Why do we not simply treat questions of contributory negligence as if they were questions of causation? Contributory negligence is a failure by the claimant to take reasonable care for his (or her) own safety that contributes to the damage about which he complains1. Such a definition intuitively gives rise to the impression that there is more to the given concept than a causal conceptualisation – whose primary relevance could be seen to lie in the aspect of the definition relating to the contribution to the damage. This is so because the definition also refers to an aspect of “reasonable care”, something which would more aptly be assessed in comparison to the “duty of care” aspect as it exists in ordinary negligence cases. It is thus submitted that the emphasis that one places on either of these two limbs of the definition will be highly relevant to assessing whether one sees the doctrine of contributory negligence as being a causal one. Moreover, it is also relevant to identify to what extent the latter, the reasonable care, limb deviates from the ordinary approach to establishing a duty of care on behalf of the defendant in negligence cases, as if there are, for instance, overwhelming similarities this may lead one to the conclusion that a separate existence of the doctrine is not warranted (at least in that context) and that it consequently ought to be dealt with under the head of causation instead. The doctrine of contributory negligence can also be seen to have a third stage in terms of the courts’ role in apportioning the damages. Identifying the significance of causation in this context also is essential to establishing whether questions of contributory negligence should simply be treated as questions of causation. First it is perhaps useful to briefly examine the state of the law before the Law Reform (Contributory Negligence) Act 1945 and draw comparisons to the modern law. The position used to be that any contributory negligence on behalf of the claimant would be a total bar to recovery for the defendant’s negligence. Quite apart from the obvious injustice to which this led, it seems to override causal principles as outlined in Hotson2 for instance that if the defendant can be shown to have caused certain damage on a balance of probabilities he/she will be found liable for that damage. Conversely the introduction of the rules of last 1 Murphy, J and Witting, C (2012) Street on Torts (Thirteenth Edition) Oxford University Press (p. 188). 2 Hotson v East Berkshire Area Health Authority [1987] AC 750 Page 1 of 4 opportunity/constructive last opportunity seem to represent unwarranted, overly complex attempts to mitigate the harshness of the former rule, and seem to have had little to do with a principled analysis of causation. In contrast the position today is rather different, contributory negligence only, arguably, being a total bar to recovery in the context of it constituting 100%. This seems much more in tune with causal doctrines, as if the claimant is 100% contributorily negligent then the claimants act is the sole cause of, or the novus actus interveniens in relation to, the damage - either preventing the establishment of a causal connection, or breaking it. Consequently, as the doctrine of contributory negligence is applied in modern times there seems to be a greater conformity with causal principles, thus making for a stronger case for merging the former into the latter and dealing with it under this head. However, one should also consider Winfield and Jolowicz’s statement that “In practice the court will not attempt a minute assessment of responsibility and even a finding of contributory negligence of 10 per cent is apparently unusual”3. Thus in practice less than 100% of contributory negligence is in fact needed to offer a defendant a full defence and if the courts’ whole assessment were to be based on causation this approach would surely be anomalous. I will therefore consider further the reasoning involved in how the courts go about apportioning damages below. Next, it is necessary to assess the reasonable care limb which means that the claimant must not fail to exercise reasonable care which would add to his injuries4. This is clearly to be distinguished from the normal duty of care requirement in the sense that the claimant does not owe, say the defendant, a duty of care. However, the objective assessment of what is reasonable, for example, is similar – taking into account for instance only such features as age and disability in determining what standard is reasonable. However, here it must be noted that Stevens has convincingly argued that the courts have proved more lenient in determining what factors are relevant to the reasonable claimant than the reasonable defendant. He considers the two cases of Condon v Condon and Leahy v Beaumont as evidence for this. In the former case the claimants phobia of being trapped in a car after wearing a seatbelt was to be attributed to the reasonable person, in the latter it was held that “Every driver, even a… driver suffering from fear of spiders, bees and moths in the car, .. must drive in as good a manner as a driver of skill, experience and care”5. Such an analysis seems sound especially as it seems to be, so Stevens argues, driven by the underlying policy considerations that the 3 Winfield, W.V.H. and Jolowicz, J.A. (2010) Tort (Eighteenth Edition) Thomas Reuters (p.379). Giliker, P and Beckwith, S (2011) Tort (Fourth Edition) Thomas Reuters (p. 486). 5 Leahy v Beaumont cited in Murphy, J and Witting, C (2012) Street on Torts (Thirteenth Edition) Oxford University Press (p. 192). 4 Page 2 of 4 defendant usually does not bear the cost of his negligence (many relevant areas where liability may arise being covered by insurance). In contrast a reduction in terms of contributory negligence is a loss a claimant will usually have to bear – having no way to protect himself/insure against such a reduction. The notion, therefore, that the sufferer of damage caused, at least in part, by another’s negligence should bear such a burden intuitively appears unjust. Similarly, special policy considerations underlie the courts’ leniency in cases where claimants are faced with an emergency created by negligence of the defendant or where rescuers ‘voluntarily’ get involved to deal with such emergencies. The factors outlined above thus indicate that there is a justified distinction between simply a reasonable care standard, as it exists in negligence for instance, and the reasonable care standard in contributory negligence which has evolved, and has been adapted, to suit the specific needs of that concept. This militates against subordinating questions of contributory negligence to a broader causation doctrine. The area of contributory negligence which is most suited to be dealt with under wider principles of causation is no doubt the requirement that the claimants conduct contributed to his damage (note, this is a contribution to damage, not to the accident6). It has already been commented above that the claimant’s fault may be found to be so great that he must bear the whole loss (even below the 100% contributory negligence mark which would indicate the claimant to be the sole cause). Winfield and Jolowicz usefully flesh out this argument further through reference to a number cases of claimants (who were experienced workmen), eclipsing the liability of their employers for breaches of strict statutory duty, through their failure to carry out clear safety precautions in which they had been properly instructed7. Thus one could perhaps say that such an approach could be governed under a special causation doctrine (as has previously been created in cases such as Fairchild8), but it would be anomalous and one should be careful before incorporating more exceptions under the broad head of causation than absolutely necessary. Even in relation to the claimants contribution to his damage a self-contained doctrine of contributory negligence must therefore be seen as preferable. Lastly, I will briefly look further into the apportionment of loss under contributory negligence, in other words the courts’ role in reducing the claimants damage as they think 6 Winfield, W.V.H. and Jolowicz, J.A. (2010) Tort (Eighteenth Edition) Thomas Reuters (p.368). Winfield, W.V.H. and Jolowicz, J.A. (2010) Tort (Eighteenth Edition) Thomas Reuters (p.370). 8 Fairchild v Glenhaven Funeral Services Ltd [2002] UKHL 22 7 Page 3 of 4 ‘just and equitable having regard to the claimant’s share in responsibility for the damage’9 as here there are two primary considerations involved: causation and blameworthiness. The interrelated nature of these requirements is aptly illustrated (in this instance in the case of a motoring accident) in the statement of the case of Froom v Butcher that “[w]henever there is an accident, the negligent driver must bear by far the greater share of responsibility. It was his negligence which caused the accident. It also was a prime cause of the whole of the damage. But insofar as the damage might have been avoided or lessened by wearing a seat belt, the injured person must bear some share”10. It is thus submitted that it would not be desirable to bring this aspect of contributory negligence under the doctrines of causation as the causal aspect, is but one of two similarly important factors which must be assessed. These factors are interrelated and should both be considered contemporaneously in the independent context of contributory negligence. Support for such an approach can also be found in how the court in the Froom v Butcher dealt with the apportionment of damages for cases of contributory negligence for not wearing a seatbelt. The fact that Lord Denning outlined specific guidelines of when not wearing a seatbelt should lead to a loss of 25%, 15% or none at all, indicates that dealing with such factors as questions of contributory negligence in and of itself has certain practical benefits, which would potentially be lost if dealt with as questions under broader concept of causation. In conclusion therefore, it has been argued that the concept of contributory negligence has central aspects, and is based on certain considerations, which do not relate to causation and which warrant its existence as a separate doctrine. Particular emphasis should be placed, for instance, on the distinct reasonable care requirement imposed on the claimant and, while causation plays a central role in ascertaining the claimants contribution to the damage or in the apportionment of loss, this does not warrant treating questions of contributory negligence as questions of causation. 9 Law Reform (Contributory Negligence) Act 1945 Froom v Butcher [1976] QB 286 10 Page 4 of 4