Presumed Consent 1 Running head: PRESUMED CONSENT Ethical Considerations Surrounding Organ Donation Models in Ontario and the Proposal of Presumed Consent Michael Mason 0384583 NURS 2500 April 4, 2008 Presumed Consent 2 Abstract In Ontario, there is an incredible need for procurable organs that is not being addressed well enough. One proposal to increase organ donation rates is to implement a model of presumed consent, which classifies all patients as potential donors unless an explicit opposition to donation is made before death. Although it is likely that this model will increase donation rates, there is a host of ethical issues that need to be considered before this approach is mandated. This paper promotes a change in provincial organ donation policy to adopt the presumed consent model. Presumed Consent 3 Introduction In 2004, a total of 120 Ontario residents died as a result of waiting for life-saving organs that were not available. Ontario’s donor rate of 13 donors per million population/year (pmp) falls just below the national donor rate of 14 pmp, and drastically short of the leading donor countries (Wallace, 2006). These dismal statistics have raised recent debates as to what should be done in order to provide more life-sustaining organs to desperate Ontarians. However, many of these proposals include a host of ethical concerns that prevent implementation, such as the proposition of presumed consent by NDP member Peter Kormos in February, 2006 (Wallace, 2006). Under presumed consent legislation, “a deceased individual is classified as a potential donor in absence of explicit opposition to donation before death” (Abadie & Gay, 2005, p.599). This “opt-out” policy is in direct contrast to the current system in Ontario, which requires a signed donor card, as well as the consent of next-ofkin following legal death. Recently, the Ontario government has made steps to increase the number of potential donors, including requiring all 13A hospitals to notify all emergency room and intensive care deaths to the Trillium Gift of Life Network for the possibility of a donor match, introducing donation after cardiac death (DCD), and enhancing education and general awareness of the facts around organ and tissue donation (Spencer, 2007). These efforts should be applauded, however donor rates still remain low. Although controversial, the additional implementation of presumed consent legislation may be the answer to Ontario’s donor shortage. Consider the following case scenario: Thomas*, a 39 year old male, has recently suffered a massive heart attack and has been given less than 2 hours to survive due to heavy ischemia in his ventricles. Thomas is carrying a valid donor card. Thomas’s immediate family has just heard of his prognosis and have been informed of the possibility of donating his organs. Due to the enormity of the situation, the family is unsure what to do and decides to refuse organ donation. Thomas dies one hour later in severe pain due to systemic organ failure. Thomas is in a major 13A Ontario hospital and a transplant team is on staff. *Please note that Thomas is a fictional patient used to illustrate a possible clinical scenario. Presumed Consent 4 This example illustrates a very difficult, yet not uncommon clinical scenario that incorporates the multitude of ethical dilemmas when considering organ donation. According to the College of Nurses of Ontario (CNO), “[Health care professionals] need to be knowledgeable of clinical situations and ethics, and they require the ability to think through a problem and reach a sound decision that they can explain and justify by referring to ethical principles” (CNO, 2005, p.3). An in depth analysis of this scenario using the principles of bioethics will be accounted for in this paper. Ethical Analysis The principle of autonomy is the “centrepiece of medical ethics”, which refers to the state of being self-governing (English and Sommerville, 2003). In general medical practice, when the wishes of a competent adult patient conflict with those of a patient’s family, the patient’s wishes take precedence. However, this is not the norm when the issue involves organ donation (May, Aulisio, & Devita, 2000). Regardless of whether a patient carries a valid donor card or has verbally stated their specific wishes following death, organs or tissue will not be procured in many countries, including Canada, unless the family agrees to donation. This undermines the basic principle of autonomy, which should state that the individual has a first right of control over the disposition of their body, both before and after death, which is consistent with society’s approach to the disposition of other forms of property after death (May, Aulisio, & Devita, 2000). The rebuttal to this seemingly faultless ideology is the argument that family interests should prevail because the family is most affected by death, and will be most affected if they feel wrong action has been taken (English & Sommerville, 2003). In the case of Thomas, his prior informed decision to donate his organs in an altruistic act to save up to eight other lives was abolished due to a potentially rash decision made by his family during a very emotional time. Although improbable, a more cynical answer to why health care professionals (HCPs) may side with the family’s decision for not procuring organs when the patient has clearly stated otherwise may be for ‘fear of being sued’ (May, Aulisio, & Devita, 2000). Moreover, physicians in charge of a potential donor may find it easier to contrive an excuse for not Presumed Consent 5 considering their patient a donor, rather than progressing with a long, complicated and potentially disagreeable procedure, regardless of patient’s wishes (Cameron & Forsythe, 2001). Above all other variables, HCPs should have a duty to respect, and an obligation to promote the free choices of competent patients (Hebert, 1995, p.25). An alternative to the debate over when to abide by patient’s prior wishes regarding procurement of their organs following death would be to implement presumed consent. Under this legislation, the wishes of the family would still be respected; however there would be a utilitarian assumption in society that donation follows death, which would result in more unsure family members choosing to donate (Abadie & Gay, 2005). Also, according to English and Sommerville, an advantage of a presumed consent model is that the main burden of making a procurement decision would be lessened because a “genuine culture change over time would mean that donation would come to be seen as the norm for most people” (2003, p.149). On the grounds of presumed consent, it would be necessary for all citizens to be informed of the policy and have the option to easily object, regardless of reason (English, 2007). One of the ethical issues preventing presumed consent to become legislated in Ontario refers to the possibility that organs can be procured from a deceased individual who is opposed to donation, but whose wishes have not been formally stated (Wright, 2007). In an ideal presumed consent system, the wishes of all citizens would be respected and followed, and donor rates would be increased. Another alternative may be to implement a more coercive version of presumed consent as utilized in Austria and recently in North Carolina, where family wishes are not taken into consideration during organ procurement (Abadie & Gay, 2005). In this system, a signed donor card acts as a legally binding document, and therefore priority is placed on the wishes of the patient, despite concerns that it may anger family members, lead to negative publicity of the health system, and discourage potential donors (Mesich-Brant & Grossback, 2005). When conflict arises between patient and family wishes during organ donation, it may be difficult for health care professionals to promote good, or act beneficently (Hebert, 1995, p.11). In the Presumed Consent 6 case of Thomas, one may argue that it would be morally right to procure his organs and potentially use his death as a means to prolong life in needy recipients regardless of his family’s wishes, especially since his prognosis is impending death. This philosophy also agrees with the utilitarianism bioethical theory that one should act with the objective of benefit for the greater good of others (Abadie and Gay, 2005, p.2). Abadie & Gay agree, stating that “from a purely utilitarian perspective, it [allowing family members to overrule a patient’s desire to donate] represents the routine disposal of a highly valuable commodity, with the potential to save lives” (2005, p.2). Another ethical variable in the given scenario that cannot be overlooked is the fact that Thomas is considered a potential donor after cardiac death (DCD), which poses significant ethical problems for end-of-life decision making in intensive care units (Doig, 2006). DCD typically involves a person who requires a ventilator, and although may have measurable brain function, is determined to have no hope of recovery. It is then up to the doctors to remove ventilation and to wait 5 minutes after the heart stops beating before pronouncing death (Western, 2006). One of the ethical concerns posed with this procedure is that there are cases where the heart has stopped beating and recommenced beating after 5 minutes of stoppage, and another is that stoppage of the heart is caused by removal of the ventilator (Western, 2006). Additionally, DCD may involve giving the donor drugs that preserve the donor’s organs, but may hasten the donor’s death (Potts, 2007). Although the intent of reducing suffering and providing life for others seems convincing, DCD violates a fundamental principle of medicine, non-maleficence or “do no harm” (Hebert, 1995, p.109), by mistreating the dying patient and using them only as a means to an end for someone else’s benefit (Potts, 2007). Potts goes as far to say that “since the patient is not truly dead until his or her organs are removed, it is the process of organ donation that causes the donor’s death” (2007, p.17). In health care, justice is usually defined as a form of fairness (Hebert, 1995, pp.11-12). As Aristotle once said, "giving to each that which is his due", implying the fair distribution of benefits and burden in society (McCormick, 1998). Although the sensitivity to family wishes is important, the Presumed Consent 7 reasons for requiring the family to consent to organ donation do not justify a practice of overriding a deceased patient’s documented wish to donate (May, Aulisio, & Devita, 2000). Honouring the documented wishes of a deceased patient to donate should be a morally required act on behalf of HCPs. Discussion and Conclusion A move to presumed consent in Ontario has benefit to all members of society, despite claims by some critics who believe presumed consent will not increase donation rates (Wright, 2007). To those who support donation, there would be no effort needed to ensure their wishes are followed. To those opposed, their wishes will be formally recorded and respectfully followed. For families, presumed consent relieves the burden of decision making when they have recently been informed that their loved-one has died or is dying. Finally, and most significantly, a presumed consent model will allow for more organs to be available, and consequently, more lives will be saved (English, 2007). Although the presumed consent model may not solve the organ shortage in Ontario, its structure seems probable to reduce waitlist numbers. In order to avoid further ethical scrutiny, the presumed consent model would have to adopt certain integral capabilities. These include notifying every adult to be formally informed of the law and giving them an opportunity to state their choice, possibly having organ donation topics as part of the provincial high school curriculum, increasing public awareness of organ donation policy to believe that such an act should be normal, and ensuring that the presumed consent program is managed effectively (Courtney, 2003). Alternative solutions of financial incentives and coercion among living donors are highly unethical (Delmonico, 2004). When considering the ethical dilemmas of presumed consent including the possibility of wrongly presuming donors, having inappropriate public support and consequently mistrust in the health care system, and the possibility of reduced willingness to donate, it is understandable that policy makers are hesitant to adopt such a model. However, the possibilities of these ramifications are extreme and the benefit of saving countless lives under the new system is highly probable. Regardless of what Presumed Consent 8 system becomes implemented, there is overwhelming support that more drastic measures need to be taken to change the public’s attitude toward organ donation in Ontario (Wallace, 2006). There is a notion in this country that giving of an organ is an act of benevolence. Agreeing with Mr. Kormos, I believe that donating organs should be as normal brushing your teeth (Wallace, 2006). Presumed Consent 9 Bibliography Abadie, A., & Gay, S. (2005). The impact of presumed consent legislation on cadaveric organ donation: A cross country study. Journal of Health Economics. 25, 599-620. Cameron, S., & Forsythe, J. (2001). How can we improve organ donation rates? Research into the identification of factors which may influence the variation. Nefrologia. 11, 68-77. College of Nurses of Ontario (CNO). Practice Standard: Ethics. Retrieved March 18, 2002, from http://www.cno.org/docs/prac/41034_Ethics.pdf Courtney, D. (2003). Your first choice! A presumed consent policy for organ donation. Retrieved March 18, 2008, from http://www.trioweb.org/resources/YourChoiceFirstCourtney070107.pdf . Delmonico, F. (2004). Financial incentives for organ donation. Medscape Transplantation. 5, 1-2. Doig, C. (2006). Is the Canadian health care system ready for donation after cardiac death? A note of caution. Canadian Medical Association Journal. 175, 905. English, V. (2007). Is presumed consent the answer to organ shortages? Yes. British Medical Journal. 334, 1088. English, V., & Sommerville, A. (2003). Presumed consent for transplantation: A dead issue after Alder Hey? Journal of Medical Ethics. 29, 147-152. Hebert, P. (1995). Doing right; A practical guide to ethics for medical trainees and physicians. Toronto: Oxford. May, T., Aulisio, M., & Devita, M. (2000). Patients, families, and organ donation: Who should decide? Milbank Quarterly. 78, 323-336. Mesich-Brant, J., & Grossback, L. (2005). Assisting altruism: Evaluating legally binding consent in organ donation policy. Journal of Health Politics, Policy and Law. 30, 687-718. McCormick, T. (1998). Principles of Bioethics. Retrieved March 19, 2002, from Presumed Consent 10 http://depts.washington.edu/bioethx/tools/princpl.html. Potts, M. (2007). Truthfulness in transplantation: Non-heart beating organ donation. Philosophy, Ethics, and Humanities in Medicine. 2, 17. Spencer, D. (2007). Backgrounder: Organ and tissue donation in Ontario. Ministry of Health and Long-Term Care. Retrieved March 18, 2002, from http://www.health.gov.on.ca/english/media/news_releases/archives/nr_07/feb/organdonation _bg_05_20070205.pdf. Wallace, J. (2006). Is it time for presumed consent for organ donation? Ontario’s private member’s bill aims to revolutionize failing system. National Review of Medicine. Retrieved March 18, 2008, from http://www.nationalreviewofmedicine.com/issue/2006/03_15/3_policy_politics02_05.html. Western, J. (2006). Controversial organ donation method begins in Canada; Organs extracted 5 minutes after heart stops. Life Site News. Retrieved March 18, 2008, from http://www.lifesitenews.com/ldn/2006/jun/06062707.html. Wright, L. (2007). Is presumed consent the answer to organ shortages? No. British Medical Journal. 334, 1089. Presumed Consent 11 Presumed Consent 12