Take Home Final K. D. Kappus Fall 2006: SOA 466 (Stivers) Social Theory Kappus 1/15 1) Compare and contrast a qualitative, dialectical approach to research and theory with a positivistic, statistical approach I will draw contrasts between qualitative and numerical/statistical approaches to research and theory. First, I will illustrate the assertion of the class lectures and authors that quantification confounds understanding and strips phenomena of their true social meaning. Second, I will contrast the motivations for use of a qualitative approach with the interests of a social thinker who uses a quantitative approach. Third, I will distinguish the concepts that quantitative and qualitative theorists use to understand the social world. Finally, I will detail what several of the course texts say in support of the distinctions I have made. “A quantitative, statistical method, on some level,” Stivers said, “reduces theory down to the variables that are used for measurement.” Vandenberg makes a similar accusation about quantification when he has his readers ponder a Cartesian view of the French Pantheon in which the value of the structure has been reduced to the number of bricks out of which the shrine was built, and their individual dimensions. If we quantify the Pantheon, we are no longer able to speak about the strong feeling it inspires in the heart of a Frenchman. We no longer see the Pantheon, but instead, merely a pile of bricks. The statisticians want the facts, but like Vandenberg points out, the facts don’t speak for themselves. Facts need context in order to convey useful meaning. We want to back away in an ostensible attempt to be “objective.” Fleeing context, a phenomena’s relationship with the whole, we attempt to abscond with the phenomena’s meaning, perhaps a single figure or index score. Arrested later for attempted robbery, we are embarrassed to find that we were caught both redhanded and empty-handed. Why would anyone wish to be caught empty-handed after so much effort? In fact, a choice to quantify is ultimately political (Habermas). Compte’s positivism and the empirical social science Kappus 2/15 that has followed his lead are attempts to control, manipulate, or forecast the future, and these attempts are mostly carried out in service to the State. Compte would have formed a committee to run the nation based on the relevant numbers, the “Stat”-istics; Osterberg notes that the study of statistics arose because princes wished to control their subjects more effectively. If a theorist doesn’t strive to serve the interests of the State, s/he can serve the interest of conserving the past into the present by using a historical/hermeneutical method. The rest of us, being interested in human liberation, can create social theory that is a criticism of power and ideology. This last approach to theory doesn’t especially lend itself to quantification because a power relationship is a holism, irreducible to decontextualized numbers. The statisticians’ intent is to use logical, positivistic concepts to describe the essential qualities of a thing in the social world. They count the bricks in the Pantheon, and the dimensions of those bricks, and they say that their conceptualization of the Pantheon as a sum of bricks, which they have counted and measured, is the same as the Pantheon itself. For the user of these logical, positivistic concepts, ideally, there is only one true, reliable, and therefore best way to capture the meaning of the Pantheon: it always has the same number of bricks, and those bricks always measure the same number of cubic meters each, no matter who measures. On the other end of a spectrum, some social scientists have used metaphor to describe the essential qualities of a thing in the social world, just as if they were poets. For the user of metaphor, there are many possible ways of conveying the meaning of something. Shall I compare thee to a summer’s day, or do you feel more like a kid at Christmas? Is capitalism from the point of the worker more like a massive machine (Charlie Chaplin comes to mind here--) or is it more like Sinclair’s jungle? Kappus 3/15 In this class, what we have done is essentially split the difference between pure metaphor and pure positivism with a third, middle way of capturing social reality. If we used metaphor, a prisoner’s release from bondage after a long sentence would be like a breath of fresh air. If we used quantification, his/her freedom would be an amount or a distinct category: we are 95% confident that we have successfully measured his/her freedom to be at least 90% greater than it was previously. In our middle way, we use dialectical concepts, and say that the former prisoner’s freedom takes its meaning in contrast to his former confinement. Unlike metaphor, there probably is a single dialectical concept that is more accurate and reliable than all the others; unlike quantification, the parts are irreducible to a single figure. Part of the work of the course in for the first month or so was to show that quantification is not the best way to capture the meaning of social phenomena. We started with Lakoff, who contests the relevance to the social sciences of the idea that standing outside and apart from the object of investigation, we are able to extract a single reliable measure of a characteristic of that object. He proposes that the overall meaning of a social phenomenon is contained within a set of internal meanings and inter-relationships that are contradictory and changing—a dialectic. Osterberg continues this argument when he talks about internal and external relations. The key for these writers and the ones we read later is that studying holistically how the parts of a system work together conveys more meaning than reducing the whole to a sum of its parts. 2) Discuss Ellul’s views on propaganda. Distinguish political from sociological propaganda. What are the sociological conditions for the existence of propaganda? Discuss in particular the mass society, public opinion, the mass communication media, and an average culture. Discuss why both the political state and the individual need propaganda. What is the new relationship between propaganda and ideology, and between action and ideology? Ellul believes that propaganda is a simple necessity in mass society. When mechanical solidarity (Durkeim’s term) is broken, the individual is left without the moorings of the small Kappus 4/15 groups that make up this sort of society. He or she is merely a member of the mass, and his/her identity is based on his/her similarities to other members of the mass. Psychologically isolated from others, the individual has no community aside from the community of people who consume the same products. Ellul draws a distinction between sociological and political propaganda. Political propaganda is an intentional and overt attempt to influence a group towards a party or government’s position. Its use is deliberate and calculated. Sociological propaganda, on the other hand, is much more diffuse. In either case, the attempt is to disseminate an ideology. Ellul defines sociological propaganda as “the penetration of ideology by means of sociological context.” By this, he means that the ideology is disseminated via the general climate in which people live their lives. In an earlier part of his work, he insists that propaganda works when it is so pervasive as to be unnoticeable. Sociological propaganda exemplifies this pervasiveness. It is in the structure of the movies, the way that social services are administered, and what clothes people wear. The upshot of the pervasive and diffuse quality of sociological propaganda is to create a common lifestyle for the mass society. Propaganda must speak to the individual both as an individual, and as a member of a grouping that is based on what s/he shares with other members of the mass. When I lived in San Francisco, I was a member of the target demographic consisting of 18-35 year-old college educated men, non-television owners, with disposable income, who lived in a leading market area. To manipulate my opinion, the propagandist needed to appeal to me as an individual and as a member of this group. Ellul says that there are both “sociological” and “objective” conditions that must be met for propaganda to flourish. The sociological requirements are for a mass society, about which I Kappus 5/15 already commented, the existence of mass media of communication, and the crystallization of public opinion. The objective conditions are the existence of an average culture and an average standard of life. I will discuss each of these in turn. In addition to a mass society, there must be public opinion. Public opinion is different from the opinions that small groups form in a mechanical society in that the people in mass society do not usually have direct experience with the subjects about which they will form common opinions. What has to happen for public opinion to form, then, is that someone has to tell these people what subjects are worthwhile having an opinion about, and ultimately, what their opinion on those topics should be. A linked sociological requirement for the flourishing of propaganda, then, is the prevalence of mass media. The mass media are the best way of spreading public opinion. The objective conditions for the flourishing of propaganda are an average culture and an average standard of living. The average standard of living is necessary so that people can buy the means to be propagandized—Ellul mentions televisions, the newspaper, and a formal education. Aside from having the means to absorb lots of unverified secondhand information, the individual must have financial means to free him or herself from worry about mere survival. Average culture is a necessity because it allows people to be predicted and controlled. The message gets to the individual because s/he is just like everyone else in the mass. In the mass society of America, propaganda is a necessity for social solidarity. It forms our identity, telling us who we are. It defines what our needs are so that we will buy more stuff in order to fill those needs. There can be no mass consumption without a million people who all believe that their identity and needs are the same, and will be similarly fulfilled by the purchase of a mass-produced tchotke. Kappus 6/15 Propaganda is a political necessity, especially in a democracy. Governance in a mass society is not possible without propaganda A ruler cannot escape the mass, but [s/]he can draw between [her/]himself and them an “invisible curtain,” a screen, on which the mass will see projected the mirage of some politics, while the real politics are made behind [the screen]. (122) 3) Discuss Bell’s theory of the disjunction of the three realms—techno-economic, polity, and culture—with special attention to that of culture. Discuss his views on modernism, especially the eclipse of distance. Discuss his ideas about a technical civilization and its relation to culture. Contrast Bell’s theory of the relationship of technology to culture with that of Ellul. Daniel Bell believes that fundamental characteristic of each of the realms mentioned in the question text put them at odds with the other realms. The two largest conflicts are between economy and polity and between culture and economy. Of Bell’s realms, the realm of culture is the most important because within it occurs the greatest rate of innovation and change. Culture, for Bell, contains the great artistic and creative expressions of the day. The contradiction between the economic and cultural realms arises because while the capitalist economy requires functional rationality (separation of personal identity and role), efficiency through the application of known rules, prudent investment, and delayed gratification, modernist culture demands absolute immediate self-realization and the breaking of all strictures related to convention. Originally, individualism helped the bourgeoisie engage in the experimentation in commerce and science that lead to the rise of capitalism. Since that time, individualism developed two different and opposed strands. In economy, individualism fostered acquisitiveness, rationality, and bourgeois values, or, in other words, disciplined rational selfinterest. By contrast, in the cultural arts, individualism became radical, and demanded the removal of all strictures and all rules in its quest towards absolute self-expression. Kappus 7/15 Bell argues that in the century that preceded his 1973 publication of The Cultural Contradictions of Capitalism, this unbridled self-expression in culture lead to ever more shocking and challenging art and literature that less and less frequently followed rational rules for composition or meaning. In these works, the artist or writer abdicated the role of rational interpreter of the world (“mimesis”) altogether. The effect was to diminish the distance between the audience and the artist, which, according to Bell, reduced the audience’s ability to rationally consider the work. As time has progressed, the unbridled narcissism and hedonism of culture has become a widespread factor in peoples’ lives, and has chafed against the economic demands of rational functionalism and efficiency. Bell spends the second, weaker half of his book talking about the conflicts that the realm of polity has with economy and culture. The modernist culture is hedonistic, and motivates people to seek out their own “self-realization.” The economy allows an endless accumulation and great competition towards individual ends. The polity, on the other hand, asserts that all people are equal, or should be. Put roughly, the disjunction here arises because the polity insists on equality, which is a group end, while the classic liberal capitalist idea is competition towards individual ends, and furthermore, the culture insists on endless hedonism. Bell’s question is how the polity might come to control the economy, perhaps despite the culture, so that goods are more evenly distributed, and more peoples’ needs are met. (Here he contrasts “needs” with “wants.”) Having summarized Bell’s main points, I can compare his conception of the relation of technology to culture with those of Ellul. Bell would argue that in the nineteenth century, it was the confounding speed of technology that created the modernist forms that evolved into those he denounces. In the everyday world of sense impressions, there was a disorientation of the sense of space and time, derived from the new awareness of motion Kappus 8/15 and speed, light, and sound that came from the revolution in communication and transport. (47) In tone, at least, this sounds similar to a quote that class lecture attributed to Ellul: “Technology is the chief organizing and disorganizing force in society.” For Bell, the technologies that were a product of capitalism have now spawned a contradictory reaction in the cultural arts. The arts respond to the speed, light, and disorientation of the train and telegraph by developing the eclipse of aesthetic distance (mimesis) and the focus on immediacy. According to lecture, Ellul, like Bell, pointed to the emphasis on technique in art (cf Bell’s comments on Jackson Pollack and abstract expressionists), the loss of a moral self in the novel/literature (cf commentary on Burroughs), and art as undisciplined self-expression or release. The difference is that while Bell sees culture as being a dominant force driving a disjointed society, Ellul sees it as a response to, and sometimes an “escape valve” from, the pressures of technology. 4) Discuss Caillois[‘] theory of games. What do games reveal about culture? Discuss the two fundamental combinations of games. Why do they tend to go together? Discuss the corruption of games, especially in the context of a technological civilization. Caillois attempts to define a sociology derived from games. To this end, he first sets out a definition of games and then a typology of games. He observes that even games that are played by a single player are truly social. He explains that while elements of games can sometimes become a part of everyday life, if elements of daily life intrude on a game, the game is corrupted. Finally, he develops a sociology derived from games. For Caillois, the essential qualities of games are that they are free, separate, uncertain, unproductive, regulated, and fictive. Games are free in the sense that people engage in them voluntarily; anyone forced to play a game is no longer truly engaged in play. They are separate in the sense that they are rituals set aside in time and space from the normal logic of peoples’ lives. They are uncertain because the course of a game is not known in advance. They are unproductive Kappus 9/15 because they do not generate new goods; wealth may pass from one player to another based on the outcome of a game, but the sum of all the players’ material wealth will not have increased. They are regulated because there are rules and forms that must be adhered to in play. Finally, because all players are aware that the game is an unreality, an artificial space apart from most life, games are fictive. After he defines what games are, Caillois sets out a typology of games based on their characteristics. Games can be based on competition (agon), chance (alea), mimicry, vertigo (ilinx)1. They can also be distinguished on the basis of where along a spectrum from rigidly and arbitrarily structured (ludus) to absolutely free (pædia). Examples of games that fit are listed, and an illustrative table can be found on page 36. Alea and agon form a natural combination on one end of a continuum with mimicry and illinx on the other end. They work together because alea and agon are rule bound (ludus) while mimicry and illinx epitomize release from rules and structure. Caillois continues in chapter three to assert the relevance of studying games to studying society. He points out that no game is truly a solitary game; all games have spectators, competitors, or both. When I fill out a crossword, I am acting alone, but I am implicitly in competition with the achievements of everyone else who fills out crosswords, The social nature of games that he explains here is the basis of his theorizing later on in the book. Some authors have said that games are worthless, entirely isolated from culture, “entirely a loss.” This is one theory of games—they are sort of a carnivalesque inverted image of society that provides participants with an “out.” Another theory, which is closer, I think, to what Caillois has in mind, is that games convey and reproduce social meaning. Children learn to play cops and 1 I will use the plain-English word and the greek/latin/???? word interchangeably. Kappus 10/15 robbers, and then they become cops and robbers in their later years. People of all ages play games that have elements of rules, fairness, equity, chance, loyalty, courage, and other qualities, and they learn something about the emphasis that their society places on associated values. It is through games that people “learn to construct order, conceive economy, and establish equity” (58). This last observation is where Caillois starts to develop a sociology derived from games. Caillois says that there is a truly reciprocal relationship between society and the games it likes to play. The corruption of games occurs when the separateness of play from real life is violated in a certain way. Without any problem, the daily lives and professions of people may contain the characteristics of games. Businessmen may compete, for example, spies may rely on deception via mimicry, and medics may base their professions on managing vertiginous risk. But if the characteristics of quotidian life creep into a game, the game becomes corrupted. Competition, agon, is corrupted when the will to power, trickery, or unregulated violence appears disrupt the careful artificial equality that made the competition meaningful. Games of chance are corrupted when the players stop believing that the game is aleatoric and instead superstitiously hope that some outside force, like the stars, controls play. If mimetic players lose themselves to the role for a time period beyond the confines of the game, they cease to be playing a character, and this corrupts the purpose of play, as well. Finally, in a similar manner, if players at vertigo become permanently spirited away into a place of freefall, the game is corrupted because it is no longer separate from life; it is a game for Hunter S. Thompson to go and ingest endless psychoactive drugs in Las Vegas, as long as the fear and loathing end when he arrives back in LA and avoids permanent dependence. Kappus 11/15 I suppose that the relationship of the corruption of games to the spread of technology happens when agon is reduced to technique, when there are statistical models to predict (even control) chance outcomes, and illinx is a permanent and necessary escape from the pressure. I only posit these relationships tentatively. 5) Compare and contrast the work of Elias, Ellul, van den Berg, Bell, and Caillois Elias, Ellul, van den Berg, and Bell all use dialectical means to make arguments about the structure of society or part of society. Each places the object of his interest within a context in which the whole is greater than the sum of its parts. Elias relates Kultur to civilization, van den Berg relates the birth of “maturation” and multivalency to technology, Ellul exponds the place of technique in society, and Bell the relationship of culture to polity and economy. Even though all of the works are about different subjects, the authors share an interest in how meaning is constructed or obliterated by the dialectical relationships on which they focus. Finally, several of them draw the dialectic relationship that is central to their argument within a context that is strongly shaped by power. Elias explains the soul of the French and German people based on their history. He notes that Kultur, for Germans, is the body of intellectual and artistic things that Germans have achieved over the years, the patrimony of the German people. To explain this term more carefully, he draws it into a dialectical relationship with the French and English “civilization.” By comparison to Kultur, civilization is a set of rules about how people think and act. Civilization is a sort of courtly virtue. In fact, the point of much of Elias’ work is to explain the historical relationship of the development of the Kultur/civilization relationship, and he shows that it arose in response to French dominance in the German court—a relationship having to do with power. In this case, the power of the French courtly manners in the German court distanced the German bourgeoisie Kappus 12/15 from the court to the extent that when the bourgeoisie took over, they did not accept the set of meanings that go into the word “civilization.” Van den Berg locates a certain universal obliteration of meaning within modernism. Words have been denuded of their context, and can now, because of the modernist technique,2 quantification, can take on multiple, and sometimes contradictory meanings. A word or cultural meme that is multivalent in this way ceases to convey value. Again, van den Berg locates the production of multivalency amongst a set of historical factors, and deals with the power that technology has to reduce words’ meaning to nihil. Ellul, for his part, examines the force of technology. Specifically, in our classwork, he is looking at propaganda as a technique or technology. Ellul asserts that propaganda exists not as a reducible object, but as a relationship between the massification of society, the individual’s relationship to the mass, and so forth. As with the other authors, Ellul is talking about power, though it’s a little harder to see where the start of the strand of power is. As previously mentioned on this exam, Bell writes about the relationship—see? the relationship is everything to these writers!—between culture, polity, and economy. And that’s not the only set of relationships that he writes about. For example, he produces an interrelationship between milieu, social characteristic, and the social games people play that looks something like the following: Milieu characteristic The games people play Nature Survival Game against nature for survival 2 I’m honestly a bit confused here. Kappus 13/15 Technology/industry industry Game of modifying nature instrumentally Post-industry Information Game against other humans But this isn’t the only one of these intriguing interrelationships. Bell loves tables like this. At any rate, aside from being prone towards making up dialectical relationships, Bell believes that the power to create meaning is in culture, narrowly defined as high culture. Finally, we come to Caillois. Caillois is talking about a system of meanings or values that are expressed by play. The games that are popular within any one society are characteristic in some way of that culture because they help in the social reproduction of values. So the games both affect and are affected by society. Just to keep my argument straight, I’ll add a table Writer Power/determining factor Parts, the sum of which is less than the whole(!) Elias French court vs. German civilization/Kultur bourgeoisie van den Berg Technology modernity+meaning=multivalency= no meaning Ellul Technology/propaganda Mass society needs propaganda and propaganda needs mass society Bell Modernist culture Culture vs. economy vs. polity Caillois --------------------- Play both affects and is affected by society Kappus 14/15