The Loop Case and Kamm’s Doctrine of Triple Effect I. Most nonconsequentialists intuitively believe that it is morally permissible to redirect the trolley in the Original Trolley Case: A runaway trolley is headed toward five people where it will kill the five. The trolley can however be redirected onto another track where an innocent bystander sits, whereby the five would be saved but the one would be killed. At the same time, most nonconsequentialists intuitively believe that it would be impermissible to do the following: Push Case: A runaway trolley is headed toward give people where it will kill five people. We can push an innocent bystander in front of the trolley, whereby the trolley’s hitting the bystander would stop it, thereby saving the five and killing the one. A principle that seems neatly to capture the intuitive judgments in these cases is the Doctrine of Double of Effect (DDE): There is a moral constraint on intending evil (such as harm), even when the evil will be used as a means to a greater good. However, we may be permitted to employ neutral or good means to promote a greater good, even though we foresee the same evil side effects, if (a) the good is proportionate to the evil, and (b) there is no better way to achieve this good. According to DDE, in Original Trolley, because we merely foresee the death of the one but we do not causally require or intend the one to be hit in order to save the five, redirecting the trolley is permissible. In contrast, in Push, because the trolley’s hitting the one is causally required to stop it from hitting the five; and because by pushing the bystander, we intend that the bystander is hit, according to DDE, our act is impermissible. Judith Jarvis Thomson has famously challenged DDE on the basis of the Loop Case: A trolley is headed toward five people, and it can be redirected onto another track where one innocent bystander sits. However, the track loops back toward the five. Hence, if it were not the case that the trolley would hit the one and grind to a halt, the trolley would go around and kill the five.1 As Thomson explains, in Loop, as in Push, the hitting of the one is causally required to stop the trolley to save the five. Also, Thomson notes that if we redirect the trolley, it seems that we would be doing so with the intention of hitting the one.2 If so, DDE would forbid our redirecting the trolley in Loop. However, according to Thomson, intuitively it 1 Let us also stipulate that if the five were not present, the trolley would not go around and hit the one, but would carry on harmless down the track. 2 Thomson, p. 1403. seems permissible to redirect the trolley in Loop. As Thomson asks, what difference can an extra bit of track make?3 Given her intuitive judgment, Thomson argues that we should give up DDE. In recent years, Frances Kamm has argued that one can modify DDE so as to accommodate Loop. In particular, Kamm argues that what she calls the Doctrine of Triple Effect (DTE) can explain the permissibility of redirecting the trolley in Loop. To supplement the intending/foreseeing distinction of DDE, DTE distinguishes further between doing something because an effect will occur and doing it in order that it occurs, whereby when one does something because an effect will occur, this need not imply that one intends that the effect occurs. To motivate this distinction, Kamm offers the Party Case: We intend to throw a party in order to have fun. We foresee though that this will result in a big mess, and we will not have a party if we will be left to clean up the mess by ourselves. However, we foresee that if we throw the party, our friends will feel indebted to us and this will cause them to help clean up. Hence, we have the party because we believe that our friends will feel indebted and because we will not have a mess to clean up. However, we do not give the party in order to make our friends feel indebted nor in order not to make a mess.4 Using the because/in-order-to distinction, Kamm argues that in Loop, when we redirect the trolley, we also act because we believe that the one will be hit, but not in order that the one is hit. This means, according to Kamm, that we do not intend that the one is hit. Consequently, Kamm believes that DTE accounts for Thomson’s intuition that redirecting the trolley in Loop is permissible. In this paper, we question both whether DTE applies to Loop, even if it were a valid principle, and whether DTE is in fact a valid principle. To do this, we begin by examining more closely why Kamm believes that DTE is applicable to Loop. II. Kamm’s analysis of Loop can be divided into four steps. The first is her general understanding of the structure of Loop. As Kamm sees Loop, initially, the only problem that faces the five that prompts our act to help them is the trolley’s heading toward them from one direction (p. 94). When we have redirected the trolley, then, according to Kamm, we have created a second, new problem, which is the trolley’s heading toward the five from a different direction. The second step is her introduction of the because/in-order-to distinction using Party as an example. On the basis of this distinction, Kamm also rejects a common test for the presence of an intention, known as the Counterfactual Test: If we decline to perform an act (e.g. redirect the trolley) because the act would not bring about the effect (e.g. hitting a bystander), this means that we intended to produce the effect. 3 4 Thomson, p. 284. (JS) See, e.g., Kamm, p. 103. According to Kamm, if we can do an act (e.g. give a party) because we believe that it has a certain effect (e.g. feeling of indebtedness), or not do an act because we believe that the act will not have that affect; and yet not intend that effect, this shows that the Counterfactual Test for the presence of intention is inadequate. If this is right, Kamm argues that this test cannot be used to show that we intend to hit the bystander in Loop just because we act on condition of our hitting him. In the third step of her analysis of Loop, Kamm appeals to Michael Bratman’s test for intention instead, which has three components: 1) if we intend to bring about x, then we seek means to accomplish the end of bringing it about. 2) if we intend to bring about x, then we pursue x. This means that if one ways fails to produce x, we would adopt another way. 3) if we intend x, and our intentions should be consistent in so far as we are rational, then we will filter out intentions that conflict with intending x. Kamm argues that we do not meet these conditions in Loop. For instance, Kamm argues that we fail to meet 1), because we do not survey the field for various ways of hitting the one. Instead, according to Kamm, we only “notice that what we must do to accomplish one of our aims, that is, stopping the trolley from hitting the five from the first direction (that is, from the front), will also, without our doing anything extra, cause the one to be hit” (pp. 96-97). Moreover, we fail to meet 2), according to Kamm, because in Loop, we need not “be committed to hitting the one by other means if the hitting fails to come about” (p. 97). To support this claim, Kamm offers the Extra Push Case: Suppose the redirected trolley would jump over the one person on the track and loop back toward the five. We need not be committed to giving the trolley an extra push, which would be unnecessary to get the trolley away from hitting the five from the front, but which would be necessary to get the trolley to hit the one person, supposing that hitting the one is what is causally necessary to prevent the trolley’s jumping over him and looping back toward the five (see Kamm, p. 97). Kamm argues that if we give the extra push in Extra Push, then we would be doing something that is undertaken especially to accomplish hitting the one, which would definitely involve intending to hit the one. However, so she argues, in Loop, we need not be willing or committed to give the extra push. This suggests, according to Kamm, that we do not intend to hit the one. Furthermore, we fail to meet 3), Kamm argues, because “it is consistent for someone who redirects the trolley because he believes that it will hit the one to then try to rescue the one from being hit” (p. 98). If so, and if intending to the rescue the one is inconsistent with intending to hit the one, then, according to Kamm, this would show that we did not intend to hit the one. To motive this idea, Kamm proposes that when we redirect the trolley in Loop, we may be thinking the following: We will redirect the trolley and then try to push the one out of the way. For if we have an opportunity to save the one and do not do so, we would be intending his being hit. If we fail to rescue the one, we still get the advantage of the five’s being saved because the one will be hit. If we succeed in rescuing the one, the five are no worse off and they had some chance of being saved.5 According to Kamm, if in Loop, these are our thoughts, then we can have the intention to rescue the one, which would mean that we did not intend to hit the one. In the fourth step of her analysis of Loop, Kamm seeks to justify the moral significance of the because/in-order-to distinction. As far as we can tell, Kamm is suggesting that the because/in-order-to distinction can be justified (or at least mutually supported) by the distinction between primary and secondary reasons for action.6 Although Kamm does not spell it out, implicitly, she appears to be claiming that one intends x, if and only if x is one’s primary reason for action. To support this idea, Kamm points out that the primary reason for giving the party in Party is to have fun. The secondary reason for giving the party is that the undesirable effect of giving the party can be taken care of by the foreseen evil (our friends’ feeling indebted) that we produce. As Kamm says, “The bad effect . . . defeats the defeaters of [our] primary reason, and so maintain the sufficiency of [our] primary . . . reason,” but it is “not, however, [our] goal in action to produce what will defeat the defeaters of [our] goal” (p. 102). By analogy, in Loop, the primary reason for redirecting the trolley is to prevent the five from being hit in the front. The secondary reason for redirecting the trolley is that the undesirable effect of redirecting can be taken care of by the foreseen evil of hitting the one. Following Kamm’s reasoning, since our goal in redirecting the trolley is not to produce what will defeat the defeaters of our goal, our primary reason for acting is not to hit the one. Therefore, we do not intend to hit the one. III. First, in Kamm’s Party, it seems plausible that one did not throw the party in order to make our friends feel indebted. This is because one can plausibly tell a story to this effect. This said, it might be worth mentioning that it is not a conceptual truth that one could not throw a party in order to make someone else feel indebted. For example, consider the Election Party Case: Suppose you are running to be elected to the board of your local country club. You could throw a party in order that your friends feel indebted and would thereby vote for you in the upcoming election. However, we contend that the same cannot be said in Loop. Unlike Party, Kamm’s proposal that we would redirect the trolley just in order to prevent the trolley from hitting the five from the front just does not sound plausible. There is simply no reason to turn the trolley except in order to hit the one. 5 See, e.g., Kamm, p. 98. Kamm says that the primary/secondary reason distinction is “another way of understanding the cases I discussed” (p. 102). 6 Secondly, Kamm’s appeals to Bratman’s account for intention for support are problematic. First of all, Bratman’s first condition is too strong. Recall that the first condition says that 1) if we intend to bring about x, then we seek means to accomplish the end of bringing it about. Consider the following: Mortal Enemy Case: At a party, we notice by chance that we could kill our mortal enemy, who is also at the party. In particular, our enemy has asked us to pass him some snacks. Unbeknownst to him but known to us, the snacks contains a kind of nuts to which he is deathly allergic. We give him the snacks at his request. Previously we had no intention of killing our enemy. Just like Loop, we do not survey the field for various ways of killing our mortal enemy. In particular, in Mortal Enemy, we also only notice that what we must do to accomplish one of our aims, that is, give our enemy snacks at his request, will also, without our doing anything extra, cause our enemy to die. Nevertheless, it seems clear that when we give our mortal enemy the snacks, we intend to kill him. If so, 1) is too strong, and the fact that we do not survey the field for various ways to hit the one in Loop does not show that we do not intend to hit the one in Loop. Similarly, Bratman’s second condition is also too strong. Consider Mortal Enemy Case II: Everything is the same as Mortal Enemy. Further, suppose that our mortal enemy decides not to eat the snacks for whatever reason, we would not try again to kill him by other means. It should be clear that in Mortal Enemy II, we still intend to kill our enemy even though we are not committed to killing him by other means if he decides not to eat the snacks he had requested. If this right, contrary to 2), Mortal Enemy II shows one can intend to do x without trying again and again. If so, Kamm’s argument that Loop is different from Extra Push is beside the point. Just as we can intend to kill our enemy without trying again and again, we can intend to hit the one without trying again and again. Here it is also worth mentioning a problem with Kamm’s discussion of Extra Push. Kamm argues that in other cases, undertaking an extra act to save the five would not indicate an intention to hit the one, even if hitting the one is a means to save the five. In particular, in the Two Loop Case: Suppose that after being redirected from its initial hit, the trolley will go around a looping track toward the five, unless it is redirected again—by an extra push, which is not needed to get the trolley away from hitting the five from the front, and which will get the trolley to go onto a second track that loops to the five as well but on which a person sits. The person will be hit and this will stop the trolley. According to Kamm, we may permissibly give the extra push in Two Loop, because the extra push is just like the first redirection in the Original Trolley, namely, we redirect the trolley the second time to save the five from the second way in which it would hit them, but we do this only because the one will be hit and stop any further looping. But now consider the Two Loop Roller Coaster Case: Suppose that after being redirected from its initial hit, the trolley will go up a special roller coaster track toward the five, unless it is redirected again—by an extra push, which is not needed to get it away from its initial hit, and which will get the trolley to go onto a lower roller coaster track that loops to the five too but on which a person sits. The person will be hit and this will stop the trolley. The Two Loop Roller Coaster is just like Two Loop. So it should be permissible to redirect the trolley in this manner. At the same time, it is hard to see how the Two Loop Roller Coaster is different from Extra Push. In both cases, the trolley will go over the person and hit the five from a different direction unless one gives the trolley an extra push. The difference between Two Loop Roller Coaster and Extra Push is just a bit of extra tracks. If, following Thomson, Kamm thinks that an extra bit of track does not matter in the case of Original Trolley and Loop, it should also not matter here. And given that Kamm believes that Extra Push involves intending to hit the one, she should also think Two Loop Roller Coaster involves intending to hit the one. If so, given that Two Loop Roller Coaster is just like Two Loop, and Two Loop is just like Loop, Kamm should also think that Two Loop and Loop both involve intending to hit the one. Moreover, Kamm’s application of Bratman’s third condition to Loop seems to lead to practical incoherence. Kamm appears to be suggesting that we can knowingly imperil the one because it is necessary to save the five, and then race off to remove that peril, which we know will prevent the five’s being saved. However, consider some variants that heighten the tension among those intentions. Two Button Case: We can only turn the trolley by pressing Button 1. Right next to it is Button 2, which sounds a whistle that will give the man on the track plenty of time to step aside. Presumably, we should push Button 1, since doing so would enable us to prevent the five’s being hit from the front. But we will then have the immediate opportunity to push Button 2, warning the one. If we omit to seize this opportunity, we will, according to Kamm, be intending to hit the one. Knowing this, we are committed from the outset to pushing Button 2 after pushing Button 1. But then can we really be intending to save the five by one action, if we are already committed to performing another action immediately afterwards that will prevent our first action from having its “intended” effect? Or consider Two Button Case II: Again, we control two buttons, this time, Divert and Slow. Pushing Divert will redirect the trolley from the five toward the one, and pushing Slow will reduce the speed of the diverted trolley so that it will injure but not kill the man on the tracks. It will, however, not stop the trolley, which will kill the five. According to Kamm, we should push Divert. At the same, following Kamm’s line of reasoning, it seems that we should then push Slow to show that we do not intend to hit the one. But this commits us to a course of action that will ensure that the man’s injury is in vain. It will not prevent the trolley from killing the five; it will merely ensure that our previous action of pushing Divert does not kill the one. Since we had the option of not pushing any buttons, letting the five die and sparing the one of any injury, we thus appear to have injured the one gratuitously. Nonconsequentialists are clearly not committed to minimizing aggregate harm, but they should be committed to avoiding harm that is necessary only to allow the agent to act on a set of intentions that allows him to make an idle gesture toward saving some from harm while avoiding the onus of intending harm to others. Finally, it is questionable whether the because of/in order to distinction and the corresponding distinction between primary and secondary reason are normatively salient. For one thing, suppose one grants that these distinctions can be made, there is a further issue about whether we regard the individual as an end in himself when we do an act because an effect will occur to that individual, that is, there is an issue about our moral attitude toward the individual. Consider Party. Suppose one grants that we are giving a party because we know that our friends will feel indebted and will help clean up but not in order that they feel indebted. Here it seems that there is the concern that we are taking advantage of our friends. That is, this seems to be a case in which we regard our friends more as a means to having a party rather than as ends in themselves, which, if true, would be morally objectionable, as it would be an abuse of the friendship. To make the problem more vivid, consider the Dinner Case: We want to have a nice dinner with our friend at a nice restaurant. We foresee though that this will be expensive, and we will not have this dinner with our friend if we have to pay. However, we foresee that if we dine at the restaurant, our friend, who is very wealthy, will be so happy to be invited, and this will cause him to pay for the meal. Hence, we have the dinner at the restaurant because we believe that our friends will pay for the meal. However, we do not dine at the restaurant in order to make our friend pay (that is, our primary goal is not to cause our friend to lose money). Again, suppose one grants that we are dining at the restaurant because our friend will pay but not in order to make our friend pay. It seems that there is still the issue of whether we are taking advantage of a property that our friend has, namely, his wealth, rather than regarding him as an end in himself. To diffuse the idea that we are taking advantage of our friends in Party, Kamm explains regarding Party that our guests would make us worse off than we would be without the party (as the mess they produce overrides the fun for us): “Hence, when they serve [our] interests, they merely eliminate the treat of the mess they themselves present to [us]. This is unlike improving [our] position from what it would be without their presence” (p. 103). But arguably, this misses the point of friendship and further suggests that in Party, we are in fact taking advantage of our friends. For, in friendship, we do not just aim to break even, so to speak. We often undertake additional burdens for the sake of the friendship. If this is right, we can make an analogous point regarding Loop. Suppose that one grants that in Loop, we are redirecting the trolley because the one will be hit, which will stop the trolley, but not in order to hit the one. It seems that we are nevertheless taking advantage of the one’s being on the track, and not regarding the one as an end in himself. Arguably, this is objectionable even if we grant that there is a distinction between because of and in order to. In response, Kamm argues that we do not treat the one as “available” for our purposes, because “we need not be willing to give the extra push in the Extra Push Case” (p. 103). But pointing out that we would not give the extra push in Extra Push does not show that we do not regard the one more as a means rather than as an end. Consider Dinner Case II: Everything is the same as Dinner, except suppose our rich friend did not want to go out for dinner for whatever reason, we would not try other means of getting him to go to dinner. Just because we are not willing to do other things to get our friend to go to dinner does not mean that we do not regard him more as a means for picking up the bill (that is, as a walking check book). In addition, Kamm faces what might be called the Narrow Because Of Problem. In particular, Kamm’s notion of ‘because of’ seems quite elastic such that even in clear cases in which we intend to x, it could be argued that we did not intend to x. For example, consider Bank Robbery Case: Sam is trying to rob the bank. To rob the bank, it is necessary to get rid of the security guard. So, Sam shoots the security guard, thereby killing the security guard. Ordinary, we would think that Sam intends to kill the security guard. But, given Kamm’s understanding of because of, Sam could argue the following: His primary reason in pulling the trigger was in order to scare the security guard. Without his doing anything else extra, he also pulled the trigger because it would kill the security guard. Hence, following Kamm’s line of reasoning, he did not pull the trigger in order to kill the security guard – at best, as a secondary reason, he pulled the trigger because it would kill the security guard. Therefore, using Kamm’s reasoning, one could Bank Robbery a case in which Sam did not intend to kill the security guard, even though Bank Robbery seems to be a clear case of intending to kill. Moreover, it seems that one can redescribe any case of intending to x as a case in which one acted because of x rather than in order to bring about x. If this is right, Kamm’s notion of “because of” may simply be too be elastic to be of normative use. [Do we need a section about why Loop might be impermissible?] [Do we need a further section about why Original Trolley is impermissible? Though I’m inclined to think that it is permissible.] IV. Kamm has argued that DTE can explain the permissibility of redirecting the trolley toward the one in Loop. In this paper, we argued that even if DTE were a valid principle, it does not apply to Loop. Moreover, we questioned whether DTE is a valid principle. The upshot is that we are skeptical that the permissibility of Loop can be justified by DTE.