than an issue to be explored in the context of a theory of just migration, they present a relevant case in which an old and seemingly outdated issue, the exploitation of the working class as a collective agent, re-surfaces with all its normative force. The remedial principles to which a similar perspective gives rise are principles seeking to abolish the exploitation of workers in general rather than the exploitation of guestworkers in particular. The problem of guestworker programmes can therefore be addressed not by considering a theory that concerns the distribution of the benefits and burdens of freedom of movement but by intervening at the level of the basic institutional structure according to which we want markets to operate. 2. The dilemmas of guestworker programmes Since the invention of the passport and the institutionalization of border controls, guestworker programmes have become an integral part of states’ efforts to cope with transitions in industrial relations and shortages of labour supply. The first attempts to regulate the entrance of temporary workers date back to the late 19th century, following a process that accompanied the consolidation of the national territorial state and the related increasing hostility towards prospective immigrants.1 Despite a short period of skepticism towards such programmes in the mid-Eighties, guestworker schemes are now in place in most affluent countries of the world: Mexican agricultural workers in the USA, Central and East-European seasonal workers in Western Europe, Mozambiquan diamond miners in South Africa, Asian construction workers in the Middle East (especially in Saudi Arabia, Kuwait, Qatar, United Arab Emirates, and Oman), Indonesian nannies in Malaysia, and Phillippina carers in Canada are only some of the relevant cases in point (S. Castles 2006; Hahamovitch 2003). And there are no Prussia’s introduction of guestworker programmes occurred in the two decades following German unification, whereas migrant workers employed in the diamond and gold mines of southern Africa followed British attempts to unify British colonies, Boer Republics and African kingdoms under British rule, see (Hahamovitch 2003). 1 3 signs that the flux is about to stop: since 1997, the number of temporary migrants traveling to OECD countries has been growing annually by 9 percent. Migration to East and West Asia, including Saudi Arabia and the United Arab Emirates, has also increased by 2.5 percent per year since 1985 (Agunias and Newland 2007). Notwithstanding a number of governmental and intergovernmental attempts to modify the procedures surrounding the employment of guestworkers (especially in the EU area), the conditions of their arrival and the contracts regulating their stay have only superficially changed (S. Castles 2006). Guestworkers are neither long-term migrants nor short-term visitors. The conditions of their temporary settlement are determined by bilateral contracts between sending and receiving societies, and they are only allowed to remain in the host state for strictly delimited amounts of time. They are also typically denied access to the political and social benefits granted to citizens (and often also permanent residents). On the one hand, it is claimed, guestworker programmes continue to serve well the interests of states (in particular Western states) experiencing industrial change, shortages in specific sectors of the labour market and demographic shifts, especially population ageing and increasing decline in fertility rates. On the other hand, the conditions under which they are able to promote these goals remain concerning. Most guestworkers cannot participate in elections, cannot claim access to public subsidies (e.g. unemployment benefits), cannot join collective bargaining processes, and are in general deprived of the right to have a say on the terms according to which the host political community requires them to conduct their lives. They are entitled to fewer benefits of membership even compared to other immigrant workers, e.g. compared to students who have decided to settle and work in the receiving state, compared to refugees or compared to other immigrants who have gained entrance as a result of practices of family reunification (to mention but some of the most prominent categories). Unlike these other immigrants, guestworkers are typically tied to one particular work sector, are prevented from changing employers, cannot apply for permanent residence and eventually citizenship after a certain period of time, are often denied the right to apply for family reunification, and are subject to being deported from the country if they lose their jobs (Ruhs and Martin 2008: 251), see also (Stephen Castles and Kosack 1985; Hollifield 1992; Parrenas 2001). 4 Applauded by employers, politicians and policy-makers and often mistrusted by ordinary citizens, guestworker programmes are likely to provoke bitter controversy both when they are rejected and when they are endorsed.2 Some see them as providing de-facto coverage to a regime of second-class citizenship which exploits the contribution of workers but offers them no membership benefits to negotiate the terms of that contribution. Others see them as a perhaps non-ideal but nevertheless acceptable form of economic support for workers who can migrate for a specific amount of time to save money, send remittances home and contribute to the development of their countries upon return. Accepting or rejecting such arguments has often been considered to depend on the terms according to which guestworkers are employed in host states, the assessment of their occupational position compared to members of receiving societies and the potential benefits they receive compared to fellow-citizens who are left behind. In other words, addressing the moral dilemmas of guestworker programmes has often been attempted in the context of theories of just migration seeking to fairly distribute the benefits and burdens of freedom of movement. That may not necessarily be the most appropriate way to go. To understand why, we need to examine in some detail one of the most vexed questions that is typically raised in the context of the employment of guestworkers: the issue of their potential exploitation. As we shall see in what follows it is when we address this question that both the moral dilemmas of guestworker programmes and the shortcomings of their solutions come prominently to the fore. 3. Guestworkers and domination The fact that guestworkers are denied many of the standard membership rights typically granted to citizens (and often also permanent residents) has induced some to criticize these programmes as exploitative, linking their exploitative nature to the political disenfranchisement from which guestworkers typically suffer (Walzer 1983: For an informative discussion of the attitudes of the American public towards temporary work programmes see Shayerah Ilias, Katherine Fennelly, and Christopher M. Federico, 'American Attitudes toward Guest Worker Policies', International Migration Review, 42/4 (2008), 741-66. 2 5 59). Being deprived of political membership implies that guestworkers are unable to appeal to the protection of state institutions to defend themselves from abuses of power in the public sphere. Although they are required to comply with the rules of receiving states, they do not have an equal say in the making of these rules. They are subjected to the laws but banned from authoring them. Political inequality leaves guestworkers in a vulnerable condition and exposes them to the possibility of others taking advantage of that condition to derive profit from it. Indeed, so the argument goes, the very point of their disenfranchised status is to prevent temporary workers from overcoming their vulnerability. For if guestworkers ceased to be treated as politically unequal, they would end up being just like domestic workers, and the benefits accrued by the programmes in which they take part would cease to serve the interests of employers in the host state. The exploitation of guestworkers depends on the status of second-class citizens to which they are confined due to the absence of political and economic rights. Of course being politically disenfranchised is not a sufficient condition for declaring guestworkers an exploited category. After all guestworkers are visitors, and like all other visitors (tourists and students, for example), it is reasonable to ask them to respect the terms under which they are admitted. We do not find problematic the fact that tourists are required to obey traffic laws in the countries that they visit, nor do we ever try to campaign to give them a say in the making of such laws. However, some might argue here that, unlike tourists and students, guestworkers are deprived of the benefits of political membership whilst being asked to contribute to the system that creates and upholds such benefits (Carens 2008; Stilz 2010). It is the contribution guestworkers make to the production of public goods in receiving societies without being able to claim back equal benefits which might then account for the unfair treatment to which they allegedly subjected. However, it is not clear why we must always expect the sphere in which a productive contribution is made and the sphere where equal benefits are claimed to overlap so neatly with each other. The argument from cooperation in the production of certain goods would have more force if guestworkers were deprived of the benefits of citizenship altogether, not necessarily if they were deprived of such benefits in a particular host country but continued to retain access to them in their home states. 6 To see this point, consider the following example. David, a prominent academic from Oxford has been invited to give a series of keynote lectures at the University of Toronto. The series lasts for one month and, although David is guaranteed accommodation on campus during that period, he has no right to borrowing facilities from the library, no access to a university of Toronto email address, and no entitlement to attend meetings of the academic board. He is of course working hard to prepare his lectures and contributing to upholding the standards of teaching and research at the University of Toronto. Yet the benefits he can claim during his visiting period in the department are significantly lower compared to those granted to his friend Joe, who is a member of the department. Still, it would be difficult to insist that David is being exploited. He is a member of Oxford University, can borrow from his college library, can use his Oxford email address, and can attend departmental meetings in his home university. He has rights of membership in the Politics department at Oxford. Although he may miss important meetings and fail to have a say on particular funding decisions during his research stay in Canada, he will be able to make up for those by being an active member of the department and influence the agenda of meetings upon his return. Guestworkers do not lose all membership rights because of their status of guests. They remain citizens of their country of origin, they enjoy diplomatic protection from such countries in their host state, and they retain relevant membership entitlements (such as voting) in the places from which they come from. Although they do make a contribution to the economy of receiving states without being able to claim the same entitlements as citizens of those states (just like David can’t claim the same entitlements as Joe at the university of Toronto even though his lectures make a productive contribution there), their work contracts have been negotiated with the input of their home states. Despite the fact that guestworkers do not have an immediate say in making the rules with which they are asked to comply, in the long term they can contribute modifying the criteria on the basis of which multilateral contracts are signed. In other words, they can negotiate acceptable terms of interaction through the institutions of their home states. Of course all this presupposes both that states signing guestworker contracts must have roughly equal negotiating powers to come up with mutually advantageous terms of cooperation, and that workers from sending states must have ample margins of 7 democratic participation to ensure their voice really is channelled by the appropriate mechanisms for political decision making. In practice this is hardly ever the case. But if guestworkers end up being exploited as a result of inequalities in bargaining power between sending and receiving states or due to insufficient channels of democratic participation in their home countries, this simply strengthens the point we are trying to make. Socio-political disenfranchisement does not by itself explain the kind of injustice suffered by guestworkers in the countries that they visit, nor does lack of equal rights of membership suffice to illustrate why such category of people is always vulnerable to exploitation. Other factors have to be taken into account before we can establish the moral baseline on grounds of which we can show that unfair advantage has been taken from them. 4. Guestworkers and egalitarianism An alternative way to think about the exploitation of guestworkers is to reflect on their condition by observing the relative inequalities of occupational position in which temporary labour programmes tend to confine them. Short-term contracts subject guestworkers to terms of employment that differ significantly from those of domestic workers. They typically work the same hours, perform the same jobs but are paid simply less. Moreover, unlike domestic workers, guestworkers are barred from trying to change employers, cannot search for jobs different from the ones that they were initially admitted to perform, are bound to remain in a particular work sector, enjoy limited opportunities for participation in workers’ unions, and have very little or no say in the possible extension of their work contracts. Guestworkers are at a relative disadvantage compared to domestic workers. Some have argued, it is precisely this relatively different position in the job market that renders them vulnerable to exploitation (Attas 2000; Carens 2008). But what exactly is the baseline with regard to which we consider the process to confer an unfair advantage upon those who buy labour at the expense of those who sell it? To answer this question we need to look at the dynamic of supply and demand governing the exchange of labour. Those who defend the egalitarian theory of 8 exploitation typically do so from a classical liberal economic perspective. On this view, a just price of labour is the one that emerges if supply and demand balance each other in circumstances of perfect competition, undistorted by extra-market factors. The problem, critics argue, is that guestworkers’ restricted access to the labour market modifies the nature of the exchange between employers and workers. Due to the contractual constraints temporary workers face, the labour market is partially closed to them. Their freedom of occupational choice is severely restricted. Consequently the negotiations in which they are involved tend to favour those placed in a stronger bargaining position, for example those that have full capacity to choose who to hire. But, unlike the domination case we examined in the previous section, the problem is not, inherently, one of limited access to the benefits of political membership. The problem is rather that, due to their socio-economic placement in society, temporary workers are treated unfairly because they are forced to accept jobs remunerated at a price which is lower than the equilibrium price for their labour. Exploitation consists in employers profiting more and workers obtaining less for their labour than they would if they were to exchange their labour in perfectly competitive markets (Attas 2000: 75-9; Carens 2008: 12-14). Those who endorse this perspective typically emphasize that one of its advantages consists in allowing us to distinguish between denying guestworkers the full package of political membership benefits and compelling us to extend them comprehensive rights of participation in the economic sphere. Whilst fellow-citizens right to self-determination may entitle them to deny permanent rights of political participation to temporary members, guestworkers are entitled to an inclusive list of rights usually associated to the economic sphere. More specifically, it is argued that freedom of exchange, freedom of occupational choice, freedom of movement and organisation, the right to participate in collective bargaining, to strike and to unemployment benefits and compensation for loss of income ought to be extended to guestworkers to allow them to remove the cause of unequal exchange for the wages they receive (Attas 2000: 77). If guestworkers’ vulnerability to exploitation is due to their limited access to the economic sphere, making that sphere fully accessible to them might sound like a plausible remedial measure. 9 We may wonder however whether drawing a sharp line of division between political and economic membership as this argument seems to require, really serves the kind of egalitarian theory that its defenders would want to support. One problem with placing the burden of the argument on a market-centred, classical liberal perspective is that it forces us to see the market and the state as independent social agents. If we want to focus consistently on the supply and demand process generated by interactions between economic agents based in different states we also have to take seriously the conditions that trigger that process in the first place: the need to fill labour market shortages in the host-society and the availability of excess labour-force in the sending state. And we also have to consider the voluntary, spontaneous and impersonal nature of labour exchange in a global, rather than simply domestic market. This drives our attention to an issue which is crucial to assessing whether guestworkers are exploited within the egalitarian theory we have just outlined: the link between the conditions on the basis of which guestworkers are admitted and the demand for labour in the host-state. Empirical analysis suggests that not all guestworker contracts are the same; not only do they vary from country to country but they also depend significantly on the kinds of jobs that temporary workers are required to perform. The higher the demand for labour in the host-state, the more attractive the contracts offered to guestworkers, the better the occupational conditions under which they are admitted. As many authors suggest, the international market for skilled and highly skilled workers is characterized by “excess” demand for labour (S. Castles 2006; Ruhs and Martin 2008) see also (Findlay 1995). An increasing number of developed countries compete with each other for a relatively small pool of highly qualified workers, for example specialists in management, information and communication technology and people working in the health sector (S. Castles 2006: 749). In this case economic exclusion does not always follow recruitment of temporary labour, and freedom of occupational choice may or may not be curtailed. The answer will depend on the kind of labour force a country is looking for. In the case of skilled labour workers can often decide whether or not to accept the contracts offered to them. Qualified migrants can to choose among a number of potential host-states, and their choice of destination depends both on prospective earnings and future terms of employment in the receiving states. 10 Some examples might be useful to illustrate this point. Canada and Australia, two countries that have traditionally focused their admissions’ policy on the recruitment of skilled workers provide qualified them with rights associated to permanent residence immediately upon arrival. Likewise, the UK’s Highly Skilled Migrant Programme offers qualified migrants the right to apply for permanent residence after only five years of residence in the UK. Ireland has also recently been involved with the introduction of a long-term residence status to attract migrants with skills in short supply in the Irish. In contrast, Germany’s “Green Card” programme designed to attract IT workers offered a five-year work permit rather than permanent residency status, and did not succeed in obtaining similar numbers of applications compared to countries with more flexible policies (these examples are taken from (Ruhs and Martin 2008: 254) who also provide more references to the relevant data). States and employers seeking to employ skilled migrant workers are likely to offer them not only high wages but also comprehensive entitlements, often resulting in migrants having more rather than less freedom of occupational choice. These examples illustrate that there are no clear-cut conclusions to be drawn from an all-purpose comparison of temporary workers to domestic workers regardless of their position in the domestic and global economy. The relationship between exclusion and inclusion in the economic sphere is itself dependent upon the prior evolution of the process of supply and demand that governs the admission of temporary workers. Yet if one takes seriously that process, it is not clear how we can justify an obligation to provide all temporary workers (regardless of their skills and without consideration for the jobs they are supposed to perform) a comprehensive package of economic membership rights. If (as in the argument above) we try to distinguish economic from political membership and say that we are only interested in the former but not the latter, on what grounds can we interfere with market processes upon which the contracts and wages offered to guestworkers depend? If a country seeks to recruit high-skilled workers and the demand is relatively high but the supply is low, chances are that guestworkers will be admitted on very inclusive terms. If a country is facing labour shortages in a low-skilled work sector, employers will only be interested in temporary work if they can make offers at rates lower than domestic ones. As with all market-based processes, the nature of this transaction is spontaneous, voluntary and 11 hard to criticize precisely for that reason. The higher the cost of foreign labour, the less beneficial it would be from the host state’s perspective to fill shortages through temporary worker programmes. The lower the supply of workers, the more advantageous the terms and conditions on which temporary migrants are admitted to perform their jobs. Even though wage parity might be desirable to ensure guestworkers and domestic workers compete on equal terms, the process of supply and demand governing the admission of guestworkers de facto limits the numbers of those to whom full economic inclusion can be offered (Chanda 2001: 635) (S. Castles 2006). One might of course fault such programmes for prioritizing the needs of receiving states. But this is not necessarily the case. As many studies emphasize, the more entitlements guestworkers obtain in host states, the more settled they feel, the less likely they are to return to their home countries. This is not good news for the citizens of these countries who might benefit from guestworker schemes in the form of remittances and regeneration of a stagnant labour market. It also explains why important limitations to temporary work contracts are often introduced with the full support of sending states whose anxiety for the potential permanent loss of critical workforce is no less relevant than their fear for the drop in remittances or the consequent decline in economic growth. To give just one example, the Canada-Mexico Seasonal Agricultural Workers Program is based on a memorandum of understanding between Mexico and Canada, in place since 1974 which established that only married men with children could participate, leaving their families behind. Restrictions were not only endorsed but actually increased by the Mexican authorities, who required temporary migrants to even bring back evaluations from their employers, in order to ensure being kept in the eligibility lists for the next work season (Ruhs and Martin 2008). Of course, we can still argue that guestworkers are vulnerable to being taken advantage of as a result of deprivation from the benefits of socio-economic inclusion in the host state. But the background context is one of competing considerations of supply and demand with a view to the stakes of all affected parties. The conditions of labour exchange in the global economic sphere are established by states who act more or less unconstrained by extra-market factors. Once we understand by “market” a global rather than simply domestic market, the equilibrium price of labour appears consequently affected, and the egalitarian case for exploitation appears harder to make. 12 To sum up, the arguments in this section illustrated two important issues. The first is that the egalitarian theory fails to show that all guestworkers are exploited. Exclusion from the socio-economic sphere is not an intrinsic feature of all guestworker programmes neither is the exploitation of all foreign workers its unavoidable outcome. The second, and more problematic issue for the view we examined, is that even if unequal access to socio-economic benefits did follow such programs, it would occur within a framework of voluntary transactions between actors whose negotiations depend on the employment needs and labour supply in both sending and receiving states. From the classical liberal perspective to which the egalitarian theory ties itself, one would have no reason to interfere with how the global markets work. Relatedly, and importantly for the point this theory tries to make, the consequent price paid for temporary labour could not be said to be unfair. 5. Guestworkers and sufficiency One final strategy for reflecting on the exploitation of guestworkers is to think of the baseline for qualifying a transaction as fair or unfair with reference to a sufficiency criterion. Many guestworkers, it is often said, are typically employed to perform jobs that are difficult, dirty and dangerous. They lack the security and welfare guarantees that would allow them to cope with such hazardous occupational circumstances, and they are vulnerable to being taken unfair advantage of because they have nothing else to opt for. According to the sufficientarian account exploitation takes place when the following two conditions occur. Firstly, an agent is made an offer that he could not refuse, on pain of being left with not enough resources to lead a minimally decent life.3 Secondly, the transaction is less beneficial or more costly than it would be if the agent started to bargain from a position of sufficiency (i.e. he had enough to begin with) (see (Mayer 2005: 321ff) for a more thorough discussion). As defenders of sufficientarian accounts often admit, establishing how much is “enough” in this case is far from trivial. There seem to be two candidate options: one Resources is here a generic term employed to refer to whatever unit of distribution we might prefer, i.e. primary goods, opportunities, capabilities etc. 3 13 which focuses more on the sending state, and one which focuses more on the receiving state. Since guestworkers are only employed for a specific amount of time and typically enter host-states with the intention of returning home at the end of their contract, it might seem that the appropriate baseline to start with is the position of a worker in the sending state. If agents have enough in their own country, they can choose whether to accept an offer of work abroad or to remain in that country. If their decision to move is constrained by not having enough to survive in the home country then it does not seem to constitute a genuine choice. And if one accepts an offer because he has no other choice, then we might say that someone is vulnerable to being taken advantage of in the host state. The prospective temporary worker in this case accepts an offer he could not refuse, on pain of being left with an insufficient amount of resources to survive. If on the other hand, someone already has sufficient resources at their disposal in the home state, they are free to decline the offer if they do not find it acceptable. Their agreement to the terms of the contract in this case might be considered mutually beneficial. For defenders of sufficientarian accounts, the relevant counterfactual to consider is what a worker earning above the threshold of sufficiency in the labourexporting nation would choose to do. As one author puts it “we judge their exploitability by whether they will have enough if they do not migrate, and we judge exploitable workers to be exploited if they gain less than one with enough at home would likely accept” (Mayer 2005: 322). Interestingly, however, when we raise the issue of guestworkers’ exploitation with a sufficientarian criterion in mind, empirical evidence leaves us with very few relevant cases. Prospective temporary workers, studies show, do not represent the bottom social strata in sending societies. The lowest-earning citizens often lack the knowledge, skills and means necessary to even take the risk of emigrating. Those that fall below the threshold of sufficiency typically rule themselves out of the prospective pool of candidates, a pool which involves citizens normally placed in the middle of the social stratification hierarchy. Unable to afford the transportation costs and risks involved in leaving everything behind, the poorest citizens of poor states are much more likely to starve at home. This also explains why, for example, in a continent like Africa, 14 with rampant poverty and the highest concentration of absolutely poor citizens in the world, emigration rates recently have in fact declined.4 All this implies that real life temporary workers negotiate from a position in which sufficientarian criteria are met. Even though they are prepared to waive some rights for a period of time in exchange for better pay, they do not act so on pain of continuing to lead a life in which their own survival is at risk. As some of the evidence from the West German guestworker programme of the Sixties and Seventies indicates, Turkish temporary workers who moved to Germany had on average better skills, comparatively higher levels of education and more financial means available than their fellow-citizens who were left behind. The standard guestworker earned four times more than domestic workers before departure and six times as much as them during his stay ((Paine 1974) see also the discussion in (Mayer 2005)). A similar trend reveals itself also in some of the more recent guestworker programmes. Empirical studies in the female migrant population of two of the major labour-exporting nations, Mexico and the Phillippines revealed that a majority of their temporary workers had decent high school education, and occupied clerical, retail, or professional positions prior to leaving these countries ((Momsen 1999), see also the discussion in (Stilz 2010)). In both these countries, despite much hope that guestworker programmes would provide a win/win solution helping relieve domestic unemployment in sending societies and fill labour shortages in host states, this did not turn out to be the case. Prospective guestworkers already had jobs in their home states and their skills were not easy to replace. Unemployment rates remained the same (Ghosh 2005). Those most vulnerable citizens who would have most desperately needed temporary contracts to ensure the survival of themselves and their families tended to stay where they were. This is perhaps the most troubling feature of the relation between migration and poverty: the more extreme the conditions of deprivation, the less people tend to move. Emigration rates are lowest in the least developing countries, and the phenomenon of In 1970 Africa supplied 12 per cent of the world’s migrant population but by 2000 that share had declined to 9 per cent of the global migrant stock, see International Organization For Migration, 'International Migration Trends', World Migration 2005 : Costs and Benefits of International Migration, (2005), 379-404 at 391. 4 15 survival migration of the poorest is local and regional at most, but hardly involves changing states (Skeldon 2005). Historical examples also confirm this point: in the case of the Irish potato famine taking place between 1845 and 1850 which triggered one of the greatest migratory flows experienced in Irish history, the most deprived families tended to starve where they were (Miller 1985). Typically, only those who have something: skills, savings, foreign contacts or all of these in combination can afford the risks that transport and the costs of settlement in a completely different environment involve. And whilst the conditions of temporary workers are not optimal, their starting position does not appear as one of desperation. Their choice is not constrained by unavoidable necessity. To be sure, temporary workers are still required to make significant sacrifices, be them living away from their families, having to integrate in a new country or getting to know a foreign labour market. But their decisions are made in the context of a plurality of options available, and they are not threatened with not having enough to survive. A similar predicament has led some to conclude that unless guestworkers fail to access sufficient resources to lead a minimally decent life in their home countries, the offers they receive are not of an exploitative kind (Mayer 2005; Stilz 2010). But we need to distinguish two questions here. The first is whether guestworkers are exploited. The second is whether guestworker programmes are exploitative. If we keep these two questions separate, the answer to them might well end up being different. Even if not all guestworkers are exploited, domestic workers might be. And even if not all workers are exploited distributively, as individuals, they may still be exploited collectively, as members of the working class. 6. Taking workers as a class To explore the possibility of class exploitation as a result of temporary worker programmes, we need to reflect on their impact on workers’ wages in labour-importing nations. A number of empirical studies suggest that guestworkers accept to exchange their labour for wages and employment conditions that are normally higher than than 16 those prevailing in their countries of origin but, as we saw earlier, small by the standards of host countries . Employers themselves often acknowledge that the kinds of wages and employment conditions offered to guestworkers are often too low to be considered acceptable by most local workers (see (Ruhs and Anderson 2010) for a review of the literature). Now, even if we find unproblematic the fact that temporary workers agree to exchange their labour for wages that improve their conditions compared to the country of origin, the effect of these contracts on offers received by domestic workers represents a rather concerning trend. If temporary workers make their decisions in a context of choice sufficient to undermine the view that offers made to them are of an exploitative kind, the same cannot be said for domestic workers. The context of choice for them ends up being significantly restricted as a result. Unless we take sufficiency thresholds to overlap perfectly, what is enough in one context may not be enough in another. After the admission of guestworkers, domestic workers have to choose between wage-offers significantly lower compared to what they might have previously considered enough. Even more worrying is that their acceptance of such offers could mark the beginning of a nasty trend towards levelling down. Does this mean that domestic workers are exploited? I suggest that it does. To see this point we need to apply the same analysis of exploitation through which we assessed the case of guestworkers to workers in receiving societies. We emphasized earlier that a person is vulnerable to being exploited if he is made an offer which he could not reject, on pain of being left with not enough. In the case of guestworkers, the relevant counterfactual with reference to which to assess the threshold of sufficiency was their position in home states. If they reject the offer of employment in a new state and are still left with a sufficient amount in their home country, then they have some margin of (genuine) choice and therefore cannot be considered exploited. But what should be the counterfactual situation with reference to which to assess thresholds of sufficiency in the case of domestic workers? There seem to be two options here, one which includes guestworkers in that assessment and one which ignores them. The first one implies that the threshold should be the same for both temporary and domestic workers. If a guestworker accepts the offer given the sufficiency constraints mentioned above, then a domestic worker should accept it too. But as we saw, the main consideration in the case of guestworkers is based 17 on their position prior to entering the host state and the threshold of what is considered enough applies to how they fare before they make a decision to migrate. Yet it would be unfair to hold domestic workers to the same standard. Sufficiency thresholds vary from country to country, and what is enough in one context may not be enough in another. To see the point, consider the following example. Compare the position of two students who attend German language courses at the same school but at two different levels: a basic level and an intermediate level. At the end of the year there is an exam and the pass mark for progressing to the next level is the same for both students, say 55. Even though the mark is the same, the level of competency in German required by students attending these different classes is completely different. One has to show that he can construct simple sentences, be able to ask for directions in the street, orient themselves with a restaurant menu and so on. The other has to be able to understand a more complex television programme, show that they are able to grasp the main ideas being discussed, and articulate an opinion in however simple terms. Clearly what is considered “enough” knowledge of German in these two groups is likely to display a great deal of difference. And it would be absurd, as well as unfair, to expect the student from the basic level class to obtain a pass at the end of an exam which has been designed to test the knowledge of members in the intermediate course. A similar argument could be made with respect to the situation of domestic and temporary workers. Life in different countries means that expectations of what might be considered sufficient in each of them are likely to differ significantly. A wage that might contribute to significant savings in one state could barely sustain a family in a different market environment. It would therefore be as absurd to conclude that wages that are acceptable to a Philippine worker because they are more than sufficient to conduct a minimally decent life in say, Manila, are also sufficient to survive in London, for example. The counterfactual circumstances should be constructed in a different way. A more plausible alternative might therefore be to assess the sufficiency threshold of domestic workers whilst abstracting from the impact of guestworkers in host societies. In this case, the relevant counterfactual evidence might require comparison with the typical wages of similarly placed domestic employees prior to the admission of temporary workers. All other things being equal, we could then define an offer as exploitative if a domestic worker accepts a job which is paid less than it would 18 have been before temporary workers entered the job market. A domestic worker is subjected to unfair treatment if he has to negotiate his wage from a position with less resources than what a worker with equal skills and ability, and performing the same job, would have received prior to the admission of temporary workers. An offer could then be considered exploitative if the agent who makes the offer benefits from it, and if the agent to whom the offer is made loses more or benefits less than he might have done in those counterfactual circumstances. As in the case of guestworkers, we judge an offer to be exploitative by whether the agent will be left with enough if he does not take the job. But in contrast to how we proceeded in the guestworkers case, we establish the sufficiency threshold by looking at what a domestic worker would have earned prior to the admission of guestworkers (all other things being equal). If we see that domestic workers earn less, we can say that they are exploited. We can conclude from this discussion that guestworker programmes may be exploitative even if they don’t actually exploit all guestworkers, as such. What makes guestworker programmes exploitative is that they contribute to a global competition for labour of those who have only their labour to sell. They help employers and firms increase profits at the expense of adverse effects on local wages and by levelling down sufficiency standards. Guestworker programmes play workers against each other, ensuring that what expands options for some workers at the same time increases constraints for others. In the end, even if workers are not exploited distributively, as citizens of different state, they may be exploited collectively, as members of the working class. 7) On workers and guests: some objections One objection to the argument we have just tried to advance might be that it relies on the existence of a competitive dynamic between foreign and domestic workers, which in reality might be absent. Temporary workers, one often hears, are admitted to fill labour shortages for jobs that local workers typically don’t want, jobs such as catering, agricultural labour, the building sectors, cleaning services or caring for the sick and the 19 elderly. Since there are not enough domestic workers interested in taking up employment in either of these occupational spheres, so the argument goes, the issue of their exploitation does not arise at all. If there simply aren’t enough local workers earning similar wages to compare with temporary workers, the idea that guestworker programmes might contribute to lower sufficiency thresholds could safely be put to one side. The standard answer to this objection is that since labour demand is socially constructed, the poor wages, degrading work conditions and lower social status typically associated to jobs performed by guestworkers is precisely what causes locals to distance themselves from such jobs. If the conditions and status associated to them were substantially improved, local workers would be more willing to take offers of employment in similar sectors (Carens 2008; S. Castles 2006). This would in turn also contribute to sending marginal employers out of business, to increase investment in labour-saving technologies and to benefit producers (especially agricultural producers) in developing countries who would no longer compete with large companies deploying cheap labour (S. Castles 2006: 761). Although this answer is plausible, it does not really confront the objection we are examining. That objection insists that where competition between domestic and foreign workers is absent, we have no reason to be concerned for what happens to local standards of sufficiency. In this sense, reflecting on what might occur in the future, if and when wages rise, is irrelevant to address a challenge that only applies to present circumstances. A better strategy for answering this objection might therefore be to confront head-on the evidence upon which it is grounded: the claim that domestic workers and foreign temporary workers do not compete with each other for the same dirty, dangerous and difficult jobs. To criticize that assumption, we might appeal to examples from two paradigmatic guestworker cases with which the empirical literature is often concerned: the Bracero programme in the United States and the employment of temporary workers in Germany. Both provide important insights into the relationship between domestic and temporary labourers in low-skilled work sectors. And both are helpful to reveal the upsetting effect of differential contracts on unionized workers and the sufficiency standards on the basis of which they negotiate. 20 In the case of the Bracero programme, the costs of hiring cheap Mexican labour to work in the Californian agricultural sector became increasingly clear after1964, when the programme officially came to an end. Although unions had always voiced concerns about the effects of importing foreign labour on local earnings, the extent to which the Bracero programme had depressed wages was evident from the unprecedented rise in agricultural workers wages that was experienced between 1964 and 1980 (when illegal immigration became a new threat) (P. Martin 2002). To mention but one prominent example, in the San Joaquin Valley of California, near Delano, Cesar Chavez and his United Farm Workers Union conducted an extremely effective campaign against local table grape growers culminating in a 40 percent increase, bringing wages from $1.25 to $1.75 an hour. In the days where Bracero workers were available to break the grapepickers strike, this would have not been possible (P. L. Martin and Teitelbaum 2001124). The difficult relationship between temporary foreign workers and local labour unions is also illustrated in a number of studies involving labourers employed in the Germany in the years following the country’s reunification. A study of the Berlin building industry showed that even though 25 per cent of unemployed people in Berlin had been construction workers by 1996, employers preferred to hire foreign contract workers to maximize profit. This competition had adverse effects especially on unionized building workers, many of whom were long-term foreign residents ((S. Castles 2006: 751). In contrast to the model of long-term employment, where the workplace and the trade union were sites of interethnic communication and integration, domestic and guestworkers were now competing against each other (S. Castles 2006). Similar outcomes could be observed also in other contexts. As recent studies of the American job market indicated, the wages of workers without high-school education declined as a result of low-skilled immigrant pressure, and that those most affected are resident immigrants in low-wage jobs and less-educated American workers, including the unemployed (Ghosh 2005: 169). It is therefore hard to maintain that because guestworkers and domestic workers are not interested in the same jobs, the latter are not vulnerable to exploitation. However, one could still object at this point that our argument focuses too much on the short-term negative impact of guestworker programmes without considering their 21 long-term positive effects. These typically include contributing to economic growth in host states, helping sending societies through remittances and other forms of support and providing temporary workers with chances to increase their earnings and gain skills and experiences through work in a different state. Notice however that all these allegedly positive features rely on the long-term promise of economic growth. Yet growth and exploitation are perfectly compatible with each other. Even if one takes the long-term view economists might prefer us to take, there are no guarantees that a fair distribution of the extra-wealth generated by migration will follow economic growth. And absent that distributional perspective, what is the guarantee that those at the very bottom of the social hierarchy will not continue to be exposed to exploitation? If improved opportunities for some come at the price of others being deprived of the same, indeed can develop precisely on that assumption (recall that short-term sacrifices are required for long-term gains) even if some individual workers might benefit, the structural conditions of collective exploitation will likely remain the same. 8. Conclusion Guestworker programmes pose many dilemmas. Conspicuous among those is the issue of whether guestworkers are exploited. A cursory look at the daily newspapers indicates that they are treated dismally: guestworkers work long hours, carry out difficult jobs and receive very little recognition (both financial and social) for the services they perform.5 Yet, when we turn to the issue from a normative perspective we seem to have trouble capturing what is the moral standard with regard to which we consider guestworkers to be taken unfair advantage of. If we rely on a domination theory of exploitation, lack of access to the benefits of citizenship does not seem For a very recent report of the conditions in which guestworkers are employed all over the European Union see an article just appeared in the Belgium daily newspaper “Le Soir”, entitled: “Les nouveaux esclaves sont parmi nous” (The new Slaves are among us) http://archives.lesoir.be/les-nouveauxesclaves-sont-parmi-nous-20-euros_t-2011101801MG25.html?query=traite+des+%EAtres&firstHit=0&by=10&sort=datedesc&when=1&queryor=traite+des+%EAtres&pos=1&all=37299&nav=1 . 5 22 sufficient to distinguish between collective political entitlements one should always have access to and others that it is acceptable to waive, at least for a time. If we rely on an egalitarian theory, we neglect how global processes of supply and demand might respond differently to different skills under offer, changing the equilibrium price for labour, and making exploitative practices often very hard to identify. If we rely on a sufficientarian theory we hit against considerable empirical evidence suggesting that guestworkers negotiate their employment offers from positions well above the threshold of sufficiency, and that it is either those who stay at home or those who are affected in host societies who are normally left with not enough. However, this last point is crucial for our purposes. Even if exploitation does not involve guestworkers as such (or at least not everywhere and at every time) guestworker programmes can still be considered exploitative. They may not exploit individual temporary workers as such but they take unfair advantage of the position of workers in both sending and receiving societies. Even if each individual guestworker has enough employment-choice to rule out that they can be taken unfair advantage of, this is only possible on condition that others don’t exercise the same choice. The case of guestworkers therefore provides a good empirical lens through which to examine a problem that has long been discussed in political theory: the issue of proletarian unfreedom (Cohen 1983). As many authors have shown, what makes the proletariat unfree as a collective is the fact that the freedom of each individual worker is contingent upon others not exercising their similarly contingent freedom. The structural conditions under which workers are forced to sell their labour are such that the offers one agent is individually free to pursue necessarily restrict the space for others taking advantage of similar options. Therefore, even if each worker is individually free to exit their collective exploitative condition, he suffers with others in circumstances that have often also been defined as circumstances of “collective unfreedom” (Cohen 1983, 11). The implications of this point are important for the kind of normative framework in which we choose to place the issue of guestworkers. So far, the question has been raised in the context of theories reflecting on the issue of justice in migration, i.e. the distribution of benefits and burdens between migrants (in this case temporary workers), citizens of sending societies and citizens of receiving societies. But if the 23 problem with guestworker programmes is not so much the condition of individual temporary workers but the way in which such programmes narrow the options of workers in general, the fact that workers happen to be separated by boundaries and that they belong to different states is a matter of secondary importance. Taking seriously the distinction between residents and aliens and asking members of one group to make sacrifices for the sake of members in the other is unlikely to be a very productive route for ending the exploitation of workers as a collective. The questions we should be asking instead are those that focus on the status of workers in general, the circumstances in which they are forced to accept certain wages, the sort of incentives that reward employers and firms seeking to hire cheap labour, and the institutional arrangements that govern the trade of labour and the accumulation of capital in the global market. Even if guestworker programmes don’t exploit each individual guestworker, they operate in a global institutional structure that exploits workers as members of a collective: the collective composed by all those who sell their labour for a living or, to put it in more familiar terms, that collective we often refer to with the term “working class”. To reflect on the remedial principles required to end their exploitation, is to engage with a radically different way of arranging the economy, and a new distribution of global benefits and burdens. BIBLIOGRAPHY Agunias, Dovelyn R. and Newland, Kathleen 'Circular Migration and Development: Trends, Policy, Routes, and Ways Forward', <www.migrationpolicy.org/pubs/MigDevPB_041807.pdf>, accessed 17th October 2011. Attas, Daniel (2000), 'The Case of Guest Workers: Exploitation, Citizenship and Economic Rights', Res Publica, 6 (1), 73-92. Carens, Joseph H. (2008), 'Live-in Domestics, Seasonal Workers, and Others Hard to Locate on the Map of Democracy', Journal of Political Philosophy, 16 (4), 419-45. Castles, S. (2006), 'Guestworkers in Europe: A resurrection?', International Migration Review, 40 (4), 741-66. Castles, Stephen and Kosack, Godula (1985), Immigrant workers and class structure in Western Europe (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Chanda, R. (2001), 'Movement of natural persons and the GATS', World Economy, 24 (5), 631-54. Cohen, G. A. (1983), 'The Structure of Proletarian Unfreedom', Philosophy & Public Affairs, 12 (1), 3-33. 24 Findlay, Allan M. (1995), 'Skilled transients: the invisible fenomenon?', in Robin Cohen (ed.), The Cambridge survey of world migration (New York: Cambridge University Press), 515-22. Ghosh, Bhimal (2005), 'Economic effects of international migration: A synoptic overview', World Migration 2005 : Costs and Benefits of International Migration (Darya Ganj, New Delhi: Academic), 163-83. Hahamovitch, Cindy (2003), 'Creating Perfect Immigrants: Guestworkers of the World in Historical Perspective 1', Labor History, 44 (1), 69-94. Hollifield, James F. (1992), Immigrants, markets, and states : the political economy of postwar Europe (Cambridge, Ma: Harvard University Press). Ilias, Shayerah, Fennelly, Katherine, and Federico, Christopher M. (2008), 'American Attitudes toward Guest Worker Policies', International Migration Review, 42 (4), 741-66. Lenard, Patti Tamara and Straehle, Christine (forthcoming), 'Temporary labour migration, global redistribution and democratic justice', Politics, Philosophy & Economics. Martin, Philip (2002), 'Mexican Workers and U.S. Agriculture: The Revolving Door', International Migration Review, 36 (4), 1124-42. Martin, Philip L. and Teitelbaum, Michael S. (2001), 'The Mirage of Mexican Guest Workers', Foreign Affairs, 80 (6), 117-31. Mayer, Robert (2005), 'Guestworkers and exploitation', Review of Politics, 67 (2), 311-34. Migration, International Organization for (2005), 'International migration trends', World Migration 2005 : Costs and Benefits of International Migration, 379-404. Miller, Kerby A. (1985), Emigrants and exiles : Ireland and the Irish exodus to North America (New York: Oxford University Press) xii, 684p. Momsen, Janet Henshall (1999), Gender, migration, and domestic service (New York: Routledge) 272p. Ottonelli, Valeria and Torresi, Tiziana (2010), 'Inclusivist Egalitarian Liberalism and Temporary Migration: A Dilemma', Journal of Political Philosophy, no-no. Paine, Suzanne (1974), Exporting workers : the Turkish case (London: Cambridge University Press). Parrenas, Rhacel Salazar (2001), Servants of globalization : women, migration and domestic work (Stanford: Stanford University Press) xi, 309 p. Ruhs, Martin and Martin, Philip (2008), 'Numbers vs. Rights: Trade-Offs and Guest Worker Programs1', International Migration Review, 42 (1), 249-65. Ruhs, Martin and Anderson, Bridget (2010), Who needs migrant workers? : labour shortages, immigration, and public policy (Oxford: Oxford University Press) xvi, 335 p. Skeldon, Ronald (2005), 'Migration and poverty: Some issues in the context of Asia', World Migration 2005 : Costs and Benefits of International Migration (Darya Ganj, New Delhi: Academic), 253-68. Stilz, Anna (2010), 'Guestworkers and second-class citizenship', Policy and Society, 29 (4), 295-307. Walzer, Michael (1983), Spheres of justice: a defence of pluralism and equality (Oxford Robertson). 25