Situationism and Virtue Epistemology Rie Iizuka (i) Introduction Sometime around the year 2000, some philosophers began criticizing virtue ethics based on social psychological data. These data could be seen in everything from the Milgram experiment on obedience to the Stanford prison experiment on authority by Zimbardo; they also appeared in empirical research on mood effects and group effects, and in the Good Samaritans studies (Alzola 2008; Darley and Batson 1973; Isen and Levin 1972; Latane and Darley 1970; Milgram 1963; Zimbardo et al. 1973). Situationists believe that various psychological data show that our behavior is heavily influenced by trivial and morally irrelevant factors; thus virtue theories, which are based on cross-situationally coherent character traits, are empirically inadequate. John Doris repeatedly emphasized the importance of committing to ‘psychological realism’ in ethics. The idea is that ethical reflection should be predicated on a moral psychology bearing a recognizable resemblance to actual human psychologies (Doris 2002: 112). Gilbert Herman is in the same camp (Herman 1999). Having complied with this methodology, these philosophers drew a conclusion that virtue ethics is empirically inadequate. At around the same time, in epistemology, the notion of intellectual virtues began to gain popularity1, in order to solve new and traditional epistemological problems. It is now widely known that virtue epistemology is divided into two main camps: reliabilist virtue epistemology and responsibilist virtue epistemology. In virtue responsibilism, virtues are understood as our excellent intellectual characters traits, typical examples being open-mindedness, intellectual courage and tenacity. Responsibilist virtue epistemology is an epistemic counterpart of virtue ethics, and could thus be easily assumed to become a target of situationist critique in the same vein. As expected, Mark Alfano recently criticized virtue responsibilism as being empirically inadequate. Alfano took intellectual courage as a typical case of intellectual virtue, and argued that we do not normally have intellectual courage as a global trait in the way that virtue epistemologists have assumed. To this end, he cites experiments designed by Solomon Asch. According to the well-known Asch paradigm experiments, ‘seven confederates and a single participant judged serially and aloud, 1 Strictly speaking, intellectual virtue (or, epistemic virtue) was first introduced in epistemology in 1980 by Ernest Sosa (1980). Here, I especially have virtue responsibilism in mind, with reference to Linda Zagzebski’s (1996) groundbreaking book on virtue responsibilism . which of two lines was longer. The correct answer was always obvious to the naked eye. Nevertheless, occasionally, the confederates unanimously said that the shorter line was longer. After hearing the confederates rattle off their wrong answers, participants often went along with the majority’ (Alfano 2012: 244). While 25% of the participants refused to go along with the majority, a great many (75% of the participants) went along with majority more often than not. This is just the tip of the iceberg, and Alfano took it as a case of people behaving under the influence of trivial and epistemically irrelevant situational factors. His assumption is that this kind of argument can be generalized into various kinds of epistemic virtues, thus threatening the empirical adequacy of responsibilist virtue epistemology. Thus, responsibilist virtue epistemology, as well as virtue ethics, are the targets of situationists’ attacks. For the sake of argument, I will hereafter use the term ‘virtue theory’ to indicate both virtue ethics and responsibilist virtue epistemology. Is virtue theory really as empirically inadequate as situationists assume? Is it incompatible to be a psychological realist as well as a virtue theorist? In the following sections of this paper, I investigate some possible interpretations of why situationists think that virtue theory is empirically inadequate, and I argue that the critique is not justified. In showing this, I will look into the psychological research on motivation, and conclude that the social psychology approach is not the only way to be “psychologically real.” (ii) Why are virtue theories under attack? The reason why neither utilitarianism nor Kantianism, but only virtue theories, are under attack is that virtues are morally thick concepts (Alfano 2012: 229). While the nature of morally thick concepts (as opposed to morally thin concepts, like what is right or good) still remains controversial, it is widely understood as a normative notion with descriptive content. For instance, intellectual courage, one of those paradigmatic intellectual virtues, pertains to the way a virtuous person takes action (by taking a risk, overcoming fear, etc.); it is normative in that it is praiseworthy. The object of situationist criticism is the descriptive part of virtue concepts; specifically, situationists are skeptical about the empirical adequacy of the properties virtues designate. Yet, the idea that the descriptive component of virtue is empirically inadequate remains uncertain, and calls for further investigation. In Doris’s picture, the explanation and predication of our behavior relates to the roles that descriptive components are supposed to serve. Attributing a quality of character invokes a depiction of behavior and psychology: the brave person acts distinctively, with distinctive motives, affects, and cognitions. Attributions also underwrite explanation and prediction: knowing something about a person's character is supposed to render their behavior intelligible and help observers determine what behaviors to expect. (Doris 2002: 5) The simplest interpretation of this argument can be reconstructed in the following manner: (1) The descriptive component of virtue is to serve the explanation and prediction of our behavior; (2) Social psychology gives us a genuine explanation and prediction of our behavior, which is not compatible with the properties involved in the descriptive component of virtue; (3) Thus, virtue theory is wrong-headed However, this is the case only if virtue theories are meant for the explanation and prediction of “our” behavior in the first place. Here “we” implies the majority of human beings. Normally, virtue theorists don’t assent to this thesis. This interpretation is based on the skewed understanding of virtue theories and, most of the time, virtue theorists admit that it is rare and difficult for normal human beings to possess virtues. In the similar vein, King explicitly opposes the situationist conclusion by saying that ‘even in some of the most ‘situationist-friendly’ studies, 13% to 20% of the subjects were reported to exhibit the relevant behavior. If we take the studies at face value, and their results as representative of the population at large, there may still be hundreds of millions of people who exhibit responsibilist virtues’ (King 2014: 252). If virtue theories describe the properties of the disposition of those 13% to 20% of human beings, there’s no reason to doubt that the descriptions might help the rest of us who are striving for virtues as well. The more precise descriptions of virtues we find, the better the possibilities of appreciating those virtues. Thus we might be able to encourage further investigation on virtues, rather than give up on this endeavor. Considering this, it can be said that virtues are our ideals. Doris, however, is skeptical about this kind of virtue theory as well. It is widely acknowledged that one of the advantages of committing to virtue theory is that it provides a way of inculcating appropriate dispositions and to escape the worry of the ‘creepiness’ of theory-driven moral reflection. It is assumed that a habituated person behaves as she should, without any reference to theory. But when we construe virtue as our ideal, ‘now worries about theoretical mediation may recur, if ethical practice consists in regulating behavior by references to an ideal of virtue instead of simply acting from virtuous dispositions’ (Doris 2002: 152). In section 4, I will argue that this worry is misplaced, because of Doris’ skewed understanding of virtue theory. In the next section, other possible interpretations of the “empirical inadequacy of the descriptive components of virtues” are considered, and the argument shows that even the most promising interpretation is compatible with virtue theory. (iii) Descriptive implication of virtues Up to this point, it has become clear that situationist critique, if understood as “the majority of us is not virtuous”, is based on a misunderstanding of virtue theory. But this is not the end of our debate. It might still be the case that situationists trace back to the descriptive implications of virtue realization, and become skeptical about the empirical adequacy of these. In other words, while the fact that many of us are not virtuous at the moment may not be harmful for virtue theory, if those descriptive implications of virtue i.e. the empirical background condition, which is necessary for realizing the properties of the descriptive components of virtues, turn out to be empirically inadequate in some way, it can prove to be detrimental for virtue theories. In essence, virtue theories turn out to be empirically inadequate only if the following conditions are true: ① Our character traits in principle never explain nor predict our behaviors at all; our actions are nothing but the construct of situational factors, never of our dispositions ② Character traits exist, but they are fixed and resistant to change ③ Character traits, if any, are not responsive to internal variables (for example, motivation) In this section, I visit ① and ②, and consider ③ in later sections. You may notice that ① and ② are mutually exclusive because ① denies the existence of character traits, and ② affirms them. Both of them, however, oppose the foundation of virtue theory in distinct ways. First of all, ① is an extremely radical standpoint. Even Doris, an eminent situationist, is reluctant to endorse this view. Among the three theoretical commitments of virtue theories: consistency, stability and evaluative integration2, he denies consistency and 2 Doris argues that virtue theorists commit to the following three conditions:(1) Consistency. Character and personality traits are reliably manifested in trait-relevant behavior across a diverse range of trait-relevant eliciting conditions that may vary widely in their conduciveness to the manifestation of the trait in question; (2) Stability. Character and personality traits are reliably manifested in trait-relevant behaviors over iterated trials of similar trait-relevant eliciting conditions. (3) Evaluative integration. In a given character or personality, the occurrence of a trait with a particular evaluative valence is probabilistically related to the occurrence of other traits with similar evaluative valences. (Doris 2002: 22). evaluative integration, but retains stability. In other words, he doesn’t believe that our behavior remains the same across situations, but rather believes it is stable in highly limited domains (for instance, honesty in tests or generosity towards family members), and he calls these ‘local traits’. So, our behavior is explained and predicted by the reference to character traits in this minimum sense. It is widely embraced that a renaissance is underway in the study of the Big Five personality traits. Many psychologists now believe that ‘there are five major dimensions along which all human characters vary. Thus, any individual can be given five scores that will tell us a great deal about the ways [in which] they are reliable to behave through their lives’ (Nettle 2007: 9). Those five factors are openness, conscientiousness, extraversion, agreeableness, and neuroticism. In each of these factors, we are placed somewhere along the continuum of personality dimensions. The idea of fixed traits is strongly supported. Point ① can be denied in this vein. Unfortunately, however, the Big Five is not a boon to virtue theorists, but just another obstacle. According to Alfano, the Big Five is different from virtue theory in a sense that personality traits are assumed as innate and relatively fixed, and that they are hard to change. Thus, those traits are not under our control, not a result of our choice, and not a proper subject of responsibility, praise or blame. On the other hand, responsibility, choice, praise and blame are all central concepts in virtue theories. Although it is undeniable that the two theories are independent, one of the threats for virtue implication (point ①) is removed by the Big Five. As for point ②, the description of the Big Five is likely to support this point, and thus threaten the descriptive implication of virtue theory. But wait, we must consider how situationism and the Big Five can be compatible, for both assume a completely different picture of human nature. In big five, our behavior is determined by innate fixed traits; in situationism, on the other hand, nothing but situational factors play an explanatory role in our behavior. When we take both these factors at face value, it is very likely that the two would seem contradictory to each other. Here, neither aims at providing a singular explanation of our behavior, but they do compete in terms of explanatory superiority with regards to our behavior. This is, quite simply, another way of drawing a debate between genetic determinism and environmental determinism. The explanatory superiority might interest philosophers, but ending this debate is not our concern at the moment. Rather, by admitting that both these theories are right to some extent, and that the two parties are at a standstill, is likely to support the denial of point ②—and this is crucial to our present argument. In this section, we have scrutinized the descriptive implication of virtue and its empirical adequacy. It was revealed that the psychological theories on our character (personality) traits did not deny our descriptive implications of virtue. Before moving on to consider point ③, however, the requirement of virtue is to be articulated. (iv) Moral and epistemic motivation In order to be virtuous (to possess virtue), what must we be equipped with? In this section, by paying close attention to the commitment to virtue theory, the conditions imposed upon us for becoming virtuous are to be articulated. First of all, let’s take a look at the epistemological requirements of virtue. Virtue responsibilists propose three conditions: (a) all intellectual virtues have in common something like a 'love of truth' or a desire for knowledge; (b) each individual virtue has its own distinctive and more immediate focus or a motivation on account of which it can be individuated from other intellectual virtues; […] (c) the immediate focus or characteristic of particular intellectual virtues is 'grounded in' or 'flows from' the more basic concern with truth, knowledge, and the like. (Baehr 2013: 100) For instance, in order to possess open-mindedness, agents are to be motivated by epistemic goods, and because of this love of epistemic goods, the person forms an individual disposition to avoid falling prey to partiality, and to listen to another person’s opinion. Along similar lines, virtue theorist Rosalind Hursthouse, emphasizes the importance of being appropriately motivated to become virtuous. Williams maintains that the virtuous choose virtuous actions “for their own sake, and that is required for acting virtuously,” and Hursthouse followed suit: The virtuous agent chooses virtuous actions ‘for their own sake’; [this] means that the virtuous agent chooses virtuous actions for at least one of a certain type or range of reasons X, where “the type or range” is typical of, and differs according to, whichever virtue is in question. What are the reasons “typical of” a virtue? They will be the sorts of reasons for which someone with a particular virtue, V, will do a V act. So, thinking of the sorts of reasons a courageous agent might have for performing a courageous act, we can come up with such things as ‘I could probably save him if I climbed up there,’ ‘Someone had to volunteer,’ ‘One can't give in to tyrants,’ or ‘It's worth the risk (1999: 127-28). Moral motivation is thus an important notion in terms of possessing moral virtues. Specifically, what is required is to act on certain reasoning that is appropriate for individual virtues. It is crucial to note that these reasons are not necessarily mediated by any theory. Virtue theorists are aware of the danger of falling prey to the platonic fantasy (the assumption that in order to possess virtue, a person must also know the theory of virtues), and deliberately avoid committing to theoretical assumptions. Uncertainty still remains on moral motivation. Some theorists suggest that it is not necessary to be consciously aware of the aforementioned reasons of action when carrying them out. They equally admit that this kind of requirement sounds too strong and severe. Hursthouse (1999:132-34) rightly points out that apparent cases of action with appropriate moral motivation sometimes fail, for example, in the cases of small children, severely mentally handicapped people, and adults who act with an appropriate reason for virtue, but “uncharacteristically” None of these agents are morally motivated in a genuine sense. What is missing in these subjects compared to the genuinely virtuous? With regards to this issue, Baehr (2013: 103) detailed further requirements. To be genuinely virtuous, the traits in question must become a person's own, i.e. they must become integrated into the person’s psychology or character in a relatively deep and personal way. In order to meet this requirement, two further conditions ought to be met: according to Baehr, first, the agent ought to identify with or endorse this trait, which in turn would seem to require at a minimum that the person take a positive view of the trait or have some grasp or awareness of its value. Second, the person himself/herself ought to become a significant part of the explanation of his/her possession of the traits in question. Baehr believes that, in this way, if an apparent virtuous trait T turns out to be infused by the person’s community or parents, and the possession of the traits are solely explainable by this, we cannot credit the person with them. Thus, in terms of virtue possession, we have both synchronic requirements of moral motivation for individual actions, and diachronic requirements on ourselves, to which those actions are attributed. These arguments have two theoretical implications for our present problems. First, it articulates that having a natural inclination and possessing a virtue is a distinct matter. Thus insight from the Big Five personality traits has nothing to do with virtue possession in any significant way. Second, this point plays an important role in replying to Doris’s worry introduced in section 1. If virtue is our ideal, he infers from it the conclusion that we must refer to the theory, and thus fall prey to theoretical mediation However, we have just seen that this is an ill-motivated worry, and that the reference to virtue theory is not necessary for virtue procession at all. What is mainly required for agents is to act on one of the reasons, X, appropriate for an individual virtue, V. As Hursthouse rightly noted, appropriate reasons can be partly shared by many of atypical virtuous people, and we might be able to learn from them through observation. In this section, we have seen the requirements of virtues and found that the Doris’s worry is misplaced. In the last section, it will be shown that our consideration on virtue is, in one sense, ‘psychologically real’. (v) Self-determination theory and virtue ethics We have seen that virtue theories as a normative ideal do not necessarily entail theoretically-heavy concepts. It is time to return to our original argument, namely, point ③. How has it been proved that we form our dispositions based on our internal variables (i.e. motivations)? While many virtue theorists implicitly see this idea as a prerequisite, unfortunately, they do not rely on any empirical data. If it is not feasible to show that this is the case on any justificatory ground, virtue theories might turn into a house of cards. In this section, empirical support for the theoretical assumption for virtue theory is to be introduced, and I will especially look into the psychological study on our motivation. Self-determination (or the study of intrinsic/extrinsic motivation) theory, proposed by Ryan and Deci, suggests that the idea of intrinsic/extrinsic motivation implies not the quantity or magnitude of motivation, but the quality of it (the orientation of our motivation); it is this that can predict the outcome of our behavior. The most basic distinction made with regards to the orientation of our motivation is between intrinsic and extrinsic motivations. Intrinsic motivation refers to doing something because it is inherently interesting or enjoyable, while extrinsic motivation is doing something because it leads to a concrete outcome. ‘Over three decades of research have shown that the quality of experience and performance can be very different when one is behaving for intrinsic versus extrinsic reasons' (Deci and Ryan 2008: 55). Already in the early stages of motivation studies, the results indicated that those who solved puzzles under the threat of punishment, or having the payment of money contingent upon their performances, were less intrinsically motivated during the free-choice period than subjects who solved the same puzzles with no threats or rewards (Deci 1972). Deci drew the conclusion that when extrinsically motivated, our interest in the activity is diminished. A more recent study on motivation indicates that the orientation of extrinsic motivations can vary. The state of lacking intention to act is called “amotivation.” Such behaviors are performed to satisfy an external demand or to obtain an externally imposed reward; this is called “external regulation.” Behaviors with a type of internal regulation that is still quite controlling—performing actions upon feeling the pressure to avoid guilt or anxiety, or to attain ego-enhancement or pride—is called “introjected regulation.” When a person has identified with the personal importance of a behavior and has thus accepted its regulation as being his or her own, it is called “identification.” The most autonomous form of extrinsic motivation is “integrated regulation.” Integration occurs when identified regulations have been fully assimilated to the self (Ryan and Deci 2000). This last type of orientation of our extrinsic and intrinsic motivation is both taken as autonomous and self-determined motivation. The qualitative difference of our motivation explains the different outcomes of our behavior. SDT and motivation theory have two implications that support the descriptive components of virtue theory, one of which gives indirect support, while the other provides more direct support. I will visit them both here. First, how does SDT support virtue theory in an indirect manner? Here, I say “indirect,” because the conclusion that we are aiming to arrive at comes not as an empirical result of SDT, but rather as a presupposition. Based on the explanatory and predictive power of SDT, it is inferred that its presupposition is also empirically adequate. SDT is not feasible unless it is possible that our behavioral outcome changes based on the orientation of our motivation. Empirical results strongly support that intrinsically motivated subjects are led to various desirable outcomes compared to the extrinsically motivated counterparts. Here, SDT is confirmed by various empirical results, thus, the adequacy of its presupposition, namely, our behavioral outcome changes based on the orientation of our motivation. Also, the orientation of our motivation is understood as our internal variables. This supports the denial of point ③. Next, how does SDT support virtue theory in a direct manner? The most important point is that SDT pays attention to subjects who engage in desirable behaviors in a variety of contexts. For example, SDT is applied to the domains of sports, education and healthcare. Believing in the importance of these domains in our life is undeniable. Among them, I will take education as a representative. Our understanding of successful or ideal agents in education is universally shared with less controversy compared to other domains, such as morality. Believing that success in education contributes towards a good life is widespread across cultures and eras. If it were argued to the contrary, I believe that the burden of proof is on the side of showing us why that isn’t the case. According to the review of studies on SDT and education, “students who are regulated by autonomous motivations (i.e., intrinsic and identified) experience positive consequences at school. These consequences can take different forms (behavioral, cognitive, or affective).” (Guay et al. 2008: 234) Behavioral outcomes are found by conducting a series of experiments. Students who dropped out of high school had lower intrinsic motivation and identified regulation, and higher amotivation compared to students who persisted. Autonomous motivation and persistence (for example, in terms of picking up additional reading or taking on optional exercise) in college students can be enhanced by activating intrinsic educational goals. It has also been shown that autonomous motivation predicted greater achievement over a one-year period (Guay et al. 2008). Thus, SDT has shown that our orientation of motivation has a strong influence on the achievement of desirable activities. This is extremely suggestive for virtue epistemology. Responsibilist virtue epistemologists inquired into what is necessary for becoming responsible, intellectual agents. They found that this could be achieved by the cultivation of intellectual virtues. In essence, as we have already seen in the previous section, it is necessary for the possession of virtues to be motivated by epistemic goods for their own sake. It is also important to cultivate individual character traits derived from these motivations, internalize its value to the self (i.e., having a positive perspective on traits), and the agents must be a significant part of the explanation of the possession of virtues. These conditions, imposed upon us, have a significant overlap with the motivational structure of autonomous agents who are led to desirable outcomes. We have already seen that students with desirable educational outcomes tend to be motivated by educational activities themselves, or that they integrated values of education within themselves. These agents precisely meet the conditions imposed upon us by virtue epistemologists to be responsible inquirers. Thus it can be inferred that these empirical findings support the adequacy of the descriptive component of (intellectual) virtues. SDT implies that agents with desirable outcomes in real life are motivated by activities, or that they integrate the value of the activities within themselves. This is the same criteria for virtuous agents. Skepticism regarding the adequacy of the descriptive component of virtue theory has been eradicated by the framework of psychological study on the orientation of motivation. In addition, experimental findings with regards to SDT and education encourage us to believe that the descriptive components of intellectual virtues are true to reality. (vi) Conclusion Although situationists have criticized virtue theory for its empirical inadequacy, the nature of this criticism remains ambiguous and the specification of them was an urgent task for us. The debate between virtue theorists and situationists drag on, especially when it comes to this ambiguity. In this paper, possible interpretations on empirical inadequacy of the descriptive components of virtues were scrutinized individually, and the conclusion was drawn that none of them diminished the validity of virtue theories. While situationists have assumed that social psychological studies undermine the empirical adequacy of virtue theory, it only shows that, at best, not many of us are virtuous. The important point is that psychology is not exhausted by social psychology, and when we pay close attention to studies on the orientation of motivation, it is more convincing to believe that our motivation has an influence on desirable behavioral outcomes. Moreover, the descriptive components of virtues are supported by those motivation studies, and they correspond well with the way people are motivated when they engage in important activities. Supporting virtue theory and being a psychological realist are, thus, compatible after all. References Alfano, M. (2012), 'Expanding the situationist challenge to responsibilist virtue epistemology', The Philosophical Quarterly, 62/247, 223-49. Alzola, M. (2008), 'Character and environment: The status of virtues in organizations', Journal of Business Ethics, 78/3, 343-57. Baehr, J. (2013), 'The Cognitive Demands of Intellectual Virtue', in T. Henning and D.P. Schweikard (eds.), Knowledge, Virtue, and Action: Putting Epistemic Virtues to Work: Routledge. Darley, J.M. and Batson, C.D. (1973), '" From Jerusalem to Jericho": A study of situational and dispositional variables in helping behavior', Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 27/1, 100. Deci, E.L. (1972), 'The effects of contingent and noncontingent rewards and controls on intrinsic motivation', Organizational Behavior and Human Performance, 8/2, 217-29. Deci, E.L. and Ryan, R.M. (2008), 'Self-determination theory: A macrotheory of human motivation, development, and health', Canadian Psychology/Psychologie canadienne, 49/3, 182-85. Doris, J. (2002), Lack of Character: Personality and Moral Behavior: Cambridge University Press. Guay, F., Ratelle, C.F., and Chanal, J. (2008), 'Optimal learning in optimal contexts: The role of self-determination in education', Canadian Psychology/Psychologie canadienne, 49/3, 233-40. Harman, G. (1999), 'Moral Philosophy Meets Social Psychology: Virtue Ethics and the Fundamental Attribution Error', Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 99, 315-31. Hursthouse, R. (1999), On virtue ethics: Oxford University Press. Isen, A.M. and Levin, P.F. (1972), 'Effect of feeling good on helping: cookies and kindness', Journal of personality and social psychology, 21/3, 384. King, N.L. (2014), 'Responsibilist Virtue Epistemology: A Reply to the Situationist Challenge', The Philosophical Quarterly, 64/255, 243-53. Latane, B. and Darley, J.M. (1970), The unresponsive bystander: Why doesn't he help? New York: Appleton-Century Crofts New York. Milgram, S. (1963), 'Behavioral study of obedience', The Journal of Abnormal and Social Psychology, 67/4, 371. Nettle, D. (2007), Personality: What makes you the way you are. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Ryan, R.M. and Deci, E.L. (2000), 'Intrinsic and Extrinsic Motivations: Classic Definitions and New Directions', Contemporary Educational Psychology, 25/1, 54-67. Sosa, E. (1980), 'The raft and the pyramid: Coherence versus foundations in the theory of knowledge', Midwest studies in philosophy, 5/1, 3-26. Zagzebski, L. (1996), Virtues of the Mind: An Inquiry Into the Nature of Virtue and the Ethical Foundations of Knowledge. Combridge: Cambridge University Press. Zimbardo, P.G., et al. (1973), 'A Pirandellian prison: The mind is a formidable jailer', New York Times Magazine, 8/1973, 38-60.