The Structure of Qualitative Thought I offer an interpretation of John Dewey's "Qualitative Thought" that synthesizes elements from Experience and Nature, Human Nature and Conduct, and Art as Experience. Its purpose is to explain how the momentary structure of habit guides the conversion of quality to sense, thought, and object through channeling the flow of qualitative experience and informing its conversion conditions. The explanation exposes a limitation of the Deweyan model of inquiry based on the problematic situation: the possibility of inquiry is dependent upon potentialities of the situation. The natural potentiality must exist prior to its experienced possibility that leads to the question of how far we may push the limits of a situation, e.g., how flexible are our habits? INTRODUCTION I offer an interpretation of John Dewey's "Qualitative Thought" that synthesizes elements from Experience and Nature, Human Nature and Conduct, and Art as Experience. The inspiration for the project is Victor Kestenbaum's The Phenomenological Sense of John Dewey and its analysis of the role of habit in meaningful experience. He writes, "[m]eaning comes into being through the dialectic of self and world, and man is a sense-giving being on the level of pre-objective experience, that of habit."i The thrust of the inspiration is to articulate the structure or mechanism of habit that orders qualitative experience as pre-objective becomes objective experience. In other words, how objects coalesce from the background to the foreground of attentive experience. In "Qualitative Thought," Dewey aims to explain "the meaning of regulation by an underlying and pervasive quality" (LW 5:246). This includes an explanation of the constitution and relationality of objects as guided by the situation (LW 5:245). He claims that an object is an element of the situation that is taken or "abstracted" from it; objects are not prior to a situation or their taking. Rather, objects manifest from an "underlying pervasive quality" that uniquely demarcates a situation and is the only "unqualifiably given" (LW 5:254). The present work is not to be taken as new historical scholarship, despite its emphasis on historic texts, but as preparatory for an expansive interpretation and new work in pragmatism. It evidences a deliberate choice between delineating and arbitrating past historic scholarship, which it performs only implicitly, and advancing contemporary work as part of a program that I call “phenomenological pragmatism.”ii QUALITY The study of quality and "Qualitative Thought" is the study of what and how something can be consciously experienced for Dewey. For present purposes, "experience" will refer to "conscious experience," i.e., primary and secondary experience, and all further discussion will assume this level of analysis. Note that this narrows the denotation or meaning of some terms, e.g., “quality” per “qualitative experience” does not have as far ranging a meaning as it would for C.S. Peirce, and “experience” is provisionally narrowed from Dewey’s wider articulation in Experience and Nature. Quality is "first directly and unreflectively experienced or had" (LW 5:254). We first experience quality as that blazin' blooming confusion noted by James. This is "first" in the sense that objects are discriminated or abstracted out of the situation, the context, and are not prior to it. They are not experientially, phenomenally, or epistemically prior if one prefers those terms. Experience "exists as a dumb quality" until it is intellectualized or taken as an object of thought (LW 5:254). As quality is the basis of conscious experience, "it forms that to which all objects of thought refer … although … it is never part of the manifest subjectmatter of thought" (LW 5:254). One could say that it is most immediate in experience, least mediated, if one recognizes that immediate means the first event of conscious experience, but by no means the first event of a natural history. The latter is mediated by brute physics, gushing biology, and the song and dance of society and culture. Hence, the initial "dumbness" of quality appears so only relative to a perspective, whereas intellectualizing quality mediates it to show its resonating relations in the environment, both physical and symbolic. Quality emerges out of the transaction of organism and environment as a functional element of the situation. Its manifestation and characteristics are due to habit and the habitual incorporation of the environment by the integral body of habits. That is, quality becomes meaningful as it blossoms in conscious experience that is when habit becomes a decisive factor rather than brute existence. Habits "incorporate an environment within themselves. They are adjustments of the environment, not merely to it" (MW 14:38; cf 142). Habits are a continual incorporating or embodying of the environment and are continuous with it. They are how the organism mediates experience so as to remain at home in its environment, and this includes the symbolic environment of society and culture. The term "situation" denotes the fundamental unit of being at home in the world that the organism actively maintains; it is homeostasis. Returning to the example, the frightful shade was part of a whole situation that was frightening. The shade did not secretly murmur its dark intentions to us, but rather we experienced the situation such, and identifying either the environment or the organism as frightened/frightening is a discrimination that we make later. It is an additional act, a mediating of what was immediately frightening. Our implicit acts in the situation lead to those qualities emerging from experience, the transaction of organism and environment as situation, and such emergences betray a movement. Quality "has as a part of its complex quality a moment or transition in some direction" that allows it to be converted into thought (LW 5:254). Thomas Alexander calls this the quality's dynamic telos; situations are teleological.iii Their momentary telos is a matter of the drama of transaction prefigured by habit and the given context that is creatively enacted at each moment. Habit is the memory of the organism that provides pattern and form; a habit strives for a completion in deed. Habit anticipates its next move as if following a script as negotiated with the environment, and the performance is acted out in the situation. When there is some tension or disruption of the enactment, the occasion spurs thought. Quality becomes intellectual, or is "taken" from merely being "had." The conversion from dumb quality to thought is accomplished by "a statement of limits and a direction of transition between them" (LW 5:254). Experience is fundamentally anticipative, and I claim that this is a source of its "movement." Aside from the dyadic rhythm of the alteration of precarious and stable, conscious experience moves because habit continually acts in anticipation of its stimulus. This is the "anticipatory" and "onward tendency of habit" (MW 14:21). Previously, it was said that habit "mediates" its environment to incorporate the latter as a situation; it is time to be more specific. A "habit" is the definite form of indefinite biological impulse(s) that integrates them into unified activity. Impulses are always active and strive for the realization of their definite form. Hence, habit gains the "onward tendency" of impulse as integrated towards some definite "anticipation." We become aware of the anticipatory nature of experience only when anticipation is frustrated or resisted. Becoming aware is attending to the focal region of experience that centers around highly tensive involvements to which we are sensitive. Sensitivity to the environment is dynamic and dependent on the context, specific habituation, the current ongoing activity, and so forth. A given region is in focus because of the frustration or failure of habit to achieve its momentarily anticipated satisfaction. Anticipation is thereby directive of we might attend or the foreground of conscious experience. In summary, quality is first unreflectively experienced or "had." quality" until it is intellectualized of taken as an object. It is a "dumb Since quality is the (phenomenal) basis of conscious experience, "all objects of thought" refer to it. Quality emerges out of the transaction of organism and environment, as an element of a situation characterized by the habitual incorporation of the environment as situation. Victor Kestenbaum calls this a "process of qualification" whereas Jim Garrison calls it “mimesis.”iv Quality has a "movement of transition in some direction," or telos as Thomas Alexander might say, that can be converted from "dumb quality" to "an object of thought" through a "statement of limits and a direction of transition between them." Conscious experience is fundamentally anticipatory, since habits are always such, and they provide the definite character of experienced meaning and objects. "Anticipatory" also includes the temporal futurity of the situation that constitutes the temporal and imaginative horizon within what Alexander calls the "temporal teleological structure of the situation."v ORGANIZED QUALITY From the previous discussion, I conclude the following. If quality has an emergent, dynamic telos that allows for its conversion from ephemeral feltness to intellection and object through limitation/resistance, then articulating these bounds is also describing the functional limits of intellection and objection. "Limit" may be understood as either the habitual bounds of an ongoing activity that provide a “structure” or order of transition, or as an event of resistance to such activity that alters those limits and activity. Moreover, if experiencing the meaning of a quality implicates its limit, then one can know something about the nominal bounds of experienced meaning by knowing this limit. There are two denotations of "limit" in my usage of the term. First, "limit" is the range of habit, i.e., our capacities. We either know how to ride a bicycle or we do not, although we can learn and thereby expand our habitual capacities. Second, "limit" is the momentarily operative, functional range of habit given the situation. This denotation primarily refers to the momentary organization of habitual activity as it meets resistance in the form of environmental resistance or a conflict of habits. A limit always implies a situation in which it is an element, although the present analysis emphasizes the contribution of habit rather than the environment. As equilibrium is never perfect, habits always meet resistance that contours the felt structure of what is called a tensive situation. We feel and navigate by resistance felt as tension that pulls our attention to a focus of attentive experience. For instance, alphabetic characters on a page were once indecipherable oddities until years of habituation allow us to read the patterns of tension productive of sense as written English. We might feel that way again upon first viewing elaborate sanskrit, which it might appear as scrollwork art to untrained Western eyes and habits. Limitation in this second sense will be the primary denotation in the present essay with an emphasis on the habitual rather than environmental contribution. Limitation as a constitutive condition for qualitative experience is an element in the structure of experience that directs its flow. A limit does not "restrain" or "constrain" meaningful experience, but is the "limiting function." It plays a role in the "construction" and "reconstruction" of qualitative experience that Dewey ascribes to "structure," which is "an arrangement of changing events such that properties which change slowly, limit and direct a series of quick changes and give them an order which they would not otherwise possess" (LW 1:64-65). Hence, the "arrangement" of limits directs the pattern of experience and is also called a "structure." These structures are not permanent, but are momentary. Dewey describes structure as "a character of events…. A set of traits is called a structure because of its limiting function in relation to other traits of events" (LW 1:64). A limit is an element of the structure of experience that gives form to its "movement." Recall that quality has a "movement of transition in some direction" from which quality becomes thought and object through being organized by limitation, or as I now indicate, by order/structure/form. Given the current habitual and phenomenological analysis, the structures in focus are habits, i.e., "energy organized in certain channels" (MW 14:54). Habit is the organic basis for the limit structure in two senses. The particularity and interpenetration of habit in both its biological stabilities and momentary operation engenders a range of satisfactions or fulfillments of a telos. This range of teloi corresponds to the first denotation of "limit" and adds a directedness; experience flows and blooms and certain directions given habit, its sedimentation, and its operation on the environment to generate the situation in each moment. For the second sense, consider the anticipatory nature of habit. Recall that habitual anticipation is ongoing activity in which habituated impulses are either achieving continuous satisfaction (outlet) or are striving for such. When anticipation is frustrated due to conflicting habits or environmental resistance, the recoil of habit generates a tension. Experience becomes tensive, and since the attentive region or foreground of experience is nominally the most tensive, the habitual structure of anticipation is a dominant factor into what we may attend. Although habitual sensitivity to the environment is dynamic and dependent on the context, momentary habitual function is determinative. This implicates the second sense of "limit"; the anticipatory structure of habit and thereby of conscious experience is nominally determinative of what, how, when, and whether something may appear as meaningful, although at the moment the focus is on "when." In any case, the matter of the experience, e.g., the sense, is correlative to but not determined by limitation. Said simply, we reflect during a problematic situation. Without a problematic situation, we do not reflect and are carried by our extant habits navigating through the environment. We may experience what we do, but we do not necessarily attend to, reflect, or know it. We may only reflect during a moment of hesitation, but the conditions for this moment nominally implicate our habits of sensitivity. Something arrests or limits us. QUALITY INTO SENSE For the next step, the leading clue is Dewey's account of the "association of ideas" in "Qualitative Thought." Before entering into what Dewey says, I would offer a brief interpretation of what I take him to mean by the phrase, because Dewey does not straightforwardly identify its source, and it appears that he is using a historic phrase within a contemporary discussion with empiricists and idealists. I argue that Dewey intends the phrase in a manner similar to Hume and subsequent empiricists insomuch as association describes the stable patterns of the unfolding of ideas. Describing the stable patterns of the "association of ideas" is describing the ordered manifestation of experiences. Dewey identifies thinking as a controlled existential process of association. For while the subject is usually treated as psychological in nature, thinking as an existential process takes place through association; existentially, thinking is association as far as the latter is controlled…. Thus, when association takes the form of thought, or is controlled and not loose day-dreaming, association is a name for a connection of objects or their elements in the total situation having a qualitative unity (LW 5:255-256). Thinking is an existential process as the existent organism is transacting with existences in the natural environment. The transactive process is "experience" that implicates the homeostatic process of the organism that includes an ongoing habitual incorporation of the environment as situation. Under certain conditions, experience enters the phase of "mind" or conscious experience in which experience may become qualitative, meaningful, and manifest objects. Since experience as a process maintains continuity with all its phases, conscious experience is no less existential than bodies slamming into each other. Thinking is the controlled association of objects. ”Control" means ordered or structured in a certain manner such as to provide a "functional limit" as previously discussed. However, "thinking" indicates the active mediation of the flow of experience, as opposed to the relatively passive sensitivity to the situation that includes attention, intellection, and/or cognition. Enculturated or sedimented habit is the proximate basis of controlled association as amendable by education or learning. Association need not always be thought or "controlled"; intellection is a particular event of association. Association is a "connection of objects or their elements in the total situation having a qualitative unity" (LW 5:255-256). Hence, thinking is a controlled "connection" of objects integrated by their qualitative unity. Association or connection is our entry into how the pervasive quality of the situation "regulates" the emergence and relation of objects. Given that Dewey is using Hume's terms with a different denotation, what does he mean? What "causes" association and how are objects associated? Hume thought that the mind associated ideas (objects) per its faculties in accord with the three principles of connection. The particular associations were habitual, e.g., the instantiations of convention. Let us focus on the habitual association of ideas/objects and their principle of connection for Dewey. Dewey argues that association is due to habit (LW 5:256). That is, the original temporal or spatial contiguity, or similarity of two things in the world, is not the cause of association. For example, he notes that thinking of a "chiffonier … does not call up that of drawers as a distinct idea" although they are in fact spatially contiguous (LW 5:256). Rather, habit produces an "immediate reaction" and not a distinct idea of an object. Distinct objects were once part of "one situational object" (LW 5:257) that were discriminated and the distinction may persist in the "organic attitude formed in consequence of a responsive act to things once coexistent or sequential" (LW 5:256). It is the distinction or "disassociation" of the two objects that must be explained. There must be a "resistant or negative factor" that produces a "tension" to forestall a direct response and produce the distinction (LW 5:257, emphasis added). The distinction comes out of the unity of the original act wherein "the quality attending it was spread over and inclusive of the two things in question" (LW 5:256). Dewey concludes that the "quality of a situation as a whole operates to produce a functional connection" (LW 5:257). In sum, thinking is a controlled existential process of association. The process is existential as it is the result of the transaction of existential elements of the environment. It is controlled per being ordered or structured by a dynamic configuration of limits that mediate the flow of experience. What is distinctive of thought is that what is associated are "objects." The association is due to habit that exists as the dynamic configuration of limits that serve a homeostatic purpose. Objects arise as distinct due to prior habituation that have sedimented a previous act of making a distinction. The prior habituation produces a "tension" within the pervasive quality of the situation to make a "functional connection" that may become an "intellectual connection." CONCLUSION The present essay explains how the momentary structure of habit guides the conversion of quality to sense, thought, and object through channeling the flow of qualitative experience and informing its conversion conditions. Its movement is partially due to the forward impulse of habit as it is organized by limitation. Limitation is a constitutive structural condition of qualitative experience that orders the "arrangement of changing events" by being a "limiting function" of the movement of experience. Limitation arises from the serial coordination or transaction of habitual activity and environmental conditions that produce a network of felt tension within the situation. Aside from directing ongoing activity, it also determines the field of focal tensive experience, i.e., the foreground and background to what we may attend. Since felt tension is a basis for the focusing of attentive experience, it carves a path out of the potential experiences to be had in the situation. Felt tension is the felt selection of the potential situations in which ongoing habitual activity has already implicated the organism. This is the horizon of feeling. Thinking serves to mediate and determine the path taken of all the potential situations that the organism may enact. However, thinking and inquiry may only intellectually mediate what is already attentively felt. This presents a circularity: we may inquire into what is wrong only if we already feel that it is wrong. The freeing of imagined possibilities in experience or the opening of the imaginative horizon, is always grounded and thereby limited by the situation. The situation is the unity of ongoing habitual incorporation of the environment that is a process of qualifying ongoing transactive experience to become conscious experience. Consciously experienced "possibilities" are grounded in part by past sedimented habit, present creativity in reconstructing it, and futural anticipations of what each reconstruction might mean, e.g., its consequences. The dilemma of the Deweyan model is that habit is the organic basis of experienced possibilities and ends-in-view that are always already limited by the momentary potentialities of habit. Perhaps the best way to counter the charge of "optimism" and a lack of "tragic sensibility" in Dewey scholarship is not to write refutations. I suggest expositing the tragic, the inherent limitations of human being that we ignorantly or knowingly strive against, such that human effort is seen on the precipice of falling back into the cave. This is not a call to pessimism, but to the heroism of struggling against human finitude as immanent transcendence. NOTES i Victor Kestenbaum, The Phenomenological Sense of John Dewey: Habit and Meaning (Atlantic Highlands, NJ: Humanities Press, 1977), 50. ii Dewey called such studies a psychological/historical/evolutionary method depending upon the article. See his “Psychology and Philosophic Method,” “The Psychological Method in Ethics,” “The Evolutionary Method in Morality I & II,” and so forth in the Collected Works. iii Thomas M. Alexander, John Dewey's Theory of Art, Experience, and Nature: The Horizons of Feeling (Albany, SUNY Press, 1987), 76. iv Kestenbaum, Phenomenological Sense, 29. Jim Garrison, "The Role of Mimesis in Dewey's Theory of Qualitative Thought,” The Transactions of the C.S. Pierce Society, Vol. 35, No. 4 (Fall 1999): 678-696. Kestenbaum writes from the perspective of a phenomenological analysis of pre-objective experience per habit, whereas Garrison writes from a metaphysical-epistemic analysis heavily reliant on C.S. Peirce. I take them to be focusing on the same event from different perspectives and levels of analysis that correspond to emphases on different phases of the same natural process, e.g., how habit informs conscious experience (Kestenbaum) or how existence is liberated in qualitative thought for intellectual mediation of meaning (Garrison). v Alexander, Horizons of Feeling, 76.