David Morrison UCLA Sociology Field Exam Supplement 9/15/01 Ethnomethodology: Ethnomethodology is the empirical study of the variety and contextual range of social processes, artful practices and sense-making procedures - broadly speaking, ‘methods’ through which individuals produce ‘social order’. Ethnomethodologists have conceptualized ‘social order’ as: (1) Durkheimian ‘recurrent social forms’ which are produced in and through the activities of individuals, but which nonetheless possess, manifest or display an objectivity independent of actor’s perceptions - that is to say that these ‘recurrent social forms’ are produced so universally as to be generally regarded as unworthy of especial notice (or even fall beneath the perceptual field of distinct reference) by the individuals who are actively, artfully and nonetheless deliberately engaged in the lived work of their production, they are often organized in such a way as to obscure the very processes which they manifest and, when called to the attention of the various social actors working so assiduously to produce them, maintain them, and organize their activities with regard to them, their manifest insignificance serves primarily as a testament to the competence of those same social actors and secondarily as evidence of their indispensability for maintaining the lived workings of ordinary, immortal society; or (2) ‘Gestalt contexture’ (based on Husserl, Shutz or Gurwitsch’s phenomenology and having implications for Kuhn’s analysis of scientific paradigm shift as a ‘one way Gestalt switch’), a fundamentally perceptual process through which individuals produce orderly properties subjectively as a way of making coherent sense of the limitless, potentially contradictory and (were it not for their 2 sense-making practices) otherwise disparate phenomena in their potential perceptual field of reference. To make matters worse for both the consumer and producer of ethnomethodological theory, this field of academic work embodies these very dualities, contradictions and uncertainties with regard to its object of study. For example, the two ways of conceptualizing ‘social order’ stated above, as either a phenomenon independent of (and possibly even antithetical to or incommensurate with) explicit subjective perception, ‘nothing more’ than a perceptual production (there’s no more ‘there’ there, nothing ‘behind’ the perception), or, worse, both - encapsulate the very subject/object dualities, dialectics and contradictions which some ethnomethodological writings (particularly Pollner’s Mundane Reason - MR) have been designed to expose, surmount and perhaps implicitly condemn and/or exalt. That is, ‘mundane reason’ serves as an object, background assumption, method, resource, alternate, basis and foil for ethnomethodological researches. You could say ethnomethodologists have an ambivalent relationship to mundane reason, but that really wouldn’t to it justice. Its a bit like watching a person contemplate their own limitations, but forced to use those very limitations in their act of contemplation. Take common sense knowledge, for example. Individuals not only orient their action based on the ‘gestalt contexture’ of their own perceptions, but also orient their actions to the actions of others based on assumptions of commonality in definitions of the situation and the common stock of knowledge and social meanings encapsulated under the rubric of ‘common-sense assumptions’: what any adequate practitioner or well-socialized 3 member of the society1 can be expected to know, understand and likewise orient their behavior with regards to. As such, is the stock of common-sense assumptions a subjective or objective feature of the social world? Is it a process of perception, a basis for ‘recurrent social forms’, or a process of orienting to shared social meanings which is itself objective, because (following Durkheim’s reasoning in The Rules of Sociological Method) it is perceived by social actors as separate from themselves, an independently existing part of the social or natural order. It is what ‘anybody knows’ and ‘everybody knows that anybody knows’ such that, if you’re asking questions about it you must either be deranged, mentally disabled, developmentally delayed - or a sociologist. Should we think of common-sense knowledge as something that spans the subject/object dichotomy? Ultimately I’m not sure one can answer this question without stepping back into one of the key assumptions of mundane reason that the question is designed to address: that an objective order exists which is independent of our own (and here I mean to reflexively include the ethnomethodologists as well) process by which it is “observed, measured or explicated [MR: 16]”. Maynard and Clayman (1991) warn against “a cognitive-interpretive solution to the problem of order, wherein actors produce patterned courses of action because the share internalized frames of reference and value systems [387]”. Referring to ‘common sense assumptions which serve as a common frame of reference for coordinating social action’, runs the risk of resurrecting internal structures of cognition similar in principle to Parsonian ‘internalized norms of conduct’ 1 The phrases ‘adequate practitioner’ and ‘well-socialized member of the society’ are intended to distinguish the shared social meanings and technical knowledge that arise within discrete and bounded social groupings operating within the society, from common-knowledge shared by members of the society at large. I will return to this issue shortly, with a discussion of the tensions and parallels between EM investigations of scientific communities and ‘immortal ordinary society’. 4 that provide general principles by which social action is coordinated, rather than viewing the processes by which social order is produced in contingent and contextually specific ways as a central topic for empirical investigation upon which EM theory should be informed. I began this discussion with the question of social order, because that is the basic question for sociology. Its often been recapitulated as the Hobbesian question, ‘how is society possible’. I agree with Barbara Rothman’s critique of this formulation as crude in its assumption of an a priori state of anarchy2. Ethnomethodological (EM) research can help reformulate this question as: ‘what are the variety of methods through with social order is produced’. Garfinkel’s starting point for this analysis was to establish empirically the “central features” of “the familiar common sense world of everyday life”. Although sociologists take socially structured scenes of everyday life as a point of departure they rarely see, as a task of sociological inquiry in its own right, the general question of how any such common sense world is possible. Instead, the possibility of the everyday world is either settled by theoretical representation of merely assumed [SEM: 36]. The stock of common sense knowledge that adequate practitioner or well socialized member of the group can be expected to share serves as a basis for coordinating social action and is thus a key part of the question of social order. The formulation substitutes the question of how ‘society’ is possible with the more approachable question of how members of society produce and orient themselves to a common frame of reference. This does not involve applying Hobbes’ crude assumptions about human nature, because EM has empirically demonstrated that the methods of order-production are robust and 2 Rothman, Barbara Katz, “Of Maps and Imaginations: Sociology Confronts the Genome”. Social Problems, 1995, 42, 1, Feb, 1-10. She states that the Hobbesian question is “absurd” and ultimately male-biased, because it assumes that people ‘sprout up like mushrooms’ into an initial state of disorder and isolation. She says that any woman who has given birth would not see individuals as arriving in society, but leaving their own bodies - the point being that our a priori 5 pervasive. While EM adapts the question in accordance with its findings, it is important to note that EM has consistently and explicitly confronted questions of fundamental concern to sociology as a discipline, from Garfinkel’s statements in this 1967 passage to recent attempts by Rawls and Hilbert to establish linkages between current EM research and classical foundations coming from This fact could be overlooked given EM’s early insistence on approaching conventional sociology primarily as an object of analysis, rather than as a theoretical resource. This insistence stemmed in part from Garfinkel’s initial empirical assault on Parson’s functionalist theory of sociology. In Garfinkel’s separate Studies in Ethnomethodology (SEM) he demonstrated that Parsons’ functionalist theory advanced an overly general and homogenous view of society. A simple reading of Durkheim (particularly Durkheim’s conception of anomie as stemming from excessive specialization of organically solidaristic societies in DOL) should have corrected the homogeneity with which Parsons approached issues such as social norms. Key topics for analysis which derive from EM investigations of social order as an emergent feature of “actors’ concerted work in making social facts observable and accountable to one another in their everyday lives [ibid., 387]” are: the relationship between rules (either formally codified or informally invoked) and individual behavior, “indexical expressions”, and “et cetera” clauses. All of these concepts in EM are rife with implications on the relationship between individual behavior and coordinated group activity. Maynard and Clayman (1991) argued that these concepts do not signal an emphasis on individual agency and interpretive action, and are not addressed to either state is permeated by communal social life; in contrast, isolation, disorder, and anomie require explanation. 6 contradict or support the concept of internalized norms for conduct specifying individual behavior - rather, that these key concepts in EM point to the significance of social context and the intentions of the actor in fitting their lines of action into the local context to achieve some practical purpose. This strikes me as a difficult line to walk between denying an emphasis on individual agency and interpretive efforts on the one hand, while simultaneously denying that actors orient their actions based on generalized group expectations of conduct - the thesis that normative expectations are internalized based on individual location within affiliative group networks. What’s left in their analysis of indexical expressions and contingency as key features of social interaction, is the investigation of “how members are from the outset embedded in contingently accomplished structures of social action consonant with their acting and reacting to one another in real time [388].” But how would social actors accomplish this coordination and shared social meaning without some previous stock of common knowledge which, along with indexical properties specified within the local history of the emergent interaction, provides the necessary background information to: specify the meaning of an utterance, inform them of the “background expectancies [SEM: 36]” shared by the other participants within the interaction, and coordinates action into socially meaningful sets of behaviors? The point of many of the breaching experiments in SEM was to show the necessity of “background understandings [49-56]” that participants must bring to the interaction. Some of these background understandings are shared within the context of previous interaction between two individuals (as, for example, a description of an interaction between spouses [25] that draws from both prevalent social meanings and personalized 7 knowledge based on shared experience). The violation of the rules of tic-tac-toe shows that social action in this case is organized into a meaningful set of possible responses, whose violation disrupts the possibility of continuing within an established mode and requires some type of reconstructive work for meaningful or orderly social action to proceed. There is a tension here between contingency, emergent social meaning and interpretive action, on the one hand, and common sets of expectations towards which adequate practitioners and fully socialized members can be expected to orient their actions, on the other. It seems to me that the following conclusions can be drawn from this discussion: coordinated action is based in part on common experience, some of this experience can be assumed to be shared by any competent member of a social group - independently of prior personal acquaintance, but a greater stock of common knowledge (as between intimate acquaintances or individuals with a detailed technical training) allows greater coordination; coordinated action is also a contingent, emergent feature of social interaction, a shared stock of knowledge can never be complete as individual experience is never entirely overlapping, therefore individuals must actively work to interpret and coordinate their actions within an evolving interaction. This discussion also raises a tension within EM between an initial focus on commonsense assumptions and mundane reason regarded as relatively independent of specific institutional contexts, and a subsequent growing appreciation and emphasis on the distinctive features imparted by technical knowledge and institutional affiliation. Two issues that are implicated in this tension are: EM’s orientation to social groupings as based either on a shared social identity or on the distinctive characteristics of group 8 members (such as a scientific community wherein membership is predicated on the ‘unique adequacy’ of technical expertise); and the relationship between the workings of mundane reason and scientific rationality. If we follow Moerman’s (1968) lead, bounded groupings such as ethnicity do exist within a wider society; but only the sense that members orient themselves and their actions with regard to such social boundaries. Initial EM investigations were focused on common-sense reasoning and the workings of everyday social life - with a corresponding emphasis on the generic characteristics of meaningful social action and the parallels between common sense assumptions and the forms of reasoning which occur within particular social contexts. We see here, Garfinkel’s early assertion that jury members arrive at the proceedings already ‘90% a juror’. In spite of Maynard and Clayman’s insistence that writers such as Alexander (1987) who characterize EM as a “ ‘reaction’ against functionalist sociology” are ‘pigeonholing’ EM, I do believe that much of this early focus on parallels between mundane reason and scientific rationality was intended to counteract the elitism of Parson’s unreflexive tendency to privilege scientific knowledge (particularly his own theory) over and against actors’ own accounts of their motivations. What better way to recognize the artfulness of ordinary social action than to demonstrate its basis for specialized knowledge in specific institutional contexts? While they state that Heritage’s writings should “lay these misconceptions to rest”, I think there’s room for disagreement on the extent of the tension between EM and functionalism (as a representative of ‘formal analysis) particularly since I recall Heritage describing the various empirical studies in SEM as a series of “guerilla attacks” against 9 key elements of Parson’s functionalist theory (in one of his lectures on EM, given as part core course for entering sociology graduate students at UCLA). There is an element of retrospective reconciliation happening within EM now, that I think such statements exhibit, but which has emerged over time, as EM has renegotiated its position within the wider sociologic lexicon. Partly this has emerged out of its a reflexive acknowledgement that some of the early statements have served to privilege EM itself and ironicize the techniques of ‘formal analysis’ - making EM subject to some of the very critiques it leveled against previous work. While I believe this is a very healthy tendency, I also believed it emerged gradually over time. In Garfinkel and EM, for example, Heritage critiques Parsons for eventual discounting of the actors’ process of accounting for their own behavior. Parsons analysis of the ‘actor’s point of view’ was one which was overwhelmingly geared to developing a causal model of the subjective elements in conduct in which the actor’s concrete reasoning was treated as epiphenomenal [1984: 21]. I regret that I have not as yet read enough of Parson’s The Structure of Social Action to speak authoritatively on the topic, so I am deferring to Heritage’s analysis for the time being. I do however, at this stage, have some questions as to whether Heritage has rendered an entirely unbiased reading of Parson’s theory of internalized norms. Weber’s writings on rationality frame all ‘rational’ (or ‘rationalized’) action as based on nonrational value premises. Following Weber, even mystic contemplation can be rationalized, in that rationalization is the process of subjecting and elaborating spontaneous (pre-rational) subjective experience into ideological doctrine and formally specified patterns of action. (Notwithstanding Garfinkel and Ciccourell’s observations that reified doctrines and praxis can never be fully specified, and always require individual interpretation and application into each specific case.) 10 Parsons’ emphasis on the ‘internalization of social norms’ could be seen as the process, not through which the subsequent forms of formalized doctrine and praxis are transmitted, but the socialization of individuals into the prerational value premises upon which subsequent rational actions are based. It seems to me that both Marx and Weber do point the way to the possibility of individuals as ‘cultural dopes’ in their ability to accept pre-rational (not to be confused with irrational) value premises which do not reflect their own interests. Marx is emphatic on this point. Weber’s comments are even more pernicious: since all rationalized forms of action and rationalized forms of thought are based on pre-rational value premises, individuals are readily subject to initial and continued socialization. Individuals could only resist one form of rationalization with another, but there is no rational, objective basis for evaluating the efficacy of the initial (prerational) value premises upon which rational action is based. A meeting of evolutionary biologists and fundamentalist Christians are distinguished not only by the scientists’ additional socialization into a rationalized vocabulary of speciation. These two social groupings are also distinguished by more fundamental value premises (such as for the empirical basis of claims about the natural world versus the basis for such claims in a biblical frame of reference). Clearly there are problems with Parson’s theory of social action. But whether there is also something worthwhile and important to be found there, ultimately depends on what stage of the rationalization process Parsons was referring to when he discussed concepts like ‘the internalization of social norms’ and exactly how sophisticated of a reading of Weber he had - or to what extent he understood the ultimately non-rational nature of the value-premises upon which rational action is based. 11 Through the rubric of hybrid studies of work, EM investigations have increasingly emphasized the distinctive features of action within specific institutional contexts, partly as a result of the immersion of ethnomethodologists like Garfinkel, Lynch, Livingston, Orr and Suchman into the detailed workings of particular contexts like scientific research or technical areas of expertise. That is why I have distinguished here between ‘adequate practitioner’ (members of an scientific or technical elite) and ‘well-socialized member of the society’. Such elite circles certainly are bounded in more than the sense referred to by Moerman - they are bounded by an additional stock of knowledge signaling prior training and additional socialization into an (often highly delineated) community operating within the wider society. Coordinated action, and technical conversation itself, is impossible without the additional shared stock of knowledge that ‘adequacy’ implies. There are two particular reasons why an ethnomethodological focus on science has been significant. Initially this focus was to demonstrating the linkages between scientific rationality and common-sense reasoning. Partly as a response to Parson’s elitism, EM studies established that, rather than standing separate from mundane cognition, common sense processes have served as a basis for scientific rationality. Subsequently, there has been increased sensitivity to the distinctiveness of institutional settings, of which scientific discovery is a specific instance. These studies do not deny the earlier linkages between scientific rationality and normal forms of problemsolving. They also do not privilege scientific investigation over common-sense reasoning. But they do point to distinctive contexts of practical reasoning. Also, since practical reasoning in scientific contexts is the subject of explicit and sustained attention by practioners to those settings, the work of scientific investigation represents a strategic 12 research setting for exploring distinctive features of practical reasoning. The ethnomethodological focus on therapeutic contexts, is more of a mixed development, because it stems in large part from the early confluence of Ethnomethodology with constructivism that I discussed in my previous essay. Much of the initial focus was cognitive in focus and subjectivist, and could be characterized as falling under the rubric of ‘sense-making activities’; such as Garfinkel’s early study in which he asked participants to participant in an ‘experimental therapy’ in which they were asked to present a personal problem to the therapist, and then interpret the therapists yes/no answers to their questions. Participants were unaware that the answers were randomly generated. Their subsequent process of interpreting the answers from within some intelligible, coherent system of meaning demonstrated some of the key workings of mundane reason – particularly in line with my comments at the start of this essay that the production of social order is partly a perceptual process of organizing subjective experience into an orderly framework. Early EM work into deviance have emphasized the attribution of deviance through the social process by which putative instances of deviance are counted (constructed) as actual instances, for example, through the activities of coroners attributing a death as an instance of suicide (Atkinson), through the documentary method of compiling bureaucratic records in clinic contexts (Garfinkel, 1967) or in the use and compilation of ‘official statistics’ in conventional sociologic research (Kitsuse and Ciccourell’s). Given the current tendency for EM to increasingly disavow constructivist theory as itself exemplary of formal analysis, it is clear the trend - for both studies within the ethnographic tradition and coming from conversation analysis - will be increasingly 13 explore issues such as the relation between normative expectations and individual behavior. An example of this is Wieder’s (1974) discussion of the ‘convict code’, not as a normative constraint restricting individual behavior, but as a discursive resource – which both staff and residents of a halfway house could invoke achieve practical and socially meaningful ends within that context. This fits within the general trend, which I have briefly discussed, of EM investigations to become increasingly sensitive to the particularities of social action within specific institutional contexts.