Feature 34 Singapore Law Gazette Awards 2015 – Best Feature Article The High Court in the recent case of PP v Hue An Li held that for an offence of negligent act causing death under section 304A(b) of the Penal Code, in a road traffic case, the benchmark sentence will be increased from a fine, to a custodial term of up to four weeks. This note examines the court’s reasoning in increasing the benchmark, and briefly discusses the uncertainties in the application and scope of the new benchmark. Jail Term as New Benchmark Sentence for Careless Driving Causing Death – PP v Hue An Li: A Case Commentary This case note assesses the Court’s reasoning in increasing the benchmark sentence, and argues that the express justification relied on by the Court for the increase is, with respect, problematic in several ways. Fortunately, the Court did allude, albeit only in quick passing, to what is a more satisfactory justification – the need to effect general deterrence – for the increase. This note will then more fully explore this justification. Finally, some uncertainties in the application and scope of the new benchmark will be briefly discussed. To be sure, the Court in Hue also touched on other pertinent issues such as the distinction between rashness and negligence in the context of s 304A,5 the aggravating factors applicable to s 304A(b) traffic death cases (eg sleepy driving),6 and when prospective overruling may be justified.7 The Court’s comments on these issues certainly also make for extremely appetizing food for thought, but remain outside the scope of this note. Introduction The recent Magistrate’s Appeal case of PP v Hue An Li (“Hue”)1 is by many measures a landmark decision in Singapore’s criminal law jurisprudence. Inter alia, the High Court pronounced that for an offence of negligent act causing death under s 304A(b) of the Penal Code (“PC”),2 in a road traffic case, the benchmark of a fine – a tariff that prevailed for over twenty years in Singapore – will no longer apply. Instead, the new starting point for such an offence will be a brief imprisonment term of up to four weeks.3 Such a critical change will no doubt impact a number of criminal practitioners as the offence is not infrequently encountered in practice, and will also be of interest to many of us who drive in our day-to-day lives. The significance of the decision is underscored by the fact that Hue was heard by a specially constituted three-member High Court bench, led by the Chief Justice,4 and an amicus curiae had to be additionally appointed to assist the bench. The material facts of Hue are these: the accused, while travelling in her motorcar along the Pan-Island Expressway, tried to overtake a lorry on her left that was transporting nine passengers in its rear cabin. While overtaking, the accused’s car gradually veered left before its front left collided into the right rear of the lorry. The collision caused the lorry to rotate, hit a barricade and flip. The nine passengers were thrown out of the vehicle, leaving eight injured, and one dead. The lorry driver and his front passenger were also injured. In the accused’s mitigation, it was submitted that the collision occurred as the accused “blanked out due to her tired mental state”.8 The accused pleaded guilty to a charge under s 304A(b) of the PC and consented to having two other charges (one count of negligent act causing grievous hurt under s 338(b) of the PC and one count of negligent act causing hurt under s 337(b) of the PC) taken into consideration in sentencing. At first instance, she was sentenced to a fine of $10,000 and was disqualified from Singapore Law Gazette December 2014 35 driving for five years. The Public Prosecutor then appealed on the basis that a custodial term should have been imposed. The High Court allowed the appeal and increased the punishment to four weeks’ imprisonment (with the fine amount refunded). The five-year disqualification period was not disturbed. Analysis of the Court’s Justification for Increasing the Benchmark At the outset, it is pertinent to point out that determining the benchmark sentence, or indeed the sentence in any particular case involving negligent act causing death, is probably one of the toughest and most morally complex task a sentencer can encounter. In my view, this is because for this offence, the usual two main sentencing considerations, extent of harm and culpability of the offender,9 are at complete opposite ends of their respective spectrums.10 On the one hand, the offence will involve (at least) a death, indubitably the most severe form of harm anyone can inflict to another. On the other hand, in terms of mens rea, the offender was merely negligent, the least serious form of culpability (relative to rashness, knowledge and intention). Those who place more weight on an offender’s culpability may feel that at most a high fine is justified as punishment, as although a life was lost, it was attributable only to the offender’s carelessness. Those, in particular the victim’s next-of-kin, who focus more on the consequence caused will feel that a harsher punishment should be imposed, because regardless of the offender’s state of mind, a precious life was lost. There is, however, no helpful guidance on whether in such a situation, one should accord more weight to the former or latter sentencing consideration. Dissecting the Court’s Reasoning How then did the High Court in Hue resolve this challenging tension?11 It first noted that the prevailing benchmark was set out over two decades ago in PP v Gan Lim Soon (“Gan”).12 In that case, Yong CJ (as he then was) held that in a case of rash driving causing death (under s 304A(a) of the PC), an imprisonment term is generally imposed, whereas in a case of negligent driving causing death, “it would be sufficient in most cases to inflict a fine”.13 The Court noted that Gan was decided prior to the 2008 amendments to the PC, where s 304A read:14 Whoever causes the death of any person by doing any rash or negligent act not amounting to culpable homicide, shall be punished with imprisonment for a term which may extend to 2 years, or with fine, or with both. Feature Following the 2008 amendments, s 304A now reads: Whoever causes the death of any person by doing any rash or negligent act not amounting to culpable homicide shall be punished – a) In the case of a rash act, with imprisonment for a term which may extend to 5 years, or with fine, or with both; or b) In the case of a negligent act, with imprisonment for a term which may extend to 2 years, or with fine, or with both, The Court then cited PP v Kwong Kok Hing (“Kwong”),15 where the Court of Appeal held that: (i) a sentence close to or at the statutory maximum would be imposed for conduct that was amongst the worst conceivable for that particular offence; and (ii) it was incumbent on a sentencing Court to take note of the statutory maximum and determine precisely where a particular offender’s conduct fell within the spectrum of punishment devised by Parliament. Extrapolating from this, the Court opined that “the default punitive position for a particular offence must be determined with reference to the punishment at the two ends of the spectrum”.16 Given that the two ends for an offence under s 304A(b) of the PC are, respectively, two years’ imprisonment and a nominal fine, two possible approximate midpoints are: a large fine, and a brief period of incarceration. Crucially, the Court went on to reason that:17 It seems clear to us that following the 2008 Penal Code amendments, the positon laid down in Gan Lim Soon is no longer tenable, given the bifurcation of the old s 304A into two limbs. Parliament could have chosen to retain the language of the old s 304A and to merely increase the statutory maximum term of imprisonment to five years. That would have left the Gan Lim Soon position untouched. Instead, Parliament chose to bifurcate the old s 304A and make it clear that causing death by negligence and causing death by rashness would each have its own sentencing range. In the premises, we are satisfied that the starting point for sentencing in a s 304A(b) traffic death case is a brief period of incarceration for up to four weeks. The above appears to be the Court’s only explicit grounds to justify the monumental increase18 in the benchmark from a fine (as expounded in Gan) to a custodial term of up to four weeks. The Court’s subsequent comments as regards “The amount of harm caused”, “Special classes of vulnerable victims”, “Speeding”, “Impaired judgment: drink-driving” Singapore Law Gazette December 2014 Feature 36 and “Impaired judgment: sleepy driving”19 seek to explain whether these qualify as aggravating factors in sentencing a s 304A(b) offender, and do not seem to relate to justifying the increase in the benchmark sentence. Careful reading of the Court’s explicit grounds reveals that there is a leap in its logic. It cannot be that simply because Parliament decided that causing death by negligence and causing death by rashness are now to have separate sentencing ranges, Parliament therefore also intended that the benchmark for the former offence be increased from a fine to a brief custodial term. A best estimate of the Court’s implicit reasoning must thus be something along the lines of: a) Prior to the 2008 amendments, the maximum penalty for causing death by negligence was in effect less than two years’ imprisonment, since negligence shared the same punishment provision as its rashness counterpart and negligence is less serious than rashness. After the amendments, the maximum penalty for causing death by negligence was increased to a clear two years’ imprisonment. b) Prior to the 2008 amendments, the prevailing benchmark for causing death by negligent act as expounded in Gan was a mere fine. c) Because after the 2008 amendments the maximum penalty for causing death by negligence was increased from less than two years to two years’ imprisonment, Parliament therefore also intended for the previous benchmark of a fine, to be increased to a short custodial term. Problems with the Court’s Reasoning Dissecting in this manner the Court’s underlying premises reveals the problems in the reasoning. Preliminarily, in relation to strand (a), on a plain reading of s 304A pre-2008 amendment, the statutory maximums of both causing death by negligence and rashness were two years’ imprisonment. While the Courts may have thought that when two mens rea share the same punishment provision, the less serious mens rea is to have a lower maximum penalty than is expressly stated, there is no evidence that in making the amendments in 2008, Parliament adopted that same position and proceeded on the assumption that the previous effective maximum penalty for causing death by negligence was less than two years’ imprisonment.20 If the previous maximum penalty for causing death by negligence is two years’ imprisonment and that is still the case after the 2008 amendments, strand (c) does not follow. Even if we accept that Parliament had treated the maximum penalty for causing death by negligence prior to the amendments as less than two years’ imprisonment, strand (c) itself remains problematic as it flies against the express intention of Parliament in effecting the 2008 amendments to the PC. In the debates, one Member of Parliament, Mr Lim Biow Chuan, sought affirmation that by amending the range of penalties prescribed in the PC, “the intention of Parliament is not for the judges to automatically increase the punishment nor should the courts interpret the setting of a higher limit to mean that the crime has become more serious”.21 To this, the Senior Minister of State for Home Affairs’ (Assoc Prof Ho Peng Kee) categorical response was:22 … we must leave it to the courts to mete out punishment … Mr Lim Biow Chuan asks whether what we have done will lead automatically to fines or punishments going up. I do not think so. He has mentioned, for example, the benchmarks, the sentencing guidelines, that the courts have. I think the guidelines will continue. It does not mean that automatically when the maximum punishment is raised, the punishment will go up. Because every punishment must depend on the facts of the case. And I think the new Chief Justice has mentioned that the punishment should fit the crime as well as the offender. So, let us see what happens (emphasis added). In other words, Parliament patently did not have any intention to automatically increase sentencing benchmarks when a maximum penalty is raised.23 Its intent was in fact to leave that decision to the Courts, after the Courts properly consider the crime and the offender. Yet, the only apparent justification the Court in Hue resorted to in increasing the benchmark was to rely on Parliament’s intention. This cannot be right. Further, the fact that Parliament could have chosen to retain the language of the old s 304A and merely increase the maximum term of imprisonment to five years, but it instead accorded negligent and rashness its own separate sentencing range, does not provide any better indication of its intention to increase the benchmark. It is equally, if not more, possible that the sole reason Parliament bifurcated the old s 304A was because it desired to only increase the maximum penalty for causing death by rash act to five years’ imprisonment, and to preserve that for causing death by negligent act at two years’ imprisonment. This is entirely consistent with some of the considerations Parliament took into account in deciding to increase maximum sentences. As explained by the then-Minister of Home Affairs (Mr Wong Kan Seng), these considerations include (i) the need to Singapore Law Gazette December 2014 37 maintain proportionality between offence and punishment; (ii) having the type and quantum of punishment that provide sufficient flexibility to the Courts to mete out an appropriate sentence in a case; and (iii) the need to maintain relativity in the punishment for related offences within the PC.24 The lattermost consideration may have played the greatest role; with the bifurcation, the severest punishment for the different manners of causing death (apart from murder) are now more neatly and relatively calibrated: 1. Negligent act causing death – maximum imprisonment of two years (s 304A(b) of the PC); 2. Rash act causing death – maximum imprisonment of five years (s 304A(a) of the PC); 3. Knowledge that likely to cause death – maximum imprisonment of 10 years (s 304(b) of the PC); and 4. Intention to cause death – imprisonment for life or up to 20 years (s 304(a) of the PC). Put simply, it is difficult to see how in bifurcating the old s 304A, one of Parliament’s intention must have been to at the same time increase the benchmark for negligent act causing death as well. Given how controversial increasing the benchmark for a s 304A(b) offence is,25 it is arguably unsatisfactory that the Court in Hue worked off what appears to be vague and speculative assumptions of Parliament’s intent. Much clearer intention of Parliament to so increase should have been necessary. For instance, in the case of Yang Suan Piau Steven v PP (“Steven”),26 Chan CJ (as he then was) was not willing to accept that policy considerations call for a custodial sentence for a first offender of Giving False Information under s 129 of the Customs Act.27 At [51], he noted that “Parliament has not evinced such a policy” (emphasis added). There is no reason why more speculation and extrapolation is permitted in the context of a negligent act causing death offence. Feature Ultimately, even assuming that the Court in Hue was right that in the 2008 amendments to the PC, Parliament had intended that the benchmark sentence for negligent act causing death be increased, the crucial question remains: why must the increase be from a fine, to a custodial term? Can it not be an increase in merely the tariff quantum of the fine (eg from around $8,000 to around $20,000)? Currently, the highest fine Courts impose for the offence is $10,000.28 But that is only because the offence is commonly classified as a Magistrate Arrest Case, where the maximum fine a Magistrate Judge may impose is $10,000.29 Certainly, the Criminal Procedure Code allows such an offence to be tried in a District Court,30 where the District Judge may then order a huge fine of up to $30,000.31 The above discussion sought to show that the Hue Court’s reasoning (see page 36 above) for increasing the benchmark is quite unjustifiable. A better rationale, which will be proposed below, is therefore needed to justify the increase. Even if we accept the Court’s reasoning as valid, there is still an outstanding issue: the Hue Court’s reasoning is wholly devoid of explicit consideration of established sentencing rationales. This ignores the direction of the Court of Appeal. In Kwong, the Court of Appeal commented that:32 ... a court should always endeavour to explain its sentencing philosophy in the interests of justice and transparency… As to the Court’s earlier reference to the approximate midpoint sentence under s 304A(b), it is not clear at all what role this played in justifying the increase in the benchmark. It could not have been an alternative standalone justification because all it led to was that there are two possible approximate midpoints: a large fine, and a brief period of imprisonment. Resort still had to be had to Parliament’s intention to explain the Court’s decision to prefer the latter. The other possible purpose for the reference is simply to show that the two most viable sentencing benchmarks are a large fine and a brief period of imprisonment. Nonetheless, referring just to Gan would have achieved the same purpose. Singapore Law Gazette December 2014 Feature 38 In arriving at an appropriate sentence, a court should almost invariably consider the relevance of the sentencing considerations of deterrence, retribution, prevention and rehabilitation at the outset. It should assess which of these considerations have the greatest cogency in any given factual matrix. Practically speaking, the laying down of a sentencing benchmark (as did the Court in Hue) will ipso facto likely improve consistency in sentencing. That should be welcomed. Nevertheless, it is submitted that when a Court sets out a sentencing guideline but omits to articulate which rationale has the foremost cogency for the particular offence, the likelihood of achieving consistency may be significantly undermined because another Court which finds it hard to accept the guideline may readily but unjustifiably depart from it by: (i) emphasising some other sentencing rationale(s) to justify the departure; or (ii) according too much weight to certain mitigating factors. In a similar vein, it has been explained that:33 [o]ne of the aims of structuring discretion should be to ensure that it is exercised in a principled manner, and one essential step must be to decide upon a rationale for sentencing. A choice should be made between deterrence, rehabilitation, incapacitation, reparation or desert as the leading aim … Unless decisions of principle are taken on priorities … the resultant uncertainty would be a recipe for disparity, and more bluntly that “[w]ithout an explicit and wellarticulated guiding aim, consistency is a forlorn hope”.34 Re-rationalising the Increase in Benchmark The sentencing rationale which best justifies increasing the benchmark for and which should take centre stage in an offence of negligent act causing death is general deterrence.35 To be fair, the Court in Hue did hint at general deterrence, although only obliquely, in the penultimate paragraph of the judgment:36 We would like to take this opportunity to signal to drivers the consequences of the tremendous risks that they take on, not only to themselves but also to other innocent road users, when they drive despite not being in a fit condition to do so. The lattermost phrase of the paragraph suggests that the Court was alluding to general deterrence specifically vis-àvis sleepy and drink-drivers. But general deterrence can go further to justify the benchmark sentence of a short custodial term, as opposed to a mere fine, for s 304A(b) offenders in general. As approved by the High Court in Tan Fook Sum:37 What will facilitate more rational and informed sentencing is recognition that there is a dichotomy between public interest and aggravating or mitigating factors. Generally speaking, only the public interest should affect the type of sentence to be imposed while only aggravating and mitigating circumstances affect the duration or severity of the sentence imposed. (emphasis added). Our Courts have held that general deterrence is warranted in offences affecting public safety.38 Driving on the roads, even if only negligently, seriously jeopardises the lives and safety of a large segment of the public, that is, road users. It has been emphasised that “the motor car is a particularly violent and potentially dangerous instrument”.39 Following from this, there is thus substantial public interest in the law signalling that any negligent driving that causes death will likely be met with a very stiff (though not disproportionate) sentence such as a brief custodial term, since “the custodial sentence is the most satisfactory and powerful way of expressing public disapproval”.40 Of course, it is hard to quibble with the proposition that “the mere fact that a human life is lost does not in itself justify the Court in passing a deterrent sentence”.41 However, it bears highlighting that negligent driving poses much more tremendous risks than other kinds of negligent acts, eg medical negligence. For negligent driving, the danger is not just to one, but potentially to numerous other road users. A single negligent act in driving can lead to the loss of many innocent lives. The need to strongly signal this is the key justification for imposing a short custodial term as benchmark sentence for s 304A(b) traffic death cases. The following analogy may help persuade those who remain unconvinced: imagine a hypothetical jurisdiction where humans are permitted to carry with them an explosive. Once dropped, the explosive has a killing radius of a dozen over metres. Any carelessness on the part of those who choose to carry the explosive may cause the loss of lives of multiple persons. In order to encourage maximum care for those who carry the explosive, it should not be hard to see that a stiff sentence in the form of a custodial term has to be imposed on those who drop the explosive and cause death(s), even if only negligently. The potential and actual consequences of the act must outweigh the culpability of the offender. This conclusion should apply with equal force to negligent driving cause death given the similar enormous risks posed. Singapore Law Gazette December 2014 39 The prevalence of fatal road accidents in Singapore may also go some way to augment the need to effect general deterrence,42 thereby further justifying a brief custodial term as starting point for s 304A(b) traffic death cases. While the number of traffic accident deaths has fallen from 168 in 2012 to 159 in 2013,43 the Courts may note that: 1. the number of such deaths is arguably still hovering at an undesirable level.44 One life loss in a traffic accident is one life too many; 2. the number of fatalities arising from accidents that involve heavy vehicles increased from 32 in 2012 to 44 in 201345; and 3. there is also an increase in traffic violations since 2011. As observed by the Singapore Police Force, “such a trend remains a concern as every traffic violation can potentially result in a fatal or injury accident and the loss of lives”.46 In sum, the public interest in ensuring sufficient general deterrence in s 304A(b) traffic death cases is a better justification for increasing the benchmark to a brief imprisonment term, at least compared to the Hue Court’s arguably misplaced reliance on Parliament’s intention. Admittedly though, even this better justification is some way from being entirely satisfactory. First, while it has been observed that “[p]sychologically, the higher the punishment, the more effective it is as a deterrent to future … general offending”,47 empirical research by criminlogists has failed to demonstrate any significant or consistent marginal deterrence, that is, the relationship between the severity of a punishment and the crime rate of an offence.48 In other words, increasing the benchmark sentence for a s 304A(b) offence from a fine to a custodial term may in fact do little or nothing to reduce the occurrence of such offences in future.49 Nonetheless, despite awareness of this deficiency, our Courts have remained willing, as a matter of judicial policy, to advance public interest by imposing deterrent sentences.50 Second, it may be contended that the desire to effect increased general deterrence for such offences need not be fulfilled by increasing the starting point sentence from a fine to a short custodial term. The same can be achieved by maintaining the benchmark of a fine, but increasing the tariff disqualification period for the offender to say 10 years. This appears to be quite an attractive option considering the observation that disqualification is “the punishment most feared by the motorist and therefore the most effective deterrent”.51 Feature Outstanding Uncertainties in Application and Scope of New Benchmark Having dealt with the rationalisation of the new benchmark, it might be useful to briefly highlight two uncertainties with its application and scope. The first is that the Courts, prosecutors and defence counsels are likely to find considerable difficulty in applying this new benchmark because the Court in Hue did not provide any guidance at all on what in its view is the archetypal road traffic negligent act case that deserves a starting point of four weeks imprisonment. Unhelpfully, Hue itself was not a case that involved the usual negligent driving - it involved aggravated or gross negligence.52 Furthermore, the Court phrased the new starting point somewhat confusingly as a custodial term of up to four weeks. So for instance, in a common case where a driver was negligent for failing to keep a proper lookout, is the starting point four weeks imprisonment, to be adjusted for aggravating (eg more than one victim involved) and mitigating (eg contributory negligence) factors? Or is the starting point for such relatively low degree negligence cases perhaps one week or even one day imprisonment, liable to be adjusted up or down, while the starting point of four weeks is meant for higher degree negligence cases? It seems that the Court in Hue was content to leave it to future Courts to develop this area on a case-by-case basis. Singapore Law Gazette December 2014 Feature 40 My tentative proposal is for Courts to take reference from pre-Hue precedents (that applied the Gan benchmark) as a rough guide, and correspondingly calibrate the sentences to be imposed in factually similar cases in light of the new benchmark: 1. Pre-Hue, even simple negligence cases arising from a failure to keep a proper lookout or to exercise proper care and caution would usually attract a heavy fine of $7,000 to $10,000 where death is caused.53 PostHue, these should form the archetypal s 304A(b) traffic death cases that attract a starting point of four weeks’ imprisonment. A custodial term lower than four weeks may be imposed where there are recognised mitigating factors such as contributory negligence on the part of the victim, and a high fine should now only be imposed where there are very exceptional mitigating circumstances. 2. Pre-Hue, short custodial terms of a week or two were ordered for negligence cases with aggravating factors, such as where there is simply no reason for the offender to have failed to spot the victim.54 Post-Hue, negligence cases with such aggravating factors (excluding those highlighted in [67] to [92] in Hue) should generally attract an imprisonment term slightly higher than the starting point of four weeks, eg. five to seven weeks. And as Hue itself clearly decided, in a negligent act causing death case where there are aggravating factors specifically analysed in Hue (ie speeding, drink-driving and sleepy driving), the starting point should be between two to four months’ imprisonment.55 The second potential uncertainty is whether the new starting point should also apply generally to non-traffic s 304A(b) cases, for instance, medical negligence causing death. While the Court in Hue held that this new benchmark is to apply to a s 304A(b) traffic death case, if we accept the Court’s reasoning in having this new benchmark (see page 36 above), then a good argument can be made that the new benchmark should apply generally to all s 304A(b) cases. This is because the benchmark expounded in Gan has previously been applied to non-traffic death by negligence cases.56 And given that Parliament bifurcated the old s 304A such that all causing death by negligence cases are to have a maximum penalty of up to two years, logically, the increase in benchmark should apply to all such cases as well. However, it is cautioned that Courts should not unthinkingly so extend the new benchmark. As argued above, the more defensible justification for increasing the benchmark is the need to signal that in traffic negligence cases, tremendous risks to multiple road users are involved. This rationale may not apply to non-traffic s 304A(b) cases. Courts should, therefore, closely examine the specific context of negligent act causing death before deciding whether to also apply the new starting point expounded in Hue. Conclusion There is little doubt that the increase in benchmark for s 304A(b) traffic death cases from a fine to a brief custodial term will be viewed as a significant, yet controversial change. After all, the position that negligent act causing death offenders would usually meet with a fine has been accepted and applied for over twenty years in Singapore.57 This well-entrenched position is similar to that adopted in England, where the Court of Appeal has held that in cases where a fatal accident has arisen through momentary inattention or misjudgment, a fine is usually sufficient.58 Indeed, in relation to the proposed amendment in 2008 to s 304A of the PC, the Law Society of Singapore went so far as to submit that:59 [g]enerally, imprisonment is not a suitable punishment for negligence and the maximum punishment of 2 years’ imprisonment under s. 304A(b) for negligent causing of death appears excessive. We recommend that no imprisonment be prescribed for the negligent causing of death. In light of this, it is unfortunate that the Hue Court’s justification for increasing the benchmark is: (i) premised on unjustified assumptions of and reliance on Parliament’s intention; and (ii) lacks transparency vis-à-vis the relevant sentencing consideration(s). Thankfully, there is a better justification – the need to effect general deterrence in s 304A(b) traffic death cases. That said, for what it is worth, even that justification is not fully satisfactory, and there are uncertainties in the application and scope of the new benchmark that criminal practitioners and the Courts will surely have to grapple with. What is clear then, is that how the Courts henceforth develop sentencing in s 304A(b) cases, will be very keenly watched by many. * I am grateful for the helpful comments provided by Jason Nim, Fong Jing Heng and Vincent Ong on an earlier draft of this case note. All errors are solely mine. ► Benny Tan* Tutor, Legal Skills Programme National University of Singapore, Faculty of Law E-mail: lawbtzp@nus.edu.sg Singapore Law Gazette December 2014 41 Notes Feature 32 Kwong, supra (note 15 above) at [19] and [33]. 33 Andrew von Hirsch, Andrew Ashworth and Julian Roberts (eds), Principled Sentencing: Readings on Theory and Policy (Oxford and Portland, Oregon: Hart Publishing, 2009), p 231. Ibid, Andrew Ashworth, “Techniques for Reducing Sentence Disparity”, p 243 at 251. 1 [2014] SGHC 171. 2 (Cap 224, 2008 Rev Ed). 3 Hue, supra (note1 above) at [61] and [133]. 34 4 The other two Judges being Chao Hick Tin JA and Tan Siong Thye JC (as he then was). 35 See also Sentencing Practice, supra (note 28 above), p 1657. 5 Hue, supra (note 1 above) at [30]-[55]. 36 Hue, supra (note 1 above) at [135]. 6 Ibid at [67]-[92]. 37 7 Ibid at [99]-[125]. See generally Kow Keng Siong, Sentencing Principles in Singapore (Singapore: Academy Publishing, 2009) at [25.025]ff. 8 Ibid at [5], quoting from the accused’s plea in mitigation. 38 See esp PP v Law Aik Meng [2007] 2 SLR(R) 814 at [24d] (“Law”). 9 See Tan Kay Beng v PP [2006] 4 SLR(R) 10 at [39], citing R v Howells [1999] 1 WLR 307, an English Court of Appeal decision that considered the relevant factors to be taken into account in deciding when to mete out custodial sentences. 39 Douglas Acres, “Consistently achieving our sentencing aims” in Donald C. Pennington and Sally Lloyd-Bostock (eds), The Psychology of Sentencing (Oxford: Centre For SocioLegal Studies, 1987), p 61 at 63. See also Jali bin Mohd Yunos v PP [2014] SGCA 50 at [24] and [36]. 10 For a similar view, see PP v Abdul Latiff Bin Maideen Pillay [2006] SGDC 245 at [10] (“Abdul Latiff”). 40 Ibid, p 61 at 64. 11 See generally Hue, supra (note 1 above) at [56]-[61]. 41 See PP v Tiyatun & Anor [2002] 1 SLR(R) 746 at [9]. 12 [1993] 2 SLR(R) 67. 42 Law, supra (note 38) at [25a]. 13 Ibid at [10]. 43 14 (Cap 224, 1985 Rev Ed). Singapore Police Force, “Annual Road Traffic Situation 2013” (10 Feb 2014), online: Singapore Police Force; available at: <www.police.gov.sg/mic/2014/02/20140210_ others_TP_stats.html>. 15 [2008] 2 SLR(R) 684. 44 C.f Lim Kay Han Irene v PP [2010] 3 SLR 240 at [42]. 16 Hue, supra (note 1 above) at [59]. 45 Supra (note 43 above). 17 Ibid at [60]-[61]. 46 Ibid. 18 That the increase was significant was certainly the view of the Court in Hue as well. See Hue, supra (note 1 above) at [127]. 47 Steven, supra (note 26 above) at [51]. 48 19 Ibid at [67]-[92], [134]. 20 All we know for certain is that in amending some provisions, Parliament had taken into account comments made by the Judges in their judgments (Parliamentary Debates Singapore: Official Report, vol 83 at col 2175 (22 Oct 2007)). See for eg Andrew von Hirsch et al, Criminal Deterrence and Sentence Severity – An Analysis of Recent Research (Oxford – Portland Oregon: Hart Publishing, 1999), ch 10.1-10.2. 49 There is also controversy as to whether it is even possible to deter negligent-type offences (see for eg Leslie Y Garfield, “A More Principled Approach to Criminalising Negligence: A Prescription for the Legislature” (1997-98) 65 Tennessee Law Rev 875 at 883ff). My view is that it is possible. 21 Parliamentary Debates Singapore: Official Report, vol 83 at col 2418 (23 Oct 2007). 22 Ibid at col 2439. 23 See for eg Lim Ghim Peow v PP [2014] SGCA 52 at [56]. 24 See Parliamentary Debates Singapore: Official Report, vol 83 at col 971 (22 May 2007). See also Ministry of Home Affairs (Singapore), “Consultation Paper On The Proposed Penal Code Amendments” (8 Nov 2006), online: Ministry of Home Affairs; available at: <www4.mha.gov.sg/data/NewsFiles/d84_2126_312_Public Consultation Paper on the proposed penal code amendments in PDF format.pdf> at [21]. 50 Law, supra (note 38 above) at [19]. See also Abdul Latiff, supra (note 10 above) at [13]. 51 Sentencing Practice, supra (note 28 above) at 71, citing PP v Chiam Liang Kee [1960] MLJ 163. See also Edwin s/o Suse Nathen v PP [2013] 4 SLR 1139 at [13]. 52 Hue, supra (note 1 above) at [98]. 53 See Sentencing Practice, supra (note 28 above) at 1659-1665. 54 See for eg Abdul Latiff, supra (note 10 above). Hue, supra (note 1 above) at [134]. 25 See para under the heading “Analysis of the Court’s Justification for increasing the Benchmark”. 55 26 [2013] 1 SLR 809. 56 Sentencing Practice, supra (note 28 above) at 354. 27 (Cap 70, 2004 Rev Ed). 57 Hue, supra (note 1 above) at [126]. 28 See the cases cited in Sentencing Practice in the Subordinate Courts, (3rd edition, Singpore: LexisNexis, 2013), pp 1659-1665 (“Sentencing Practice”). 58 Sentencing Practice, supra (note 28 above) at 1657, citing the English case of R v Guilford [1973] RTR 272. 29 Criminal Procedure Code (Cap 68, 2012 Rev Ed), s 303(3)(b). 59 30 Ibid at First Schedule (Tabular Statement of Offences under the Penal Code). 31 Ibid at s 303(2)(b). The Law Society of Singapore, “Executive Summary of Council’s Report on the Proposed Amendments to the Penal Code”, online: The Law Society of Singapore; available at: <www. lawsociety.org.sg/forMembers/ResourceCentre/FeedbackinPublicConsultation/2007/ ExecutiveSummaryProposedAmendmentstothePenal.aspx> at [5.2]. Singapore Law Gazette December 2014 Feature 34 Singapore Law Gazette Awards 2015 – Best Feature Article by a Young Lawyer While there are important principles fundamental to the Singapore Constitution, they do not form a legally unchangeable “basic structure”. Even if it were possible to identify a substantive “basic structure”, its exact content would be indeterminate and we would be left with only broad, unhelpful truisms. Instead, the true safeguards against potential undesirable constitutional amendments lie in democratic political processes. The Basic Structure Doctrine in Singapore: A Reply Introduction In The Constitution of Our Constitution: A Vindication of the Basic Structure Doctrine,1 Mr Calvin Liang and Ms Sarah Shi (“the authors”) explore the “‘basic structure doctrine”, which “posits that a constitution has certain written or unwritten features so fundamental that they cannot be abrogated through constitutional amendments”, in the context of Singapore. They argue that “the Legality Principle against the separation of powers form the basic structure of the Constitution of the Republic of Singapore”, and that Singapore’s constitutional actors have openly acknowledged this. Moreover, they argue that the “basic structure” must exist by virtue of the very nature of a constitution, or at least of Singapore’s Constitution.2 To the contrary, it is argued in this article that the local case law does not support the “basic structure” doctrine. At most, it supports the truism that the Constitution features several fundamental principles, but these principles are either not necessarily “basic” in the strict sense of being unchangeable or are too general to be of use as a “basic structure”. Moreover, the reasons for the doctrine of a “basic structure” do not necessitate the particular basic structure advocated by the authors or the level of generality at which it has been pitched. Instead, the true safeguards against constitutional change that severely curtails subjects’ rights are political in nature. The Meaning of the Basic Structure Doctrine The “basic structure doctrine” comes from the Indian case of Kesavananda Bharati v State of Kerela3 (“Kesavananda”). Interestingly, Kesavananda represented an increase, not a decrease, in Parliament’s powers of constitutional amendment: the majority (of seven against six) overruled an earlier case4 which held that no amendments to the fundamental rights provisions in the Constitution were allowed, favouring instead the idea that only the basic structure cannot be amended. Some of the Judges in Kesavananda saw the issue as one of imposing legal limits on constitutional amendment;5 others saw it as one of pointing out logical limits on Singapore Law Gazette November 2014 35 constitutional amendment (viz that the Constitution cannot be changed so drastically that it ceases to be the same Constitution);6 and yet others merely pointed to non-legal political duties not to make certain types of amendment.7 In other words, the “basic structure” refers to something more than a set of important features of the Constitution: it refers to: (i) features that legally or logically cannot be abrogated; or, perhaps, (ii) features that politically should not be abrogated. Let us focus on: (i), since (ii) is not the business of the Courts. In the constitutional law context, it is, therefore, necessary to distinguish between two meanings of the word “basic”: concepts which are very important and concepts which are unchangeable. The two may overlap, but are not the same. Let us focus primarily on the second meaning (which is the meaning in Kesavananda), for discussing the first meaning runs the risk of stating the obvious: since all constitutions, by their “very nature”, play the basic roles of “power-defining” and “power-limiting”,8 the debate would then become merely a political one about the merits of schemes of division of power, and would only become a legal debate if there are schemes which are either fundamentally necessary or repugnant to the core of the Constitution. There are, therefore, two questions to consider: 1. Whether there are features of the Singapore Constitution which it is not legally possible to change; and 2. If not, then whether there are features of the Singapore Constitution which, if removed, would lead to a product that is something other than the Singapore Constitution. Let us refer to these as “question (1)” and “question (2)”. A study of the cases reveals that the answer to both is no. Does Singapore’s Structure”? Constitution Have a “Basic Let us examine the different contenders for the basic structure of Singapore’s Constitution. The “Legality Principle” and the Availability of Judicial Review: Teo Soh Lung v Minister for Home Affairs (“Teo Soh Lung (HC)”)9 and Chng Suan Tze v Minister for Home Affairs (“Chng Suan Tze”)10 In Teo Soh Lung (HC), Chua J rejected the submission that there are constitutional amendments which Parliament has no legal power to make; to hold otherwise, he said, would be “usurping Parliament’s legislative function contrary to art 58 of the Constitution”.11 He distinguished Kesavananda on Feature the grounds of differences between Indian and Singaporean constitutional history.12 The authors reply that Chua J erred in neglecting the “Legality Principle”13 and in focusing on the text of art 58 to the exclusion of the possibility of implied limits to amendment which should be, as the Privy Council appeared to suggest in Hinds v R14 (“Hinds”), “taken for granted”.15 However, these arguments do not establish that there are legally unchangeable features of the Singapore Constitution. The authors begin by asserting the importance of the “Legality Principle” from Chng Suan Tze that “All power has legal limits and the rule of law demands that the courts should be able to examine the exercise of discretionary power”, which they say flows from “the separation of powers and the need for a system of checks and balances on powers”.16 But even if this is true, accepting it merely postpones the question: why is it legally impossible for Parliament to abrogate the rule of law? Three problems emerge. The first issue has to do with question (1) as defined above. In India, an answer to the question in the previous paragraph is based on popular sovereignty: Sikri CJ in Kesavananda said that constitutional amendments which go against the popular “common understanding” or ignore it by causing “the very democratic principles which [Parliament] appeal[s] to” in invoking the process of constitutional amendment to “disappear”17 are forbidden. This is because, as Shelat J put it, the invocation of popular sovereignty in the Preamble to the Indian Constitution is the “key to the understanding of the Constitution”.18 It is also the key to the distinction between the constitutional histories of India and of Singapore to which Chua J alluded. To be fair, it is unclear whether this means that it is legally impossible for Parliament to make such constitutional amendments in India, or merely that the people reserve the political power to resist such an amendment even if it is legally valid. Nonetheless, it does not matter to Singapore, where, by contrast, the power of constitutional amendment is not explicitly made ultimately contingent on the approval of some other body such as “the people”, nor is the power said to have been delegated by “the people”. Second, what, in the context of constitutional amendment, are the “limits” to which the “Legality Principle” as it is formulated refers? All that the dictum from Chng Suan Tze says is that judicial review is possible; it says nothing about the grounds or standards of review. The “Legality Principle” therefore cannot be used, as the authors do, to answer the question of what the content of the “basic structure” is. Moreover, a claim that the “basic structure” is simply that Singapore Law Gazette November 2014 Feature 36 there are limits to executive power would answer question (2) affirmatively but be an empty, and thus unhelpful, claim: the mere existence of limits to power is a feature inherent in the act of delegation of power; since it is by definition impossible for delegated power not to have limits (for, otherwise, it would be transferred power), it would not add anything to say that it is also unlawful. Third, similarly, it does not follow from the idea that “all power has legal limits” that “the courts must be able to examine the exercise of discretionary power”19 (emphasis added). While it may be that “[i]t is emphatically the province and duty of the [body with judicial power] to say what the law is”,20 this does not aid our enquiry as it tells us nothing about exactly how “the law” in Singapore affects validity or how exactly “the law” says judicial review is to be performed. It may be that the basic structure is simply that there must be judicial power, but this does not address the question of whether the basic structure renders unlawful certain constitutional amendments which define the scope of judicial power. In short, besides the circularity in the authors’ asserting the importance of the “Legality Principle” and then criticising Chua J’s rejection of the basic structure doctrine because it conflicts with it,21 which assumes the very thing which the authors aim to prove, the “Legality Principle” does not contain enough content to form a basic structure which is fit for purpose. Let us now examine the recent cases cited by the authors to see whether this problem may be solved through other principles. be non-justiciable”.27 However, the hypothetical situations in which review would be available – if the Cabinet were biased, acting in bad faith, or in breach of the procedural requirements in art 22P of the Constitution, eg if it did not meet to discuss a clemency petition or made its decision based on a coin toss28 – are not about the separation of powers per se; they concern only the manner in which one of the powers is to be exercised. Neither do they concern the Courts’ policing the limits to powers: the Legality Principle is concerned with the extent of vires,29 not the ways in which discretion is exercised or whether or not it is exercised. It may now be argued that it is these grounds of review that form the “basic structure”. But the grounds are contingent on legislative approval: the judicial review jurisdiction was said to cover “every legal dispute on a subject matter in respect of which Parliament has conferred jurisdiction on”30 (emphasis added). The ratio of Yong Vui Kong – the real reason why the “Legality Principle” can be said to have “trump[ed] the argument that constitutional powers may be non-justiciable”31 – is that the power in question was said to be a legal power, as opposed to a “purely personal discretion”, for the Court stressed for the first time that only “legal powers … have legal limits”32 (emphasis in original). The matter cannot be said to be based on an unabrogable basic feature that demands that judicial review be possible, for if, hypothetically, art 22P did not exist, then there would be no power of clemency at all and thus no right of judicial review to abrogate. It is not necessarily true that that the Legality Principle applied in Yong Vui Kong cannot be changed by Parliament. On the contrary, the Court accepted that it can: in holding that there “will (or should) be few, if any, legal disputes between the State and the people from which the judicial power is excluded”24 (emphasis added), the Court acknowledged that there may be some matters which are not susceptible to judicial review. There is no conflict between this and the “doctrine of separation of powers” which the Court held to be the basis of the “fundamental law” of Singapore25 and the authors concluded to be part of the basic structure26: the doctrine is capable of encompassing partial separation of powers, and, more fundamentally, says nothing about the content or scope of those powers. These points may be further illustrated by turning briefly to Mohammad Faizal (HC), which the authors cite as the “clearest recognition of the basic structure doctrine”.33 In fact, the words “basic structure”34 in that case referred to the idea in Hinds that it is, in a Westminster-style constitution, “taken for granted that the basic principle of separation of powers will apply”.35. With respect, however, this is not strictly relevant in Singapore, where, to use the words of the minority in Hinds, “[t]he principle that there should be a separation of powers between the three organs of government is not just taken for granted. Effect is given to that principle by the written terms of the Constitution”36 through arts 38, 23(1), and 93 of the Singapore Constitution which explicitly vest legislative, executive, and judicial powers in the Legislature, the Executive, and the Judiciary, respectively. The crux of Mohammad Faizal was thus not about the separation of powers as a basic structure, but rather about the content of the powers, viz whether sentencing an individual is an exercise of legislative or judicial power. The authors characterise Yong Vui Kong as having “trump[ed] the argument that constitutional powers may Therefore, all that the basic structure doctrine allegedly adds to the law on executive clemency is that the Courts The Separation of Powers: Yong Vui Kong v Public Prosecutor22 (“Yong Vui Kong”) and Mohammad Faizal bin Sabtu v Public Prosecutor23 (“Mohammad Faizal (HC)”) Singapore Law Gazette November 2014 37 have, on occasion, some role to play in reviewing executive actions. This point has already been dealt with above. The authors also argue that, in Yong Vui Kong, the basic structure doctrine was further used as an “interpretive tool”.37 However, the fact that a constitutional principle is so significant that it leads to an interpretive norm does not mean that it therefore cannot lawfully be abrogated. On the contrary, if all that the principle does is to give rise to implication or interpretation, then surely the latter can be trumped by an express provision to the contrary;38 this would not count as an abrogation of the principle, but merely a statement of its scope, ie that it simply does not apply in such a manner as to give rise to that implication or interpretation. Constitutional Supremacy: Tan Eng Hong v Attorney-General39 (“Tan Eng Hong”) The authors also seek to link the separation of powers with constitutional supremacy. Thus, they say that the Court in Tan Eng Hong “adopted a functional analysis; reasoning from the function of the Constitution to its necessary components”, ie from the Constitution’s role in maintaining the rule of law and protecting fundamental liberties to the necessary feature of constitutional supremacy.40 With respect, this begs the question: constitutional supremacy can only be said to be necessary if we presuppose that the functions of the Constitution are necessary, but those functions are themselves defined by the Constitution which claims supremacy. Feature only basic structure we are left with is that there should exist a document titled Constitution of the Republic of Singapore. Again, the answer to question (2) is yes, but only vacuously so. The Content of the Basic Structure Lessons from Foreign Jurisdictions We have seen that many important constitutional principles are not part of the basic structure in the Kesavananda sense; the authors’ argument that it follows from the fact that judicial review has been performed without legislative interference that judicial review must be part of the basic structure41 is neither here nor there, for it confuses practice and legality.42 But even if they were, another problem arises: exactly how is the basic structure to be defined and framed? There are at least several possibilities. The Authors’ Proposal One possibility is, as the authors have suggested, that the basic structure is a combination of the Legality Principle Moreover, although it cannot be denied that constitutional supremacy is a vital feature of the Constitution, it does not follow that it cannot be abrogated by an Act of Parliament, either because such an amending Act would be unlawful or because it would make the Constitution lose its identity. There are at least two ways to look at the matter: 1. First, an Act incompatible with the Constitution is void simply because art 4 says so. Consequently, to attempt to repeal art 4 by legislation is not unlawful; it is simply an impossible contradiction in terms. Again, for the proposition that the basic structure consists of unabrogable constitutional principles to mean anything, it would have to be the case that, if those principles were not part of the basic structure, then it would be possible (to put it loosely, “physically possible”) to abrogate them; this is simply not true in the case of art 4. The answer to question (1) is, therefore, no. 2. Second, if it is lawful by virtue of art 5 for the Legislature to repeal every other provision of the Constitution, the Singapore Law Gazette November 2014 Feature 38 and the separation of powers.43 But these are, at most, a structure. If there were some basic provisions, then answering the question of lawfulness would be as simple as checking whether the provision purportedly amended was one of the “basic” ones. By contrast, the Legality Principle and the separation of powers are principles which cannot be said either to apply or not, but rather only to apply in different ways or to different degrees. For this reason, in Australian Capital Television Pty Ltd v Commonwealth of Australia (“Australian Capital Television”), it was held that a provision may only be implied on a “structural” (as opposed to “textual”) basis if it is “logically or practically necessary for the preservation of the integrity of that structure”. 44 Democracy and Responsible Government In Australian Capital Television, an implied constitutional right of “political communication”45 was said to be required by the “concept of representative government and representative democracy”, as evidenced by the fact that Members of Parliament and Ministers in Australia were “not only chosen by the people but exercise their legislative and executive powers as representatives of the people”.46 The Court did not have to consider whether these implied principles were expressly abrogable. But if we imagine arguendo that they could not be, this case would illustrate the difficulty of defining the basic structure. Which would be a better candidate for the basic structure of Singapore’s Constitution: the Legality Principle, or representative democracy? Neither is necessarily more correct. If it is the latter, given the reasoning from the provisions in the Australian Constitution about the election of democratic representatives, it may well be that the “basic structure” leads to the political remedy of removing the unsatisfactory members of legislature or the executive through democratic processes47 rather than the legal remedy of judicial review. Similarly, in Federal Commissioner of Taxation v Munro, it was held that “the Constitution is for the advancement of representative government”, and that different types of powers are “capable of assignment … to more than one branch [legislative, executive, or judicial] of government … [d]eny that proposition, and you seriously affect the recognised working of representative government”.48 This is significant because it puts paid to the idea that question (2) may be answered by pointing to a particular specific definition of some or all of the three powers. Fundamental Rights and the Principal Aim of the State In Kesavananda too, judicial views differed as to the content of the basic structure. While Sikri CJ listed constitutional supremacy; republicanism and democracy; secularism; separation of powers; and federalism,49 which are features of the framework of the State, Shelat and Grover JJ added such substantive values as human dignity, fundamental freedoms, and welfarism.50 Ray J, by contrast, in rejecting the basic structure doctrine, said that the crux of a constitution was the “great ends” of “the safety, the greatness and the well-being of a people”.51 This demonstrates the difficulty in determining not only the specific content of the basic structure, but also the level of generality at which it should be described. The Particular Role of Judicial Review Kesavananda also displays diversity of judicial opinion about the role of judicial review, which was the issue in Teo Soh Lung. Shelat and Grover JJ described it as being of “paramount importance” and part of the “heart and core of a democracy”;52 Khanna J explicitly said that abrogating it “strikes at the basic structure of the Constitution”.53 But Khanna J also warned that, as for the manner in which judicial review is conducted, “Judicial Oligarchy” must be avoided as “[t]he proper forum to fight for the wise use of the legislative authority is that of public opinion and legislative assemblies”, otherwise “people of fundamentally differing views” may be neglected.54 Similarly, Hegde and Mukherjea JJ acknowledged the usefulness of judicial review but suggested that legislative checks and balances might sometimes suffice: If [a] question … is considered as the exclusive function of the executive, then, not only the judicial review will be taken away, even the legislature will not have the opportunity of examining the correctness or appropriateness …” (emphasis added).55 The Case of Singapore In Singapore, by contrast, it is difficult to identify a defining overarching principle which, if abrogated, would make the Constitution into something other than the Constitution of the Republic of Singapore. As we have seen, there are various possible candidates for an implied overarching principle. As for an express one (as is present in the Constitutions of Mauritius,56 India,57 Germany,58 and Belize,59 to which the authors have alluded), the Proclamation of Singapore declares Singapore to be “forever a sovereign democratic and independent nation, founded upon the principles of liberty and justice and ever seeking the welfare and happiness of her people in a more just and equal society”,60 Singapore Law Gazette November 2014 39 but it is doubtful whether this should be taken to be more than political rhetoric. The Constitution explicitly mentions sovereignty, independence, and liberty;61 the drafters could easily have mentioned explicitly the other values in the Proclamation such as “democra[cy]” and “justice” if they wished to make these true constitutional principles. Of course, this does not mean that Singapore is not democratic – it patently is in at least one sense, for the Constitution specifically provides for elected representatives. Rather, it may be taken to exclude a particular conception of democracy, eg “[not only] that the people must decide who should govern them, [but also] the principle that fundamental rights should be protected by an impartial and independent judiciary”.62 On the other hand, it is equally plausible that the drafters of the Constitution did intend to enshrine such a view: such rights would complement the Legality Principle by describing the “legal limits” to executive and legislative power.63 Yet another possible view is that the primary purpose of the “freedoms of the people” is to facilitate “free elections” and prevent the “Government so elected … perpetuat[ing] itself”.64 All these equally plausible possibilities illustrate the difficulty in searching for a “basic structure” or saying that “democracy” is the basic structure: such moves either shore up ambiguities that add little to existing difficulties such as determining the appropriate level of “judicial restraint” (it is unclear how the authors’ observation that “the basic structure doctrine may not necessarily expand the scope of judicial review”65 (emphasis added) helps to address the established common-law problem of determining exactly which the “appropriate cases” in which to exercise restraint are), or risk crossing the boundary from constitutional interpretation into imputing to the Constitution ideas which are in reality the creation of the common law. Feature Analogies with Foreign Constitutions The authors argue that it “seems absurd” to suggest that the basic structure doctrine cannot be said to apply in Singapore by analogy with Germany and India because Singapore’s Constitution has no eternity clause (unlike art 20 of Germany’s Basic Law) and no popular supremacy clause (unlike the Preamble of India’s Constitution).68 However, these differences are highly significant. As for Germany, the authors cite a dictum quoted by the Federal Constitutional Court that “[t]here are constitutional principles that are so fundamental and so much an expression of a law that has precedence even over the constitution that they also bind the framers of the constitution”. However, in context, the content of these “fundamental” “constitutional principles” was the explicit statement in art 20(1) of the Basic Law: “The Federal Republic of Germany is a democratic and social federal state”. Hence, the basic structure doctrine applies in Germany only as a matter of the “inner unity” of the text of the Basic Law.69 (Interestingly, even this doctrine is qualified by art 146 of the Basic Law: “This Basic Law … shall cease to apply on the day on which a constitution freely adopted by the German people takes effect".) The authors cite an article which argues that the idea of an “implied eternity clause” may help distinguish between “the In short, therefore, we cannot give a definite answer to question (2); even if we could, it is likely that our answer would consist “not [of] concrete provisions of the Constitution, but … instead … statements of general principles … There can be wide differences of opinion about the scope and application of each of these principles… these principles are too general to provide either guidance or any real basis of agreement”.66 For this reason, the authors’ claim that “it may even be the case that a constitutional amendment to abolish the elected presidency may run into basic structure objections even though it is supported by referendum”67 is misconceived. Even if a basic structure doctrine did apply in Singapore, the Presidency, being part of the Executive, cannot be said to be more “basic” than the existence of the Executive itself. Singapore Law Gazette November 2014 Feature 40 amendment of an existing constitution and the establishment of a new constitution”.70 However, it is doubtful whether such an “implied” clause can trump express wording to the contrary. Moreover, the difficulty of determining exactly what the implied eternity clause covers would remain. As for India, Kesavananda suggests that, notwithstanding the majority’s judgments, the basic structure can be changed. It may be true that “what Parliament had not given, it could not take away”.71 But as Khanna J pointed out, “the people in the final analysis are the ultimate sovereign and if they decide to have an entirely new constitution, they would not need the authority of the existing constitution for this purpose”, even in the absence of an explicit comprehensive scheme for constitutional amendment.72 Indeed, sovereignty is vested in “the people of India” as noted in the Preamble of the Constitution of India. But the same Preamble recites that “the people” had acted through not just “constituent power” (as the German Basic Law states73), but the institution of “our constituent assembly”. It may, therefore, be possible for “extraconstitutional methods like revolution”74 (not in the sense of violent uprising, but simply in the sense of fundamental change) to be led by a democratically representative body – such as the Indian Parliament. The debate thus becomes merely one of whether the body is truly democratically representative75 – an important debate, but hardly one that is specific to the particular context of constitutional reform. Conclusion: A Political Constitution Constitutional theory is all about the balance of power, but this balance need not be struck by purely legal means. For example, Dicey posited two political limits to legislative power: the “external limit” (which is that the sovereign cannot, in practice, make legislation that subjects will disobey) and “internal limit” (the sovereign will not, in practice, make such legislation that it is “hardly conceivable” that it will as it will go against its interest to do so).76 The authors state that a basic structure is necessary for the Constitution to achieve its basic purpose. But it is equally arguable, as the minority said in Hinds that if a “great deal [were] left to necessary implication, [then] a written constitution would largely fail to achieve its object. If it does not define clearly what Parliament can do and cannot do by ordinary enactment, then the Government and Parliament of a territory may find that as a result of judicial decision after a considerable lapse of time all the time spent in legislating has been wasted and that laws urgently required have not been validly enacted”.77 The Courts must have some theory behind how they go about constitutional interpretation; this theory may well be that “public administration is not principally about stopping bad administrative practices but encouraging good ones”.78 It might seem unthinkable for the Courts to stand idly by in the face of “oppressive and wholly undemocratic legislation”.79 But such legislation would be exactly that – validly made legislation, which has the force of law. Unless the Courts are willing to abandon the notion that express words, however unsavoury one may think them to be, trump implied concepts,80 the Courts will, in such a case, be doing something other than giving effect to the law. If, instead, we posit that the limits postulated by Dicey are the true limits to the power of constitutional amendment in Singapore, then, while there is a meaningful distinction between amending the Constitution and replacing it with a new Constitution,81 in the case of the latter, it should not be assumed that the Courts ought to play a leading role in reform. Implicit support for this view may be inferred from dicta from Jeyaretnam Kenneth Andrew v Attorney-General, where the “green-light” model of the State, which focuses on “seek[ing] good government through the political process and public avenues rather than redress[ing] bad government through the courts”,82 was explicitly endorsed.83 While the Courts may, in time, see the need to examine more closely the content of legislative debates rather than simply assuming that the Legislature has carefully considered all relevant matters,84 they can do so at most as part of the process of interpretation;85 they cannot override the express words of legislation.86 It is, therefore, submitted that the true position in Singapore is that espoused by Kirby P in Building Construction Employees and Builders’ Labourers Federation of New South Wales v Minister for Industrial Relations87: In the end, it is respect for long standing political realities and loyalty to the desirable notion of elected democracy that inhibits any lingering judicial temptation, even in a hard case, to deny loyal respect to the commands of Parliament by reference to suggested fundamental rights that run ‘so deep’ that Parliament cannot disturb them. This conclusion does not leave our citizens unprotected from an oppressive majority in Parliament. The chief protection lies in the democratic nature of our Parliamentary institutions. To apply a “basic structure doctrine” to the extent of holding that amendments to the contrary are void is essentially to denounce a piece of legislation as “not law”. But, as Hart Singapore Law Gazette November 2014 41 argued, this would neglect the more important questions: If it is not truly law, how did it ever come to be considered valid law, not least of all by the Legislature itself? Perhaps it, though not truly law, is better than the law?88 While the question of validity is a legal question, these questions are arguably political questions for the people to answer. It is, therefore, best that they be answered through democratic fora. 6 Ray, Mathew, and Beg JJ, cited ibid, J-18. 7 Mathew J, [1714], cited ibid, J-15. 8 Supra (note 1 above)at [38]. 9 [1989] 1 SLR(R) 461. Courts performing judicial review are, to be sure, democratic institutions as they seek to give effect to democratic will89, but, even if their role is cut down, Parliament itself can also be equipped to answer these questions, albeit acting qua elected representative body rather than qua legislative authority90 (and perhaps taking a more directly representative approach than usual). In fact, notwithstanding the absence of a preamble like that in India’s Constitution, it may even be argued that the true Grundnorm is the social fact of popular sovereignty,91 such that even sweeping constitutional change following popular unhappiness with a legislative amendment cannot wholly be characterised as being extra-legal. In short, the authors have rightly identified the Legality Principle and the separation of powers as key constitutional principles, but these principles may well play out in such a way as to suggest that the Singapore Constitution is not only a legal document, but also a political one. The Constitution seeks to protect individual rights and uphold the rule of law, and it does so by separating each branch of the State and by establishing mutual checks and balances, but it is not at all clear that it does so via an immutable “basic structure”. This is, furthermore, not a bad thing: while enduringness is a strength of a constitution, inflexibility can be just as much a weakness.92 ► Benjamin Joshua Ong* 10 [1988] 2 SLR(R) 525. 11 Supra (note 9 above)at [35]. 12 Ibid, [37]-[47]; supra (note 1 above)at [16]. 13 Supra (note 1 above) at [8]. 14 [1977] AC 195. 15 Supra (note 1 above)at [9]. 16 Supra (note 10 above)at [86], cited supra (note 1 above) at [2]-[3]. 17 Supra (note 3 above), p 1534 at [291]-[295]. 18 Supra (note 3 above), p 1577 at [523]. 19 Supra (note 16 above). 20 Marbury v Madison 5 US (1 Cranch) 137 (1803), 177. 21 Supra (note 1 above) at [8]. 22 [2011] 2 SLR 1189. 23 [2012] 4 SLR 947. 24 Supra (note 22 above) at [31]. 25 Ibid at [31]. 26 Supra (note 1 above) at [26]-[28]. 27 Supra (note 1 above) at [27]. 28 Supra (note 22 above) at [83], [85], [111]-[112]. 29 Supra (note 16) at [86]. 30 Supra (note 22 above) at [31]. 31 Supra (note 1 above) at [27]. 32 Supra (note 22 above) at [59], [78]. 33 Supra (note 1 above) at [34]. 34 Supra (note 23 above) at [11]. 35 Supra (note 14 above), 212D-E, cited ibid at [12]. 36 Supra (n 14 above), 238H-239A. 37 Supra (note 1 above) at [27]. 38 This is trite law, and is evident in such cases as AAG v Estate of AAH, deceased [2010] 1 SLR 769 at [7]; Seow Wei Sin v Public Prosecutor [2011] 1 SLR 1199 at [21]; Building Construction Employees and Builders’ Labourers Federation of New South Wales v Minister for Industrial Relations (1986) 7 NSWLR 372, 406B; and R v Secretary of State for the Home Department, ex parte Simms [2000] 2 AC 115, 131F. 39 [2012] 4 SLR 476. *BA (Hons) (1st Class) Jurisprudence (Oxon); currently reading for the BCL (Oxon). Notes Feature 1 Calvin Liang and Sarah Shi, Singapore Law Gazette (August 2014), p 12. 40 Supra (note 1 above) at [29]. 2 Ibid, preamble, [3], [23]ff, [37]ff. 41 Supra (note 1 above) at [40]. 3 AIR 1973 SC 1461. 42 Cf. the criticism by the authors at note 1 at [41]. 4 I C Golak Nath v State of Punjab AIR 1967 SC 1643. 43 Ibid at [3]. 5 Sikri CJ, Shelat, Hegde, Grover, Jaganmohan Reddy, Khanna, and Mukherjea JJ, cited Subba Rao, “The Two Judgments: Golaknath and Kesavananda Bharati” (1973) 2 SCC (Jour) 1, J-18. 44 (1992) 177 CLR 106, 135. Singapore Law Gazette November 2014 Feature 42 45 Ibid, 170. 46 Ibid, 137-138. 75 Supra (note 3 above), p 1624 at [669]; p 1628 at [680]. 47 Cf. the fact that the Australian Constitution makes no explicit mention of fundamental rights because of a “deliberate” choice based upon a faith in the democratic process to protect Australian citizens against unwarranted incursions upon the freedoms which they enjoy”, such protection to be done “by the constituencies and not by the courts”: ibid, 182, (per Dawson J, dissenting). 76 Dicey, Introduction to the Study of the Law of the Constitution (10e, 1959), pp 76-81. 77 Supra (note 14 above), pp 238-239. 78 Jeyaretnam Kenneth Andrew v Attorney-General [2014] 1 SLR 345 at [48]. 79 R (Jackson) v Attorney-General [2006] 1 AC 262, [102], cited supra (note 1 above) at [50]. 48 or abridge fundamental rights” but have such an amendment blocked by the judiciary. (1926) 38 CLR 153, 178-179 49 Supra (note 3 above), p 1535, at [302]. 80 Supra (note 38 above). 50 Supra (note 3 above), p 1603 at [599]. 81 Supra (note 3 above), eg p 1750 at [1163]. 51 Supra (note 3 above), p 1693 at [959]. 82 Chan, “Judicial Review – From Angst to Empathy” (2010) 22 SAcLJ 469, p 480. 52 Supra (note 3 above),pp 1601-1602 at [594]. 83 53 Supra (note 3 above), p 1902 at [1548(2)]. For a comment on the difference that the green-light model made to the case, see Ong, “Public law theory and judicial review in Singapore” (2013) Singapore Law Watch Commentary (Issue 1/Dec 2013), p 3 54 Supra (note 3 above), pp 1901-1902 at [1547] 84 55 Supra (note 3 above), p 1639 at [722]. 56 Section 1, Constitution of Mauritius, as interpreted in State of Mauritius v Khoyratty [2007] 1 AC 80. As it did in Vellama d/o Marie Muthu v Attorney-General [2013] 4 SLR 1. See also the arguments in Kavanagh, “Proportionality and Parliamentary Debates: Exploring Some Forbidden Territory” (2014) 34 OJLS 443 (albeit in a different context). 85 Section 9A(2), Interpretation Act (Cap 1). 57 Preamble, Constitution of India. 86 Supra (note 38 above). 58 Preamble and Arts 20 and 79(3), Basic Law for the Federal Republic of Germany, trans Tomuscha, Currie, and Kommers; available at: https://www.btg-bestellservice. de/pdf/80201000.pdf (accessed 3 October 2014). 87 (1986) 7 NSWLR 372, pp 405D-E 88 Hart, “Positivism and the Separation of Law and Morals” (1958) 71 HarvLRev 493, section IV. 89 Kavanagh, “Participation and Judicial Review: A Reply to Jeremy Waldron” (2003) 22 Law and Philosophy 451. 90 See generally the possible models in Weill, “Evolution vs Revolution: Dueling Models of Dualism” (2006) 54 American Journal of Comparative Law 429. 91 Kirby, 1997 Deakin Law School Public Oration: Popular Sovereignty and the True Foundation of the Australian Constitution; available at: http://www.hcourt.gov.au/ assets/publications/speeches/former-justices/kirbyj/kirbyj_deakin2.htm (accessed 6 October 2014), fn 35. 92 Supra (note 3 above), p 1850 at [1406]; p 1859 at [1436]. 59 Section 1, Constitution of Belize, as interpreted in Bowen v Attorney-General BZ 2009 SC 2 (cited supra (note 1 above) at [17], though it is here argued that the Court in fact did not go so far as to hold that the principle of democracy was part of the “basic structure” of the Constitution of Belize in the Kesavananda sense). 60 Proclamation of Singapore, part of preamble to Independence of Singapore Act 1965. 61 Article 3; art 6(1)(a); and Part IV respectively. 62 [2007] 1 AC 80, [12]. 63 In Singapore, such limits include (for example) the requirement that deprivation of life or personal liberty be done only “in accordance with law” (art 9(1)) and that the rights to freedom of speech, expression, assembly, and association can only be restricted by Parliament, which must “consider” the restrictions necessary on one of a limited number of grounds. 64 Supra (note 5 above), J-6. 65 Supra (note 1 above) at [47]. 66 Tripathi, “Kesavananda Bharati v The State of Kerela: Who Wins?”, (1973) 1 SCC (Jour) 3, J-32. 67 Supra (note 1 above) at [48]. 68 Supra (note 1 above) at [44]. 69 1 BVerfGE 14 (1951), cited supra (note 1 above) at [42]; reproduced in Kommers, The Constitutional Jurisprudence of the Federal Republic of Germany (2e, 1997), p 62 at [2]-[3]. 70 (2011) 44 Israel LR 321, 336-338, cited supra (note 1 above) at [42]. 71 Supra (note 1 above) at [43]. 72 Supra (note 3 above), p 1861 at [1444]. 73 Preamble, Basic Law for the Federal Republic of Germany, supra (note 58 above). 74 To use the phrase of Khanna J, supra (note 3 above), p 1850 at [1406]. It is notable that Khanna J saw undesirable revolution as the product of inflexibility in constitutional amendment, eg if “the overwhelming majority of people” were to want to “take away Singapore Law Gazette November 2014