THE DOCTRINE OF LAST CLEAR CHANCE* The controversial doctrine of last clear chance appears to be passing out of existence. Taking its place in the law of torts are new doctrines which are better adapted to changes in our society. This conclusion can be sustained, it is believed, by an examination of the doctrine's present status in our courts and by an analysis of the theories behind the doctrine. The celebrated "Donkey 4Case" of Davies v. Mann' illustrates how the doctrine is applied. This case, thought to be the origin of the doctrine of last dear chance, was decided in England in 1842. The plaintiff shackled the forefeet of his donkey and left it on the highway. Subsequently, the defendant came past, traveling a short distance behind his wagon team "at smartest pace." Because of the defendant's negligence, the wagon team ran over the donkey and killed it. It was held that the defendant was liable, for even though the accident would not have happened but for plaintiff's leaving his donkey on the highway so fettered as to prevent its getting out of the way of carriages, the defendant, by the use of care and prudence, had the last dear opportunity to avoid the danger.2 The court concluded that "though the act of the plaintiff might be illegal," still if the accident was caused by defendant's improper conduct, and the defendant could with proper care avoid the accident, plaintiff may recover. Or, to express it more succinctly, "When an accident happens through the combined negligence of two persons, he alone is liable to the other who had the last opportunity of avoiding the accident by reasonable care."' The doctrine has a variety of names in addition to last clear chance. In some jurisdictions it is referred to as the humanitarian doctrine;' in others it is known as the doctrine of discovered peril.' Some jurisdictions call it the doctrine of discovered negligence; some call it the doctrine of subsequent negligence." Still others refer to it as the doctrine of superven. ing negligence.! At least one court has called it the doctrine of antecedent and subsequent negligence Several courts know it as the Rule of Davies V. Mat,4.2 Requisites and Conditions The application of the doctrine presupposes negligence on the part of the person injured. If the plaintiff has not, by accepted standards, been guilty of negligence, then there is no need to consider the doctrine. * By Alexander L. Benton, L.L.B., American University, while a student at Washington College of Law, American University. Member of District of Columbia Bar. 1 10 M & W 546, 152 Eng. Reprint 588 (1842). 2 10 M & W 549, 152 Eng. Reprint 589 (1842). , Salmond on Torts (8th Ed. 1934), p. 480. 4l Winegardner v. Afanny, 237 Iowa 412, 21 N.W. 2d 209 (1946); Alullins v. Cincinnati, N. & C. Ry. Co., 253 Ky. 156, 68 S.W. 2d 790 (1934); Bohlen, Cases on Torts (4th Ed. 1941), p. 522n: "Only in Missouri and Virginia is the humanitarian doctrine applied, as such, although in substance itappears in many other states by a failure on the part of the courts to distinguish between a p aintiff who by his negligence gets himself into a physically helpless position of peril and one who is merely psychologically helpless, i. e., negligently inattentive. Is the distinction justifiable?" 5Barlow v. Lowery, 143 Me. 214, 59 A. 2d 702 (1948). 0 Cline v. Killingbech, 288 Mich 126 284 N.W. 669 (1939). 1Hulsey v. Ill. Cent. Ry. Co., 242 Ala. 136, 5 So. 2d 403 (1941). 8 Tefft v. N.Y., N.H. & H. Ry. Co., 116 Conn. 127, 163 A. 762 (1933). 9 Union Traction Co. v. Ringer, 199 Ind. 405, 155 N.E. 826 (1927). "0Lovell v. Sandersville R. Co., 72 Ga. App. 2d 692, 34 S.E. 2d 664 (1945) [58] The very core of the doctrine is founded upon the fact that both parties to the controversy have been guilty of negligence. The doctrine is used to counteract the defendant's defense that the plaintiff was guilty of contributory negligence, which prior to the advent of Davies v. Mann was a good defense and a complete bar to the plaintiff's recovery. But it does not by any means follow that, because both parties are negligent, the conditions for applying the doctrine have been met. As one authority holds, "If the defendant does not discover the plaintiff's situation, but merely might do so by proper vigilance, it is obvious that neither party can be said to have a 'last dear' chance. The plaintiff is still in a position to escape, and his lack of attention continues up to the point of the accident, without the interval of superior opportunity of the defendant which has been considered so important. The plaintiff may not demand of the defendant greater care for his own protection than he exercises himself. All but a few courts hold that there can be no recovery".U The so-called "Washington Formula,'" devised by the Supreme Court of the State of Washington, states the conditions for applying the doctrine as follows: "Where the defendant actually saw the peril of a traveler on the highway, and should have appreciated the danger, and failed to exercise reasonable care to avoid injury, such failure made the defendant liable, although the plaintiff's negligence may have continued up to the instant of the injury. Where the defendant did not actually see the peril of the plaintiff, but, by keeping a reasonably careful lookout commensurate with the dangerous character of the agency and the locality, should have seen the peril and appreciated it in time, by the exercise of reasonable care, to have avoided the injury, and failure to escape the injury results from failure to keep the lookout and exercise that care, the defendant was liable only when the plaintiff's negligence had terminated or culminated in a situation of peril from which the plaintiff could not, by the exercise of reasonable care, extricate himself." But, to illustrate the lack of accord that exists, negligence of the injured person is not included as one of the essential elements of the doctrine in some jurisdictions. It is held that, provided the injured person did not voluntarily seek injury, the cause of his peril is immaterial.' In Mooney v. Terminal Railway Association of St. Louis," the court held that a plaintiff may recover under the humanitarian doctrine, although he was guilty of any contributory negligence, and consequently could have sued also for any primary negligence of the defendant proximately causing his injury. Present Status of the Doctrine Generally speaking, courts presently limit application of the doctrine of last clear chance in several ways. The doctrine is not applicable where the emergency is so sudden that there is no time to avert the accident. 11Prosser on Torts (1941), . 414. 13Leftridge v. Seatle, 130 Wash. 541, 228 P. 302 (1924). Teague v. Plaza Express Co., 354 Mo. 582, 190 S.W. 2d 254, 258 (1945) 4 353 Mo. 245, 176 S.W. 2d 605 (1944). sa [ 59] As was said in Bagwill v. Pacific Electric Railway Co.,' "Certainly the doctrine of last clear chance never meant -a splitting of seconds when emergencies arise. . . The words mean exactly as they indicate, namely, last clear chance, not possible chance." Other cases have expressed a similar view? Another limitation of the doctrine is its inapplicability where the defendant, although aware of the plaintiff's perilous situation, is prevented by his own antecedent negligence from avoiding it.a Generally, courts refuse to apply the doctrine where both plaintiff and defendant are negligent in being equally inattentive, or where there is lacking sufficient evidence to establish not only actual knowledge of the plaintiff's peril, but also the existence of such knowledge at a time when it is within the defendant's power to avert the injury. Forcefully demonstrating this is the decision in Panarese et at. v. Union Railway Co. of N.Y.C.' This was an action for the death of pedestrian who negligently ran into an approaching street car. The court held that the street railway company was not liable, although the motorman might have stopped the car by exercising reasonable care; that the doctrine of last clear chance does not apply where two people are both guilty of continuous negligence causing injury to one of -them; and that to render the street railway company liable under the last dear chance doctrine, the motorman must have actually known, not only that the decedent was in peril, but that he would or could not get out of the way in time to stop the car by exercising reasonable care. In WIoloszynowski v. N. Y. Central Railroad Co." the court also refused to apply the doctrine. In that case the plaintiff, a boy struck by defendant's engine, went upon the -tracks after the lowering of the gates, and stood there in the path of the train and within the overhang of the engine without looking to the right or left. The court said: "The doctrine of last dear chance, however, is never wakened into action unless and until there is brought home to the defendant to be charged with liability a knowledge that another is in a state of present peril, in which event there must be a reasonable effort to counteract the peril and avert its consequences. Knowledge may be established by circumstantial evidence, in the face even of profession of ignorance; but knowledge there must be, or a negligence so reckless as to betoken indifference to knowledge." Admiralty courts do not generally apply the doctrine of last dear chance. To determine which party shall bear the loss or the greater part thereof, one of two rules is used, i.e., either the equal division of loss rule or the apportionment rule. Under the equal division rule, if there is a collision between two ships, and both are unquestionably at faulteither equally or in varying degrees-the total damages sustained by both parties are determined, and each party is assessed one-half of the total 1"90 Cal. App. 114, 121, 265 P. 517, 519 (1928). =DeVore V. Paris,88 Cal. App. 2d 576, 199 P. 2d 391 (1948); Correnl v. Calino, 115 Conn. 213, 160 A. 892 (1932). 11Johnson v. Dir. Gen. of Railroads, 81 N.H. 289, 125 A. 147 (1924); Capolla v. R.I. Co., 103 A. 700 (1918). 18261 N.Y. 233, 185 N.E. 84 (1933). "254 N.Y. 206, 172 N.E. 471 (1930). [601 sum." Under the apportionment rule, admiralty courts apportion responsibility for the damages, and each party must bear that portion of the total loss directly attributable to his negligent conduct.4 The present status of the doctrine of last clear chance in courts which apply it can be summarized by classifying the principal cases under four well-recognized categories:' 1. Plaintiff is helpless, and defendant has a conscious last dear chance to avoid injury to plaintiff. Plaintiff can recover. 2. Plaintiff is inattentive, and defendant has a conscious last dear chance to avoid injury to plaintiff Plaintiff generally can recover. 3. Plaintiff is helpless, and defendant has an unconscious last clear chance to avoid injury to plaintiff. There is serious conflict of authority as to plaintiffs recovery, although there is much authority for it." 4. Plaintiff is inattentive, and defendant has an unconscious last clear chance to avoid injury to plaintiff. By the great weight of authority, plaintiff cannot recover. Legal Justification There have been a number of attempts to justify the doctrine of last clear chance on the basis of some legal theory. As a result, there have evolved two major factions, one of which advances the theory that the rule of proximate cause is being applied to a situation where both the plaintiff and the defendant are guilty of contributory negligence.' The negligence of the plaintiff is considered a remote cause. The defendant's negligence is failing to exercise ordinary care to avoid harming the plaintiff becomes the immediate or proximate cause of the accident. This subsequent negligence is considereJ as intervening between the accident and the more remote negligence of the plaintiff. ' This theory has been subjected to severe criticism. One commentator writes: "The unsoundness of the 'proximate cause' basis of the exception (i.e., last clear chance) may be demonstrated in another fashion. If the negligence of both plaintiff and defendant cause injury to a third person, both plaintiff and defendant may be held liable, even though the defendant had the last clear chance. Clearly plaintiff could not be held unless his negligence was a proximate cause of the injury. Nor can plaintiff defend on the ground that defendant had the last dear chance. It is a simple case of two or more proximate causes producing the injury, any one or more of which can be held responsible." " And, in Davies v. Swdn Mole and Wilson, A Stody of Comlarative Negligence, 17 Cornell 1932). The equal division of damages nile is applied by the U.S. This ception from the general practice of other nations. See The Margaret, 30 1929, Ibid.at 339. 340. "See Note, 92 A.L.R. 47, 83 (1934); 119 A.L.R. 1041, 1052 (1939); 375 (1947). L.Q. 339 (Apr., represents an exF.2d 923 (CA-3, 171 A.L.R. 365, ORestatement, Torts, Sec. 479(b)lII (1934). "Clari v. Wilmington & W. R. Co., 109 N.C. 430, 14 S.E. 43 (1891). _ Gregory v. Maine C. R. Co., 317 Mass. 636, 59 N.E. 2d 471 (1945); Seay v. So Ry. Carolina Div., 205 S.C. 162, 31 S.E. 2d 133 (1944). "Green, Contributory Negligence and Proximate caue, 6 N.C.L.R. 29, 30 (1927). [61) Moto" Co.,' the court said: "The doctrine of contributory negligence was based on causation. If the plaintiff's negligence was one of the causes of his own damage, he could not recover anything. In order to resolve the question of causation, the courts used to apply the so-called doctrine of last opportunity.' That was not a principle of law, but a test of causation. It was a fallacious test, because the efficiency of causes does not depend on their proximity in point of time; but it held sway for many years because it enabled the courts to mitigate the harshness of the doctrine of contributory negligence..." The use of the phrase "proximate cause" in many cases involving the doctrine is either a poor selection of words to describe the liability causative factor or -a poor use of the words selected, or it may be both. An example is treating as interchangeable such terms as "proximate cause," "legal cause," and "natural and probable consequence." ' Another critic of the doctrine writes: "According to the typical modern judicial statement, the last dear chance rule is no more than a logically necessary deduction from the principle of proximate cause; under it plaintiff can recover because his negligence is 'but a 'condition' or 'remote cause' of his injury, the defendant's wrong its sole 'proximate cause.' Now it must 'be obvious at once that this explanation cannot stand the most superficial analysis if it purports to apply to plaintiff the tests of legal cause generally used today in the inquiry as to a defendant's liability. This has often been demonstrated. Certainly if a man's negligence has put himself or his property in a position of peril, that negligence is a proximate cause of the injury which follows when the perils of the position become realized. In such case the likelihood of the danger that befell was one of the very things that made his original act negligent, and probable consequences are proximate ones." ' The conclusion to be gathered from the various hostile sentiments, with supporting reasons, relative to the validity of the proximate cause theory, is aptly summed up in the statement: "Questions arising under the last dear chance doctrine should not be confused ,by the injection of discussions of proximate cause. If the courts will consider the conscious control of the situation, they may well hold defendants responsible for failure to avoid accidents without attempting to express the doctrine in terms of cause." ' The other major theory, advanced by some of the more modern cases, and recommended by some of the leading authorities, expressly repudiates the proximate cause theory. This theory regards the last clear chance doctrine as a true exception to, rathef than a logical qualification of, the doctine of contributory negligence, so that when it operates, it permits a recovery in spite of contributory negligence. " This exception, its advocates hold, is fundamentally based upon practical considerations of what is required 'by fairness, comparative fault, social well-being and public policy." In Cavanaugh v. Boston & M. R. Co., the court said: "It may be ... that the real foundation for the rule is merely its fundamental justice and reasonableness. The justice of the rule that the contributory negli- (1949) 2 K.B. 291. "s See Myers, Causation and Common Sense, 5 Miami L. Q. 239 and n. 6 (1951). 2"James, Lait Clear Chance, 47 Yale L.J. 707 (1938). "Comment, 21 Cal. L.R. 265 (1933). [ 62] gence of the party injured will not defeat the action, if it can be shown that the defendant might, by the exercise of reasonable care and prudence, have avoided the consequences of the injured party's negligence, may be a sufficient foundation for it." " It is submitted that the 'true exception" theory has the greater appeal to logic and reason. Since the question of last clear chance is for the jury, it is difficult to perceive how the average jury would be able to comprehend the many distinctions incidental to an instruction on proximate cause as being the basis for liability under last dear chance. To attempt to set up a standard for the rendition of the jury's verdict on the basis of proximate cause merely tends to complicate and confuse. Indeed, it is not necessary, for a jury can readily arrive at a just verdict without recourse to one predominant cause to be selected from many possible causes. The jury is primarily concerned with whether the defendant or plaintiff is at fault, and whether the fault of one is greater than that of the other. The "true exception" theory, unhampered by the cumbersome dogma applied to causation, is much more easily explained by the court, and equally more easily understood by the jury. Reasons for the Doctrine Several reasons have been advanced for the doctrine of last clear chance; of them, three appear more frequently in the literature and are probably the more readily accepted. The first is a growing dissatisfaction with the defense of contributory negligence, which was a complete bar to recovery by the plaintiff. The doctrine of contributory negligence was a rigid rule, and it was strictly applied. This resulted in harsh consequences to the plaintiff in many instances, particularly where the plaintiff was at fault, but his fault or negligence was not nearly as great as that of the defendant. As was said by the court in West v. Gillette,' "The application of this rigid rule was in many cases found to work injustice, for it would surely be unjust to hold that one should be denied the protection of the law because of acts of carelessness on his part, which were followed by subsequent acts of negligence on the part of another, which latter acts were the proximate cause of the injury. It would, in effect, be holding that where, for example, one goes upon a railway track without exercising proper precautions as to danger, the railway company would be relieved thereafter of the duty to exercise ordinary care for his safety." The second reason is -based on humane considerations of fairness and comparative fault." Many juries, experience has shown, tend to decide BeKinney v. Chicago G. W.. R.R., 17 F.2d 708 (CA-8, 1927). See McCleary, The Basof the Humanitarian Doctrine Reexamined, 5 Mo. L.R. 61 (1940). 32Green, sapra Note 26 at 3. 31, 32; James, supra Note 29 at 704, 709, 715; Mactntyre, The Rationale of Last Clear Chance, 53 Harv. L.R. 1225, 1241, 1245 (1940). M76 N.H. 68, 79A. 694 (1911). ,495 Ohio St. 305, 116 N.E. 521, 522 (1917). "In Galena & Chicago Union R.R. v. Jacobs, 20 Ill.,478, 497 (1858), the court defined camparative negligence as follows: 'The degrees of negligence must be measured and considered; and whenever it shall appear that the plaintiff's negligence is comparatively slight and that of the defendant gross, he shall not be deprived of his action." [631 negligence cases on the basis of comparative fault."' For example, in Smith v. Dobson' the court issued rather specific and concise instructions which left no doubt that contributory negligence, no matter how slight, constituted a total bar to plaintiff's recovery. Notwithstanding these instructions, the jury's verdict awarded plaintiff one-quarter of the damages. This verdict was not disturbed on appeal, the court giving due cognizance to the fact that comparative fault was the basis for the jury's reasoning. Moreover, there is a feeling by some that the last dear chance doctrine is only a means of escape from the strict application of the contributory negligence doctrine, that the escape is disguised -by way of comparative fault. Summarily, it is considered unjust and inequitable to permit the defendant wholly to escape liability for his negligent act if his negligence was greater than that of the plaintiff.* The third reason for the doctrine of last clear chance centers around social well-being and "public policy." The doctrine is founded upon reasons humane which forbid a wrongdoer from taking advantage of the perilous position of his fellow man to inflict injury and escape responsibility. It is felt by some that to permit the defendant to escape liability under such circumstances disrupts the social order of a community and contravenes public policy."' The Future of the Doctrine It may be said that today the doctrine of last dear chance is anything but static. Several factors lend strong support to the conclusion that last dear chance is on the way out. There are courts which refuse to recognize the doctrine.' Some courts have never adopted it, and others have repudiated it since adoption of the apportionment of damages doctrine." There is a growing indication that the courts of Missouri are retreating from the humanitarian doctrine.' One leading authority" holds that there is no such rule as the last dear chance. His theory, in substance, is that -the 'basis of liability should be on the one whose act caused the harm, and not necessarily on the one who had the last opportunity to avoid the harm, or, more aptly stated: "Itis tempting to conclude that the last act or omission in point 0:Madn tyre supra Note 32 at 1229, after examining many cases involving contributory neglig ce, concluded: "These cases show the courts charging the jury to the effect that contributory negligence is a complete bar. This the jury promptly ignores and divides the damages. And the judges seem unwilling to disturb the jury's disregard of the 'law'." 3 M & G 59, 133 Eng. Reprint 1057 (1841). "MacIntyre, mupra Note 32 at 1251. C Mole and Wilson. supra Note 20 at 333. ") See Note, 92 A.L.R. 47, 53, 140 (1934); 119 A.L.R. 1046 (1939); 171 A.L.R. 369, 370 (1947). 41 Peterson v. Baltimore & 0. R.R., 73 F. Supp. 597 (D.C. Pa. 1947); Kasanovich v. George, 348 Pa4 199, 34 A. 2d 523 (1943)' Brennan v. Public Service Ry., 106 N.J. Law 464 148 A. 775 (1930); Blackwell v. First IMatl. Bank, 185 S. C. 427, 194 S. E. 339 (1937); Spillers v. Griffin, 109 S. C. 78. 95 S.E. 133 (1918). U"Smith v. American Oil Co., 77 Ga. App. 463, 49 S.E. 2d 90 (1948); St. Louhi Southwestern R.R. v. Simpson, 184 Ark. 633, 43 S.W. 2d 251 (1931); Sefferi v. Hines, 108 Neb. 62, 187 N.W. 108 (1922). "In 1937 an effort was made to limit the doctrine so as to be consistent with the American Law Institute's Restatement of the Law of Torts, Sec. 480. See Becker, The Humani. tarian Doctrine, 3 Mo. L.R. 392 (1938). Salmond on Torts (10th Ed. 1945), p. 458. [64] of time is of necessity not only the last link in the chain of causation, but the determining factor in the result, since, ex hypothesi, but for that last link the result would never have happened. But legal responsibility does not necessarily depend on the last link. Though the last opportunity in most cases is a useful guide, it does not always provide the decisive test for detemining whose negligence contributed to or caused the accident, even when it is not necessary to take a microscope to discover a separation of time, place or circumstance." It is submitted that, in the face of such widespread dissatisfaction, the doctrine will not remain unchanged. At present the predominant trend is in the direction of apportionment of damages; there is an increasing tendency to think in terms of comparative fault. This, it appears, would be a compromise between two extremes-the strict common law doctrine of contributory negligence on one end, and the doctrine of last dear chance on the other-both of which are objectionable in that they place the entire loss on one party, notwithstanding the fact that both parties negligently contributed to the loss. If the contributory negligence doctrine is invoked, the plaintiff must bear the loss; if the doctrine of last dear chanoe is invoked, the defendant must bear the entire loss. The upshot of this is that instead of an elimination there is merely a substitution of one evil for another-the cure is as damaging as the disease. Recent years have seen the enactment of a number of statutes which expressly adopt some scheme of comparative or proportional negligence in accident cases, and they are designed to cover negligence cases generally." The majority of these statutes are patterned after the Federal Employers' Liability Act, which reads in part as follows:' "In all actions hereafter brought against any such common carrier by railroad, under or by virtue of any of the provisions of this chapter, to recover damages for personal injuries to an employee, or where such injuries have resulted in his death, the fact that the employee may have been guilty of contributory negligence shall not bar a recovery, but the damages shall be diminished by the jury in proportion to the amount of negligence attributable to such employee... Notwithstanding the fact that this Act was designed and intended to be limited to the relatively simple situation where the maximum number of parties is two (i. e., employer and employee), it has been broad in its application. It has been applied by both federal and state courts, and in its administration the courts have not been presented with any insurmountable difficulty. Notable in this connection is the uncontroverted fact that juries, after receiving instructions on the provisionsof the Act, have been able, with a minimum of effort, to reach verdicts proportioning the fault of the litigants. Also indicative of its successful application is 44Wis. Stats. Sec. 331.045 (1933); Miss. Code Ann. Secs. 511, 512 (1930); Neb. Comp. Stats. Sec. 20-1151 (1929); Contributory Negligence Act, 1945, 8 & 9 Geo. 6, C. 28, Stat 221; Ont. Stats. 20 Geo. V. C. 26 (1931). See Gregory, L'islative Loss Distribution in Negiigtnce Actions. 57 and n. 5 (1936). "635 Stat. 66 (1908), 45 U.S.C. No. 53 (1926). [65 ] that there has been no increase in the number of appeals as a result of adoption of this rule. Appellate courts are most reluctant to disturb the findings of the lower courts on questions of fact relative to proportioning fault and allocating damages. A still better statute governing comparative negligence is that of the province of Ontario," which is designed to cover situations arising between more than two parties. It makes provision for contribution between joint tort-feasors, and sets up a rule to ,be applied where it is impractibable to determine the relative degree of fault as between any parties to the action. It also provides for adding as a party defendant any person not a party to the action who it appears may be wholly or partly responsible for the damage claimed. As an alternative to enactment of comparative negligence statutes, courts of common law might demand that they be allowed to adopt and apply the equal division of damages rule in situations where the interests of justice would warrant its invocation. This, however, should be only a stop-gap measure-a step forward, away from both the strict contributory negligence doctrine and last clear chance, in the direction of the comparative negligence rule, for, as has been ably pointed out" the equal division rule is riddled with inequities, and its strict application, in many instances, would cause one of the parties to be harmed to a greater extent than he should be. Admiralty courts, for example, are steadily pressuring for abandonment of the equal division of damages rule and for adoption of a more flexible proportionment of damages rule. There are those who recommend total abandonment of negligence and substituting therefor liability without fault as a means of determining the distribution of -loss in automobile injury cases.' This, however, as has 'been forcefully demonstrated,' is not desirable at this time. It is somewhat premature. It might be looked upon as the ultimate goal or objective, but it can be attained only by taking necessary intermediate steps. There is quite a jump 'between the present status of negligence, and its attendant doctrine of last clear chance, and the ideal of liability without fault. Adoption of comparative negligence statues appear to be the intermediate step. Conclusion The doctrine of last dear chance as it exists today represents an evil almost as bad as -the one it was designed to correct, i.e., strict application of the contributory negligence doctrine. It permits all of the loss to fall on one party to a negligence action when the negligence of both parties contributed to the total damage. This is inequitable and unjust. Each person should bear the proportion of the loss occasioned by his own negligent conduct. There are several alternatives which could 'be adopted to replace last 47 Ont. Stats., supra Note 47, for which note also see Gregory, op. cit. at 156.172 for a proposed statute which is much broader in scope, consisting ot some seventeen sections, and more closel a roximates ideal 4s ile and Wilson, upraan Note 20statute. at 341. 4 Report by the Committee to Study Compensation for Automobile Accidents to the Co. lumbia University Council for Research in Social Sciences (1932). o Gregory, op. cit. supra Note 47 at 174. E66J clear chance-(1) the equal division of damages rule, (2) the apportionment of damages rule, or (3) the liability without fault rule. Of these experience has shown the apportionment rule to be the most effective. The equal division rule, as used by admiralty courts, has been ineffective in producing the desired results in certain cases in that it has caused one party to suffer more harm than he deserved. The liability without fault rule has not been tested. Its theory is logical, but very little is known about its practical application. It discards all notions of negligence and permits all to recover, the extent of each party's recovery being determined by the extent to which his conduct contributed to the total damage. Perhaps it represents the final objective to be reached with respect to negligence actions, but common law courts of today are not yet equipped to administer such a rule. On the other hand, the proportionate loss or apportionment of damages rule has been given the practical test. The Federal Employers' Liability Act is a striking example. Its administration has not proved difficult, and the same is true of comparative negligence statutes enacted by the several states. This rule eliminates the harshness of both the contributory negligence doctrine and the doctrine of last dear chance; all of the burden of the loss is not borne by one party. The objection that the proportionate loss of the parties cannot be determined has been refuted by jury verdicts under these statutes. Moreover, a comparative negligence statute, in many instances, serves as a deterrent to the bringing of negligence actions under the last dear chance theory, particularly where the plaintiff's negligence is great while that of the defendant is only slight. Today, unfortunately, the comparative negligence doctrine is in effect in only a limited number of jurisdictions, and in all of these jurisdictions its application is the result of statutory law. Common law courts are under a disability to set up the doctrine by judicial fiat; this is a task for the legislatures. There has been much agitation by admiralty courts for enactment of comparative negligence legislation, and common law courts should also urge such reform. Only by application of such a doctrine will the courts, in the administration of law in negligence cases, be able to keep abreast of today's social conditions. [67]