Forthcoming in _ JERUSALEM REV. LEG. STUD. _ (2013). “Foundational” Originalism? On Jack Balkin’s “Living Originalism” Barak Medina * 1. Balkin’s Theory Jack Balkin’s Living Originalism1 offers a theory of constitutional interpretation. As the book’s title tells, it aims at integrating the two leading competing theories of constitutional interpretation, “living constitutionalism” and ”originalism.” The book offers a rich theory, which is both descriptive and normative, about constitutional construction and the role of constitutions in social change. The result is a book which is a must read for every scholar who is interested in constitutionalism. It is not surprising that in the year following the book’s publication it was already the subject of almost thirty(!) scholarly reviews.2 As I understand it, Balkin’s main idea, which he terms as “framework originalism,”3 is this: In determining the meaning of a certain Constitutional provision we must start by identifying the purpose of “constitutionalizing” this provision. This idea may bring to mind Chief Justice Marshall’s famous statement about constitutional interpretation: “We must never forget that it is a constitution we are expounding.”4 In fact, however, Balkin’s thesis aims at revising the underlying premise of this statement. The implicit assumption in Marshall’s position is that a constitution, as such, has some specific aim. There is, of course, a strong disagreement about what this aim exactly is (among the prevailing approaches: the aim is to limit the powers of government, to “rulify” morality, to set a “focal point” for political discourse, to entrench a national compromise, and more). Arguably, the aim of adopting a constitution compels employing a certain theory of interpretation (schematically, originalism or a living constitutionalism). It is thus not surprising that the debate among advocates of the competing theories of interpretation is, at its heart, a dispute about the aim of the constitutionalization of the provisions that are to be interpreted. But these competing approaches share the idea that identifying this aim is not, in itself, a matter of constitutional interpretation. Rather, it is a matter of considerations about sociological and normative “legitimacy,” axiomatic ideals about the “essence” of a constitution, consequentialist arguments, and so forth. Importantly, this metaconstitutional process is distinctively non-originalist, as it is not based on the specific constitutional text or other facts about intentions or reasonable expectations at the time of drafting and adopting the Constitution. Indeed, the implicit theme is that “we * Lawrence D. Biele Associate Professor of Law, Faculty of Law, the Hebrew University of Jerusalem. I thank Alon Harel and Shay Levi for their insightful comments. Barak.medina@mail.huji.ac.il. 1 JACK M. BALKIN, LIVING ORIGINALISM (2011). 2 The book (and an earlier article which presented its basic ideas) is the subject of several review articles, as well as at least four academic symposia. See 24 CONST. COMMENT. 291-532 (2007); 2012 U. ILL. L. REV. 611-877; 92 B.U.L. REV. 1127-1306 (2012); and this issue of the JERUSALEM REV. LEG. STUD. Balkin’s companion book (infra note 23) was discussed in 71 MD. L. REV. 953-1172 (2012). 3 BALKIN, supra note 1, at 21-23. 4 McCulloch v. Maryland. 17 U.S. 316. 407 (1819) (emphasis added). 2 must never forget that we are expounding” a constitution, not the Constitution.5 It is this premise about the essential, non-originalist character of the aim of the Constitution which Balkin’s theory contests. Balkin suggests that the “framework” of the Constitution, and in fact the framework of each of its provisions, is a matter of interpretation. The act of constitutionalizing certain norms may have distinctively different purposes. In particular, while in some cases it may aim at limiting future decision-makers’ discretion, in others the purpose is to set up a framework for future generations’ constitutional construction, or, in Balkin’s words, to charge “each generation… with the obligation to flesh out and implement text and principles in their own time.”6 Balkin argues that the primer source for identifying the “original meaning” of the constitutional framework is the type of text chosen for the relevant norms. Specifically, the relevant distinction is between the use of rules as opposed to the use of standards or principles: “Adopters use fixed rules because they want to limit discretion; and standards or principles because they want to channel politics through certain key concepts but delegate the details to future generations.”7 It is the second type of norms, those that should be “constructed” according to their current understanding, which is at the heart of Balkin’s book.8 To a great extent, Balkin’s is thus a theory of living constitutionalism,9 which offers an originalist justification for employing this theory—it is the Constitution’s original character that justifies interpreting it (or “constructing” it) according to living constitutionalism. I agree with substantial parts of Balkin’s approach about the preferred theory of interpretation.10 My critique refers mostly to the book’s “originalist” elements. I offer three main comments, that address different aspects of an idea which is central to Balkin’s theory—the concept of “procedural legitimacy.” In a nut shell, Balkin justifies “framework originalism” by referring to “the fact that [the Constitutional text] was created through successive acts of popular sovereignty.”11 The interpretation theory chosen by the framers and adopters of the 5 Following common usage, I use the capital-c “Constitution” to denote a specific legal institution (e.g., the U.S. Constitution), and a lowercase-c “constitution” to refer to this generic institution. 6 BALKIN, supra note 1, at 3. 7 Id., at 6-7. 8 Balkin is not the first to point at the distinction between provisions that authorize interpreters to work out a changing meaning over time, and those that prescribe a fixed meaning. See, for instance, JOHN HART ELY, DEMOCRACY AND DISTRUST 1 (1980) (“More often the Constitution proceeds by briefly indicating certain fundamental principles whose specific implications for each age must be determined in contemporary context.”). See also David A. Strauss, Can Originalism Be Saved?, 92 B.U.L. REV. 1161, 1167 (2012). 9 I agree with James Fleming’s observation that Balkin’s living originalism would pass the ultimate test of verifying whether a theory represents living constitutionalism: If the American People would have ratified today a Constitution whose text is identical to the current U.S. Constitutional, Balkin would offer giving the text exactly the same meaning as he does without such ratification. James E. Fleming, The Balkinization of Originalism, 2012 U. ILL. L. REV. 669, 682. 10 Balkin presents an argument in favor of a certain type of living constitutionalism, one which is closely related to “popular constitutionalism.” It is a theory of interpretation by citizens as the standard case. Accordingly, Balkin opposes the principle of judicial supremacy (but accepts judicial review), arguing that courts have neither the first nor the last word on the practical meaning of the Constitution. BALKIN, supra note 1, at 68. These are important, and very interesting elements of Balkin’s theory, but due to space limits, I will not be able to discuss them here. 11 Id., at 55. 3 text is binding since it was approved by the People. My first comment suggests that “procedural legitimacy” cannot serve as an exclusive justification for the binding power of the Constitution. I then question Balkin’s claim that procedural legitimacy can justify the constitutional framework that he envisions. The third and related argument refers to the implementation of Balkin’s “framework originalism.” I suggest that additional elements of original character should be considered in establishing the Constitutional framework. The ultimate result of my analysis is that Balkin’s book provides a convincing argument in favor of (a certain version of) living constitutionalism, but it is an argument which is based on originalism only as a complimentary but not as the central basis. Balkin’s theory is based in fact on moral and sociological legitimacy, what he calls the property of the Constitution as “our law.” In what follows, I start by briefly addressing the debate about the proper classification of Balkin’s theory and offer to consider it as “foundational” originalism (Section 2). I then move to discuss my three substantial comments: “procedural legitimacy” cannot serve as an exclusive justification for the binding power of the Constitution (Section 3), procedural legitimacy does not justify Balkin’s “framework originalism” (Section 4), and the way Balkin implement his “framework originalism” is too narrow (Section 5). I conclude with comments on some implications of Balkin’s theory to the current Constitutional debate in Israel (Section 6). 2. Classification: Is Balkin’s Theory Originalist or Living Constitutionalist? A distinctive aspect of the reactions to the book is the disagreement among commentators about the appropriate classification of Balkin’s theory. Balkin is a prominent “living originalist,” who endorses liberal or progressive constitutional principles. Some scholars suggest that in this book Balkin has in fact “converted” to the originalist camp. Most notably, Randy Barnet described the book as “a serious explication and defense of original public meaning originalism.”12 He even concluded his contribution to this issue of the Jerusalem Review of Legal Studies with a glee: “I welcome [Balkin] to the growing club of new originalists.”13 David Lyons,14 Gary Lawson,15 and Ethan Leib16 expressed similar, although more nuanced positions. In contrast, others addressed the book as following the path of “living constitutionalism.” For instance, David Strauss wrote that he is not sure “there is any deep inconsistency between Balkin’s ‘constitutional construction’ and a common-lawlike approach to the Constitution, which I believe to be the most plausible form of living constitutionalism.”17 Similar views were presented by James Fleming,18 Hugh 12 Randy E. Barnett, Jack Balkin's Interaction Theory of “Commerce”, 2102 U. ILL. L. REV. 623, 625 (2012). 13 Randy E. Barnett, Welcome to the New Originalism, _ JERUSALEM REV. LEG. STUD. _ (2013). 14 David Lyons, Constitutional Principles, 92 B.U.L. REV. 1237 (2012). 15 Gary Lawson, Dead Document Walking, 92 B.U.L. REV. 1225 (2012). 16 Ethan J. Leib, The Perpetual Anxiety of Living Constitutionalism, 24 CONST. COMMENT. 353, 355 (2007). 17 Strauss, supra note 6, at 1166. Strauss added that “much of the book consists of learned and elegant arguments about issues in constitutional law that draw on all the various sources that inform ‘constitutional construction’ …[b]ut at this point, originalism seems to have left the stage: constitutional construction is just a form of living constitutionalism.” Id. at 1166. See also Martin H. Redish & Matthew B. Arnould, Judicial Review, Constitutional Interpretation, and the Democratic Dilemma: Proposing a ‘Controlled Activism’ Alternative, 64 FLA. L. REV. 1485, 1509 (2012). 4 Baxter,19 Michael Dorf,20 and Larry Alexander.21 Larry Solum suggested that Balkin’s theory is in fact “a middle ground” between the two approaches.22 Balkin himself, most expressly in his book Constitutional Redemption, the companion volume to Living Originalism, chose to classify his position as originalism.23 He even devoted chapter 8 of that book to the question “How I Became an Originalist.” Balkin argues there that he is not engaging in adopting a label used by his political opponents (as originalism is typically identified with the conservative ideology). In Balkin’s view, the text of the U.S. Constitution stands as a focal point for settling otherwise fractious questions, and as a “potent symbol” of popular sovereignty.24 It is this commitment to the idea of taking the text seriously that puts his theory, so argues Balkin, in the originalist camp. Who is right then? One answer is that the definition of “originalism” is simply too vague.25 Originalism is a family of views which suggests that the meaning given to the Constitutional text in the past, namely when the text was framed and adopted (including, but not exclusively, intentions, expected application and expected meaning), is relevant or even decisive in interpreting the Constitution. But all reasonable theories of constitutional interpretation do not ignore the (linguistic meaning of the) Constitutional text and other aspects of its original character. Thus, as long as “originalism” means giving at least some (non-trivial) weight to facts from the period in which the Constitution was drafted and approved, “we are all originalists.”26 However, the term originalism is often characterized in a narrower way, in which the data from the past get lexical priority over other sources of identifying the meaning of the provisions of the Constitution.27 The idea is that the (linguistic) meaning of the text is fixed when that provision is framed and ratified, and that meaning, which is to be recovered by referring to the text’s “original meaning” is binding.28 Subject to the difficulties in determining whether there is indeed a “purely” 18 James E. Fleming, Living Originalism and Living Constitutionalism as Moral Readings of the American Constitution, 92 B.U.L. REV. 1171 (2012); Fleming, supra note 9, at 673. 19 Hugh Baxter, Why the “Originalism” in Balkin’s Living Originalism?, 92 B.U.L. REV. 1213 (2012). 20 Michael C. Dorf, The Undead Constitution, 125 HARV. L. REV. 2011 (2012). 21 Larry Alexander The Method of Text and ?: Jack Balkin’s Originalism with no Regrets, 2012 U. Ill. L. REV. 611. 22 Lawrence B. Solum, Construction and Constraint, _ JERUSALEM REV. LEG. STUD. _ (2013). 23 JACK M. BALKIN, CONSTITUTIONAL REDEMPTION: POLITICAL FAITH IN AN UNJUST WORLD 226-50 (2011). 24 Id. at 237. 25 Mitchell Berman has identified seventy-two (!) varieties of originalism. Mitchell N. Berman, Originalism is Bunk, 84 N.Y.U. L. REV. 1, 14-15 (2009). However, Berman rejects the notion that originalism is too ambiguous to capture a subject of genuine debate. See also Fleming, supra note 9, at 670 (arguing that “we are witnessing the ‘Balkanization’ of originalism (when originalism splits into warring camps.)”). 26 Randy E. Barnett, Underlying Principles, 24 CONST. COMMENT. 405 (2007); James E. Ryan, Laying Claim To The Constitution: The Promise Of New Textualism, 97 VA. L. REV. 1523 (2011). 27 28 See, e.g., Berman, supra note 25, at 10-12. According to Larry Solum, originalism claims that: (1) the (linguistic) meaning of each provision of the Constitution becomes fixed when that provision is framed and ratified; (2) sound interpretation of the Constitution requires recovery of its original public meaning; and (3) original public meaning has the force of law, such that courts and officials are bound by the text of the Constitution. Lawrence B. 5 originalist aspect in Balkin’s theory, an issue on which I elaborate below, I think that Balkin does aim at offering an originalist argument of a special type. In its more common usage, for instance the one endorsed by Justice Scalia,29 or Randy Barnett,30 originalism is a theory of constitutional interpretation, giving meaning to substantial provisions in the Constitution. As indicated, as a general matter, originalists support this position not on the basis of originalist-based arguments about the way the Constitution should be interpreted, but based on some substantive arguments about the appropriate theory of interpretation. In contrast, Balkin calls for employing (a certain form of) “originalism” for the purpose of choosing the method in which the Constitutional provisions are to be interpreted. Using an (admittedly only partially suitable) analogy from normative ethics,31 we may distinguish between “factoral” originalism and “foundational” originalism. A factoral moral theory defines the factors that determine the morality of an act, and their relative weight. In analogy, a factoral theory of interpretation determines the sources that should be used in giving meaning to a given legal text. It is; however, the role of foundational theories to explain and justify the relevance of the various factors and their interaction. Balkin’s approach takes originalism as a foundational theory of interpretation. Balkin’s claim is that the result of “foundational” originalism is that central elements of the U.S. Constitution should be interpreted (or “constructed”) according to a distinctively non-originalist “facotral” theory. Balkin argues that the “interpretation” of the Constitution (i.e., the process of identifying the text’s linguistic meaning) must be based on the words’ strict “semantic meaning,” and cannot be changed over time, except by formal amendment; but then adds that the “construction” of the text (i.e., determining its legal effect and applying it to concrete cases) should be subject by later generations, so as to better reflect contemporary values. The original meaning of the Constitution is not that of a “finished produce, subject to only Article V amendments;” rather, it is understood as an “initial framework for governance that sets policies in motion and must be filled out over time through constitutional construction.”32 3. Foundational Originalism and Democratic Legitimacy Balkin’s approach, that we should pay careful attention to the reasons why constitutional designers chose particular kinds of language, and employ a theory of interpretation and constitutional construction accordingly, may prove to be a doubleedged sword from the perspective of the living constitutionalism camp. As far as its rhetoric is concerned, it might unintentionally induce judges to employ originalism, disregarding the fine distinction between the use of originalism in identifying the Constitutional framework and its use as an interpretation theory.33 Moreover, Balkin’s Solum, We are All Originalists Now, in ROBERT W. BENNETT & LAWRENCE B. SOLUM, CONSTITUTIONAL ORIGINALISM: A DEBATE 1, 3-4 (2011). 29 Antonin Scalia, Common-Law Courts in a Civil-Law System: The Role of United States Federal Courts in Interpreting the Constitution and Laws, in A MATTER OF INTERPRETATION: FEDERAL COURTS AND THE LAW 17 (Amy Gutmann ed., 1997). 30 RANDY E. BARNETT, RESTORING THE LOST CONSTITUTION: THE PRESUMPTION OF LIBERTY (2004). 31 Shelly Kagan, The Structure of Normative Ethics, 6 PHIL. PERSPECTIVES 223, 224–36 (1992). 32 BALKIN, supra note 1, at 21. 33 For a related argument see Dorf, supra note 20, at 2014. 6 justification of living constitutionalism can work only as long as it can be reasonably inferred from the text and the original characteristics of the Constitutional framework. If the reasonable interpretation of the text results in the conclusion that its aim, according to the public original meaning, was to limit future generations’ discretion, Balkin’s “foundational” originalism might undermine the legitimacy of living constitutionalism. But the more general question is, why (if at all) is the drafters’ purpose in choosing between the two constitutional frameworks (or the “original public meaning” of this choice) normatively relevant? For that matter, would an explicit “interpretation clause” in the Constitution, if there were one,34 have been binding just as the text of substantive clauses do? Balkin does not directly address the dilemma should the “author” of a legal norm be empowered to bind interpreters in choosing what interpretation theory will be employed in giving meaning to the text. Originalists and living constitutionalists alike may well argue that the choice of theory of interpretation should not be resolved according to originalist considerations. This position seems to be prominent in other contexts of legal interpretation. For instance, the power of parties to a contract to determine what theory of interpretation courts should employ in giving meaning to their contractual obligations is limited.35 The same is true with respect to the power of the legislature to dictate the method that will be used in interpreting a certain statute (or in interpreting legislation in general). A theory of interpretation determines the binding power of the author of the text. Schematically, the more weight is given to originalist elements in giving meaning to the text, the more power is given to the author/adopter of the text. It is conventionally assumed, on the basis of good substantive considerations, that the legislature is not authorized to determine its own powers. The legislature’s powers, including the choice of the appropriate method on interpretation, are a matter to be determined by the Constitution. Balkin may be read as suggesting that we should recognize the authority of the Constitutional text to determine the scope of its own binding power. He suggests that this power results from the recognition of the Constitution as “law,” and from “the fact that it was created through successive acts of popular sovereignty.”36 It is in fact an argument for giving the text a decisive power on the basis of “procedural legitimacy.” Given that it is the People that adopted the Constitution, the framers enjoy limitless powers, including the authority to determine how far to limit the discretion of future generations, and thus also to choose the method of interpretation of the Constitution that will govern its future enforcers.37 34 An example of such a clause is Section 39(1) of the Constitution of the Republic of South Africa, 1996: “When interpreting the Bill of Rights, a court, tribunal or forum: (a) must promote the values that underlie an open and democratic society based on human dignity, equality and freedom; (b) must consider international law; and (c) may consider foreign law.” 35 See, e.g., Alan Schwartz & Robert E. Scott, Contract Interpretation Redux, 119 YALE L.J. 926, 939 (2010) (“[T]he [interpretive] rules are mandatory in the sense that parties cannot contract directly for textualist or contextualist interpretive rules.”). 36 37 BALKIN, supra note 1, at 55. A similar result is reached on the basis of the positivist idea that a “constitutional assembly” enjoys, by definition, limitless powers. See, e.g., CLAUDE KLEIN, THÉORIE ET PRATIQUE DU POUVOIR CONSTITUENT (1996). 7 I doubt, however, not only whether this position is justified (I think it isn’t) but also whether Balkin in fact endorses it. The normative justification for the binding power of the Constitution, and thus also that of its choices about the framework of “constitutional construction,” is based on three related elements. Procedural legitimacy is indeed one of them: the Constitutional text is binding as long as it was adopted in a “legitimate” process. But we must also take into account two additional types of considerations. One is moral justifications (in terms of both normative ethics and political philosophy) of the relevant constitutional interpretation theory. The other is the acceptance of the relevant framework of constitutional interpretation and construction by the current generation and the fact that it both reflects and accommodates the current generation’s values. The reference to all three sources is what generates the “democratic legitimacy” of the binding power of the Constitution in general, and of its “original framework” in particular. Balkin explicitly incorporates these two non-procedural sources of democratic legitimacy. In chapter 4 of the book Balkin argues that the Constitutional interpretation theory should be constructed in a way that will ensure that all people take part in the interpretation project.38 Similarly, Balkin’s elaborated discussion of the practice of constitutional change and transformation in the U.S. is aimed not only for descriptive purposes but to suggest that the framework of constitutional construction also enjoys sociological legitimacy.39 In his response to critique Balkin acknowledges that in fact the basis of his position to “ascribe” to the text the specific meaning of the use of principles is the distinctively non-original (and thus nonprocedural) elements of democratic legitimacy: “My account of original meaning assumes that adopters recognize that a great deal will have to be worked out through construction and that their choice of rules, standards, and principles is deliberate. It ascribes this understanding and these purposes to the adopters. They are creating a constitution not only for their time, but for a later time they cannot know much about. …The democratic legitimacy of the Constitution …arises from the processes of constitutional construction over time. Constitutions cannot maintain their democratic legitimacy without contributions from multiple generations.”40 Balkin does not tell us what should be the outcome when the preferred theory of interpretation according to these non-original elements of democratic legitimacy, living constitutionalism, is not supported by the Constitutional text, and thus cannot gain the assumed procedural legitimacy. He implicitly assumes away this possibility by arguing that “framework originalism,” the “fidelity to the basic framework” chosen by the framers of the Constitution, “allows each generation to do its part in making 38 BALKIN, supra note 1, at 62: “A Constitutional theory that distrusts all delegation to the future fails as ‘our law’ … A Constitution is our law when we feel that we have a stake in it.” 39 Id., at 81-97. Balkin questions there the influential theory of Bruce Ackerman about constitutional change outside the formal procedures of Article V, in what Ackerman describes as “Constitutional moments,” in which people rediscover the Constitution. 40 Jack M. Balkin, Nine Perspectives on Living Originalism, 2012 U. Ill. L. Rev. 815, 830 (emphasis added). Balkin adds there that “the democratic legitimacy of the Constitution is not established at the moment of adoption. Rather, it derives from multiple sources. The first source of democratic legitimacy is the act of adoption or amendment. The second arises from the processes of constitutional construction over time. Constitutions cannot maintain their democratic legitimacy without contributions from multiple generations.” (id). 8 the Constitution its own Constitution.”41 However, as Jeffrey Goldsworthy noted, this assumption of perfect alignment between the text and the requirement of legitimacy through contributions from multiple generations may well be “too good to be true.”42 Indeed, Balkin himself recognizes that in certain contexts the original framework does not allow for such an on-going public participation, since it uses “rules.” It is not clear how, according to Balkin, these parts of the Constitution establish their democratic legitimacy. A theory of framework originalism must determine the priority (or at least the relative “weight”) of the different sources of legitimacy, as it should apply regardless of one’s position about moral democratic legitimacy. For instance, if it were a general theory of framework originalism it should also address the case in which it is assumed, like Larry Alexander does, that moral considerations refute the use of “principles” as a Constitutional framework.43 As indicated, while in some places in the book Balkin seems to suggest that the “originalist framework” is decisive,44 it is hardly compatible with Balkin’s own position.45 To my view, there is no good reason to recognize the authority of the text, i.e. the power of the framers and adopters of the Constitution, to determine the method of interpretation regardless of moral and sociological considerations. The study of the text is clearly relevant, as in appropriate instances it serves for legitimizing the conclusions of the non-originalist analysis. But I did not find in Balkin’s book a convincing argument for giving the text (or its original public meaning) lexical priority. The opposite is true. Balkin’s detailed account of the moral and sociological considerations, along with other scholarship endorsing living constitutionalism,46 suggest that when in conflict, these are the considerations that should prevail. Balkin’s project aims at demonstrating that the framework that provides the Constitution its moral and sociological democratic legitimacy, namely living constitutionalism, is reasonably reflected in the choices of the drafters and adopters of the US Constitution. Their choice is morally meaningful since “it is a constitution we are expounding,” but it holds only subject to the moral considerations supporting the specific choice. But Balkin’s theory does not support foundational originalism of the type which assigns lexical priority to original considerations as the factoral theory of interpretation. 4. Foundational Originalism and Procedural Legitimacy According to the originalists’ critique, living constitutionalism is flawed since it does not take the text (and other original characters) of the Constitution seriously, and thus deprives the Constitution of its procedural legitimacy. Balkin seems to endorse this position in his critical discussion of the non-originalist-based living constitutionalism, such as the one endorsed by David Strauss. Balkin presents the latter approach as one 41 Id., id. 42 Jeffrey Goldsworthy, Constitutional Cultures, Democracy, and Unwritten Principles, 2012 U. Ill. L. Rev. 683, 691-93. 43 See, e.g., Alexander, supra note 21. 44 For instance: “The initial authority of the text comes from the fact that it was created through successive acts of popular sovereignty, and the text continues in force today because it is law.” BALKIN, supra note 1, at 55. 45 See, e.g., id., at 66. 46 See, e.g., DAVID A. STRAUSS, THE LIVING CONSTITUTION (2010). 9 which “denies that the text is an authoritative command or political decision made in the past to which we owe duty of fidelity or obedience. The text merely serves as a focal point for political activity…”.47 According to Balkin, the problem with this approach results from its deficit in procedural legitimacy: “[Strauss’ approach] offers no obvious connection between the law Americans live under and popular sovereignty. …The text could be any text produced by anyone.”48 Balkin claims that his framework originalism solves this difficulty, as it justifies living constitutionalism in a way that “directly connects the reason why we follow the text as our law to past exercises of popular sovereignty.”49 Promulgating this idea, which is discussed in the book quite at length, is probably one of the central aims of the book. I am doubtful, however, whether this reply to the originalists’ critique is fully successful. Recall that Balkin’s argument that his version of living constitutionalism enjoys procedural legitimacy is based on his assertion that the Constitutional text that the People adopted is one which “very often use[s] open-ended language that deliberately delegates questions of application to future interpreters.”50 If Balkin is right in this characterization of the Constitutional framework, it means that his theory of constitutional construction satisfies a formal, “thin” version of procedural legitimacy. Balkin’s assertion that the People decided that “it is better to adopt language that shape the future discourse of debates about rights without trying to fully determine everything in advance”51 is a successful response to the claim that future generations’ constitutional construction violates popular sovereignty. However, if the act of adopting the Constitution, this process of exercising popular sovereignty, has merely delegated power to determining the required social choices, it fails to satisfy a “thick” notion of the requirement of procedural legitimacy. A “thick” notion of procedural legitimacy closely resembles the rationale of the Congressional “Non-Delegation” doctrine. A decision of the legislature to delegate legislative powers to another agency, while formally a legislative “decision,” fails to fulfill the aims of requiring the legislature to make the substantial choices and set the required policies.52 As stated by Chief Justice Rhenquist, “...Congress [should] lay down the general policy and standards that animate the law, leaving the agency to refine those standards, ‘fill the blanks’ or apply the standards to particular cases.”53 In 47 BALKIN, supra note 1, at 50. 48 Id., at 54. This position resembles the theory that used to be (pejoratively) termed as “noninterpretivism” (as opposed to “interpretivism”). 49 Id., id. 50 Id., at 27. 51 Id., at 31. 52 The classical statement of this view was promulgated by John Locke: “[The legislative power], being derived from the People by a positive voluntary Grant and Institution, can be no other than what that positive Grant conveyed, which being only to make Laws, and not to make Legislators, the Legislative can have no power to transfer their Authority of making Laws, and place it in other hands”. John Locke, The Second Treatise of Government, in TWO TREATISES OF GOVERNMENT 265, § 141 at 363 (1988, Peter Laslett, ed.). See also Larry Alexander & Saikrishna Prakash, Reports of the Nondelegation Doctrine's Death Are Greatly Exaggerated, 70 U. CHI. L. REV. 1297, 1299-1300 (2003). For a different view see Eric A. Posner and Adrian Vermeule, Interring the Nondelegation Doctrine, 69 U. CHI. L. REV. 1721 (2002). 53 Industrial Union Dept. v. American Petrol. Inst. 448 U.S. 607, 675 (1980). 01 Edmund Burke’s words, the representatives owe us not only their industry but mostly their “judgment.”54 The analogy to the current discussion does not carry on to the consequences of violating this doctrine, as I agree that the framers and adopters of the Constitution may delegate powers to others. My claim is that a decision to “frame” the Constitution as a text that, in Balkin’s words, “may not do much more than provide a constitutional grammar and vocabulary, a set of basic principles and textual commitments, and a practice of constitutional argument,”55 is insufficient to gain it procedural legitimacy. Such a constitution does not reflect substantial moral choices of the People.56 For a constitution to gain procedural legitimacy it is insufficient that the “process” of its adoption fulfills certain properties of form (e.g., that it was adopted in a “constitutional moment,” “behind a veil of ignorance,” by a qualified majority, etc.).57 It is also required to fulfill some properties of substance, which includes resolving policy issues, “rulifying” morality (possibly by forming “standards”),58 and so forth. Therefore, the binding status of the Constitution, if its content is the one envisioned by Balkin, cannot be based on the idea of procedural legitimacy. It must resort to other elements of democratic legitimacy. 5. Implementing “Framework Originalism:” Text and Context As indicated, Balkin’s theory focuses almost exclusively on one type of originalist consideration—the choice between rules and standards and principles in the Constitutional text. According to Balkin, the Constitutional text reflects a choice between two main approaches: Setting rules, which do not leave much room for future generations to interpret or construct; and standards and principles, which delegate much power to future generations. While I’m sympathetic to Balkin’s call for an originalist inquiry of the constitutional framework, I find his decision to focus almost exclusively on the choice between rules and principles questionable. One difficulty is that the distinction between rules and principles is insufficient to establish the “public original meaning” of the Constitutional framework. First, it is hardly self-evident to what type a certain provision belongs. Relatedly, constitutional provisions should not be interpreted in isolation from other norms, or from the underlying moral theory of the Constitution.59 Identifying the original “framework” often requires addressing more than one provision in the Constitution, and when the set of relevant provisions consists of norms of both types, Balkin’s focus on the text may well be insufficient to identify the correct original choices. For instance, it can hardly be justified to ignore aspects such as the inclusion (or omission) of provisions such as an “override clause” in the Constitution, a “limitation clause,” which authorizes the legislature to infringe 54 Edmund Burke, Speech to the Electors of Bristol, in THE WORKS OF THE RIGHT HONORABLE EDMUND BURKE 2, 10 (1826). 55 BALKIN, supra note 1, at 31. 56 For a discussion of the degree of constraint that the Constitution provides according to Balkin’s approach see Solum, supra note 22. 57 See, e.g., 1 BRUCE ACKERMAN, WE THE PEOPLE: FOUNDATIONS THE PEOPLE: TRANSFORMATIONS (1998). 58 59 (1991); 2 BRUCE ACKERMAN, WE Larry Alexander, Judicial Review and Moral Rights, 33 QUEEN’S L.J. 1 (2007). A well-known expression of this idea about the “impossibility of a Clause-bound interpretivism” is of course Ely, supra note 8, at 11-41. 00 liberties under a certain set of conditions, and other structural elements of the Constitutional text. Second, Balkin’s theory is based on a prior assumption about the purpose of using principles—to create a framework for future constitutional construction. But the purpose may well be a different one, for instance to refer to a term of art, to indicate not more than its original expected application. In certain contexts, such as the scope of human rights and their protection, it is simply inevitable to use principles, regardless of one’s preferred constitutional framework. In certain places Balkin’s analysis may be read as suggesting that the choice between rules and principles, as such, teaches the interpreter about the purpose of the relevant Constitutional provision. But if this was the case, Balkin’s theory would not qualify as framework originalism, but as an inquiry that is aimed at finding a basis in the text to one’s preferred theory of interpretation, based on distinctively ahistorical, non-originalist considerations about the choice between rules and standards.60 In fact, Balkin’s position is more complex. It is not based on a mere abstract inference of the Constitutional framework from the text. Balkin acknowledges the legitimacy of considering additional sources of original character to establish what he calls the “public original meaning” of the choice between rules and standards. However, Balkin seems to object using sources of original character about the theory of interpretation that the framers and adopters of the Constitution expected or desired. One such source is historical evidence about the prevailing theory of interpretation (independent of the choice between rules and principles) at the time of adopting the Constitution. Some scholars suggest that historical research in this respect shows that the preferred method of interpretation at the time of adopting the U.S. Constitution was distinctively non-originalist, one which “favored a mobile over a static theory of textual interpretation.”61 An additionally important original element in identifying the Constitutional framework is information about the particular purpose of entrenching a certain norm in the Constitution. Larry Alexander criticized Balkin’s position by arguing that the idea that the framers chose to write Constitutional provisions in the form of “principles” is highly unlikely, because principles do not provide any meaningful guidelines.62 Criticism of this sort is plausible if one assumes, as Alexander does, that the purpose of having a certain norm in a constitution is to “rulify morality,” that is, to limit the discretion of future generations.63 But societies may well adopt certain constitutional provisions for other purposes. For instance, Joseph Raz suggested that the purpose of constitutionalizing the prohibition to violate certain human rights is to enable “a common culture to be formed round shared intermediate [moral] 60 Cf. John O. McGinnis & Michael B. Rappaport, The Abstract Meaning Fallacy, 2012 U. ILL. L. REV. 737. 61 Hans W. Baade, “Original Intent” in Historical Perspective: Some Critical Glosses, 69 TEX. L. REV. 1001, 1004 (1991). For further discussions on this issue see, e.g., Saul Cornell, The People’s Constitution vs. The Lawyers’ Constitution: Popular Constitutionalism and the Original Debate over Originalism, 23 YALE J.L. & HUMAN. 295 (2011); Larry Kramer, Two (More) Problems with Originalism, 31 HARV. J.L. & PUB. POL’Y 907 (2008). 62 Alexander, supra note 21, at 617. Alexander suggested that it is improbable that the original meaning of various clauses in the Constitution is “an instruction to consult ‘moral reality’ and apply the ‘principles’ one finds there.” (id). 63 Alexander, supra note 58. 02 conclusions.”64 In other contexts, most commonly in deeply divided societies, the quest for achieving consensus may be unattainable, and a constitution may be formed only to ensure an ongoing dialogue through the interaction between the judiciary, the political branches and the public opinion at large. In such cases, the Constitution does end the debate but merely frames it. In other cases the Constitution serves to remove certain issues from the debate.65 Balkin seems to be reluctant to take into account these types of original characters of the text.66 He particularly opposes the use of evidence about original intent and original expected application of the Constitutional text.67 Balkin’s position in this respect is based on the unique status of the Constitutional text in his theory. In his view, the U.S. Constitution’s text stands as a “potent symbol” of popular sovereignty and the trans-generational project of self-government.68 In his words: “Inevitably, then, we face a choice in the present about what aspects of cultural meaning should constitute ‘original meaning’ for purposes of constitutional interpretation. There is no natural and value-free way to make this selection. …It is a choice that is informed by the purposes of a constitution and the promotion of the kind of legitimacy (democratic, social, procedural, or moral) we want our government to have.”69 I disagree. I suggest that Balkin should have distinguished here between the original sources that are relevant for interpreting the Constitution (according to a nonoriginalist choice of the preferable theory of interpretation) and those suitable for identifying the Constitution’s original framework (to determine the theory of interpretation on the basis of originalist considerations). The centrality of the text and its semantic meaning as a “potent symbol” of popular sovereignty are relevant for the former purpose. The non-originalist choice of a theory of interpretation, and for that matter the decision what original sources should be considered in giving meaning to the text, should indeed take into account issues of democratic legitimacy. I agree with substantial parts of Balkin’s analysis in this respect, and to his insistence on ignoring 64 JOSEPH RAZ, THE MORALITY OF FREEDOM 181 (1986): “Assertions of rights are typically intermediate conclusions in arguments from ultimate values to duties... The fact that practical arguments proceed through the mediation of intermediate stages so that not every time a practical question arises does one refer to ultimate values for an answer is... of crucial importance in making social life possible, not only because it saves time and tediousness, but primarily because it enables a common culture to be formed round shared intermediate conclusions, in spite of a great degree of haziness and disagreement concerning ultimate values.” 65 See, e.g., Ruth Gavison, What Belongs in a Constitution? 13 CONST. POL. ECON. 89 (2002); SUJIT CHOUDRY (ED.) CONSTITUTIONAL DESIGN FOR DIVIDED SOCIETIES: INTEGRATION OR ACCOMMODATION? (2008); HANNA LERNER, MAKING CONSTITUTIONS IN DEEPLY DIVIDED SOCIETIES (2011). 66 See, e.g., Balkin, supra note 40, at 829: “In Living Originalism, I focus on original semantic meaning (including generally recognized terms of art) and the adopters’ choice of basic technologies of linguistic constraint: rules, standards, principles, and silences. The remaining aspects of cultural meaning I treat as resources for construction, but not as part of the framework.” 67 BALKIN, supra note 1, at 11. 68 BALKIN, supra note 23, at 232-37. See also Jack M. Balkin, The Roots of the Living Constitution, 92 B.U.L. REV. 1129, 1133 (2012), where Balkin distinguishes between his “framework originalism,” which “argues that fidelity to ‘original meaning’ requires fidelity to the semantic meanings of the words in the text at the time of adoption, including generally recognized terms of art,” and “thick original meaning,” to which he opposes, that “might include the original principles, purposes, expectations, or assumptions of the adopting generation.” 69 Balkin, supra note 40, at 829. 03 original sources that are external to the text, such as the intentions of the framers or expected original application of the text. But not so as far as the latter purpose is concerned. Here the underlying assumption is that the original choice of the framers and adopters about the Constitutional framework is relevant. As discussed above, this original framework may be relevant to refute the argument that living constitutionalism violates some originalist aspect of the Constitution, and it may be needed to accord living constitutionalism some procedural legitimacy. In sum, I don’t see a good reason to disqualify certain sources of original character. As indicated above, the original elements do not gain lexical priority over other considerations in choosing the appropriate constitutional framework. Taking into account all original elements may well increase the persuasive power of Balkin’s living originalism project. 6. Applying Balkin’s Theory to New Constitutions: A Comment on Israel The Israeli Supreme Court, following the lead of its former President Aharon Barak,70 has adopted a distinctively non-originalist method of constitutional interpretation. A central example is the expansive interpretation of the right to human dignity (entrenched in Article 2 of Basic-Law: Human Dignity and Liberty), to cover the rights to equality, freedom of expression, and more, despite indications from originalist sources contradicting this interpretation of human dignity as a “principle.”71 In fact, even the decision that the Basic-Laws are the supreme law of the land, and are thus binding the legislature and authorize the Court to employ judicial review of legislation, was primarily based on non-originalist considerations and despite some contradicting originalist sources.72 The Israeli Court’s endorsement of living constitutionalism, which I find justifiable, is probably among the main reasons of the reluctance of the majority in the Knesset (which serves as both the legislature and the constitutional assembly) to complete the process of enacting Israel’s Constitution. An important (although mostly implicit) reason for the deadlock in the attempts to agree on a new Constitution is the disagreement about the underlying purpose of having a constitution. The debate revolves around two main competing approaches. One position refers to the formation of a new constitution as a codification of preexisting norms and perceptions. It does not aim at creating a new social order or “constitutional identity.” The Constitution is rather perceived as a manifestation of an already existing identity, and the aim to provide a greater convergence between the text and this identity. In contrast, a second position suggests that a new constitution is aimed at establishing a new or at least a modified constitutional identity. (Following the discussion above, if this debate is resolved, the choice between the competing approaches should be considered in the inquiry of the “original” character of the 70 AHARON BARAK, THE JUDGE IN A DEMOCRACY (2006). 71 See, e.g., H.C.J. 466/07 Galon v. The Attorney General (2012). 72 C.A. 6821/93 United Mizrachi Bank v. Migdal Cooperative Village, 49(4) P.D. 221 (1995). See, e.g., Adam Shinar, Accidental Constitutionalism: The Political Foundations and Implications of Israeli Constitution-Making, in, THE SOCIAL AND POLITICAL FOUNDATIONS OF CONSTITUTIONS (Dennis Galligan & Mila Versteeg, eds., 2012). 04 Constitutional framework, and thus of the “original” choice of a constitutional interpretation theory.)73 Balkin’s book suggests that we should consider a third purpose of having a new constitution to Israel. The two positions discussed above share an underlying premise, namely that the “constitutional identity” is entrenched in the constitutional document. Both approaches reflect, to a great extent, the view that the Constitution is a finished product, subject to only formal constitutional amendments. Balkin points at an alternative view, of the Constitution as a merely initial framework for governance, that must be filled out over time through constitutional construction. According to this view, the Constitutional identity is an ever evolving, rather than a fixed concept. The main purpose of adopting a formal constitution is not to entrench a certain—either a pre-existing or a new—social identity. To the contrary, it is aimed at establishing a mechanism that will enable society to constantly reevaluate and when needed to redefine its Constitutional identity. The Constitution, this “thing” that binds the current majority, is not a set of answers. Rather, it is mostly a reference to the rule of reason, or to the Rawlsian concept of “public reason”. The text of the Constitution serves as a “focal point” for an on-going debate and dialogue, in which all members of society participate.74 My suggestion here addresses in particular the recent debate in Israel about the proposed Basic-Law: the Legislation. This proposal, whose recent version was published in 2012, is aimed at supplementing the set of eleven Basic-Laws which forms Israel’s Constitution. The proposed version is far from being optimal from the perspective of those who believe that the Constitution should entrench Israel’s constitutional identity as a liberal democracy. Among the central concerns is the proposal to authorize the legislature to override a judicial decision which declared a statute unconstitutional. While I share these concerns, I think that the proposal provides an important opportunity to adopt a constitution which is based on the above mentioned third model. The proposed Basic-Law’s explicit recognition of the normative status of the Basic-Laws as the supreme law of the land, as well as the enactment of an override clause, can serve the vital purpose of enhancing a “constitutional dialogue” which is missing in Israel’s politics and public discourse. As Balkin admits, the method of principles does not bind future generations to a certain set of constraints. It is true that the principles may not do much more than provide a “Constitutional grammar and vocabulary.”75 Nevertheless, it may well serve the role of enhancing constitutional discourse, a role which is of special importance in a divided society as the Israeli one, which not only lacks a consensus about the state’s “constitutional identity,” but also hardly engaged in a popular constitutional dialogue. 73 For instance, the former approach gives greater “procedural” legitimacy to interpret the Constitution according to the newly formed “constitutional identity.” For a discussion see, e.g., GARY J. JACOBSOHN, CONSTITUTIONAL IDENTITY (2010). 74 In Balkin’s words, “the Constitution is simultaneously a text, a set of political institutions, a source of values and aspirations, and a repository of cultural memory.” BALKIN, supra note 1, at 97. 75 Id., at 31.