SAME-SEX MARRIAGE — NEW YORK COURT OF APPEALS DENIES INDIVIDUALS THE ABILITY TO MARRY THEIR SAME-SEX PARTNERS. Hernandez v. Robles, 855 N.E.2d 1 (N.Y. 2006). Josef W. Mintz* I. INTRODUCTION In Hernandez v. Robles,1 a plurality of the Court of Appeals of New York upheld the constitutionality of a statute that prohibits marriages between same-sex couples. The plurality deferred the permissibility of samesex marriage in New York to the state legislature. This Comment will examine the court’s treatment of the due process and equal protection arguments of the parties to the case, and analyze the constitutional decisionmaking techniques employed by the several opinions of the court. This Comment concludes that the plurality opinion of the Hernandez court erroneously selected the highly deferential minimum rationality standard of review and improperly applied it. Had the plurality considered the full scope of arguments available, it would have been forced to apply heightened scrutiny and recognize that the statute in question deprived plaintiffs of their fundamental right to marry the spouse of their choice while impermissibly discriminating against plaintiffs’ sex and sexual orientation. * J.D. Candidate, Rutgers University School of Law—Camden, May 2008; B.A., Vassar College, 2002. Thank you to my family, especially Shari. Also, thank you to Professor Ann E. Freedman for her helpful comments on an earlier draft. 1. 855 N.E.2d 1 (N.Y. 2006). 1431 1432 RUTGERS LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 38:1431 II. STATEMENT OF THE CASE Hernandez was a consolidated action comprising four separate suits involving a total of forty-four same-sex couples, each seeking a valid New York State marriage license.2 Plaintiffs represented a wide variety of socioeconomic backgrounds from across the State of New York.3 Defendants were the separate licensing authorities of New York City, Albany and Ithaca, the New York State Department of Health, and the State itself.4 In each of the consolidated cases, plaintiffs challenged the constitutionality of the various sections of the New York Domestic Relations Law (“DRL”) that mandated marriage to be between a man and a woman.5 The holdings of the lower courts differed: one of the trial courts ruled in favor of plaintiffs6 and the other three courts ruled in favor of defendants.7 At the appellate level, defendants were uniformly victorious; the highly deferential rational-basis standard of review was applied to plaintiffs’ due process and equal protection claims.8 2. See Kane v. Marsolais, 808 N.Y.S.2d 566 (N.Y. App. Div. 2006), aff’d sub nom. Hernandez v. Robles, 855 N.E.2d 1 (N.Y. 2006); Samuels v. State Dep’t of Health, 811 N.Y.S.2d 136 (N.Y. App. Div. 2005), aff’d sub nom. Hernandez v. Robles, 855 N.E.2d 1 (N.Y. 2006); Hernandez v. Robles, 794 N.Y.S.2d 579 (N.Y. Sup. Ct. 2005), rev’d, 805 N.Y.S.2d 354 (N.Y. App. Div. 2005), aff’d, 855 N.E.2d 1 (N.Y. 2006); Seymour v. Holcomb, 790 N.Y.S.2d 858 (N.Y. Sup. Ct. 2005), aff’d, 811 N.Y.S.2d 134 (N.Y. App. Div. 2006), aff’d sub nom. Hernandez v. Robles, 855 N.E.2d 1 (N.Y. 2006). 3. Hernandez, 855 N.E.2d at 22 (Kaye, C.J., dissenting). Plaintiffs included a doctor, a police officer, a public school teacher, a nurse, an artist and a state legislator. Id. Many Hernandez plaintiffs were raising children of varying ages, and many were active in their communities, serving on local school boards and apartment building cooperative boards. Id. 4. Id. at 5 (plurality opinion). 5. All parties acknowledged that the sections of the DRL in question limited marriage to opposite-sex couples, though plaintiffs argued that such is impermissible. Id. This was not always the case. Petitioners in the Kane and Seymour cases unsuccessfully argued that the DRL implicitly permitted same-sex marriage by virtue of omission of a hard and fast definition of marriage between a man and a woman. See Kane, 808 N.Y.S.2d at 566; Seymour, 790 N.Y.S.2d at 862-63. 6. The trial-level decision in Hernandez stood out as the single lower-court holding in favor of plaintiffs in this case. In her opinion, Supreme Court Judge Doris Ling-Cohan determined that the DRL violated plaintiffs’ fundamental right to marry. Hernandez, 794 N.Y.S.2d at 609. 7. See Kane, 808 N.Y.S.2d at 567; Samuels, 811 N.Y.S.2d at 147; Seymour, 790 N.Y.S.2d at 866. 8. For example, the Appellate Division reversed Judge Ling-Cohan’s trial level decision. Hernandez v. Robles, 805 N.Y.S.2d 354, 363 (N.Y. App. Div. 2005), aff’d, 855 N.E.2d 1 (N.Y. 2006). The appellate majority found that because the parties agreed that the DRL discriminated solely on the basis of sexual orientation, the classification was not subject 2007] SAME SEX MARRIAGE: HERNANDEZ v. ROBLES 1433 III. HISTORY OF THE AREA State high court decisions regarding same-sex marriage have fostered a national debate. Beneath the agendas seeking particular results in these decisions lie the legal arguments both for and against same-sex marriage. Considering the due process argument for marriage equality, the fundamental right of marriage is undisputed.9 However, numerous courts have declined to adopt the view that the right of marriage permits same-sex couples to marry each other.10 The idea that the fundamental right of marriage includes the right for one person to marry another regardless of either party’s sex or sexual orientation has been accepted by only one state high court.11 The gist of the equal protection claims in marriage equality cases is that state statutes that deny same-sex marriage arguably treat homosexuals differently on the bases of their sex and sexual orientation.12 However, even when state high courts find these equal protection arguments compelling, to strict scrutiny and had not been proven irrational by plaintiffs. Id. at 360-61. The appellate majority also held there to be no fundamental right to same-sex marriage. Id. at 361-62. The appellate majority specifically noted that plaintiffs’ reliance on Loving v. Virginia, 388 U.S. 1 (1967), was inapposite as the fundamental right issue in Loving was the “right to be free from racial discrimination based on the Equal Protection Clause” and not the fundamental right to marry. Hernandez, 805 N.Y.S.2d at 362; see also Kane, 808 N.Y.S.2d at 567 (affirming order “for the same reasons stated in [Samuels] . . . .”); Samuels, 811 N.Y.S.2d at 143-147 (applying rational-basis review and finding for defendants); Seymour, 811 N.Y.S.2d at 135 (finding no merit to plaintiffs’ constitutional claims). 9. See Zablocki v. Redhail, 434 U.S. 374, 384 (1978) (“Although Loving arose in the context of racial discrimination, prior and subsequent decisions of this Court confirm that the right to marry is of fundamental importance for all individuals.”); Loving, 388 U.S. at 12 (“The freedom to marry has long been recognized as one of the vital personal rights essential to the orderly pursuit of happiness by free men.”). 10. See, e.g., Standhardt v. Superior Court ex rel. County of Maricopa, 77 P.3d 451, 460 (Ariz. Ct. App. 2003) (holding that the historical understanding of marriage as between “one man and one woman,” supported by various indicia of the “reaffirmation[] of that view,” mandate the finding that the right to same-sex marriage is not fundamental). 11. See Goodridge v. Dep’t of Pub. Health, 798 N.E.2d 941, 959 (Mass. 2003) (“The liberty interest in choosing whether and whom to marry would be hollow if the Commonwealth could, without sufficient justification, foreclose an individual from freely choosing the person with whom to share an exclusive commitment in the unique institution of civil marriage.”); see also Lewis v. Harris, 908 A.2d 196, 229 (N.J. 2006) (Poritz, C.J., concurring in part and dissenting in part) (arguing that the previously established fundamental right of marriage should allow plaintiffs the ability to marry their same-sex partners). 12. See Lewis, 908 A.2d at 220 (majority opinion) (holding the disparate treatment inherent in a law that prevents same-sex couples from obtaining rights “comparable to those of married couples . . . bears no substantial relationship to a legitimate governmental purpose”). 1434 RUTGERS LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 38:1431 state constitutions may be later amended to specifically define a marriage as exclusively being between one man and one woman, thus circumventing the equal protection argument.13 IV. THE COURT’S REASONING In Hernandez, a plurality of the Court of Appeals of New York held that the New York State Constitution “does not compel recognition of marriages between members of the same sex.”14 The court found that the permissibility of such a right would need to be determined by the state legislature.15 Until Hernandez, the Court of Appeals had not previously heard the issue of whether same-sex marriage was permitted under the New York State Constitution.16 A. The Plurality Opinion The plurality opinion, authored by Judge R.S. Smith and joined by Judges G.B. Smith and Read, framed the main issue of the case to be whether or not a “rational legislature” could have decided to afford marriage benefits to opposite-sex couples but deny those same benefits to same-sex couples.17 13. Compare Baehr v. Lewin, 852 P.2d 44, 67 (Haw. 1993) (finding that the challenged statute mandating marriage to be between one man and one woman “denies same-sex couples access to the marital status . . . thus implicating the equal protection clause of [the Hawaii Constitution’s] article I, section 5”), with HAW. CONST. art. I, § 23 (effective Nov. 3, 1998) (“The legislature shall have the power to reserve marriage to opposite-sex couples.”). A similar situation occurred in Brause v. State, 21 P.3d 357 (Alaska 2001). There, the Alaska Supreme Court held that plaintiffs’ constitutional claims for marriage equality were “mooted” by the 1999 amendment to the Alaska constitution mandating marriage to be between one man and one woman. Id. at 358. 14. Hernandez v. Robles, 855 N.E.2d 1, 5 (N.Y. 2006) (plurality opinion). The New York version of the due process clause states that “[n]o person shall be deprived of life, liberty or property without due process of law.” N.Y. CONST. art. I, § 6. New York’s equal protection clause states: No person shall be denied the equal protection of the laws of this state or any subdivision thereof. No person shall, because of race, color, creed or religion, be subjected to any discrimination in his civil rights by any other person or by any firm, corporation, or institution, or by the state or any agency or subdivision of the state.” N.Y. CONST. art. I, § 11. 15. Hernandez, 855 N.E.2d at 5 (plurality opinion). 16. Id. at 9. 17. Id. at 7. Plaintiffs agreed with defendants that the DRL does not permit same-sex marriage. Id. at 5. Although none of the sections of the DRL relevant to marriage specifically require marriage to be between a man and a woman, the laws contain certain references to the 2007] SAME SEX MARRIAGE: HERNANDEZ v. ROBLES 1435 The plurality asserted two bases by which the legislature could rationally decide to outlaw same-sex marriage.18 First, the plurality found that oppositesex marriage promotes stability in the parenting relationships in which children are biologically conceived and raised.19 The legislature could rationally offer “an inducement” to those opposite-sex couples who have children by offering them the benefits of marriage.20 Second, the legislature could rationally favor opposite-sex parents over same-sex parents finding that opposite-sex parents are better suited to raise children than same-sex parents.21 Having affirmatively answered its question of whether a “rational legislature” could outlaw same-sex marriage, the plurality then turned to its constitutional inquiry by asserting that the right to marry is “unquestionably a fundamental right.”22 However, the plurality found that the right to marry a member of one’s same sex is not fundamental because it is not “‘deeply rooted in this Nation’s history and tradition.’”23 Furthermore, because the relatively narrow definition of marriage which limits the right to oppositesex couples was already found to be rationally based, the plurality did not consider the need to broaden the right in question to include same-sex marriage.24 gender-specific roles of husbands, wives, brides and grooms. See N.Y. DOM. REL. LAW § 12 (McKinney 1999) (stating that “the parties [to a marriage] must solemnly declare . . . that they take each other as husband and wife”); id. § 15(1)(a) (requiring municipal clerks to obtain information from “the groom” and “the bride”); id. § 5 (prohibiting incestuous marriages between brothers and sisters, uncles and nieces, as well as aunts and nephews without mentioning incestuous marriages between members of the same-sex); id. § 50 (stating that the property of “a married woman . . . shall not be subject to her husband’s control”). 18. Hernandez, 855 N.E.2d at 7 (plurality opinion). 19 . Id. 20. Id. As a justification for this interest, the plurality suggested that it is only oppositesex couples that can become parents by “accident or impulse.” Id. As such, it is opposite-sex couples, specifically those who suddenly and unexpectedly find themselves pregnant, who benefit from the legislature’s decision to proscribe same-sex marriage by availing themselves of the option to marry and thus, facilitate a better environment for their children. Id. 21. Further, the plurality stated that plaintiffs and amici “argue that . . . a home with two parents of different sexes has no advantage, from the point of view of raising children, over a home with two parents of the same sex. Perhaps they are right, but the Legislature could rationally think otherwise.” Id. 22. Id. at 9. 23. Id. (quoting Washington v. Glucksburg, 521 U.S. 702, 721 (1997)). 24. Id. at 9-10. The plurality considered the development of fundamental rights jurisprudence in Lawrence v. Texas, 539 U.S. 558 (2003), which examined the right of homosexuals to engage in sodomy, a right rejected in Bowers v. Hardwick, 478 U.S. 186 (1986). Specifically, Lawrence considered the impermissibility of homosexual sodomy 1436 RUTGERS LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 38:1431 Turning to the New York equal protection clause, the plurality broached the threshold determination of the applicable standard of review to apply.25 The plurality immediately excluded strict scrutiny since its application is predicated on a finding of a denial of a fundamental right.26 Next, the application of “heightened” or intermediate scrutiny was considered, because plaintiffs alleged that the DRL discriminates on the basis of sexual orientation.27 The plurality first considered and rejected plaintiffs’ argument that the DRL discriminates on the basis of sex, and found that the DRL treats men and women equally; neither may marry a member of their same sex.28 The plurality then conceded that the DRL does discriminate based on sexual preference.29 However, under the circumstances, the plurality found that such discrimination did not trigger heightened scrutiny and, instead, required mere rational-basis scrutiny since homosexuals have “‘distinguishing characteristics relevant to interests the State has the authority to implement.’”30 established in Bowers and permitted the very practice by broadening the fundamental right in question to become the “right to privacy in intimate relationships.” Hernandez, 855 N.E.2d at 10 (plurality opinion). However, in Hernandez, the plurality found that plaintiffs sought access to a right “that the legislature has rationally limited to opposite-sex couples” whereas, in Lawrence, petitioners sought freedom from “state intrusion on intimate, private activity.” Id. The plurality suggested that if they had found the law in question limiting marriage to opposite-sex couples to be irrational, the narrow definition would have failed. Id. 25. Hernandez, 855 N.E.2d at 10. 26. Id. 27. Id. Though the plurality proceeded as if plaintiffs had raised an equal protection claim alleging sex discrimination, the plurality noted that “[p]laintiffs do not argue here that the legislation they challenge is designed to subordinate either men to women or women to men as a class.” Id. at 11. 28. Id. 29. Id. The plurality admitted that, because only heterosexual couples may marry, “[t]hose who prefer relationships with people of the opposite sex and those who prefer relationships with people of the same sex are not treated alike.” Id. The question of whether heightened scrutiny should be to applied to sexual discrimination cases was previously unanswered by New York precedent. See Under 21 v. City of New York, 482 N.E.2d 1, 10 (N.Y. 1985) (leaving open the question of “whether some level of ‘heightened scrutiny’ would be applied” in sexual discrimination cases). Accordingly, the plurality picked up where Under 21 left off, holding specifically that homosexuality does not merit heightened scrutiny in cases “review[ing] legislation governing marriage and family relationships.” Hernandez, 855 N.E.2d at 11 (plurality opinion). 30. Hernandez, 855 N.E.2d at 11 (plurality opinion) (quoting City of Cleburne v. Cleburne Living Ctr., 473 U.S. 432, 441 (1985)). The plurality conceded that heightened scrutiny may be appropriately applied to some classifications that discriminate on the basis of sexual orientation. Id. However, the plurality held that “legislation governing marriage and family relationships” deserved mere rationality review, especially considering that the court 2007] SAME SEX MARRIAGE: HERNANDEZ v. ROBLES 1437 Finally, the plurality defended its application of rationality review by extinguishing plaintiffs’ arguments that the DRL creates classifications that are both underinclusive and overinclusive.31 Plaintiffs asserted that the DRL is underinclusive since both opposite-sex as well as same-sex couples may have children.32 However, since the legislature may rationally wish to incentivize opposite-sex marriage over same-sex marriage, the court found the degree of underinclusiveness to be tolerable.33 Plaintiffs asserted that the DRL is overinclusive since not all opposite-sex couples choose to have children.34 Considering what might be necessary to better tailor the DRL to meet its asserted ends, the court found that “limiting marriage to oppositesex couples likely to have children would require grossly intrusive inquiries, and arbitrary and unreliable line-drawing.”35 Accordingly, the plurality held that the DRL did not offend the New York equal protection clause since the challenged statute is rationally based.36 The plurality thus concluded its opinion, pausing to state its hope that “the participants in the controversy over same-sex marriage will address their arguments to the Legislature.”37 B. Judge Graffeo’s Concurrence Although Judge Graffeo concurred in the result reached by the plurality, she wrote separately to elaborate on the applicable standard of review.38 Judge G.B. Smith joined Judge Graffeo’s concurrence.39 Discussing plaintiffs’ due process argument first, Judge Graffeo gave a precedential explanation of the rationale for concluding that the fundamental right to marry cannot be extended to same-sex couples: neither the United States had identified the promotion of child welfare as a rational end of the DRL and found that “[a] person’s preference for the sort of sexual activity that cannot lead to the birth of children is relevant to the State’s interest.” Id. 31. Id. To be overinclusive, a law must “regulate[] individuals who are not similarly situated, that is, if [the law] covers more people than it needs to in order to accomplish its purpose.” ERWIN CHEMERINSKY, CONSTITUTIONAL LAW: PRINCIPLES AND POLICIES 660 (2d ed. 2002). On the other hand, a law is underinclusive if it “do[es] not regulate all who are similarly situated.” Id. at 659. 32. Hernandez, 855 N.E.2d at 11 (plurality opinion). 33. Id. 34. Id. 35. Id. at 11-12. 36. Id. at 12; see also supra notes 19-21 and accompanying text (discussing establishment of rational bases). 37. Hernandez, 855 N.E.2d at 12. 38. Id. at 13 (Graffeo, J., concurring). 39. Id. at 34. 1438 RUTGERS LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 38:1431 Supreme Court nor the New York Court of Appeals has considered the right to marry in any other way than the traditional, opposite-sex context.40 In the same vein, Judge Graffeo found that plaintiffs’ argument that Loving established the “right to marry the spouse of one’s choice” to be incorrect, as Loving was a decision singularly based on the need to avoid racial discrimination in laws governing marriage.41 Lastly, Judge Graffeo reiterated the plurality’s dismissal of plaintiffs’ Lawrence argument, distinguishing Lawrence from the case at bar and finding the two cases to be inapposite.42 Judge Graffeo then turned to plaintiffs’ equal protection claims and proceeded through her analysis in a manner substantially similar to the plurality, finding no gender discrimination within the classification created by the DRL.43 However, with regard to discrimination based on sexual orientation, Judge Graffeo applied a more pronounced analysis of the DRL 40. Id. at 14-15. (Graffeo, J., concurring). Judge Graffeo found explicit connections between the traditional definition of marriage and procreation. For support, she relied on federal precedent establishing that marriage is “‘fundamental to the very existence and survival of the [human] race.’” Id. at 15 (alteration in original) (quoting Skinner v. Oklahoma ex rel. Williamson, 316 U.S. 535, 541 (1942)). Judge Graffeo pointed out that the primacy of marriage is due to the fact that it is “the primary institution supporting procreation and childrearing.” Id. 41. Id. at 15-16. Judge Graffeo noted that while Loving, like Skinner, found the right to marriage to be fundamental, Loving held Virginia’s antimiscegenation statute to be unconstitutional because it discriminated on the basis of race. Id. at 16. Moreover, while the Loving Court did discuss the right of one to choose their spouse, such a right was framed within the need to avoid racial discrimination. Id. Loving held that “‘[t]he Fourteenth Amendment requires that the freedom of choice to marry not be restricted by invidious racial discriminations.’” Id. (alteration in original) (emphasis omitted) (quoting Loving v. Virginia, 388 U.S. 1, 12 (1967)). Judge Graffeo also criticized the two New York cases relied on by plaintiffs to suggest a gender-neutral definition of marriage, Crosby v. State Workers’ Compensation Board, 442 N.E.2d 1191, 1194 (N.Y. 1982), and People v. Shepard, 409 N.E.2d 840, 842 (N.Y. 1980). Judge Graffeo asserted that these cases “merely cite[] Loving when including marriage in a list of [fundamental] rights” without making any decisions regarding the marriage issue itself. Hernandez, 855 N.E.2d at 16 n.2 (Graffeo, J., concurring). 42. Hernandez, 855 N.E.2d at 17-18 (Graffeo, J., concurring). Unlike the plurality, which dealt with the distinction between rational and arbitrary line drawing, see supra note 24 and accompanying text, Judge Graffeo found Lawrence to be incomparable to plaintiffs’ case because “[t]he right affirmed by the Supreme Court in Lawrence is not comparable to the new right to marry plaintiffs assert here, nor is the Texas statute criminalizing homosexual sodomy analogous to the [sections of the DRL] under review.” Hernandez, 855 N.E.2d at 18 (Graffeo, J., concurring). 43. Id. at 19-20. Like the plurality, Judge Graffeo found that “neither men nor women are disproportionately disadvantaged or burdened by the fact that New York’s Domestic Relations Law allows only opposite-sex couples to marry.” Id. at 20. 2007] SAME SEX MARRIAGE: HERNANDEZ v. ROBLES 1439 as a purportedly neutral rule with disparate impact on lesbians and gays but, like the plurality, found no equal protection violation.44 Finally, Judge Graffeo agreed with the plurality that rational-basis review ought to be applied in order to uphold the constitutionality of the DRL.45 C. Chief Judge Kaye’s Dissent Chief Judge Kaye dissented, finding that the DRL denied plaintiffs their fundamental right to marriage and violated plaintiffs’ rights under the Equal Protection Clauses of the New York and Federal Constitutions.46 Utilizing New York precedent, Chief Judge Kaye found that the “right to marry the person of one’s choice” is “central” to the fundamental right of marriage.47 Because of the fundamental nature of the right of marriage, and the DRL’s denial thereof to plaintiffs, Chief Judge Kaye found that strict scrutiny should be applied and the state must prove that the infringement of plaintiffs’ fundamental rights is “narrowly tailored to achieve a compelling state interest.”48 However, Chief Judge Kaye found that the plurality improperly foreclosed that possibility by ruling that same-sex marriage is “not deeply rooted in tradition” and, as a result, cannot be considered a fundamental right.49 To this, Chief Judge Kaye responded that the plurality had engaged in 44. Id. at 20. Judge Graffeo found the DRL to be “facially neutral,” as people may seek marriage licenses regardless of their sexual orientation. Id. Furthermore, the DRL “create[s] a classification that distinguishes between opposite-sex and same-sex couples” and therefore has a disparate impact on homosexuals. Id. However, where no “invidious discriminatory intent” underlies the enactment of such a facially neutral statute, no equal protection claim may lie. Id. (citing Washington v. Davis, 426 U.S. 229, 240 (1976); Campaign for Fiscal Equity, Inc. v. State, 655 N.E.2d 661, 669 (N.Y. 1995)). With that, Judge Graffeo noted that “[p]laintiffs concede that the [DRL] was not enacted with an invidiously discriminatory intent – the legislature did not craft the marriage laws for the purpose of disadvantaging gays and lesbians.” Id. 45. Id. at 21-22. 46. Id. at 22 (Kaye, C.J., dissenting). 47. Id. at 22-23 (citing Crosby, 442 N.E.2d at 1194 (“[C]learly falling within [the individual’s right of privacy] are matters relating to the decision of whom one will marry . . . .”); People v. Shepard, 409 N.E.2d 840, 842 (N.Y. 1980) (“[T]he government has been prevented from interfering with an individual's decision about whom to marry . . . .”)). 48. Id. at 23 (citing Carey v. Population Servs. Int’l, 431 U.S. 678, 696 (1977)). 49. Id. at 23; cf. supra note 23 and accompanying text (discussing plurality’s history and tradition argument). Chief Judge Kaye rebutted the plurality’s conclusion that same-sex marriage is not “deeply rooted in tradition” and therefore cannot be considered a fundamental right because the plurality has too narrowly characterized the fundamental right at issue. Hernandez, 855 N.E.2d at 23 (Kaye, C.J., dissenting). Chief Judge Kaye noted that the plurality failed to heed the value of the United States Supreme Court’s reversal of its prior ban 1440 RUTGERS LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 38:1431 “‘circular reasoning’” by arguing that homosexuals must be excluded from marriage because the traditional definition of marriage demands such.50 Indeed, following Supreme Court precedent established in Loving, the fundamental right of marriage must be afforded even “to those whose exclusion from the right was ‘deeply rooted.’”51 Chief Judge Kaye asserted that in failing to recognize the fundamental nature of the liberty at stake, the plurality perpetuated a “constitutional wrong.”52 Turning to plaintiffs’ equal protection claims, Chief Judge Kaye found that the classification created by the DRL should be subjected to strict scrutiny for three reasons. First, homosexuals met the criteria for a suspect class, and as a result, the state must show that the DRL is narrowly tailored to meet a compelling state interest.53 Second, the DRL discriminated on the basis of sex because a woman may not marry another woman precisely “because she is not a man.”54 As a result, the state must show that the DRL is “substantially related to the achievement of important governmental objectives.”55 Third, and finally, because the DRL infringed on plaintiffs’ fundamental right to marry, the legislation must be defeated unless it is shown to narrowly meet compelling state interests.56 As such, Chief Judge Kaye found that the DRL would be invalidated under strict scrutiny, as of homosexual sodomy in Lawrence. Id. (“In narrowing the claimed liberty interest to embody the very exclusion being challenged, Bowers ‘disclose[d] the Court’s own failure to appreciate the extent of the liberty at stake.’” (alteration in original) (quoting Lawrence v. Texas, 539 U.S. 558, 567 (2003))). Just as “Lawrence rejected the notion that fundamental rights it had already identified could be restricted based on traditional assumptions about who should be permitted their protection,” the plurality has accepted that very notion. Id. at 24. 50. Hernandez, 855 N.E.2d at 26 (Kaye, C.J., dissenting) (quoting Halpern v. Toronto, [2003] 65 O.R.3d 161, 181 (Can. Ct. of App.)). Moreover, seeking to exclude individuals from the institution of marriage because those individuals have been traditionally excluded from that institution is “‘conclusory and bypasses the core question’” of whether or not such individuals may be rightfully excluded. Id. (quoting Goodridge v. Dep’t of Pub. Health, 798 N.E.2d 941, 972-73 (Mass. 2003) (Greany, J., concurring)). 51. Id. at 24. 52. Id. at 26. 53. Id. at 27. 54. Id. at 29. Chief Justice Kaye rebuked the plurality for its “equal application” argument that the DRL treats men and women equally in that neither may marry a member of their same sex. Id. (“‘[W]e reject the notion that the mere ‘equal application’ of a statute containing [discriminatory] classifications is enough to remove the classifications from the [constitutional] proscription of all invidious . . . discriminations . . . .’” (quoting Loving v. Virginia, 388 U.S. 1, 8 (1967) (alterations in original))); cf. supra note 28 and accompanying text (detailing the plurality’s equal application argument). 55. Hernandez, 855 N.E.2d at 29 (Kaye, C.J., dissenting). 56. Id. at 30. 2007] SAME SEX MARRIAGE: HERNANDEZ v. ROBLES 1441 defendants conceded that neither compelling nor important governmental interests existed for upholding the classification the DRL creates.57 In the alternative, Chief Judge Kaye found that rational-basis review must similarly lead to the defeat of the DRL since, of the purported interests asserted by the state and applied by the plurality, “none [was] rationally furthered by the exclusion of same-sex couples from marriage.”58 V. THE AUTHOR’S ANALYSIS Hernandez is a controversial case for at least two reasons. First, Hernandez represents New York’s contribution to the recent surge of samesex marriage cases in state high courts.59 Second, Hernandez took the familiar issue of the permissibility of same-sex marriage and disposed of it in an unsound way. It is this second reason on which the following analysis centers.60 The plurality’s opinion in Hernandez is unsound because the means by which the plurality made its decision leaves considerable room for discussion of better alternative means. A close examination of the rational bases that the plurality asserted in its highly deferential opinion shows the numerous flaws of this standard of review. At the same time, by its nature, rationality review 57. Id. at 27. 58. Id. at 30. Chief Judge Kaye reframed the plurality’s main question posed in applying rational-basis review as not whether the state has a rational or legitimate interest in supporting heterosexual marriage, but rather whether the state has a rational basis for prohibiting homosexuals from marrying. Id. 59. See, e.g., Standhardt v. Superior Court, 77 P.3d 451, 465 (Ariz. Ct. App. 2003) (upholding statutory ban on same-sex marriages); In re Marriage Cases, 49 Cal.Rptr.3d 675, 686 (Cal. Ct. App. 2006), review granted, 149 P.3d 737 (Cal. 2006); Baehr v. Lewin, 852 P.2d 44, 67 (Haw. 1993) (holding statutory ban on same-sex marriage unconstitutional qua sex discrimination under equal protection analysis); Goodridge v. Dep’t of Pub. Health, 798 N.E.2d 941, 948 (Mass. 2003) (holding limitation of marriage benefits to opposite-sex couples to be unconstitutional); Lewis v. Harris, 908 A.2d 196, 200 (N.J. 2006) (holding statutory ban of same-sex marriage to be unconstitutional); Baker v. State, 744 A.2d 864, 867 (Vt. 1999) (holding statutory ban of same-sex marriage unconstitutional under common benefits clause of state constitution); Andersen v. King County, 138 P.3d 963, 968 (Wash. 2006) (upholding constitutionality of statutory ban of same-sex marriage); see also 1 U.S.C. §7 (2000) (“Defense of Marriage Act”) (“‘[M]arriage’ means only a legal union between one man and one woman as husband and wife, and the word ‘spouse’ refers only to a person of the opposite sex who is a husband or a wife.”); 28 U.S.C. § 1738C (“Defense of Marriage Act”) (allowing states to disavow same-sex marriages consummated in other states). 60. Instead of assessing the broader debate, this Comment explores the various analytical pathways that are available to courts considering the same-sex marriage question and the extent to which the Hernandez plurality correctly traversed those pathways. 1442 RUTGERS LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 38:1431 turns a blind eye to all contrary arguments, such as plaintiffs’ arguments in Hernandez. A. Soundness of the Plurality’s Opinion There are three major areas of weakness in the plurality’s opinion: (1) the plurality’s decision to employ rational-basis review before considering plaintiffs’ fundamental rights and equal protection arguments; (2) its failure to consider alternatives to the history and tradition argument in locating fundamental rights; and (3) its wooden, formalistic understanding of what constitutes discrimination under equal protection jurisprudence. 1. Choice of Standard of Review The plurality’s heavy reliance upon rational-basis review is immediately apparent from the very beginning of its opinion. The plurality began by locating rational bases to uphold the challenged sections of the DRL and, having established such, found that “[o]ur conclusion that there is a rationalbasis for limiting marriage to opposite-sex couples leads us to hold that that limitation is valid under the New York [d]ue [p]rocess and [e]qual [p]rotection clauses.”61 With this statement, the plurality seems to have misunderstood, or at least inaccurately represented, the Supreme Court’s famous logic expressed in United States v. Carolene Products Co.62 In laying the groundwork for the application of the varying levels of judicial scrutiny available, the Carolene Court implied that judges must first determine if heightened scrutiny ought to be applied before simply deferring to the legislature.63 The plurality failed to so much as reference the alternatives to the rational-basis test before framing the main issue as “whether a rational legislature” could limit marriage to opposite-sex couples.64 Though the plurality later considered and rejected the availability of heightened and intermediate scrutiny via due process and equal protection considerations, its early and seemingly exclusive reliance upon the rational-basis standard 61. Hernandez, 855 N.E.2d at 9 (plurality opinion). 62. 304 U.S. 144, 152 n.4 (1938) (holding that a “more searching judicial inquiry” ought to be deployed when the challenged statute interferes with individual rights, restricts the operation of the political process or discriminates against “discrete and insular minorities”). 63. Id. 64. Hernandez, 855 N.E.2d at 7 (plurality opinion). 2007] SAME SEX MARRIAGE: HERNANDEZ v. ROBLES 1443 belies whatever thoughtful deliberation upon the proper standard of review the plurality employed.65 Even assuming rationality review is the correct standard of review in this case, the plurality’s asserted rational bases66 do not pass minimum rationality’s muster. First, the rational bases asserted by the plurality do not rationally promote child welfare. Instead, denying to same-sex couples who raise children the numerous rights and benefits that come with a legally recognized marriage disadvantages their children.67 Second, the plurality’s asserted rational bases do not further the state’s interest in encouraging procreation within marriage. It is well established that a requirement of procreation in marriage cannot pass rational-basis review.68 Finally, it is 65. Perhaps Judge Graffeo, in concurring only in the result that the plurality reached, considered the plurality’s hasty deployment of rational-basis review as a sign of analytical impropriety. To this possible end, Judge Graffeo noted that the primary purpose of her concurrence was to properly determine the “level of constitutional review” to be applied in this case. Id. at 12 (Graffeo, J., concurring). Furthermore, Judge Graffeo, before settling on the application of rational-basis scrutiny, first methodically ruled out the application of heightened and intermediate scrutiny, in accordance with the dictates of Carolene Products. Id. at 14-20. 66. All of the plurality’s legitimate interests include the welfare of children. The essence of these interests is the notion that unmarried opposite-sex couples who are pregnant or contemplating becoming pregnant and married opposite-sex couples who already have children deserve some sort of incentive to become or remain legally obligated to each other via the institution of marriage. See supra notes 19-21 for a more detailed description of the plurality’s rational bases. 67. The plurality itself noted that some 316 separate benefits are conferred to married individuals. Hernandez, 855 N.E.2d at 6 (plurality opinion). To this, Chief Judge Kaye considered the “tens of thousands” of children being raised by same-sex couples in New York and concluded that prohibiting their same-sex parents from marrying actually undermines their welfare. Id. at 32 (Kaye, C.J., dissenting). Chief Judge Kaye pointed out that the Court of Appeals has considered the same premise and ruled against it when holding that unmarried, same-sex partners may adopt each others’ children. Id. (citing In re Jacob, 660 N.E.2d 397, 398 (N.Y. 1995) (“To rule otherwise would mean that the thousands of New York children actually being raised in homes headed by two unmarried persons could have only one legal parent, not the two who want them.”)). An accurate count of exactly how many same-sex couples are raising children in New York or the United States is hard to come by. However, estimates of same-sex households raising children in the United States range from one to five million. See WILLIAM N. ESKRIDGE JR., EQUALITY PRACTICE: CIVIL UNIONS AND THE FUTURE OF GAY RIGHTS xi (2002). 68. Chief Judge Kaye found that “the ability or desire to procreate is not a prerequisite for marriage.” Hernandez, 855 N.E.2d at 30 (Kaye, C.J., dissenting). As Chief Judge Kaye pointed out, even Justice Scalia has agreed that rational-basis review of legislation denying marriage to gay and lesbian couples is not served by a procreative argument. Id. As he dissented in Lawrence “what justification could there possibly be for denying the benefits of marriage to homosexual couples exercising the liberty protected by the Constitution? Surely 1444 RUTGERS LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 38:1431 improper to suggest, as the plurality does, that the state could rationally favor heterosexual parents over homosexual parents. A state preference of heterosexual parents over homosexual parents would be a “flagrant” equal protection violation as it would acknowledge “purposeful discrimination” and the preference would stand contrary to the legislative policy of New York.69 Thus, even though the plurality correctly held that the New York equal protection clause is “‘no broader in coverage than the Federal provision,’”70 the plurality structured its rational-basis review in a way that undermines federal precedent.71 2. The Fundamental Right of (Same-Sex?) Marriage The right to marriage is recognized as a fundamental right in New York.72 The Hernandez plurality, in denying plaintiffs the due process relief not the encouragement of procreation, since the sterile and the elderly are allowed to marry.” Lawrence v. Texas, 539 U.S. 558, 605 (2003) (Scalia, J., dissenting) (internal quotations omitted). 69. Hernandez, 855 N.E.2d at 32 (Kaye, C.J., dissenting) (citing N.Y. COMP. CODES R. & REGS. tit. 18, § 421.16(h)(2) (2006) (stating that applicants for adoption “shall not be rejected solely on the basis of homosexuality”)). Judge Graffeo, based on her analysis of discriminatory intent, see supra note 44 and accompanying text, would likely agree that such a preference for opposite-sex parents, if actually articulated by the legislature, would fail judicial review under the equal protection clause. 70. Hernandez, 855 N.E.2d at 9 (plurality opinion) (quoting Under 21 v. City of New York, 482 N.E.2d 1, 7 n.6 (N.Y. 1985)). 71. The plurality’s only proffered explanation as to how limiting marriage to oppositesex couples actually benefits children is severely underinclusive: the welfare of those children who are conceived in some manner other than heterosexual intercourse is neglected. Similarly, the welfare of those children who are heterosexually conceived but adopted by a homosexual couple is neglected. The plurality felt confident that the state’s conscious efforts to undermine the welfare of these children is acceptable, simply because the “legislature could rationally proceed on the commonsense premise that children will do best with a mother and father in the home.” Id. at 8 (citing Goodridge v. Dep’t of Pub. Health, 798 N.E.2d 941, 979-980 (Mass. 2003) (Sosman, J., dissenting)). For an interesting critique of the application of state high court rationality review upon positive grants of rights to individuals, see Helen Hershkoff, Positive Rights and State Constitutions: The Limits of Federal Rationality Review, 112 HARV. L. REV. 1131, 1169 (1999). Of course, the idea that marriage is a positive right is a topic beyond the scope of this analysis, however, for a theory that places marriage well within the context of positive grants of rights, see generally NANCY F. COTT, PUBLIC VOWS: A HISTORY OF MARRIAGE AND THE NATION 200-27 (2000). 72. See Crosby v. State Workers’ Comp. Bd., 442 N.E.2d 1191, 1194 (N.Y. 1982) (“[C]learly falling within [the constitutional right to privacy] are matters relating to the decision of whom one will marry. . . .”). 2007] SAME SEX MARRIAGE: HERNANDEZ v. ROBLES 1445 that they sought, 73 refused to locate the right of same-sex marriage as within the fundamental right of marriage.74 The reasoning employed by the plurality to reach this conclusion is unsound because the plurality quickly and unpersuasively concluded that plaintiffs’ arguments to the contrary were without merit. The plurality correctly noted that the existence of a fundamental right is predicated on that liberty being “‘deeply rooted in this Nation’s history and tradition.’”75 However, the plurality then concluded that “[t]he right to marry someone of the same sex . . . is not deeply rooted” simply because such a right has only been asserted recently.76 The plurality then went on to discuss its choice to narrowly define the right at stake as “[t]he right to marry someone of the same sex” with no further discussion of the critical lack of deep roots of the liberty that plaintiffs seek. 77 While deep roots of an asserted liberty are helpful in locating a fundamental right, they are not dispositive of the existence of such a right. For example, in Lawrence, the Supreme Court noted that “[h]istory and tradition are the starting point but not in all cases the ending point of the 73. Reply Brief for Plaintiffs-Appellants at 9, Hernandez v. Robles, 855 N.E.2d 1 (N.Y. 2006) (No. 103434/04) (“Plaintiffs seek to exercise a right this Court has already recognized: the fundamental right to marry the person of one’s choice, free from unwarranted government interference.”). 74. See supra notes 22-24 and accompanying text. 75. Hernandez, 855 N.E.2d at 9 (plurality opinion) (quoting Washington v. Glucksburg, 521 U.S. 702, 721 (1997)). 76. Id. (citation and internal quotations omitted). The plurality did properly acknowledge that New York courts have, at times, been more protective of substantive due process rights guaranteed by the New York State constitution than the federal courts have been with the “federal counterpart.” Id. The plurality qualified its assertion by pointing out that New York has only adopted a more liberal reading of its due process clause in cases regarding criminal defendants or prisoners. Id. 77. Id. The Hernandez dissent believed that the plurality made the same mistake that the U.S. Supreme Court made in Bowers, only to later chastise itself in Lawrence for “‘fail[ing] to appreciate the extent of the liberty at stake.’” Id. at 23 (Kaye, C.J., dissenting) (quoting Lawrence v. Texas, 539 U.S. 558, 567 (2003)). According to the dissent, Bowers “narrow[ed] the claimed liberty interest to embody the very exclusion being challenged.” Id. The Supreme Court has warned against excessively narrow interpretations of substantive due process in the past. See id. at 23-24 (citing Planned Parenthood of Se. Pa. v. Casey, 505 U.S. 833, 847 (1992) (“It is also tempting . . . to suppose that the Due Process Clause protects only those practices, defined at the most specific level, that were protected against government interference by other rules of law when the Fourteenth Amendment was ratified. But such a view would be inconsistent with our law.” (citations omitted))). 1446 RUTGERS LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 38:1431 substantive due process inquiry.”78 The reason for this crucial limitation on the probative value of history and tradition is simply that, as times change, the liberties seen as fundamental may change as well.79 In recognition of this, Chief Judge Kaye, in dissent, noted that various groups have been granted fundamental rights despite their historical exclusion from enjoying those very liberties.80 To wit, plaintiffs in Loving were historically excluded from the fundamental right of marriage because of the Virginia antimiscegenation statute in place, yet the Supreme Court did not hesitate to uphold plaintiffs’ asserted right to marriage as fundamental.81 78. Lawrence, 539 U.S at 572 (quoting County of Sacramento v. Lewis, 523 U.S. 833, 857 (1998) (Kennedy, J., concurring)). 79. See, e.g., id. at 579 (“[T]imes can blind us to certain truths and later generations can see that laws once thought necessary and proper in fact serve only to oppress.”); City of Cleburne v. Cleburne Living Ctr., 473 U.S. 432, 466 (1985) (Marshall, J., concurring) (“[W]hat once was a natural and self-evident ordering later comes to be seen as an artificial and invidious constraint on human potential and freedom.” (citation and internal quotations omitted)). 80. New York, in contexts other than marriage, has granted due process rights to groups that had traditionally been excluded from them. See Hernandez, 855 N.E.2d. at 24 n.1 (Kaye, C.J., dissenting) (citing In re Raquel Marie X., 559 N.E.2d 418, 419 (N.Y. 1990) (granting child custody rights to unwed fathers, despite the traditional exclusion of the practice); Rivers v. Katz, 495 N.E.2d 337, 342-43 (N.Y. 1986) (granting the mentally disabled the right to refuse medical treatment, despite the traditional exclusion of the practice)). See also PETER J. GALIE, THE NEW YORK STATE CONSTITUTION: A REFERENCE GUIDE 49 (1991) (discussing New York Court of Appeals precedent holding “broader” range of due process protections than those protected under the Federal Constitution). 81. Chief Judge Kaye ultimately concluded that “even though it was the ban on interracial marriage—not interracial marriage itself—that had a long and shameful national tradition, the Supreme Court determined [in Loving] that interracial couples could not be deprived of their fundamental right to marry.” Hernandez, 855 N.E.2d at 25 (Kaye, C.J., dissenting). In contrast to the plurality, Chief Judge Kaye contended that Loving’s holding is not confined to race discrimination. Id. The Court in Loving overturned Virginia’s antimiscegenation law not only because race is a suspect class, but also because the law in question infringed on the Lovings’ fundamental right to marry. Id. Here, Chief Judge Kaye cited the United States Supreme Court’s decision in Zablocki v. Redhail, noting that the Court’s opinion in Loving “could have rested solely on the ground that the statutes discriminated on the basis of race in violation of the Equal Protection Clause. But the Court went on to hold that the laws arbitrarily deprived the couple of a fundamental liberty protected by the Due Process Clause, the freedom to marry.” Id. (quoting Zablocki v. Redhail, 434 U.S. 374, 383 (1978)); see also Carlos A. Ball, The Positive in the Fundamental Right to Marry: Same-Sex Marriage in the Aftermath of Lawrence v. Texas, 88 MINN. L. REV. 1184, 1223-31 (2004) (providing a detailed argument as 2007] SAME SEX MARRIAGE: HERNANDEZ v. ROBLES 1447 3. The Plurality’s Equal Protection Analysis a. Discrimination Based on Sexual Orientation The plurality employed unsound reasoning in finding that the DRL fostered no impermissible discrimination based on sexual orientation. While there has been neither a Supreme Court82 nor a New York Court of Appeals83 decision as to what level of scrutiny, other than rational-basis review, should apply in cases alleging discrimination based on sexual orientation, the plurality recognized that the DRL “does confer advantages on the basis of sexual preference.”84 The plurality’s sole justification in not granting homosexuals strict scrutiny under the DRL was that rational-basis scrutiny is appropriate where individuals classified by a statute “‘have distinguishing characteristics relevant to interests the State has the authority to implement.’”85 This justification is based on precedent that is arguably inapposite to the case under review.86 to the faults of the history and tradition justification often used to defeat due process challenges to same-sex marriage). 82. In Romer v. Evans, the United States Supreme Court invalidated a Colorado law that repealed all state legislation outlawing discrimination against homosexuals utilizing rationalbasis review. 517 U.S. 620, 635 (1996). However, the Court has not yet considered the issue of whether classifications based on homosexuality ought to be subject to heightened or, in the alternative, intermediate scrutiny. 83. See supra note 29. 84. Hernandez, 855 N.E.2d at 11 (plurality opinion). 85. Id. (quoting City of Cleburne v. Cleburne Living Ctr., 473 U.S. 432, 441 (1985)). 86. The plurality’s reliance upon Cleburne was misplaced because Cleburne, in finding that rationality review ought to apply to a statute governing a classification over which the state has relevant regulatory authority, referred to the Court’s prior holding in Massachusetts Board of Retirement v. Murgia, 427 U.S. 307 (1976). In Murgia, the Court held that rationalbasis review of age classifications was permissible because those subject to age classifications have not “been discriminated against on the basis of race or national origin, have not experienced a ‘history of purposeful unequal treatment’ or been subjected to unique disabilities on the basis of stereotyped characteristics not truly indicative of their abilities.” Id. at 313. However, homosexuals have historically experienced discrimination based on inaccurate stereotypes. See, e.g., infra note 87 (discussing the New York Legislature’s finding of purposeful discrimination against homosexuals in passing the Sexual Orientation Non Discrimination Act (“SONDA”)). Even the plurality admitted to the dearth of conclusive scientific evidence on the abilities of same-sex couples to raise children. Hernandez, 855 N.E.2d at 8 (plurality opinion). Therefore, the “authority” that the plurality afforded the state to maintain the DRL’s sexual orientation classifications is based on nothing more than stereotypical knowledge, not truly indicative of the relevant abilities of same-sex couples. 1448 RUTGERS LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 38:1431 The three-part analysis for locating a suspect class suggested by Chief Judge Kaye87 presents a sturdy counterargument to the plurality. The threestep inquiry, though not attributed with precedential backing in her opinion, has been recognized by federal courts.88 Moreover, plaintiffs, in their moving papers, argued for the application of this same three-step inquiry.89 The plurality’s unwillingness to address plaintiffs’ concerns is certainly problematic, but the plurality’s ability to apply the three-step inquiry was undermined by its exclusive reliance upon Cleburne.90 b. Discrimination Based on Sex In concluding that the DRL is free of sex discrimination, the plurality ignored all but the most abstract, formal notions of equality. To find, as the 87. Hernandez, 855 N.E.2d at 27-28 (Kaye, C.J., dissenting). Chief Judge Kaye identified three criteria used by the Supreme Court to determine whether a group marginalized by a legislative classification should be deemed a suspect class. Id. The first criterion was whether the group has been the subject of “purposeful discrimination.” Id. Here, Chief Judge Kaye considered the New York Legislature’s passage of the SONDA as evidence of such discrimination and referred specifically to the legislature’s findings that “‘many residents of this state have encountered prejudice on account of their sexual orientation.’” Id. (citation omitted). The second criterion was “whether the trait used to define the class is unrelated to the ability to perform and participate in society.” Id. Chief Judge Kaye found one’s sexual orientation to be “obviously” irrelevant to one’s ability to participate in society. Id. The third and final criterion was “the group’s relative political powerlessness.” Id. Chief Judge Kaye was not persuaded by defendants’ argument that the passage of SONDA evidences the relative political power of homosexuals. Id. Chief Judge Kaye noted that not only did SONDA repeatedly fail on the floor of the legislature for thirty-one years following its introduction in 1971, but the passage of antidiscrimination legislation has traditionally signaled the precise need for the application of heightened scrutiny. Id. 88. See, e.g., Steffan v. Cheney, 780 F. Supp. 1, 5 (D.D.C. 1991) (citing Bowen v. Gilliard, 483 U.S. 587, 602-03 (1987)) (holding that a suspect class is manifest if members of a group: “1) have suffered a history of discrimination; 2) exhibit obvious, immutable, or distinguishing characteristics that define him as a member of a discrete group; and 3) show that the group is a minority or politically powerless, or alternatively show that the statutory classification at issue burdens a fundamental right.”), rev’d on other grounds sub nom. Steffan v. Perry, 41 F.3d 677 (D.C. Cir. 1994). 89. See Reply Brief for Plaintiffs-Appellants at 37-38, Hernandez v. Robles, 855 N.E.2d 1 (N.Y. 2006) (No. 103434/04) (arguing for application of the three-criteria approach for finding a suspect class). Plaintiffs argued for the application of the identical three-criteria approach as it was articulated in San Antonio Independent School District v. Rodriguez, 411 U.S. 1, 28 (1973). Reply Brief for Plaintiffs-Appellants, supra, at 37-38. 90. See supra notes 85-86. For a detailed application of the three-factor test concluding that homosexuals are a suspect class, see generally Eric A. Roberts, Note, Heightened Scrutiny Under the Equal Protection Clause: A Remedy to Discrimination Based on Sexual Orientation, 42 DRAKE L. REV. 485, 493-510 (1993). 2007] SAME SEX MARRIAGE: HERNANDEZ v. ROBLES 1449 plurality did, no incidence of discrimination based on sex simply because both gay men and lesbians are equally prohibited from marrying their respective same-sex partners is not sound. Such a finding failed to address the reality that a woman cannot marry another woman precisely because she is a woman and a man cannot marry another man because he is a man. As Chief Judge Kaye asserted in her dissent, the plurality’s reliance on such an “equal application” argument is improper according to Loving.91 If the plurality were to employ the intermediate scrutiny standard that is constitutionally required for evaluating sex classifications, the DRL could not be upheld.92 B. The Implications of the Plurality’s Decision Hernandez affects the ability of future New York cases to be decided based on compelling policy rationales because the plurality established an extremely high threshold of irrationality, which is not likely to be met by all but the most conclusive policy evidence. In upholding the constitutionality of the classification created by the DRL, the plurality found that empirical studies “do not establish beyond doubt that children fare equally well in same-sex and opposite-sex households.”93 The plurality conceded that these same empirical studies contain “limited observation” that concludes that there are “no marked differences” between children of same-sex and 91. See supra note 54 and accompanying text. In his dissent at the appellate level, Judge Saxe noted the similarities between the logic of Loving and the need to apply similar reasoning to the case at bar. See Hernandez v. Robles, 805 N.Y.S.2d 354, 385 (N.Y. App. Div. 2005) (Saxe, J., dissenting) (“That the law equally denies both sexes the right to marry one of their own gender does not remove it from the category of gender discrimination, just as equally denying members of different races the right to marry someone of another race is still race discrimination.”), aff’d, 855 N.E.2d 1 (N.Y. 2006). 92. In United States v. Virginia, 518 U.S. 515 (1996), the Supreme Court articulated the intermediate scrutiny standard of review as it applies to sex segregation. There, the Court held that the actual purpose of the policy of excluding women from admission to Virginia Military Institute was discriminatory to women in general. Id. at 534. To uphold such a practice, the government was required to show, in an “exceedingly persuasive” manner, that a gender neutral admissions policy would not work as well as the male-only admissions policy. Id. at 533. Because the government did not meet this burden, the male-only admissions policy was found to violate the equal protection clause. Id. at 534. With regard to Hernandez, if the intermediate scrutiny standard were applied to the DRL, plaintiffs would prevail as defendants have not met or exceeded the “exceedingly persuasive” threshold. For a critical assessment of the prevalence of sex discrimination in same-sex marriage cases, see Andrew Koppelman, Why Discrimination Against Lesbians and Gay Men is Sex Discrimination, 69 N.Y.U. L. REV. 197, 208-214 (1994). 93. Hernandez v. Robles, 855 N.E.2d 1, 8 (N.Y. 2006). 1450 RUTGERS LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 38:1431 opposite-sex households.94 However, the finding of a lack of differences is not nearly as persuasive as the “conclusive scientific evidence” that the plurality requires.95 Rationality review, by its nature, must dispense with counterarguments, deferring the wisdom required to choose between the divergent arguments to the legislature. Furthermore, as the plurality notes, the legal standard that applies to rational-basis review in New York casts rationality review as “‘a paradigm of judicial restraint.’”96 However, by refusing to consider compelling evidence that strongly suggests the irrationality of the classification created by the DRL, the plurality has raised the bar of irrationality to one which insists upon only the most conclusive, objectively verifiable data. VI. CONCLUSION In Hernandez v. Robles, the New York Court of Appeals stopped the progression of same-sex marriage equality in the New York courts dead in its tracks. By refusing to acknowledge compelling substantive due process, equal protection and policy arguments that mandate the formal recognition of marriage equality for same-sex couples, the plurality maintained the DRL’s implicit and explicit prohibition of same-sex marriage. In so doing, the plurality overlooked numerous arguments, the discussion and thoughtful 94. Id. 95. Id. It is difficult to conceive of a policy argument with the evidentiary integrity to overcome the plurality’s deferential standard. Indeed, the plurality was not persuaded by the assertion by the American Psychological Association, the American Psychiatric Association and the New York State Psychiatric Association that “there is no scientific basis for concluding that gay and lesbian parents are any less fit or capable than heterosexual parents, or that their children are any less psychologically healthy and well adjusted.” Brief of American Psychological Ass’n, American Psychiatric Ass’n, & New York State Psychiatric Ass’n as Amici Curiae at 34, Hernandez v. Robles, 855 N.E.2d 1 (N.Y. 2006) (No. 103434/04), available at http://data.lambdalegal.org/pdf/645.pdf. 96. Hernandez, 855 N.E.2d at 12 (plurality opinion) (quoting Affronti v. Crosson, 746 N.E.2d 1049 (N.Y. 2001)). In dissent, Chief Judge Kaye raised an interesting threshold point that revealed a crucial oversight of the plurality’s rationality review. Chief Judge Kaye noted that “equal protection requires that it be the legislated distinction [or classification] that furthers a legitimate state interest, not the discriminatory law itself.” Id. at 30 (Kaye, C.J., dissenting). Chief Judge Kaye proceeded to note that “no one rationally decides to have children because gays and lesbians are excluded from marriage.” Id. at 31. Perhaps this is true, however, the plurality’s deferential standard of review allows it to conclude that the legislature could rationally disagree with Chief Judge Kaye, placing the plurality and dissent at loggerheads. 2007] SAME SEX MARRIAGE: HERNANDEZ v. ROBLES 1451 disposition of which would have substantially increased the soundness of its opinion. In the absence of such a thorough analysis, the New York Court of Appeals undermined plaintiffs’ liberty and equality rights. Furthermore, the Hernandez ruling suggests that rationality review in New York requires highly probative, conclusive policy data to overcome the judicial presumption of rationality.