UNIT 2: EMPIRICISM HANDOUT 3: LOCKE’S ESSAY, BOOK II CHAPTER XXVII 1: DIFFERENTIATION AND IDENTITY In chapter XXVII Locke addresses how we derive our ideas of identity and diversity. In other words, how we come to think that two entities are the same or that two entities are different. There are two questions regarding identity. Question 1 (Principle of Differentiation): How can we differentiate one object from another at any given instant? Question 2 (Identity over Time): What accounts for the identity of some object over time? In other words question 2 fills in the blank of the following sentence. X at time t1 and Y at a later time t2 are identical if and only if . 1.1 LOCKE’S PRINCIPLE OF DIFFERENTIATION Most of Locke’s discussion focuses on Question 2, but he begins with Question 1. Locke argues that two objects must be different if they cannot occupy the same place at the same time. When we see anything to be in any place in any instant of time, we are sure (be it what it will) that it is that very thing, and not another which at that same time exists in another place, how like and undistinguishable soever it may be in all other respects: and in this consists identity, when the ideas it is attributed to vary not at all from what they were that moment wherein we consider their former existence, and to which we compare the present. For we never finding, nor conceiving it possible, that two things of the same kind should exist in the same place at the same time, we rightly conclude, that, whatever exists anywhere at any time, excludes all of the same kind, and is there itself alone (134). This leads Locke to posit the following as the “Principum individuationis.” From what has been said, it is easy to discover what is so much inquired after, the principium individuationis; and that, it is plain, is existence itself; which determines a being of any sort to a particular time and place, incommunicable to two beings of the same kind (135). 1.2 IDENTITY AND KIND This brings us to the issue of how can something preserve its identity over time. One of Locke’s most lasting contributions to this question has to do with his idea that identity over time depends upon what sort of being that thing is. For Locke, the identity of material bodies over time is rather fluid. 1 For, being at that instant what it is, and nothing else, it is the same, and so must continue as long as its existence is continued; for so long it will be the same, and no other. In like manner, if two or more atoms be joined together into the same mass, every one of those atoms will be the same, by the foregoing rule: and whilst they exist united together, the mass, consisting of the same atoms, must be the same mass, or the same body, let the parts be ever so differently jumbled. But if one of these atoms be taken away, or one new one added, it is no longer the same mass or the same body (135). For material bodies, any change in that body will make it such that it is no longer the same thing. This might seem like a rather strange idea at first. Consider the much discussed ship of Theseus. In this thought experiment we are to imagine that over time all of the material components of the ship have been replaced from when it was originally made. This brings up the question of whether the ship is still the same. Many people’s intuitions are that the same ship does remain, but at first glance it might seem that Locke’s theory cannot give us that conclusion. This is because there has been change in the material constitution of the ship. However, this is not the case. Locke points out that we have to consider what kind, or sort, of thing we are talking about. Considered as a material body, the ship of Theseus is no longer identical to what it was before. Yet, considered as a ship (something meant to sail certain routes at sea) it is still the same ship. This is because it still serves the function that is associated with its kind. Thus, it depends upon the kind of thing we are talking about. We can see this from Locke’s discussion of the identity of living creatures. In the state of living creatures, their identity depends not on a mass of the same particles, but on something else. For in them the variation of great parcels of matter alters not the identity: an oak growing from a plant to a great tree, and then lopped, is still the same oak; and a colt grown up to a horse, sometimes fat, sometimes lean, is all the while the same horse: though, in both these cases, there may be a manifest change of the parts; so that truly they are not either of them the same masses of matter, though they be truly one of them the same oak, and the other the same horse. The reason whereof is, that, in these two cases a mass of matter and a living body identity is not applied to the same thing (136). Locke notes that when an oak tree grows taller, or some of its branches are chopped off, we do not say that it is a different oak tree. It may be a different material object, but it still serves the same function of oak tree. Of course, there will be other oak trees that serve that function as well. However, they are not all the same because (according to Locke’s principle of differentiation) they cannot occupy the same space at the same time. Locke applies the same sort of analysis to the identity of non-human animals as well, noting that their identity consists in the organization they have toward some end (136). 2: IDENTITY OF THE HUMAN ANIMAL The identity of human beings, however, is more complicated. Locke notes that human beings can be considered under three different types: substance, man (human animal), and person (137). We can consider humans as a substance (as either a body or soul), a member of the biological human 2 species, and as persons (which as we will see Locke equates with reason and consciousness). Human identity will differ depending upon what concept we are considering the human being under. 2.1 REJECTING SOUL THEORY Locke notes that the identity of a human being (the biological species) is determined in the same way as all other animals. This also shows wherein the identity of the same man consists; viz. in nothing but a participation of the same continued life, by constantly fleeting particles of matter, in succession vitally united to the same organized body (137). Locke makes clear that in taking this position he is rejecting the soul theory of identity. Soul theory states the following. Some human being X at time t1 and some human being Y at a later time t2 are identical if and only if X and Y share the same soul. Descartes, for instance, seems to accept this view when he states that what we are is a thinking thing. Locke does not disagree with this view because he denies the existence of a soul. He just does not think it explains animal identity very well. This goes back to something we saw him discuss previously with the possibility of souls moving from one body to another. For if the identity of soul alone makes the same man; and there be nothing in the nature of matter why the same individual spirit may not be united to different bodies, it will be possible that those men, living in distant ages, and of different tempers, may have been the same man: which way of speaking must be from a very strange use of the word man, applied to an idea out of which body and shape are excluded. And that way of speaking would agree yet worse with the notions of those philosophers who allow of transmigration, and are of opinion that the souls of men may, for their miscarriages, be detruded into the bodies of beasts, as fit habitations, with organs suited to the satisfaction of their brutal inclinations. But yet I think nobody, could he be sure that the soul of Heliogabalus were in one of his hogs, would yet say that hog were a man or Heliogabalus (137). If souls can move from one body to another, then people who never shared any of the same material body could be the same animal. Locke thinks this idea is absurd and therefore rejects the soul as a criterion of identity of the human animal. Locke notes later, in section 21, that human identity must consist both of body and soul: “the same immaterial spirit united to the same animal” (145). 2.2 ANIMAL IDENTITY AND REASON Thus, animal identity is simply determined by having certain parts that are coordinated to bring about some end and serve some function. What is important is having our body organized in the correct way. This implies that reason is not especially important to our human identity. 3 Since I think I may be confident, that, whoever should see a creature of his own shape or make, though it had no more reason all its life than a cat or a parrot, would call him still a man; or whoever should hear a cat or a parrot discourse, reason, and philosophize, would call or think it nothing but a cat or a parrot; and say, the one was a dull irrational man, and the other a very intelligent rational parrot. A relation we have in an author of great note, is sufficient to countenance the supposition of a rational parrot (138). A human who cannot use language or reason is still a human, and a parrot that can do those things is still a parrot. Each has the correct biological structure of its kind. 3: PERSONAL IDENTITY However, Locke’s main concern here lies with a different type of identity entirely: personal identity. What does it mean to say that X at t1 and Y at t2 are the same person? 3.1 LOCKE’S DEFINITION OF PERSON Understanding personal identity requires first understanding what it means to be a person. This being premised, to find wherein personal identity consists, we must consider what person stands for; which, I think, is a thinking intelligent being, that has reason and reflection, and can consider itself as itself, the same thinking thing, in different times and places; which it does only by that consciousness which is inseparable from thinking, and, as it seems to me, essential to it: it being impossible for anyone to perceive without perceiving that he does perceive. When we see, hear, smell, taste, feel, meditate, or will anything, we know that we do so (138). Locke states that persons have the following sorts of characteristics. (i) thought (ii) intelligence (iii) reason and reflection (iv) self awareness of one’s existence over time and place (v) self awareness of one’s perceptions Thus, though Locke’s previously described rational parrot is not a human, it does seem that being is a person. This has some interesting implications. Consider someone who gets in a car accident and as a result ends up in a coma. We might ask the question is the person prior to the accident the same as the person after the accident? Locke would say that it depends upon the manner in which we are conceiving this person. The person prior to the accident, and following the accident, are the same human animal. The body is organized in the same way in each case. However, after the accident the person is like the non rational human that Locke mentions above. Yet, they would not be the same person. The person in the coma no longer shares the same stream of consciousness with the person 4 before the accident, or even has any stream of consciousness. That person does not presently exist even though their physical body is still technically alive. 3.2 PERSONAL IDENTITY AND MEMORY For Locke, we know that two persons are identical if they are connected by consciousness. More specifically, Locke uses a criterion where memory is what is of primary importance. For, since consciousness always accompanies thinking, and it is that which makes every one to be what he calls self, and thereby distinguishes himself from all other thinking things, in this alone consists personal identity, i.e. the sameness of a rational being: and as far as this consciousness can be extended backwards to any past action or thought, so far reaches the identity of that person; it is the same self now it was then; and it is by the same self with this present one that now reflects on it, that that action was done (138). We can state this more formally as the following. Some person X at t1 and some person Y at t2 are the same person if and only if Y remembers being X. 3.3 PERSONAL IDENTITY AND (BODILY/MENTAL) SUBSTANCE If this is the case, then two people do not have to share the same substance in order to be identical. This is the case both for material substance (body) and mental substance (soul). Locke first provides an example involving bodily substance. Thus, the limbs of his body are to every one a part of Himself; he sympathizes and is concerned for them. Cut off a hand, and thereby separate it from that consciousness he had of its heat, cold, and other affections, and it is then no longer a part of that which is himself, any more than the remotest part of matter. Thus, we see the substance whereof personal self consisted at one time may be varied at another, without the change of personal identity; there being no question about the same person, though the limbs which but now were a part of it, be cut off (139). 3.3.1 TWO SOULS AND ONE PERSON The same holds for mental substance as well. But yet, to return to the question before us, it must be allowed, that, if the same consciousness (which, as has been shown, is quite a different thing from the same numerical figure or motion in body) can be transferred from one thinking substance to another, it will be possible that two thinking substances may make but one person. For the same consciousness being preserved, whether in the same or different substances, the personal identity is preserved (141). 5 Imagine the soul as a kind of container for consciousness. In fact, recall from earlier that Locke believes the soul is just a passive receptacle. Imagine also two people: person X and person Y. Person X is conscious and person Y is in a coma (and of course unconscious). All of a sudden X’s stream of consciousness is removed from X’s soul and placed into Y’s soul causing X to enter a coma and Y to wake up from a coma. According to Locke, X and Y would have different souls, but they would be the same person. What is important for personal identity is having psychological connectedness through memory. 3.3.2 ONE SOUL AND TWO PERSONS Locke also brings up a case where there could be a single soul but multiple people. Suppose a Christian Platonist or a Pythagorean should, upon God's having ended all his works of creation the seventh day, think his soul hath existed ever since; and should imagine it has revolved in several human bodies […] would anyone say, that he, being not conscious of any of Socrates's actions or thoughts, could be the same person with Socrates? Let any one reflect upon himself, and conclude that he has in himself an immaterial spirit, which is that which thinks in him, and, in the constant change of his body keeps him the same: and is that which he calls himself: let him also suppose it to be the same soul that was in Nestor or Thersites, at the siege of Troy, (for souls being, as far as we know anything of them, in their nature indifferent to any parcel of matter, the supposition has no apparent absurdity in it), which it may have been, as well as it is now the soul of any other man: but he now having no consciousness of any of the actions either of Nestor or Thersites, does or can he conceive himself the same person with either of them? Can he be concerned in either of their actions? attribute them to himself, or think them his own, more than the actions of any other men that ever existed? […] For this would no more make him the same person with Nestor, than if some of the particles of matter that were once a part of Nestor were now a part of this man; the same immaterial substance, without the same consciousness, no more making the same person, by being united to anybody, than the same particle of matter, without consciousness, united to anybody, makes the same person. But let him once find himself conscious of any of the actions of Nestor, he then finds himself the same person with Nestor (141-142). If in a past life, for instance, Ryan’s soul was in the body of Socrates, this does not mean that Ryan is the same person as Socrates. This is because Ryan cannot remember anything about Socrates or share any stream of consciousness with him. We can imagine a similar case with someone who has Dissociative Identity Disorder (formerly Multiple Personality Disorder). This is described in the Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders (4th edition) as the following. Dissociative Identity Disorder reflects a failure to integrate various aspects of identity, memory, and consciousness. Each personality state may be as if it has a distinct personal history, self-image, and identity, including a separate name.1 1 Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders, 4th edition, 526. 6 If this person has two streams of consciousness, each of which has no recollection of the other, then there would be (for Locke) two persons sharing one mental substance. Thus, the soul is not primary for Locke when determining personal identity. We should already be familiar with this idea from Locke’s Castor and Pollux example in Part I. He also provides a very similar example of the day man and the night man on pg. 146. 3.4 RESURRECTION AND THE BODY Locke also believes that his account of personal identity can provide an explanation of certain problems that arose at the time for thinking about life after death.2 According to the Bible in the afterlife we will have the same body as we had when we were on Earth. One of Locke’s contemporaries, Robert Boyle, noted that this brings up a number of problematic issues. When a man is once really dead, divers of the parts of his body will, according to the course of nature, resolve themselves into multitudes of steams that wander to and fro in the air; and the remaining parts, that are either liquid or soft, undergo so great a corruption and change, that it is not possible so many scattered parts should be again brought together, and reunited after the same manner, wherein the existed in a human body whilst it was yet alive. And much more impossible it is to effect this reunion, if the body have been, as it often happens, devoured by wild beasts or fishes; since in this case, though the scattered parts of the cadaver might be recovered as particles of matter, yet already having passed into the substance of other animals, they are quite transmuted, as being informed by the new form of the beast or fish that devoured them and of which they now make a substantial part.3 It is unclear how our body is supposed to be reassembled in the afterlife. The problem is even more pressing when we think of those who die as a result of being eaten by cannibals. And yet far more impossible will this reintegration be, if we put the case that the dead man was devoured by cannibals; for then, the same flesh belonging successively to two different persons, it is impossible that both should have it restored to them at once, or that any footsteps should remain of the relation it had to the first possessor.4 How can one’s body reappear in heaven when it has combined with the body of another person? Locke believes that his theory can make sense of this issue by stressing that bodily continuity is not the most important aspect of personal identity. The body, as well as the soul, goes to the making of a man. And thus may we be able, without any difficulty, to conceive the same person at the resurrection, though in a body not exactly in make or parts the same which he had here,- the same See Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Entry, Personal Identity and the Immateriality of the Soul, Supplement to John Locke, on this point (link). 3 Robert Boyle, Selected Philosophical Papers of Robert Boyle, ed. M.A. Stewart, Manchester University Press, New York, 1979. 198. 4 Ibid., 198. 2 7 consciousness going along with the soul that inhabits it. But yet the soul alone, in the change of bodies, would scarce to anyone but to him that makes the soul the man, be enough to make the same man (142). He argues for this with an example of a prince and a cobbler. For should the soul of a prince, carrying with it the consciousness of the prince's past life, enter and inform the body of a cobbler, as soon as deserted by his own soul, everyone sees he would be the same person with the prince, accountable only for the prince's actions: but who would say it was the same man? The body too goes to the making the man, and would, I guess, to everybody determine the man in this case, wherein the soul, with all its princely thoughts about it, would not make another man: but he would be the same cobbler to everyone besides himself (142). If the souls of the prince and the cobbler were switched, then according to Locke’s view the prince would be waking up in the cobbler’s body and the cobbler would be waking up in the prince’s body. However, because there has been such radical change in the composition of each entity, neither would be the same “man” they were before. Thus, the fact that the being in heaven does not have the same sort of bodily organization as the person who lived on earth does not mean that we cannot survive our deaths. All that matters is that our stream of consciousness continues in the afterlife. 4: PERSONAL IDENTITY AND MORAL/LEGAL RESPONSIBILITY One of advantages Locke thinks it has is that it explains our views about moral responsibility, reward, and punishment. In this personal identity is founded all the right and justice of reward and punishment; happiness and misery being that for which everyone is concerned for himself, and not mattering what becomes of any substance, not joined to, or affected with that consciousness (144). Recall the example we looked at earlier when discussing Leibniz. Imagine Bob1 committed a murder. When the police eventually arrest someone for the crime they will not be arresting Bob1, but instead will arrest Bob2. How is this fair? It only seems fair if Bob1 and Bob2 are the same person. Locke thinks that when we accuse someone of a crime we only feel we are identifying the right person if that person can remember doing the crime; namely, if Bob2 remembered committing the crime of Bob1. 4.1 RESPONSIBILITY AND FORGETTING OUR WRONGS Consider the following example. This may show us wherein personal identity consists: not in the identity of substance, but, as I have said, in the identity of consciousness, wherein if Socrates and the present mayor of Quinborough agree, they are the same person: if the same Socrates waking and sleeping do not partake of the same consciousness, Socrates waking and sleeping is not the same person. And to punish Socrates waking for what sleeping 8 Socrates thought, and waking Socrates was never conscious of, would be no more of right, than to punish one twin for what his brother-twin did, whereof he knew nothing, because their outsides were so like, that they could not be distinguished; for such twins have been seen (144). If Socrates committed a crime while he was sleep walking, it would be wrong (in Locke’s view) to punish Awake Socrates for that crime if Awake Socrates had no recollection of doing it. Locke notes that some will object that even if we forget what we did in the past, we were still the one’s who performed those actions. Locke again appeals to the distinction between man and person. But yet possibly it will still be objected, Suppose I wholly lose the memory of some parts of my life, beyond a possibility of retrieving them, so that perhaps I shall never be conscious of them again; yet am I not the same person that did those actions, had those thoughts that I once was conscious of, though I have now forgot them? To which I answer, that we must here take notice what the word I is applied to; which, in this case, is the man only. And the same man being presumed to be the same person, I is easily here supposed to stand also for the same person. But if it be possible for the same man to have distinct incommunicable consciousness at different times, it is past doubt the same man would at different times make different persons; which, we see, is the sense of mankind in the solemnest declaration of their opinions, human laws not punishing the mad man for the sober man's actions, nor the sober man for what the mad man did, thereby making them two persons: which is somewhat explained by our way of speaking in English when we say such an one is "not himself," or is "beside himself"; in which phrases it is insinuated, as if those who now, or at least first used them, thought that self was changed; the selfsame person was no longer in that man (144-145). Imagine someone who committed a crime while blacked out drunk, and then had no recollection of it the next morning. Locke admits it was the same “man” who did the crime; however, it is not the same person. Therefore, the sober person is not technically responsible for the crime. Dissociative Personal Disorder is again relevant here. 4.2 PRACTICAL REASONS FOR LEGAL PUNISHMENT The sober man is not genuinely responsible for the madman’s actions because the sober man and the madman are not the same person (even if they are the same man). However, Locke admits that we might still have some practical reasons to punish the sober man for the madman’s misdeeds. Human laws punish both, with a justice suitable to their way of knowledge;- because, in these cases, they cannot distinguish certainly what is real, what counterfeit: and so the ignorance in drunkenness or sleep is not admitted as a plea. For, though punishment be annexed to personality, and personality to consciousness, and the drunkard perhaps be not conscious of what he did, yet human judicatures justly punish him; because the fact is proved against him, but want of consciousness cannot be proved for him. But in the Great Day, wherein the secrets of all hearts shall be laid open, it may be reasonable to think, no one shall be made to answer for 9 what he knows nothing of, but shall receive his doom, his conscience accusing or excusing him (146). We are still justified in punishing the sober man, because our knowledge is limited. As a practical matter, it would be impossible to determine in every case whether someone really committed a crime or not. If this seems wrong, Locke tries to comfort us by appealing to divine justice. God would only punish the madman’s stream of consciousness, but not the sober man’s stream of consciousness. 4.3 “PERSON” IS A FORENSIC TERM From this Locke draws a conclusion about the purpose of denominating someone a person. "Person" a forensic term. Person, as I take it, is the name for this self. Wherever a man finds what he calls himself, there, I think, another may say is the same person. It is a forensic term, appropriating actions and their merit; and so belongs only to intelligent agents, capable of a law, and happiness, and misery. This personality extends itself beyond present existence to what is past, only by consciousness,whereby it becomes concerned and accountable; owns and imputes to itself past actions, just upon the same ground and for the same reason as it does the present. All which is founded in a concern for happiness, the unavoidable concomitant of consciousness; that which is conscious of pleasure and pain, desiring that that self that is conscious should be happy. And therefore whatever past actions it cannot reconcile or appropriate to that present self by consciousness, it can be no more concerned in than if they had never been done: and to receive pleasure or pain, i.e. reward or punishment, on the account of any such action, is all one as to be made happy or miserable in its first being, without any demerit at all (148). Person is a forensic term, meaning its entire purpose is to allow us to denominate people as responsible for what they have done and worthy of praise, blame, reward, and punishment. 10