Robi Kroflič Legitimnost etične norme in (dis)kontinuiteta pedagogike moderne (Draft Version) Povzetek: Splošno sprejeta hipoteza, da je pedagogika kot normativna znanost vzniknila iz razsvetljenske filozofske antropologije in politične teorije, še posebej iz Kantovih konceptov, postaja danes zanimiva v luči Lyotardove postmoderne filozofije. Lyotardova teza o smrti velikih zgodb moderne filozofije in znanosti postavlja pod vprašaj legitimnost temeljev pedagogike kot znanosti in eno najpomembnejših vprašanj je vprašanje o legitimnosti deduktivno postavljenih pedagoških smotrov. Preprosta rešitev, da je po padcu deontološke etike pravna teorija, zasnovana na Deklaraciji o človekovih pravicah, postala orodje legitimiranja pedagoških ciljev in metod, je preprosto nezadostna za pedagogiko in še posebej za argumentacijo na področju moralne vzgoje. Da bi našli novo osnovo legitimiziranja v pedagogiki, bom raziskal možnosti izgradnje etične argumentacije na Levinasovi etiki, in da bi našli novo osnovo etične argumentacije v moralni vzgoji, bom predstavil osnovno idejo induktivnega vzgojno-disciplinskega pristopa. Ključne besede: razsvetljenska pedagogika, postmoderna pedagogika, normativnost, Lyotard, Levinas, Hoffman, induktivni pristop Legitimacy of ethical norm and (dis)continuity of pedagogy of modernity Common accepted hypothesis that pedagogy as a normative science arouse from enlightenment philosophical anthropology and political theory, specially from Kant’s concepts, becomes interesting in the light spot of Lyotard postmodern philosophy. Lyotard thesis about the death of great narratives of modern philosophy and science points the question of legitimacy of millstones of pedagogy as science and one of the most important questions is the question about legitimacy of main deductive pedagogical goals. A simple solution that after the fall of deontological ethics law theory, based on the Declaration on human rights, became a tool for legitimization of pedagogical goals and methods, is simply insufficient for pedagogy and also for argumentation in the field of moral education. To find a new basis of legitimization in pedagogy I will explore the possibility to build ethical argumentation on Levinas ethics and to find a new basis for ethical argumentation in moral education I will present the basic idea of inductive approach. Key words: pedagogy of enlightenment, pedagogy of postmodernity, normativity, Lyotard, Levinas, Hoffman, inductive approach 1 Common accepted hypothesis that pedagogy as a normative science arouse from enlightenment philosophical anthropology and political theory, specially from Kant’s concepts, becomes interesting in the light spot of Lyotard postmodern philosophy. Lyotard thesis about the death of great narratives of modern philosophy and science points the question of legitimacy of millstones of pedagogy as science and one of the most important questions is the question about legitimacy of main deductive pedagogical goals, or even more general question of normative character of pedagogy as a science. But if we want to find more clear answers to these questions, we have to approach first the question of (at least relative) unity of enlightenment philosophical anthropology and political theory and second, the question if Lyotard description of two great narratives of enlightenment describes the whole scale of different pedagogical concepts that were inspired by enlightenment philosophy. After this task I intent to approach how can the turn in the idea of ethical normativity in Levinas philosophy influence the search for new approaches on the models of moral and civic education, and finally which are weaknesses and benefits of the inductive approach, first described in late sixties of the twentieth century as special parental discipline practice by M. Hoffman. My general hypothesis is that even postmodern pedagogy (like ethics and developmental psychology) remains a normative science but the turn of normativity is not only a political question of participation of pupils/students and their parents to become more active in negotiation about the content of pedagogical goals (basic principle of democratic education). It is also the question of new understanding of normativity, of normative agency on the field of moral acting, and of ethical responsibility that arise from the turn of responsibility to follow societal norms and ethical principle of justice to the concept of responsibility to treat fellow person in a respectful manner, which in the terms of postmodern philosophy enables acceptance of otherness and differences as central values of the present time. Unity or diversity of enlightenment philosophy For Usher and Edwards (1994, p. 24) the very rationale of the modern understanding of education is founded “on the humanist idea of a certain kind of subject who has the inherent potential to become self-motivated and self-directing.” Consequently the main task of education became that of bringing out this potential so that subjects could become “fully autonomous and capable of exercising their individual and intentional agency” (ibid., pp. 34–35). And according to Lyotard the supposition of autonomous subject is the ultimate great narrative of enlightenment philosophy that became the grounding idea of normative sciences like psychology, sociology, law theory, and also pedagogy. But when we take a closer look to the greatest philosophers of enlightenment period we can find different answers to two, for pedagogy crucial questions: What forms the anthropological basis of autonomy? How can we support a development of autonomy of individual by educational endeavors? 2 The biggest discrepancy to the first question can be found between Kant and Rousseau on one side and Hume on the other side. While first two authors try to prove that rationality is the ultimate founding of human ethical agency (categorical imperative in Kant’s philosophy and human soul, will, and rationality at Rousseau), Hume is convinced that human sympathetic emotions form the basis for compassion and are therefore the source of autonomous morality. While Kant’s and Rousseau’s ideas became the basis for development of psychology and pedagogy in nineteenth and the beginning of twentieth century, Hume’s concept of sympathetic emotions started to influence seriously to psychological and pedagogical ideas in last three decades by the discovery of importance of prosocial and moral emotions for human agency. We can find even bigger diversity in the enlightenment answers to the second question. While Kant is convinced that autonomy can be developed through strict discipline and cultivation of human understanding (the thesis that is later fully accepted in so called authoritative assertive type of discipline practices and educational concepts), Rousseau believes that strict discipline causes rebellion of youngsters so moral education should be founded on control over the child, on the construction of educational environment where the child has as little as possible opportunity to chose social contacts or activities that we believe are not good for him, and on indirect influence of educator’s personality. In this concept of natural education a child should feel the full freedom from directive discipline, but as Rousseau directly explained in the fourth book of Emile, behind the child’s sense of (fictive) freedom there lies a trick which can be bind with the concept of hidden authority (more in Kroflič 1997 and 2005). This thesis was later developed in the concepts of preventive discipline and permissive/progressive educational movement. Although Hume didn’t leave us strong pedagogical cues how to cultivate “sympathy as a natural communication of passions from person to person”, A. Baier (1998, pp. 232-233 and 236) stresses out further universal virtues which lead to compassionate behavior: intelligent attention to the consequences of actions as desirable in a person that is object of our activity, ability to listen to others, and imaginative powers which enable transcending of particular personal viewpoints. The answer to a question, how to educate described capacities successfully can not be deduced from the authoritarian – permissive conceptual dichotomy, that was developed from thirties in twentieth century according to the methodical discrepancy between Kant and Rousseau. Although we can find a notion about importance of love and acceptance of a child “instead” of thinking about successful education in terms of strict discipline and pedagogical authority in the closing chapter of the study The Authoritarian Personality (In the last sentence of very extensive study we read: “If fear and destructiveness are the major emotional sources of fascism, eros belongs to democracy.” (Adorno et all 1969, p. 976)), more detailed answers about the normative role of a parent or a teacher who want to foster empathic and compassionate virtues of a child can not be found earlier than in late sixties in M. Hoffman approaches on so called inductive discipline (Hoffman 2000). 3 On normative character of postmodern ethics and pedagogy In philosophy of education, history of pedagogical concepts, and curriculum theories we can find several reasons why pedagogy remains a normative science, although it has to legitimize normative goals by ethical (and later also legal) principles and norms. As long as education means following anticipating goals by chosen pedagogical endeavors, there are logical, scientific, political and economical, educational, and humanistic (ethical) reasons for clear planning of educational goals as the basis of curriculum planning. If we follow I. Sheffler, P. Hirst, and R. Peters, then teaching and learning are intentional activities so it is logical that recognizing supposed intentions and educational goals should be the basis of educational planning (Kelly 1989). This “logic” becomes even more obligatory in the field of political, economical, legal, and ethical reasons. If education is a common societal cost (of the tax-payers) and also an intervention into human being, then the citizens have the right to know for what reasons and effects they give their money; even more, when according to the Declaration on human rights education becomes a primarily right of parents, then a state should get the permission to have influence under the children minds from their parents according to their agreement about aims, content, and methods of education (ibid.). To conclude, despite Lyotard thesis about the fall of great narratives of enlightenment philosophy which have defined basic goals of education, and despite “an emphasis on the process of (moral) education which is more important than a product, postmodern pedagogy should not deny the importance of clear definition of telos – at least basic system of common values” as goals of education as intentional activity (Medveš 1991). If we take into account described reasons, we can accept a hypothesis about an inherent normativity of educational action which is legitimated through ethical, pedagogical, and legal principles. But the answer to the question, if ethical reasons of the enlightenment period are today still strong enough for legitimizing the right to educate a person in a public space/institution, is not so easy to take. When we try to defend a thesis on an inherent normativity of educational action on one side and the thesis about the need for new arguments for legitimizing our right to educate, we have to presuppose an existence of new normative concepts that fit better with postmodern time than enlightenment deontological ethics and law theory. One of the theorists in the field of ethics who is becoming more and more influential also on the ground of pedagogical explications is for sure E. Levinas. His basic idea about radicaly heteronymous character of ethical act is a concrete example of denial of Kant’s ethical ideal (autonomous morality). On the critique of enlightenment deontological ethics Levinas constructs not only a new view on basic ethical questions (about common good, ethical principles, and personal sources of moral acting), but also a new concept of moral responsibility that can be easily transformed to pedagogy as criteria of good education. The basic idea of Levinas ethics can be found in his article The I and the Totality (1954/2006): 4 “…the reciprocity of this respect (between two persons, R. K.) is not an indifferent relationship, such as serene contemplation, and it is not the result, but the condition of ethics. It is language, that is, responsibility. Respect attaches the just man to his associates in justice before attaching him to the man who demands justice.” (Levinas 2006, p. 30) According to Levinas a responsible moral orientation is therefore not a consequence of contemplative moral reasoning of autonomous person (“under the veil of ignorance”, as J. Rawls presupposes in his Theory of Justice (1971)), but a respectful dialog, evoked by the face of associate person. With this basic statement Levinas opens up a dialogical space where pedagogy becomes an event rather than being a preprogrammed process; but an event with clear enough normative idea that was in history of ethical ideas recognized as an ethical principle of respectful attitude to all humans, and that can be also found in Kant’s second definition of categorical imperative: “you should never treat the other person a means but always as an aim”. If Kant has already recognized an importance of respectful attitude to associate person, where is the new dimension of Levinas ethics? Is it just in pointing out a new priority of ethical demands (the principle of respect before the basic principle of justice)? Or does Levinas anthropology open radical new insights into normative character of pedagogy? Although the answer to the first question is positive (demand on respectful attitude before contemplating about justice), Levinas concept of ethics opens also a new dimensions of normative character of pedagogy, and also some concrete ideas about new possible concepts of methodic of moral education. In the following paragraphs I will point out some of the most important ideas of Levinas thought for further development of postmodern pedagogy: If Kantian autonomous subject could be a responsible agent of morality in a stable (protestant) culture, where all rational persons could rich the agreement on just relations, Levinasean moral agents meet associates as unique persons, different from themselves. The critical objection of C. Chalier on Kants ethics looks very plausible: “… (In Kantian ethics; R. K.) the other deserves my respect because of his or her rationality, his or her capability of being an autonomous person like myself,” and not because of “the otherness of the other” (Chalier 2002, p. 68). Or as Levinas speaks by himself: “The Other as Other is not only an alter ego: the Other is what I myself am not. The Other is this, not because of the Other’s character, or physiognomy, or psychology, but because of the Other’s very alterity.” (Levinas 1987, p. 83) One of the most well known dilemmas in recent time education that deals with described theoretical thesis is the gap between cultural differences in describing the importance of symbols of Islamic cultures like women scarf and prohibition of portraying God. Both symbols are in Europe usually described as an attack to the basic human rights: to equal rights of men and woman (scarf should be a symbol of deprivileged status of women in Islamic cultures), and the protest against caricatures of Mohamed in Danish newspaper should be a symbol of denying the right of free speech/expressing personal opinions. 5 Defenders of this kind of judgments usually forget, that in at least some Islamic cultures many women deliberately wear scarf as a way to protect the view on themselves as mere sexual objects; and that even in European cultures we are condemning hate speech as an example of verbal attack following Locke’s argument of limiting principle of tolerance when intolerant person attack tolerant one despite her willingness to be open to her different arguments, although we usually don’t understand comical caricatures of Christian God as an assault on our religion. Levinas ethics does not open only the possibility of moral communication in a world of differences. S. Todd claims that the Other of E. Levinas is “infinitely unknowable”, but anyway susceptibility to absolute difference defines how we relate to each other; even more, learning from the unknowable Other tells us who we really are (Todd 2003, p. 3 and 34): “When I think I know, when I think I understand the Other, I am exercising my knowledge over the Other, shrouding the Other in my own totality. The Other becomes an object of my comprehension, my world, my narrative, reducing the Other to me. What is at stake is my ego. But if I am exposed to the Other, I can listen, attend, and be surprised; the Other can affect me, she ‘brings me more than I contain’ (Levinas, Totality and Infinity 1961).” (Todd 2001, p. 73) In classical pedagogical (and also psychological) concepts understanding the logic of other is the basic condition of successful communication and also education. And despite Freud’s notions on the importance of unconsciousness, even listening to the other was focused to the topics of understanding and uncovering shadows of unconsciousness by the rational tools of comprehension of other’s identity and of our own inner obstacles that block successful relationship. In contemporary understanding of principles of pedagogy of listening the emphasis on dialog with children or youngsters is “...giving value to the other...” (Rinaldi 2006, p. 114) and opening ourselves to the narrative of the other in a dialog, that becomes transformative for my own identity (ibid., p. 76). What we should add to the famous advocates of pedagogy of listening like C. Rinaldi, classical enlightenment conception of normativity where a teacher as autonomous subject is an ultimate criteria of truth and morality, can not be accepted anymore as epistemological basis of educational dialog in before described terms of pedagogy of listening. However even Levinas admits that in life there are situations when meeting with other’s face as ultimate ethical criteria becomes impossible. Levinas himself became a victim of Nazi anti-Semitic regime, so he experienced that in concentration camp the executioner of evil calls for violence and no longer has a Face. In that case, “…there is a certain measure of violence necessary in terms of justice (that must be regulated by a state). But, on the other hand, it is in terms of the relation to Face … that we can speak of the legitimacy or illegitimacy of the state. A state in which the interpersonal relationship is impossible … is a totalitarian state. So there is a limit to the state.” (Levinas 1987, p. 90) As we can see, even in (postmodern) emphasis on openness to the dialog with the other as different, the idea of importance of accepting limitations for possible violence in public space in terms of universal human rights that we became aware in enlightenment 6 period is still important. What changes in the theoretical frame of Levinas ethics (and also in some other postmodern theories) is the believe that the spirit of human rights and living in just and caring community can be strengthened more successfully with the emphasis on respectful relation to the other’s face than with models of disciplining and cultivating moral reasoning of autonomous subject. This methodical turn is developing in the most clear and (in pedagogical sense) applicable form in the concept of inductive moral education, which I will present in the following section of the paper. Normativity in inductive moral education The concept of inductive approach was introduced in late sixties by M. Hoffman as a new concept of parent’s discipline practice, and what is for most common classifications of educational approaches important, as a concept in opposition to authoritative-assertive type of education on one side and emotional conditioning (permissive type of education) on the other side. According to Hoffman with inductive discipline, we: Express our disapproval of the child’s act and indicate implicitly or explicitly that the act is wrong and that the child has committed an infraction (this dimension is present also in other two discipline concepts); Call attention to the victim distress and make it salient to the child; Point up the role of the child’s action in causing that distress, what creates the condition for feeling empathy-based guilt, which is a feeling of intense disesteem for oneself for wrongfully harming another (Hoffman 2000, p. 151). Further empirical approaches confirmed that inductive discipline has statistically significant impact on faster development of empathy and pro-social attitudes in children (if we compare this impacts with “Kohlbergian” authoritative-assertive discipline practices; e.g., Krevans and Gibbs 1996, Eisenberg 2003). The researchers of inductive discipline had more difficulties with distinguishing of empathy-based guilt from oedipal guilt, and of inductive approach from emotional conditioning (Krevans and Gibbs 1996). Concerning the first distinction we have to mention later approaches of S. Tood (2003), who confirmed Hoffman’s thesis about existence of guilt in early childhood prior to solution of oedipal crisis. Furthermore K. Kristjansson (2004) philosophical investigation of Hoffman’s concept, where he affirmed the importance of sympathetic distress and prosocial emotions like compassion, indignation, and empathic guilt, and who despite reproach on theoretical indistinctness of concepts of emphatic distress and sympathetic distress ended his investigation with thesis, that “…philosophers have probably much more to learn about children and morality from psychologists of Hoffman's standing than psychologists have to learn from philosophers.” (Ibid, p. 304) What is new in Hoffman’s inductive approach? As we can already see from this short survey, in description of inductive discipline Hoffman is following Hume’s concept of normative agency on the field of moral acting, derivating from human’s sympathetic emotions toward well-being of a relative person. In 7 his complex theory of the development of empathy, Hoffman confirmed arise of prosocial motivation from empathic guilt and he also mentioned the possibility of positive educational endeavors when we confirm and therefore strengthen child’s considerate behaviors (Hoffman 2000, p. 151). But if we want to defend thesis about the possibility to build a new educational concept on the basis of inductive approach, we have to widen Hoffman’s approaches on several theoretical and methodical questions, like: What could be the profound anthropological basis of inductive educational approach? How can we define basic educational goals (and therefore a new concept of pedagogical normativity)? Which are the principles of a new educational methodic? How can we define active role of educator in inductive educational approach? As many theorists of so called liberal pedagogy have already emphasized, one of the basic anthropological ideas of inductive approach is the thesis about equal importance of pro-social emotions (personal virtues) as well as cognitive competencies (rational tools for ethical reasoning) for morality. So R. S. Peters (1998) stressed out the importance of authenticity, rational reflection, and strength of will for the development of autonomy, and among personal virtues that are important for moral reasoning and acting, he mentioned courage, integrity, and determination, while K. Strike (2003) is speaking about the importance of critical capacity, but also of virtues like courage, temperance, compassion, and considering the needs of others. In this place I would like to mention also the idea of H. Gardner (2007) about necessity of the development of two relatively separated sets of competencies of our mind – respectful mind and ethical mind – that are important for our moral reasoning and acting. If we add to this list of prominent theorists already mentioned notion of K. Kristjansson about the importance of pro-social emotions like compassion, indignation, and empathic guilt, we see that more and more theorists are becoming aware of the importance of different personal dimensions for moral reasoning and acting which were not in the spot light of interest in models of moral development that were built on the Kantian concept of man as autonomous moral subject. Another anthropological basis of inductive educational approach can be found in the idea of developmental priority of personal competencies for morality, based on empathic guilt, in relation to rational competencies for moral reasoning. Discovery of so called empathic guilt in very early childhood by M. Klein and S. Tood, and the discovery of early development of empathy as a source of pro-social emotions by M. Hoffman confirms the thesis, that we have much more possibilities for fostering moral development than pure discipline practices which help young child to act responsible according to set of social and moral rules in the developmental period when a child is yet not capable to understand the meaning of social and moral obligations. As we will see later, formation of personal virtues and pro-social emotions based on empathy can begin in very early childhood by motivating a child to step into interpersonal relations and to become sensitive for emotional reactions to those relationships and mutual activities. Therefore discipline 8 practices that are based on rewards and punishment of child’s behavior and on our efforts to enable child’s internalization of social and moral rules, that were the basis of moral education in Freud’s, Piaget’s, and Kohlberg’s concepts of moral development, are simply not the only answer to moral education. According to R. S. Peters one of the biggest paradoxes of moral education is, that while we aim at “the intelligent adaptability of a rational code” with “spontaneous delight in practising it” (Peters 1998 a, p. 32), “the brute facts of child development reveal that at the most formative years of a child’s development he is incapable of this form of life and impervious to the proper manner of passing it on.” (Ibid., p. 38) The third anthropological idea that is important for inductive educational approach is the recognition of the special value of so called relational goods and virtues, like love and friendship for the development of pro-social and moral orientation as important part of the child’s identity. According to M. Nussbaum (1986) we can trace this idea in Aristotle’s ethics in notion that more than a content of teaching the personal relationship between pupil and a teacher is important for pupil’s ethical development. If we mention again Klein’s and Tood’s idea about arise ob emphatic guilt from the early relation between the child and important other, we can confirm thesis of many proponents of so called ethics of virtue that moral and identity development is growing from encumbered interpersonal relations and activities, so the quality of this social space is the most important educational factor (MacIntyre 1981). Second necessary element of inductive educational paradigm is the question about possible changes of basic educational goals. Although educational goals were in history usually described in terms of basic values or ethical norms, to describe specific of inductive educational paradigm I will use the question, in what terms we can describe the core of moral responsibility? According to changes of shifts in Kant and Levinas ethics, we can describe the distinction between responsibility in modern and post-modern pedagogy, which accepts basic principles of Levinas ethics. If the former concept defined ethical responsibility as the demand to follow societal norms (in so called conventional phase of morality) and ethical principles (in so called post-conventional phase of autonomous morality), today we can define ethical responsibility as primarily respectful ethical response to an existential call of the other, as personal commitment to respectful being and acting, and as care for our life mission and consistent identity (see more in Kroflič 2007). When we speak about the shift in normative idea, we have to consider also the importance of anthropological thesis about the priority of respectful relationship before ethical principle of justice. This last thesis contains two dimensions: we can speak about the priority of respectful relationship before ethical principle in epistemological sense (of “competing” ethical criteria for moral reasoning), and also about the priority of respectful relationship before ethical principle in the developmental sense. The last thesis simply means that personal qualities for respectful attitude can be developed before child’s capabilities for ethical reasoning. 9 Ethical and anthropological ideas lead us to the basic structure of inductive educational methodic which can be described in three phases: If ethical consciousness demands complex cognitive capacities, child is even in first years capable to step to relations of love and friendship, through which he/she develops relational response-ability and normative agency for pro-social activities in most authentic way; because personal encumbered relation may be harmful when empathic overarousal, empathic bias, pity and paternalism arise, next step is development of the sense of respect toward concrete persons or activities; the last step of moral education is to become aware of ethical principles and humanistic demands, concerning specially human rights and ecological values, and learn how to use them as basis for democratic negotiation in cases of interpersonal conflicts (ibid.). What is important to add to this short description is that proposed model should not be understood as classical linear developmental step model (like Kohlberg’s model of the development of moral reasoning) because every phase of the model remains important for morality even when next developmental step was reached. As we have already seen through the short analysis of conflicts about the meaning of Muslim cultural symbols, keeping in mind the principle of respect while we are trying to apply logic of justice in public space is especially very important in multicultural societies. And second notion, that the best way of using inductive model of moral development is – inclusive school environment and not only an abstract learning of solving moral dilemmas in the classroom. We finally reached the last question that is important for the development of inductive approach of pro-social and moral education - how to define an active role of educator? Since I started to develop inductive approach as a complex educational paradigm from Hoffman’s notions of specific discipline practice, it is obvious that in discipline practices a teacher has very active role which is connected with specific normative idea how to stop child’s not acceptable behavior. In inductive discipline a teacher has to demand child’s responsibility for the effects of his act, call attention to the victim distress, and make it salient to the child. This simply means that a teacher should not allow the child to “look away” and avoid the recognition of the damage, his behavior has produced. But with careful observation we can notice an important shift in his normative position toward the child. A teacher is no longer in a position of ultimate criteria of morality in terms of calling attention to the ethical value, norm, or principle. The ultimate normative criteria lie at child’s obligation to look at the face of the victim, which we have already recognized as pre-ethical criteria of morality in Levinas philosophy. Although an educator’s role in inductive approach remains active, described shift in relation toward ultimate criteria of morality changes the character of educator’s authority. While describing the basic structure of pedagogical authority I propose two important features: 10 authority is a dialogical and not a substantial concept, that could be described in terms of a set of personal (or formal) features of an educator, a pupil, and/or educational setting (Kroflic 1997 and 2005; see also Bingham and Sidorkin 2004, Bingham 2008); authority is (like concept of transfer in psychoanalysis) a concept that enables educational effects but on the other hand it is a main obstacle to reach the ultimate goal of moral education – development of personal responsibility and critical moral reasoning (Kroflic 1997 and 2005). The solution of this last paradox can be described in terms of creating a type of educational authority that is constructed through the relationship between teacher and pupil with the following maxim: “The good teacher is therefore a person who is always working himself out of a job.” (Hirst and Peters 1970); a maxim that was developed from similar principle of Aristotle: Amicus Plato, magis amica veritas. It is a type of authority that I defined as self-limiting authority (Kroflic 1997), similar to C. Bingham (2008, p. 95) hypothesis about possible deliberating dimension of authority: “Students need to think of teachers and schools as centres of authority, authority they can use to increase their own agency.” According C. Bingham (ibid.), a traditional concept of authority as substance leads us to an educational (or better say discipline) situation that is similar to Kafkean novels, where teacher as the doorkeeper doesn’t allow students to step behind the wall where the ultimate source of the moral truth suppose to lie. And possible deliberation lies in a changing role of a teacher in an educational relation. Inductive teacher is no more pointing a finger to imaginary ultimate source of moral law and describing himself as a guard at the gates of wisdom. He is stressing out the importance of the face of a person who was a victim of conflict and this person is a kind of witness that somebody has crossed the line of respectful relationship. Self-limitation of teacher’s authority in epistemological sense opens the possibility of activating moral sentiments and reasoning which leads to a possibility to restore damage. Combining elements of emotional distress, of pro-social emotions, moral reasoning, and moral acting is the way how we draw moral education near to the principles of experiental learning and realistic educational approach (Korthagen 2001). Conclusion If we started discussion with hypothesis that pedagogy as a normative science arouse from enlightenment philosophical anthropology and political theory, specially from Kant’s concept of morality, we first discovered a heterogeneity of enlightenment ideas about ultimate source of autonomous morality, and second even bigger heterogeneity of pedagogical ideas how to foster moral development in education. All described ideas had a big influence on understanding of pedagogical normativity, and question of different normative moral ideas became even more clear in a spotlight of Kant’s and Levinas ethics. Binding principles of Hume’s and Levinas ethics with Hoffman’s investigations in inductive discipline and Kristjansson’s arguments on the importance of pro-social emotions we found a confirmation of hypothesis, that shift in basic vision on moral 11 responsibility (toward respectful relationship) opens possibilities for development of complex inductive approach to moral education. This shift of normativity in a way refreshes old antiquity debate between Plato and Aristotle about how to draw moral principles from the sky to the ground, from abstract societal norms and ethical principles to the responsibility for human interrelations, which is brilliantly visualized in Rafael’s painting School of Athens (Vatican 1510-1511). And finally we saw that shift in moral normativity can be connected with the possibilities of structuring new type of pedagogical authority (which we described as self-limiting authority) which can strengthen pupil’s moral agency, a goal that can be characterized as one of the most complex questions in the history of pedagogy. LITERATURE: Adorno et all. (1969). The Authoritarian Personality. New York: W. W. Norton& co. Baier, A. C. (1998). Hume on moral sentiments, and the difference they make. Philosophers on Education (New Historical Perspectives) (ed. by Rorty, A. O). London and New York: Routledge. Pp. 227-237. Bingham, C. and Sidorkin, A. M. (ed.) (2004). No Education Without Relation. New York...: Peter Lang (Counterpoints: Studies in the Postmodern Theory of Education, vol. 259). Bingham, C. (2008). Authority Is Relational (Rethinking Educational Empowermehnt). New York: State University of New York Press, Albany. Chalier, C. (2002). What Ought I to Do? Morality in Kant and Levinas. Ithaca: Cornell University Press. Eisenberg, N. et all. (2003) Longitudinal Relations Among Parental Emotional Expressivity, Children’s Regulation, and Quality of Socioemotional Functioning. Developmental Psychology. Vol. 39, No. 1, Pp. 3–19. Gardner, H. (2007). Five Minds for the Future. Boston, Massachusetts: Harvard Business School Press. Hirst, P. H. and Peters R. S. (1970). The Logic of Education. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul. Hoffman, M. L. (2000). Empathy and moral development: implications for caring and justice. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Kelly A. V., 1989, The Curriculum - Theory and Practice, London: Paul Chapman Publishing Ltd. Korthagen, F. (2001). Linking practice and theory. The Pedagogy of Realistic Teacher Education. Mahwah, New Jersey: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, Publishers. Krevans, J. And Gibbs, J. C. (1996). Parent's use of Inductive Discipline: Relations to Children's Empathy and Prosocial Behavior. Child Development. Vol. 67. pp. 3263-3277. Kristjansson, K. (2004). Empathy, sympathy, justice and the child. Journal of Moral Education. Vol. 33, No. 3, pp. 291-305. Kroflič, R. (1997). Avtoriteta v vzgoji. Ljubljana: Znanstveno in publicistično središče (Zbirka Alfa, 1997, 4). 12 Kroflič, R. (2005). New concepts of authority and citizen education. V: ROSS, Alistair (ur.). The Seventh Conference of the Children's Identity and Citizenship in Europe Thematic Network. Teaching citizenship : proceedings of the seventh conference of the Children's Identity and Citizenship in Europe Thematic Network, Ljubljana 2005. (Proceedings of the seventh CiCe Conference). London: CiCe, pp. 25-34. Kroflič, R. (2007). Vzgoja za odgovornost onkraj razsvetljenske paradigme: od razvoja odgovora-zmožnosti k spoštljivemu odnosu in razvoju etične zavesti. Sodobna pedagogika. (Posebna izdaja iz posveta Vzgojni koncept šole na razpotjih sodobnosti). Vol. 58 (124). pp. 56-71. Levinas, E. (1987). Time and Other and additional Essays. Pittsburg: Duquesne University Press. MacIntyre, A. (1981). After Virtue (Second Edition). Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press. Medveš, Z. (1991). Pedagoška etika in kocept vzgoje (1. in 2. del). Sodobna pedagogika. Vol. 42. No. 3-4 in 5-6. Pp. 101-117 and 213-226. Nussbaum, M. C. (1986). The Fragility of Goodness. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Peters, R. S. (1998). Freedom and the development of the free man. Philosophy of Education. Major Themes in the Analytic Tradition. Volume II. Education and human being. ed. by P. H. Hirst and P. White. London and New York: Routledge. pp. 11-31. Peters R. S. (1998 a). Reason and habit: the paradox of moral education. Philosophy of Education, Mayor Themes in the Analytic Tradition, Volume IV, Problems of Educational Content and Practices. ed. by P. H. Hirst and P. White. London and New York: Routledge. pp. 27-39. Rinaldi, C. (2006). In Dialogue with Reggio Emilia (Listening, researching and learning). London and New York: Routledge. Strike, K. A. (2003). Toward a liberal conception of school communities (Community and the autonomy argument). Theory and Research in Education. vol. 1 (2). London: Sage Publications. pp. 171-193. Todd, S. (2001). On Not Knowing the Other, or Learning from Levinas. of Education 2001. http://www.ed.uiuc.edu/EPS/PES-Yearbook/2001/todd%2001.pdf Todd, S. (2003). Learnig from the Other (Levinas, Psychoanalysis, and Ethical Possibilities in Education). New York: State University of New York Press (Suny Series). Usher, R. and Edwards, R. (1994). Postmodernism and Education. London and New York: Routledge. 13