Judicial Deference to Executive Precedent Author(s): Thomas W. Merrill Source: The Yale Law Journal, Vol. 101, No. 5, (Mar., 1992), pp. 969-1041 Published by: The Yale Law Journal Company, Inc. Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/796961 Accessed: 08/05/2008 16:13 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use. Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=ylj. Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. JSTOR is a not-for-profit organization founded in 1995 to build trusted digital archives for scholarship. We enable the scholarly community to preserve their work and the materials they rely upon, and to build a common research platform that promotes the discovery and use of these resources. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org. http://www.jstor.org Articles Judicial Deference to Executive Precedent Thomas W. Merrillt In 1984, the SupremeCourt adopted a new frameworkfor determining when courts should defer to interpretationsof statutesby administrativeagencies. Previousdecisions hadlooked to multiplecontextualfactorsin answering this question.1Chevron U.S.A., Inc. v. National ResourcesDefense Council, Inc.2appearedto reject this approachand requirethat federal courts defer to any reasonableinterpretationby an agency chargedwith administrationof a statute, provided Congress has not clearly specified a contraryanswer.The Courtjustified this new generalrule of deferenceby positingthatCongresshas implicitlydelegatedinterpretativeauthorityto all agencieschargedwith enforcing federal law.3 Chevronis widely regardedas a kind of "counter-Marbury" for the administrativestate.4Indeed,readfor all it is worth,the decisionwould makeadmint Professor of Law, NorthwesternUniversity School of Law. I served as Deputy Solicitor General, Departmentof Justice, from 1987 to 1990, during which time I arguedor helped brief a large numberof the Supreme Court cases involving the "Chevrondoctrine."The analysis of these cases (and all others pending while I was with the Justice Department)is strictly my own, and not necessarilythe same as that of the Justice Departmentor its client agencies. I wish to thankJustice Antonin Scalia, the 1991 Howard J. Trienens Visiting Judicial Fellow at NorthwesternSchool of Law, and my colleagues at Northwestern for a stimulating discussion at a faculty workshop.Special thanks to Robert Bennett, Steven Calabresi, CharlotteCrane,Keith Hylton, Paul Larkin,Gary Lawson, MartyRedish, and Peter Schuck for comments on an earlier draft, and to Melissa McGonigal for her diligent researchassistance. 1. See infra notes 7-29 and accompanyingtext. 2. 467 U.S. 837 (1984). 3. Id. at 843-44, 865-66. 4. Cass R. Sunstein, Law and AdministrationAfterChevron,90 COLUM. L. REV.2071, 2075 (1990). 969 970 The Yale Law Journal [Vol. 101: 969 istrative actorsthe primaryinterpretersof federalstatutesand relegate courts to the largely inertrole of enforcingunambiguousstatutoryterms.This in turn would have enormousimplicationsfor the overallbalanceof poweramongthe three branches of government.Executive branch agencies would gain new power to achieve rapid changes in policy through reinterpretationof their legislative authority;courts would play a diminishedrole in checking agency aggrandizementandin protectingrelianceinterestsassociatedwithpastinterpretations;andCongress,unableto rely on the courtsto honorunstatedinstitutional understandings,could react by enacting excruciatinglydetailed statutesor intensifying the use of oversighthearings. This Article has two primarytasks.The first, which is the subjectof Parts I, II, and III, is to determinewhetherChevronin fact operatesin the Supreme Courtas the "counter-Marbury" portrayedby commentators.It turnsout that the Courtdoes not regardChevronas a universaltest for determiningwhen to deferto executive interpretations:the Chevronframeworkis used in only about half the cases that the Courtperceivesas presentinga deferencequestion.Nor have the multiple factorsidentifiedin the pre-Chevronperiod disappeared;to the contrary,the Courtcontinuesto rely uponthemin manycases, despitetheir apparentirrelevanceunderChevron.Perhapsmost strikingly,in recentTerms the applicationof Chevronhasresultedin less deferenceto executiveinterpretations than was the case in the pre-Chevronera. Thus, instead of functioning as a "counter-Marbury," there are signs that Chevronis being transformedby the Courtinto a new judicial mandate"to say what the law is."5I will argue that the failure of Chevronto perform as expected can be attributedto the Court'sreluctanceto embracethe draconianimplicationsof the doctrinefor the balance of power among the branches,and to practicalproblemsgeneratedby its all-or-nothingapproachto the deferencequestion. The second task of the Article is to proposean alternativeto Chevronthat avoids its theoretical and practical failings and is more congruentwith the actualpracticeof the SupremeCourt.PartIV sets forthwhatI call the "executive precedentmodel." The root idea is that executive interpretationsshould be viewed as a form of precedentand integratedinto the process of statutory constructionin much the same way thatjudicial precedentis integrated.The model begins with the understandingthat both the executive branchand the judicial branchhave inherentauthorityto interpretenacted law-and thus to generate"precedent"construingthatlaw.The modelthenpositsthatthejudicial power includesnot only the powerto determinewhetherto follow pastjudicial precedentinterpretingenactedlaw, butalso the powerto determinewhatweight to give to past executive precedentconstruingthat law. Under the proposed model,courtswould treatexecutiveprecedentapproximatelythe same way they regardthe precedentof anothercourtof coordinatejurisdiction:as primafacie 5. Marburyv. Madison, 5 U.S. (1 Cranch) 137, 177 (1803). 1992] Executive Precedent 971 correct,and as entitledto moreor less deferencedependingon variouscontextual factors(such as the thoroughnesswith which the executive agency considered the issue, how long the executive interpretationhas been followed, and so forth). Part V comparesChevron'sdeferencemodel and the executive precedent model. Chevronrests on a principleof mandatorydeference:courts are compelled to defer to agency interpretationsbecause Congress has directedthem to defer. The executive precedentmodel, in contrast,rests on a principle of discretionarydeference:courtsdeferto executiveinterpretationsbecausesound judicial decisionmakingrequiresthatthey follow the precedentof a coordinate branch of government. I contend that the discretionarydeference principle implicit in the executive precedentmodel fits betterwithin the constitutional andlegal frameworkthatgave rise to the modernadministrativestate,provides a unifying theory explaining why the traditionalfactorssupposedlybanished by Chevron are relevant and how they relate to ordinarymodes of judicial interpretation,and offers better incentives than does Chevronfor principled decisionmakingby courts, agencies, and Congress. I. CHEVRON:THE REVOLUTIONON PAPER The attitudeof courtstowardadministrativeinterpretationsof statuteshas ranged between two extremes.6At one pole, courts ignore the administrative view. When operatingin this "independentjudgment"mode, a courtemploys traditionaltools of statutoryinterpretation-analysisof text, legislativehistory, and various canons of construction-to arrive at what it regardsas the best interpretationof the statute,just as it would in a case where the executive branchhas not spoken previously.At the other pole, courts frame the inquiry in terms of whetherthe administrativeinterpretationis one that a reasonable interpretermight embrace. In this "deference"mode, a court implicitly acknowledges thatthe statuteis susceptibleto multiplereadings.The task of the courtis viewed not as discoveringthe best interpretation,butratheras assuring that the executive view does not contradictthe statuteand otherwise furthers legitimate objectives. Chevronis widely understoodto marka significanttransformationin the SupremeCourt'sjurisprudenceof deference.This part spells out the support 6. See PittstonStevedoringCorp. v. Dellaventura,544 F.2d35, 49 (2d Cir. 1976) (Friendly,J.) (noting two extremes in judicial attitudetowardadministrativestatutoryinterpretation),affd sub nom. Northeast Marine Terminal Co. v. Caputo, 432 U.S. 249 (1977); 5 KENNETHC. DAVIS,ADMINISTRATIVE LAW TREATISE 403 (2d ed. 1984) (same);NathanielL. Nathanson,AdministrativeDiscretionin the Interpretation of Statutes, 3 VAND.L. REV.470 (1950) (distinguishingbetween occasions when courts requireagency interpretationsto be "correct"and when they requiresuch interpretationsto be merelyreasonable).In recent literature,the standardterms for the two poles, which I will use here, are "independentjudgment"and "deference."See, e.g., CynthiaR. Farina,StatutoryInterpretationand the Balance of Power in the Administrative State, 89 COLUM.L. REV.452, 453-54 & n.10 (1989); Henry P. Monaghan, Marburyand the AdministrativeState, 83 COLUM.L. REV. 1, 6-7 (1983). 972 The Yale Law Journal [Vol. 101: 969 for this view by brieflyexaminingthe pre-Chevrondecisionallaw andcontrasting it with the frameworkset forthin Chevron.Afterdescribingthe revolutionary potentialof Chevron,I will turnin the next partto a considerationof how Chevronhas in fact affected the practiceof the SupremeCourt. A. Pre-Chevron:The MultipleFactors Regime Prior to 1984, the SupremeCourthad no unifying theory for determining when to defer to agency interpretationsof statutes.7The approachwas instead pragmaticandcontextual.One featureof the Court'spracticewas thatdeference could range over a spectrumfrom "great"to "some"to "little"8(althoughno attempt was ever made to calibratedifferentdegrees of deference with any precision). A particularlycommon approachwas to cite the views of those chargedwith administrationof the statuteas one of severalreasonsfor adopting a particularconstruction.Thus,the Courtmightembracea particularinterpretation (1) becauseit was supportedby the languageof the text, (2) becauseit was consistentwith the legislative history,and (3) becauseit was the longstanding constructionof the administrativeagency.9To be sure, there were also decisions at the polar extremes duringthis era-either ignoring the agency view or treatingit as virtuallydispositive.?1But in practice,deferenceexisted along a sliding scale, bridgingthese outer limits. In addition, in deciding what degree of deference to give an executive interpretation,the Courtrelied on an eclectic cluster of considerations.1Althoughthere was no explicit rationalelinkingthe various factorstogether,the overallapproachhad an implicitlogic. The defaultrule was one of independent judicialjudgment.Deferenceto the agency interpretationwas appropriateonly if a courtcould identify some factoror factorsthatwould supplyan affirmative justification for giving special weight to the agency views. Admittedly,the factors tended to be invoked unevenly. But in this respect, they probably 7. See RobertA. Anthony,WhichAgencyInterpretationsShouldBindCitizensand the Courts?,7 YALE J. ONREG.1, 6 (1990); Monaghan,supra note 6, at 31. 8. See Battertonv. Francis,432 U.S. 416, 425 n.9 (1977); 5 DAVIs, supra note 6, at 400. 9. For examples of this approach,see Bell v. New Jersey,461 U.S. 773 (1983); Blum v. Bacon, 457 U.S. 132 (1982); United States v. Clark, 454 U.S. 555 (1982); Federal Election Comm'n v. Democratic SenatorialCampaignComm'n, 454 U.S. 27 (1981). 10. CompareNewport News Shipbuilding& Dry Dock Co. v. EEOC, 462 U.S. 669 (1983) (Court discusses EEOCguidelineswith no suggestionthatthey areentitledto deference)with Hecklerv. Campbell, 461 U.S. 458, 466 (1983) (Court states that its review is limited to determining whether Secretary's regulationsare arbitraryor capricious). 11. For useful accounts of the multiple factors employed during this period, see Colin S. Diver, StatutoryInterpretationin the AdministrativeState, 133 U. PA. L. REV.549, 562 n.95 (1985); ErnestH. Schopler,Annotation,SupremeCourt'sViewas to Weightand Effect to be Given, on SubsequentJudicial Construction,to PriorAdministrativeConstructionof Statute,39 L.R.A.2d942 (1975); DavidR. Woodward & Ronald M. Levin, In Defense of Deference:Judicial Review of AgencyAction, 31 ADMIN.L. REV.329, 332-41 (1979). 1992] Executive Precedent 973 functionedin a mannernot too differentfromthe way the canons of interpretation operate in statutoryinterpretationcases.12 The pre-Chevrondeferencefactorsmay be classified in various ways. For presentpurposes,I will groupthem into threecategories:(1) factorsaddressed to Congress' interpretativeintent(thatis, whetherCongressintendedcourtsto defer to an agency's interpretationof a statutoryprovision);(2) factors addressed to the attributesof the particularagency decision at issue; and (3) factorsthoughtto demonstratecongruencebetweenthe outcomereachedby the agency and congressionalintent regardingthat specific issue. The first factor focused on Congress' probableinterpretativeintent. The important distinction was between "legislative rules" and "interpretative rules."13Legislativerules were the productof a specific delegationof authority from Congress to an administrativeagency to interpreta specific statutory termor fill in a statutorygap. Interpretative ruleswereexecutiveinterpretations not backedby this type of specific delegatedauthority.The SupremeCourton several occasions suggested that interpretationsin the formercategory were entitled to great deference, but those falling within the latter category were entitled only to whateverpersuasiveeffect they might have.'4 A second groupof factorsfocusednot on the agency's authority,butrather on various attributesof its decision. One factor was whether the issue fell within an area of agency "expertise."15 The idea was that courts are generalwhereas are ists, agencies specialists.Specialistsusuallyhave a bettergraspof technical terms'6or the practicalconsequencesof a decision,'7and thus their views should be given deferenceby generalists.Anotherimportantfactorwas the notionthat"longstanding," "consistent,"or "uniform"administrativeinterpretations(the terms were used more or less interchangeably)are entitled to special deference.'8A third factor in this category was that interpretations 12. The dominant view for many years, following Llewellyn, was that the canons are mutually contradictory,and hence are of little or no value in guidingjudicial decisionmaking.See KarlN. Llewellyn, Remarkson the Theory of Appellate Decision and the Rules or Canons About How StatutesAre to Be Construed, 3 VAND.L. REV. 395, 401-06 (1950). More recently, a revisionist trend has set in, and commentatorshave begun to take a more sympatheticattitudetowardthe canons. See CASSR. SUNSTEIN, AFTER THE RIGHTSREVOLUTION:RECONCEIVING THE REGULATORY STATE 111-92 (1990); William N. Eskridge,Jr.,Public Valuesin StatutoryInterpretation,137 U. PA. L. REV.1007 (1989); Geoffrey P. Miller, Pragmatics and the Maximsof Interpretation,1990 WIS. L. REV.1179. 13. See 5 DAVIS, supra note 6, at 421-25; LOUIS JAFFE,JUDICIALCONTROLOF ADMINISTRATIVE ACTION 564-65 (1965); JAMESM. LANDIS,THEADMINISTRATIVE PROCESS 146-52 (1938). 14. See, e.g., Heckler v. Campbell,461 U.S. at 466-68 & n.10 (deferringto rule promulgatedunder grantof generalrulemakingpower);Herwegv. Ray,455 U.S. 265,274-75 (1982) (deferringto interpretation with "legislative effect"); Batterton v. Francis, 432 U.S. 416, 424-26 & nn.8-9 (1977) (distinguishing delegated "legislative power"from nondelegated"interpretativepower"and accordinggreat deferenceto agency interpretationsusing former). 15. See, e.g., AluminumCo. of Am. v. CentralLincolnPeoples' Util. Dist., 467 U.S. 380, 390 (1984). 16. See, e.g., E.I. du Pont de Nemours & Co. v. Train,430 U.S. 112, 134-35 & n.25 (1977). 17. See, e.g., NLRB v. Seven-Up Bottling Co., 344 U.S. 344, 348 (1953); Woodward& Levin, supra note 11, at 332. 18. See United States v. Clark, 454 U.S. 555, 565 (1982); Haig v. Agee, 453 U.S. 280, 291 (1981); NLRB v. Bell AerospaceCo., 416 U.S. 267, 275 (1974); Udall v. Tallman,380 U.S. 1, 16 (1965). Compare 974 The Yale Law Journal [Vol. 101: 969 supportedby a reasonedanalysis were entitledto deference.The most prominent statementto this effect is found in Skidmorev. Swift & Co.,19where the Courtstatedthatthe weight to be given to an agencyinterpretationwill depend upon "the thoroughnessevident in its consideration,the validity of its reasoning, its consistencywith earlierandlaterpronouncements,and all those factors which give it power to persuade, if lacking power to control."20A final decision-relatedfactor,encounteredless often, was whethermultipleagencies agreed or disagreed about the correctinterpretationof the statute.21 A third set of factors was designed to measurethe degree to which the specific outcome reached by an agency was likely to reflect the intent of Congress.One old idea was thatan executive interpretationis entitledto extra weight "whenit involves a contemporaneousconstructionof a statuteby the men charged with the responsibilityof setting its machineryin motion."22 Contemporaneousinterpretationswere thoughtto be especially probativeof hadthemselvesparticipatcongressionalintent,eitherbecausethe administrators ed in the draftingprocess23or because such an interpretationwas "itself evidence of assumptions-perhaps unspoken by either the administratorsor Congress-brought to a regulatoryproblemby all involved in its solution."4 In addition, there was the recurrentnotion that executive interpretationsare entitled to special deference if they have been ratified in some fashion by Congress. The notion of what would count as a ratificationwas never very precise. The paradigmsituationwas when Congress,after being informedof an agency's construction,reenacteda statutewithout any relevantmodification.25 Standing alone, these factors did not comprise, either individually or collectively, what could be describedas a coherentdoctrine.No attemptwas made to connect the various factorstogetheror to explain their relevancein terms of a model of executive-judicialrelationship.Indeed,my own attempt to organizethem in functionalcategoriesmay impose a greatersense of order than the cases themselves warrant.Moreover,there is little evidence that the factorshad much predictiveor constrainingpower.To take but one example, Nashville Gas Co. v. Satty,434 U.S. 136, 142 n.4 (1977) (consistentlymaintainedEEOCGuidelinegiven significant weight by Court) with General Elec. Co. v. Gilbert, 429 U.S. 125, 142-43 (1977) (EEOC Guideline that conflicts with earlier agency interpretationentitled to little weight). 19. 323 U.S. 134 (1944). 20. Id. at 140; see also Adamo WreckingCo. v. United States, 434 U.S. 275, 287 n.5 (1978) (quoting Skidmore,323 U.S. at 140); SEC v. Sloan, 436 U.S. 103, 117-18 (1978); InvestmentCo. Inst. v. Camp, 401 U.S. 617, 626-27 (1971). 21. See North Haven Bd. of Educ. v. Bell, 456 U.S. 512 (1982); GeneralElec. Co. v. Gilbert,429 U.S. at 144-45; see also BERNARD ADMINISTRATIVE LAW664-66 (1984) (discussing a case where SCHWARTZ, federal agencies adoptedconflicting positions on whethera particularsubstancewas "oleomargarine"). 22. Norwegian Nitrogen Co. v. United States, 288 U.S. 294, 315 (1933). 23. See United States v. Moore, 95 U.S. 760, 763 (1877). 24. SEC v. Sloan, 436 U.S. at 126 (Brennan,J., concurring). 25. See, e.g., NLRB v. HendricksCountyRuralElec. Corp., 454 U.S. 170, 177 (1981); NLRB v. Bell AerospaceCo., 416 U.S. 267, 275 (1974); Red Lion BroadcastingCo. v. FCC, 395 U.S. 367, 381 (1969). 1992] Executive Precedent 975 in SEC v. Sloan26the Securities and Exchange Commission argued that its interpretationnot only was entitledto deferencebecausethe interpretationwas longstandingand consistentbut also becauseit had been ratified by Congress when its constructionwas cited with approvalin a committeereportat the time the statute was reenacted.27The Courtrejected these arguments,noting that the interpretationwas not supportedby a careful analysis of the statutory language and that evidence of congressionalratificationwas not enough if "based only upon a few isolated statementsin the thousands of pages of legislative documents."28 As Sloan suggests, applicationof the variousfactorsin individualcases is manipulable.Still, it wouldbe presumptuousto dismissthemas emptyrhetoric. Some factors-such as the importance of longstanding and consistent or contemporaneousadministrativeconstructions-have been invokedas reasons for deferring to executive interpretationsfor over 150 years.29Given the durabilityof these factors,it is plausibleto view them as reflectingdeep-seated judicial intuitionsabout the kinds of considerationsthat ought to bear on the decision to defer. If they do not determinethe outcome of cases with logical certainty,neitherdoes any other "traditionaltool" of statutoryinterpretation. At least the factors turned the attentionsof courts and litigants-including administrators-toward relevant considerationsthat presumablyshape the judicial response. B. The ChevronFramework Chevron was an unlikely candidateto produce a landmarkdecision on deference to executive interpretationsof statutes. The governmenthad not sought a reconsiderationof the established approachto judicial review of administrativeinterpretations,30 and only six Justicesparticipatedin the decision. Moreover,the disputedissue could be seen as partof the generaldereguInChevron,the Environmental latorythrustof the earlyReaganAdministration. ProtectionAgency (EPA)haddefinedthe term"stationarysource"in the Clean Air Act to permit owners of pollutingfacilities to treatall emitting devices as if they were undera single "bubble,"therebyminimizingthe costs of comply26. 436 U.S. 103 (1978). 27. Id. at 117-20. 28. Id. at 121. 29. See, e.g., Brownv. United States, 113 U.S. 568,570-71 (1885) (longstandingandcontemporaneous construction);United States v. Moore, 95 U.S. 760, 763 (1877) (contemporaneousconstruction);Edward's Lessee v. Darby, 25 U.S. (12 Wheat.) 206, 210 (1827) (contemporaneousconstruction);United States v. Vowell, 9 U.S. (5 Cranch) 368, 371 (1809) (longstandingconstruction);see also Annotation,Effect of Practical or AdministrativeConstructionof a Statuteon SubsequentJudicial Construction,73 L. Ed. 322 (1929) (citing hundredsof state and federal cases discussing deference to executive views). 30. The United States arguedthat the "normalrule"of deferenceshould apply, and that the court of appeals was "fundamentallyat odds with the most basic principlesof administrativelaw." See Brief for the National Resources Defense Council at 19, Chevron(No. 82-1005). 976 The Yale Law Journal [Vol. 101: 969 Just the previous year, in Motor Vehicles ing with the emissions standard.31 ManufacturersAss'n v. State Farm Mutual,32the Court had reacted with skepticismto a similarderegulatoryinitiative;thus, it seemed unlikelythatthe Court would write a broad prodeferenceopinion in response to the EPA's "bubblepolicy." Indeed, there is reason to believe that the participatingJustices did not regardChevronas a departurefrom priorlaw. Justice Stevens' opinion for the Court generated no concurring or dissenting statementsprotesting or even remarkingon his approach.And in the year following Chevron,the Court decided nineteen cases involving deference issues, but applied the Chevron frameworkonly once.33In time, however, lower courts, agencies, and commentatorsall came to regardthe analysis of the deferencequestion set forth in Chevronas fundamentallydifferentfrom that of the previous era. Justice Stevens' opinion contained several features that can only be described as even if no revolutionwas intendedat the time. "revolutionary,"34 Chevron'sfirst importantinnovationwas the prescriptionof a procedural formulafor courtsto follow in determiningwhetherto deferto agencyinterpretations. Each case, the Courtsuggested, shouldproceedin two steps. At step one, the court would operatein the independentjudgmentmode. It would ask, using traditionaltools of statutoryconstruction,whetherCongresshad"directly spoken to the precise question at issue."35If the court concluded that Congress had a "specific intention"36with respect to the issue at hand, it would adopt and enforce that answer.But if the court failed to uncoverany such intention, it would move on to step two, where it would shift into the deferencemode. Here, the question would be whetherthe agency's position was "a reasonable of the statute. interpretation"37 On its face, the two-step formulaseems innocuousenough. Indeed,after the formlessness of the previous era, it offers the beguiling promise of an orderlymethodfor resolvinga wide varietyof controversies.Whatwas unclear at the time, however, was that the two-step inquiry as framed by Chevron 31. 467 U.S. at 840. 32. 463 U.S. 29 (1983). 33. See Chemical Mfrs. Ass'n v. National ResourcesDefense Council, 470 U.S. 116 (1985); see also Table 1, infra. JusticeStevens' behaviorseems to confirm this point. Earlyin the nextTerm,JusticeStevens authoredan opinion that was much more consistent with pre-Chevroncase law than with the Chevron doctrine. ConnecticutDep't of Income Maintenancev. Heckler,471 U.S. 524 (1985). And less than three weeks before Chevronwas decided, JusticeStevens authoreda dissentingopinion statingthat no deference was due to an administrativeinterpretationbecause it "has not been a model of consistency."Aluminum Co. of Am. v. CentralLincolnPeople's Util. Dist., 467 U.S. 380,402-03 n.3 (1984) (Stevens, J., dissenting). These opinions tend to suggest that Justice Stevens himself regardedChevronas a restatementof existing law ratherthan a new approach. 34. KennethW. Starr,Judicial Review in the Post-ChevronEra, 3 YALEJ. ONREG.283, 284 (1986). As Judge Starrcorrectlynotes: "Thisrevolutionaryeffect is not apparentfrom a quick examinationof the opinion itself." Id. at 284. 35. Chevron,467 U.S. at 842. 36. Id. at 845. 37. Id. at 844. 19921 Executive Precedent 977 would have profoundconsequencesfor the way in which courts approachthe deference question. There are several reasons for reachingthis conclusion. First, in contrastto the previous approach,the two-step structuremakes deferencean all-or-nothingmatter.If the courtresolvesthe questionat step one, then it exercises purelyindependentjudgmentandgives no considerationto the executive view. If it resolves the questionat step two, then it appliesa standard of maximumdeference.In effect, Chevrontransformeda regime that allowed courts to give agencies deferencealong a sliding scale into a regime with an on/off switch. Second, the Court'snew frameworkinvertedthe traditionaldefaultrule. In the pre-Chevronperiod, deference to executive interpretationsrequired specialjustification;independentjudgmentwas the defaultrule.UnderChevron, the court must initially establishwhetherthe issue is suitablefor independent judicial resolution;if it is not, the court automaticallyshifts into a deferential mode. As a result,independentjudgmentnow requiresspecialjustification,and deference is the default rule. If, as the Courtseemed to suggest, the circumstancesjustifying independentjudgmentwere definednarrowly,this inversion portendeda majortransferof interpretativepower from courts to agencies. Third,the two-step frameworkhas importantimplicationsfor the kinds of considerationsthatenterintojudicialdecisionmaking.In particular,the framework appearsto exclude any examinationof the multiple factors historically relied upon by courts. The most immediatebasis for this conclusion is the Court's decision to defer to the EPA'sdefinition of "stationarysource"even thoughit arguablyrepresenteda "sharpbreakwith priorinterpretationsof the Act."38Thus, the decision appearedto downgradethe frequentlycited factor stressing the importanceof agency views that were longstandingand consistent.39More importantly,none of the traditionalfactorsfits understep one or step two of the new framework.They are clearly irrelevantunderstep one, which focuses entirelyon whathappenedin Congress,not on the agency or its decision. The factors could conceivably enter into the calculus at step two, where the court asks if the executive interpretationis "reasonable."But by "reasonable,"the Courtseemed to meanreasonablein light of the text, history, and interpretativeconventionsthat govern the interpretationof a statuteby a court;at least, this was the way the Courtconductedthe reasonablenessinquiry in Chevron40and subsequentcases.41The question whetheran interpretation 38. Id. at 862. 39. See Antonin Scalia, Judicial Deference to AdministrativeInterpretationsof Law, 1989 DUKEL.J. 511, 517 (under Chevron, "there is no longer any justification for giving 'special' deference to 'longstanding and consistent' agency interpretationsof law"). On the other hand, Chevronitself made passing reference to one traditionalfactor-agency expertise. See Chevron,467 U.S. at 865. 40. 467 U.S. at 843-45. 41. See, e.g., Pauley v. BethenergyMines, Inc., 111 S. Ct. 2524, 2534-35 (1991); Rust v. Sullivan, 111 S. Ct. 1759, 1769 (1991); United States v. RiversideBayview Homes, Inc., 474 U.S. 121, 131 (1985). Two decisions from last Termillustratethe problemof whatto do with the traditionalfactorsunderChevron. In Pauley, 111 S. Ct. 2524, the Courtconsideredtwo traditionalfactors (expertise and longstandingand 978 The Yale Law Journal [Vol. 101: 969 is reasonablein light of these traditionalnormsof judicial interpretationlikewise provides no place for the various contextualfactorsthat played such an importantrole in the pre-Chevronera. In addition to its novel framework,Chevronalso broke new ground by invoking democratic theory as a basis for requiringdeference to executive interpretations.Congress, Justice Stevens reasoned,is the ultimate source of lawmakingauthorityin a democracy."If the intent of Congressis clear, that is the end of the matter;for the court, as well as the agency, must give effect to the unambiguouslyexpressedintentof Congress."42 If the intentionsof the not are then we are clear, however, primarylawgiver presentedwith a choice: who should undertaketo fill in the gap in the understandingof congressional will, the courtor the agency?Chevrondeclaredthatthe agency is the preferred gap filler. Judges "are not part of either political branch";they "have no An agency,on the otherhand,while "notdirectlyaccountable constituency."43 to the people,"is subjectto the generaloversightand supervisionof the President, who is accountable.Thus, it is fitting that agencies, ratherthan courts, resolve "thecompetinginterestswhichCongressitself eitherinadvertentlydid not resolve, or intentionallyleft to be resolvedby the agency chargedwith the administrationof the statutein light of everydayrealities."44 This new emphasis on democratictheory was importantto the doctrinal frameworkbecause it suppliedthe justificationfor switching the defaultrule from independentjudgmentto deference.Underthe pre-Chevronregime, not every agency decision wouldqualify for deferencein the face of an ambiguous statute. In order to make deference a general default rule, the Court had to come up with some universalreasonwhy administrativeinterpretationsshould be preferredto the judgmentsof Article IIIcourts.Democratictheorysupplied thejustification:agencydecisionmakingis alwaysmoredemocraticthanjudicial consistent interpretation)as part of the discussion of whetheror not to defer. In Rust, 111 S. Ct. 1759, on the other hand, the Court appendeda discussion of traditionalfactors (lack of consistency in the agency position andthe well-reasonednatureof the decision)to its discussionunderstep two. These recentdecisions indicate that the Courtcontinuesto believe the traditionalfactorsare relevant,but has no idea what to do with them under the Chevronframework. 42. 467 U.S. at 842-43. 43. Id. at 865-66. 44. Id. For a recent elaborationof the democratictheory foundationsof Chevron,see LaurenceH. Silberman, Chevron-The Intersectionof Law & Policy, 58 GEO.WASH.L. REV.821, 822-24 (1990). Chevron'sdemocratictheory thesis appears to presupposea unitary executive, i.e., an interpretationof separationof powers that would place all entities engaged in the execution of the law-including the socalled independentregulatoryagencies-under Presidentialcontrol.See Steven Calabresi& Kevin Rhodes, The StructuralConstitution:UnitaryExecutive,Plural Judiciary, 105 HARV.L. REV.(forthcomingApr. 1992);Geoffrey Miller,IndependentAgencies, 1986 SUP.CT.REV.41. Agencies arenot directlyaccountable to the people; they can invoke a popularmandateonly if they are accountableto the elected President. Althoughthe unitaryexecutive constructionwas dealt a setbackin Morrisonv. Olson, 487 U.S. 654 (1988) (permittingCongress to insulate independentcounsel from removalexcept for good cause), it is far from clear thatthe matterhas been settled conclusively.See Toubyv. United States, 111S. Ct. 1752, 1757 (1991) (noting that "[t]he Constitutionvests all executive power in the President,U.S. Const., Art. II, ? 1"). 1992] Executive Precedent 979 decisionmakingbecause all agencies are accountable(to some degree) to the President,and the Presidentis elected by the people. Chevron'sheavy reliance on democratictheory left one majorproblem. Congresspresumablyrankshigheron the democracyscale thando the agencies. After all, Congress is directly elected by the people; agencies are at most indirectlyaccountableto the electoratethroughthe President.Yet how do we know thatCongress,the ultimatedemocratictrumpcard,wantsambiguitiesand gaps to be resolved by agencies ratherthan by courts? Chevronsolved this potentialquandaryby adoptingits thirdand probably most controversialinnovation: a presumptionthat whenever Congress has delegatedauthorityto an agency to administera statute,it has also delegated authority to the agency to interpret any ambiguities present in the statute.45 Previous cases, as we have seen, suggested that deferencewas appropriateif Congress had expressly delegatedto an executive agency the power to define a particularterm. Chevronin effect adopteda fiction thatassimilatedall cases involving statutoryambiguitiesor gaps into the expressdelegationor "legislative rule" model.46 In short, the Chevron opinion can be understoodas a prescriptionfor resolvingquestionsof statutoryinterpretationthrougha series of presumptions about primary and delegated lawmaking. Congress is presumed to be the primarylawmakinginstitution,and whereit has spoken,its will must prevail. But when Congress has not addressedthe precise issue in dispute and has delegatedauthorityto an administrativeagency,thenwe presumethatinterpretative authorityhas been delegatedto the agency.Onlyif Congressis silentand has failed to designatean agency to administerthe statutedo we presumethat power to interpretambiguouslaw has been delegatedto an Article III court. Given the rhetoricof JusticeStevens' opinion,the most apparentobjective of this series of presumptionswas to maximize the role of democratically accountableinstitutionsin the processof legal interpretationand to restrictthe discretionof unelectedcourts.Conceivably,the formalismof Chevronmay also 45. In Chevron,the Court stated the presumptionin terms of "implicit"delegations: 'The power of an administrativeagency to administera congressionallycreated ... program necessarily requires the formulationof policy and the making of rules to fill any gap left, implicitly or explicitly, by Congress.' If Congresshas explicitly left a gap for the agency to fill, there is an express delegation of authorityto the agency to elucidate a specific provisionof the statute by regulation.... Sometimes the legislative delegation to an agency on a particular question is implicit ratherthan explicit. 467 U.S. at 843-44 (quoting Mortonv. Ruiz, 415 U.S. 199, 231 (1974)). Recent decisions have reaffirmedthat the generalduty to defer identifiedin Chevronis groundedin a theory of presumeddelegation. See Pauley, 111 S. Ct. at 2534; Martinv. OccupationalSafety & Health Review Comm., 111S. Ct. 1171, 1175 (1991) (discussingdeferenceto an agency's interpretationof its own regulations);Adams FruitCo. v. Barrett, 110 S. Ct. 1384 (1990). For an especially clear recognitionthat Chevronrests on a presumptionthatambiguitiesentaila delegationof interpretativepower,see Scalia,supra note 39, at 516-17. 46. See Kevin W. Saunders,InterpretativeRules with LegislativeEffect:An Analysis and a Proposal for Public Participation, 1986 DUKEL.J. 346, 357 (Chevwron appearsto eliminate the distinctionbetween legislative rules and intepretativerules). 980 The Yale Law Journal [Vol. 101: 969 have reflected a desire to streamlinethe deference inquiry by reducing the multiple variablesof the precedingera to two basic inquiries.In any event, in the clarity of its proceduralformula,and the implicationsof that formulafor the balance of power among the branches,Chevrondoes indeed appearto presage a "revolutionary"transformationof the old order. II. CHEVRON: THEREVOLUTION IN PRACTICE Each year the SupremeCourtdecides somewherebetweenten and twenty cases in which it confrontsan issue aboutwhetherto deferto an administrative interpretationof a statute.This steadystreamof deferencecases has abatedonly slightly since Chevronwas decided.As a result,thereis now an extensivebody of decisionallaw within the Courtthatcan be used to gauge Chevron'simpact. Surprisingly,no one has undertakena comprehensivesurvey of these decisions.47To the contrary,the commentaryon Chevrontends to assume-almost always based on only a handfulof the Court'spost-Chevrondecisions-either that the Court has faithfully followed Chevronin succeeding years48or that the Courthas essentiallydisregardedthe radicalimplicationsof the decision.49 A surveyof the full rangeof the Court'sdecisionsbeforeandafterChevron discloses a more complex and indeed ratherbewilderingpicture.On the one hand, Chevron clearly has resulted in a significant shift in the deference doctrine.On the otherhand,Chevronhas notproducedanythinglike a complete revolution in the Court's jurisprudence.On the whole, the overall picture suggests that the judicial understandingthatinformsthe deferencequestionis probablymore confused today than it has ever been. A. The IncompleteRevolution One way to measurethe impactof Chevronis to examine the Court'sown post-Chevrondeference cases in the aggregate. In order to make such an assessment,I reviewedall SupremeCourtdecisionsfrom the 1981 Termto the end of the 1990 Term.The resultsfor the seven post-ChevronTerms(Chevron was decided near the end of the 1983 Term)are summarizedin Table 1.50 47. The most complete account of post-Chevrondevelopments in the Supreme Court is found in Sunstein, supra note 4, at 2091-104. 48. See, e.g., RichardJ. Pierce, Ji., Chevronand its Aftermath:Judicial Review of AgencyInterpretations of StatutoryProvisions, 41 VAND.L. REV.301, 302 (1988); Starr,supra note 34, at 291. 49. See, e.g., Linda R. Hirschman,PostmodernJurisprudenceand the Problem of Administrative Discretion, 82 Nw. U. L. REV.646, 703 (1988). 50. The cases thatcomprisethe dataare summarizedin the tables,infrapp. 981-82, 992, and are listed in the Appendix, infra. Executive Precedent 1992] 981 TABLE1. Post-Chevron Terms A B C E F CHEVRON CHEVRON TOTAL CASES TERM D INVOLVING CHEVRON FRAMEWORK:FRAMEWORK:CASESCIING DEFERENCE AGENCYVIEW FRAMEWORKAGENCYVIEW DECIDEDAT TRADITIONAL APPLIED STEPTWO FACTORS ACCEPTED ACCETED QUESnON 1990 11 1989 14 8 (73%) 8 (57%) 6 (55%) 9 (62%) 3 (33%) 1988 9 1987 14 4 (44%) 9 (64%) 1986 9 5 (55%) 5 (36%) 2 (22%) 1985 14 1984 19 11(78%) 18 (94%) 6 (43%) 1 (5%) TOTAL1984-90 90 63 (70%) 32 (36%) 4 (66%) 4 (44%) 2 (33%) 2 (25%) 1 (33%) 3 (60%) 1 (50%) 1 (33%) 3 (50%) 1 (50%) 5 (83%) 1 (100%) 4 (66%) 1 (100%) 19 (59%) 14 (44%) 6 (55%) 4 (29%) 6 (66%) 3 (21%) 2 (22%) 6 (43%) 7 (35%) 34 (37%) Column A reportsthe total numberof cases each Termin which at least one Justicerecognizedthe presenceof a question(concerningeithera primary or a subsidiaryissue) about whether to give deference to an administrative interpretationof a statute.5'ColumnB indicateshow many of these decisions Column C shows how many of the accepted the executive interpretation.52 total cases appliedthe two-stepChevronframeworkor its equivalent;53 column 51. Adopting a principlefor includingcases in the survey posed some problems.On the one hand,it is commonly perceived that there are many cases in which the Court substitutesits judgmentfor that of the agency and fails even to mentionthe possibilityof deference.See 5 DAVIS,supra note 6, at 403. Ideally, these cases would be included in the sample in orderto determinethe true incidence of deference.On the other hand, it would be very difficult to determineall the cases in which the Court could have deferred. I would have had to read the briefs and records in all cases involving a question of federal statutory interpretation.Moreover,determiningthe full set of potentialdeferencecases based on some independent standardwould pose difficult conceptual problems in defining what is a potential deference case. For instance, would a decision count as a potential deferencecase if it involved an interpretationadoptedfor the first time in briefs filed in court defending an agency action? Would a decision count as a potential deference case if it involved an interpretationof a provisionthat the agency is not directly empoweredto regulate? Given these competing considerations,I compromisedand adopted a selection principle that included all cases in which at least one Justice mentioned the possibility of deferring to an agency interpretation.This picks up some of the cases wherethe majoritysubstitutesjudgmentanddoes not mention deference, but a dissenting or concurringJusticeraises the issue. Thus, it producesa slightly largersample than would an approachthat looked solely to majorityopinions. But clearly the one-Justiceprincipledoes not include all potential deference cases (for example, it skips cases where the Court is unanimousand substitutes its judgment). Consequently,the sample still undercountsthe total number of cases where deference could have been invoked. Anotherproblemwas what to do with cases thatpresentslight variationson the questionof deference to agency interpretationsof statutes,such as cases involvingan agency interpretationof its own regulations, agency interpretationsof a treaty,or challenges to agency policies on the ground that they were adopted in an arbitraryand capricious manner(as opposed to being in conflict with a statute).These cases (which were relatively few in numbercomparedto the statutoryinterpretationcases) were excluded in the interest of minimizing complexity. 52. "Acceptingthe agency interpretation"is not the same as ruling in favor of the government.In a few cases the Courtruled against the governmenteven though it acceptedthe agency interpretation.This might happen,for example, if the SolicitorGeneraldisclaimedthe agency view, but the Courtagreedwith it. See, e.g., Bob Jones Univ. v. United States, 461 U.S. 574 (1983). 53. I adopted a very broad test for determining whether the Court was "applying"the Chevron framework.I includedin this category not just the cases thatquoted the two-step procedure,or organized the discussion aroundthe two-step procedure,but also those that cited Chevronor post-Chevrondecisions, The Yale Law Journal 982 [Vol. 101: 969 D reportshow many of the cases following the Chevronframeworkaccepted the executiveinterpretation; columnE revealsthe numberof Chevroncases that consideration to the some reasonablenessof the executive view (step two gave of the framework) as opposed to stopping at step one. Finally, column F indicates how many controllingopinions in the cases rely on one or more of the traditionalfactorsappliedin the pre-Chevronperiod, such as longstanding and consistent interpretation,contemporaneousinterpretation,congressional ratification,and so forth.54In orderto providea basis for comparison,Table 2 reproducesdata for some of these variables (total deference cases, cases accepting the administrativeinterpretation,and cases applying traditional factors) for the three pre-ChevronTerms, 1981-83. TABLE2. Pre-Chevron Terms A TERM B F TOTALCASESINVOLVING CASESCITING DEFERENCE FACTORS QUESTION AGENCYVIEWACCEPTED TRADITIONAL 1983 19 13 (68%) 11 (57%) 1982 15 11 (73%) 11 (73%) 1981 11 10 (90%) 8 (73%) TOTAL1981-83 45 34 (75%) 30 (66%) A numberof interestingconclusions can be derived from the figures in Tables 1 and 2. First, it is clear that Chevronis often ignoredby the Supreme Court.Althoughthe Chevronopinionpurportsto describea universalstandard by which to determinewhetherto follow an administrativeinterpretationof a statute,the two-step frameworkhas been used in only about one-thirdof the total post-Chevroncases in which one or more Justices recognized that a deferencequestion was presented.55 AlthoughChevronbegan to be used more after the 1987 it is still far from the monolithic norm the Term, frequently such as K MartCorp. v. Cartier,Inc., 486 U.S. 281 (1988), in setting forth the standardof review, or that otherwiseindicatedthatdeferencewould be owed to any agencydecisionprovidedCongresshadnot clearly answeredthe question. Essentially,I tried to determinewhetherthe authorof the controllingopinion was thinkingabout Chevronin setting forth the analysis of deference. Although admittedlythis is a highly subjective standard,I believe it is more reliable than any other yardstick.If anything,it tends to overstate the influence of Chevron. 54. Column F includes both Chevronframeworkcases and non-Chevronframeworkcases. Most of the cases in this column either ignore or disclaim reliance on Chevronin favor of the traditionalapproach. Some, however,purportto rely on the Chevronframework,even if this is (arguably)inconsistentwith also relying on the traditionalfactors. 55. This undoubtedlyunderstatesthe extent to which Chevronis ignored,because cases where there is an executive interpretation,but where the Court fails to note even the possibility of deferring to that interpretation,were excluded from the survey.In otherwords, the most extremeinstancesof "independent judgment"were ignored. See supra note 51. 1992] Executive Precedent 983 opinionseems to describe.If we look solely at the 1987-90period,the two-step frameworkwas still appliedin only half of the deferencedecisions. Althoughsome of the failureto rely on Chevronmay be attributedto time as lag, awarenessof the decisionslowly disseminatedthroughthe administrative bar,56this cannot accountfor the persistentresistanceto using the framework in the SupremeCourt. By the end of the 1987 Term,for example, the Court had appliedthe Chevronframeworkin fifteen differentcases in a wide variety of areas.57Any Justice who was paying attention to the Court's own work productshould have been thoroughlyversed in the tenets of Chevronby this time. Moreover,even if administrativelawyersin specializedareaslike tax and laborlaw were late in comingto an awarenessof Chevron,the federalagencies were representedin the SupremeCourt almost exclusively by the Solicitor General'soffice-a small groupof"generalists"who havebeenvery conscious of Chevron.58Thus, by 1987 at the latest, the agencies could be expected to take maximumadvantageof Chevronin the SupremeCourt.Yetin the 1988-90 Terms,the Courtcontinuedto apply the Chevronframeworkin only half the cases presenting a deference question. The persistentspottiness of Chevron duringthis period stronglysuggests thatthe Courtin many cases was simply 56. The surveyclearly suggests such a time lag. As previouslynoted,it took some time for the Chevron doctrine to appearin the Court'sopinions;the 1984 Termmust for all intents and purposes be considered partof the pre-Chevronera. Moreover,even in yearswhen Chevronis appliedwith some frequency,it tends to be invoked less often in areas where there is a particularlyrich traditionof pre-Chevronprecedenton deference.Forexample,in Title VII, labor,tax, social security,andenvironmentalcases, the Court(no doubt guidedto a degree by the submissionsof the parties)still tends to framethe deferencestandardin the terms expressedin earlierdecisions specific to these areas,ratherthanin termsof Chevron.See, e.g., CottageSav. Ass'n v. Commissioner,111 S. Ct. 1503 (1991) (citing previous cases for deference standard;no mention of Chevron);EEOC v. ArabianAm. Oil Co., 111 S. Ct. 1227, 1235 (1991) (citing pre-Chevroncases for standardof deference to EEOC); Robertson v. Methow Valley Citizens Council, 490 U.S. 332 (1989) (Council on EnvironmentalQuality'sinterpretationof NEPA assessed undertraditionalfactors,no citation to Chevron);Atkins v. Rivera,477 U.S. 154 (1986) (review of Social SecurityAdministrationinterpretation based on legislative/interpretativedistinctionof pre-Chevronera); MeritorSav. Bank v. Vinson, 477 U.S. 57, 65 (1986) (same);NLRB v. Action Automotive,Inc., 469 U.S. 490,494-96 (1984) (citing PackardMotor Car Co. v. NLRB, 330 U.S. 485 (1947), and NLRB v. HearstPublications,Inc., 332 U.S. 111 (1944) (deference approachto NLRB decisions). In contrast,in areasin which the pre-Chevroncase law was less well developed-ERISA andbanking cases seem to fall in this category-Chevron seems to have made more headwayin the Court. See. e.g., Pension Benefit Guar.Corp. v. LTV Corp., 110 S. Ct. 2668, 2676 (1990) (applying Chevronstandardin ERISA controversy);Mead Corp. v. Tilley, 490 U.S. 714 (1989) (same); Clarkev. SecuritiesIndus.Ass'n, 479 U.S. 388 (1987) (Chevronappliedto interpretationby Comptrollerof Currency);Board of Governors v. Dimension Fin. Corp., 474 U.S. 361 (1986) (Chevronframeworkappliedto FederalReserve interpretation). 57. K Mart Corp. v. Cartier,Inc., 486 U.S. 281 (1988); EdwardJ. DeBartolo Corp. v. FloridaGulf Coast Bldg. & Constr.TradesCouncil, 485 U.S. 568 (1988); Bethesda Hosp. Ass'n v. Bowen, 485 U.S. 399 (1988); ETSI Pipeline Projectv. Missouri, 484 U.S. 495 (1988); Honig v. Doe, 484 U.S. 305 (1988); NLRB v. United Food & Commercial Workers Union, Local 23, 484 U.S. 112 (1987); INS v. Cardoza-Fonseca,480 U.S. 421 (1987); Clarke v. Securities Indus. Ass'n, 479 U.S. 388 (1987); Japan Whaling Ass'n v. American Cetacean Soc'y, 478 U.S. 221 (1986); United States Dep't of Transp. v. ParalyzedVeteransof Am., 477 U.S. 597 (1986); Youngv. CommunityNutritionInst.,476 U.S. 974 (1986); United States v. City of Fulton, 475 U.S. 657 (1986); Board of Governorsv. Dimension Fin. Corp., 474 U.S. 361 (1986); United States v. RiversideBayview Homes, Inc., 474 U.S. 121 (1985); Chemical Mfrs. Ass'n v. National Resources Defense Council, 470 U.S. 116 (1985). 58. This was true by the fall of 1987, when I joined the Solicitor General'sOffice. 984 The Yale Law Journal [Vol. 101: 969 not preparedto abide by the type of analysis dictatedby Chevron-although apparentlyit was not preparedto abandonit or explain why it ought not to be controllingeither. Second,althoughChevronis generallyregardedas directingthatcourtsgive thereis no discerniblerelationship greaterdeferenceto executiveinterpretations, between the applicationof the Chevronframeworkand greateracceptanceof the executive view. Indeed,cases applyingthe Chevronapproachhave on the whole producedfeweraffirmancesof executive interpretationsthanthose that do not follow Chevron.59Althoughthe numberof cases is too small to attribute significance to the precisepercentages,the generalphenomenonis apparent when we compare the rate of acceptancesin the cases actually applyingthe Chevron frameworkin the post-Chevronperiod-59% adoptingthe agency view-with eitherthe overallacceptanceratein the post-Chevronperiod(70%) or the ratein the pre-Chevronera (75%).Paradoxically,it appearsthatadoption of the Chevronframeworkhas meant, if anything,a decline in deferenceto agency views. The suggestion that Chevronhas had little discernibleinfluence on the SupremeCourtcontrastssharplywith the only otherpublishedempiricalstudy of Chevron'simpact. ProfessorsPeter Schuckand Donald Elliot undertooka survey of Chevron'sinfluence on lower courts and found that deference to Their findings,howagency interpretationsincreasedsharplyafterChevron.60 ever, are not necessarilyinconsistentwith my datasuggestingno such change in the SupremeCourt. Lower courts probablytake SupremeCourt opinions more seriously than does the Courtitself.6'Moreover,one would predictthat as it became increasinglyevident over time that the SupremeCourtemploys the Chevronapproachonly sporadically,lower courtswould begin to revertto their old habits. And indeed, there is evidence in the Schuck and Elliot study that suggests the "Chevroneffect" in the lower courts may have been only temporary.62 Third, the tables indicate that the emergence of Chevron has caused a decline in relianceon the traditionalcontextualfactorsfor determiningwhether 59. This conclusionis to some extent probablya reflectionof my samplingmethodology.In particular, the non-Chevroncases may contain a disproportionatenumberof affirmances.This is because when the Courtagrees with an agency construction,it may often throwin deferenceto the administrativeagency as an additionalfactoror considerationin supportof its judgment.But when it disagreeswith the agency view, it may not mention the issue of deference.On the other hand, this possibility is mitigatedby the fact that even if the majorityignoresthe agency interpretation,a dissentingor concurringopinionmay raise the issue of deference-and these cases are also included in the sample. Moreover,even if the rate of agency affirmancesis overstatedin the non-Chevroncases, this would not accountfor the relativelylow percentage of affirmances in the cases applyingthe Chevronframework,where the issue of deference is necessarily presentedin each instance. 60. Peter H. Schuck & E. Donald Elliott, To the Chevron Station: An EmpiricalStudy of Federal AdministrativeLaw, 1990 DUKEL.J. 984. 61. Indeed, they are requiredto do so in many circumstances.See Hicks v. Miranda,422 U.S. 332, 343-45 (1975) (lower courts bound by SupremeCourtsummaryaffirmance,even if Court itself is not). 62. Schuck & Elliott, supra note 60, at 1037. 1992] Executive Precedent 985 deferenceis appropriate.Again, the numbersare too small to attributesignificance to precise percentages,but in the pre-Chevronperiod (1981-83 Terms) 66% of the deference cases cited one or more of these traditionalfactors.In the post-Chevronperiod,in contrast,the percentageof cases citing one of these factorsdeclined to 36% overall. Still, it is obvious that the Court'sinvocation of these factorspersists, with no visible trendpointingtowardtheir complete extinction.This is not whatone wouldexpect to find if Chevronhadcompletely transformedthe practice of deciding when to defer. B. The ContestedRevolution When we turn from the aggregatedata to an examinationof the Court's opinions, the picture that emerges again suggests that the Chevronrevolution-although real-is a tenuous one. I will not discuss the many routine applicationsof Chevron,the even more numerouscases that ignore Chevron, or even those cases where the majorityand dissent disagree over the proper application of Chevronto particularcircumstances.More revealing are the opinionsthatengagein disputesoverwhatmightbe called"Chevronfundamentals." The presence of these disputes is not necessarily surprising.There has probably never been a watershedSupremeCourt opinion (considerBrown, Miranda,Mapp, and Roe)63that did not generatesubsequentcontroversyover the scope and meaning of the original decision. Whatis striking,however,is the extent to which the Court'sresolutionsof disputesover the meaningof the Chevron framework rest uncomfortablywith the rationale of the original decision. Without a doubt, the most remarkableepisode occurred in INS v. a case involving interpretationof immigrationlaw, where Cardoza-Fonseca,64 the Courthas traditionallyshown considerabledeferenceto executive views.65 Specifically, the issue was whetherthe statutorystandardfor awardingasylum could be construedas requiringthe same showing of likelihoodof persecution uponreturnto the countryof originas the standardfor withholdingof deportation. The AttorneyGeneral,actingthroughthe Bureauof ImmigrationAppeals, determinedthatthe two provisionsrequiredthe same showing.A baremajority of five Justices-in an opinionby JusticeStevens,the authorof Chevron-held thatthis executive interpretationwas not entitledto deference.The first reason was entirely consistent with the Chevronframework:"Employingtraditional tools of statutoryconstruction,we haveconcludedthatCongressdid not intend 63. Brown v. Board of Educ., 347 U.S. 483 (1954); Mirandav. Arizona, 384 U.S. 436 (1966); Mapp v. Ohio, 367 U.S. 643 (1961); Roe v. Wade,410 U.S. 113 (1973). 64. 480 U.S. 421 (1987). 65. See, e.g., INS v. Rios-Pineda,471 U.S. 444, 452 (1985) (admonishinglower courts not to usurp authoritygrantedto the AttorneyGeneralin administeringthe immigrationlaws); Hamptonv. Mow Sun Wong, 426 U.S. 88, 101-02 n.21 (1976) (noting that "power over aliens is of a political characterand thereforesubject to only a narrowjudicial review"). 986 The Yale Law Journal [Vol. 101: 969 the two standardsto be identical."66In what appearedto be an alternative holding, however,Justice Stevens statedthatthe Chevronstandardwas in any event inapplicablebecause the issue for decision was a "pure question of Deferencewould be appropriate,he suggested,only statutoryconstruction."67 if the case concernedthe applicationof the standardto particularfacts.68 The notion that deferenceto agency views should turnon the distinction between pure questionsof law and questionsof law applicationcan be found in some SupremeCourtdecisions of the 1940's.69But the distinctionhad been abandonedfor all practicalpurposeslong before Chevronwas decided.70The suggestionthatwhatChevronhaddone was to restorethis ancientlearningwas truly astonishing,as JusticeScalia madeclearin an acidic concurrence.In fact, as Justice Scalia correctlynoted, the issue in Chevron,concerningthe proper definition of the statutoryterm "source,"was obviously a "purequestion of law," and hence would be entitled to no deferenceunderthe Court'sdistinction.71Moreover,the dispute about the propermeaning of Chevronhad not been briefed and argued in Cardoza-Fonseca,nor was it necessary to the decision. It was thus inappropriatefor the Court to cast doubt on such "an extremely importantand frequentlycited opinion."72 Cardoza-Fonsecagave rise to a brief period of uncertaintyin the lower courts over whether Chevronstill applied to pure questions of law.73By the end of the next Term, however, the Court was again applying the Chevron doctrine(irregularly,as ever) to questionsof law,andCardoza-Fonsecaquietly droppedfrom sight.74But if Cardoza-Fonsecahad no lasting impact on the 66. Cardoza-Fonseca,480 U.S. at 446. 67. Id. 68. Id. at 448. 69. ComparePackardMotor Car Co. v. NLRB, 330 U.S. 485, 493 (1947) (no deference to agency views on "nakedquestion of law") with NLRB v. HearstPublications,Inc., 322 U.S. 111, 130-31 (1944) (great deference to NLRB's determinationof how statutorystandardappliedto particularfactual circumstances). 70. See, e.g., FederalElectionComm'nv. DemocraticSenatorialCampaignComm.,454 U.S. 27 (1981) (deferringto agency interpretationof purequestion of law); FordMotorCreditCo. v. Milhollin,444 U.S. 555 (1980) (same); Monaghan,supra note 6, at 29-30. 71. Cardoza-Fonseca,480 U.S. at 455 (Scalia, J., concurringin judgment). 72. Id. at 454 (Scalia, J., concurringin judgment). 73. See NLRB v. FederalLaborRelationsAuth., 834 F.2d 191, 198 (D.C. Cir. 1987) (underCardozaFonseca no deferencedue to agencyinterpretationof "purequestionof law");Union of ConcernedScientists v. United States Nuclear RegulatoryComm'n, 824 F.2d 108, 113 (D.C. Cir. 1987) (Cardoza-Fonseca "stronglyindicate[s] that courts are to apply the Chevrontest only in circumstancesin which an agency is requiredto apply a legal standardto a particularset of facts").But see NLRB v. FLRA, 834 F.2dat 202 (Starr, J., concurring)("I continue to believe that Chevron'stwo-step interpretativeprocess, which was reaffirmed in Cardoza-Fonseca,provides the polestar that is to guide us."); id. at 203 (D. Ginsburg,J., concurring)(sharing Judge Starr's belief). 74. Early in the next term, Justice Scalia stated in a concurringopinion, NLRB v. United Food & CommercialWorkersUnion, Local 23, 484 U.S. 112, 133-34 (1987) (Scalia, J., concurring),thatCardozaFonseca was not being followed by the Court(althoughthe majorityin that case cited both Chevronand Cardoza-Fonseca).Shortlythereafter,the Courtrevertedto the Chevronframeworkwithoutany suggestion thatit was confined to cases of law application.See MeadCorp. v. Tilly, 490 U.S. 714 (1989); PittstonCoal Group v. Sebben, 488 U.S. 105 (1988); K Mart Corp v. Cartier,Inc., 486 U.S. 281 (1988). 1992] Executive Precedent 987 Court'sunderstandingof the Chevrondoctrine,the episode neverthelesssuggests that the Court's commitmentto Chevron-at least in its unvarnished original form-was at best fragile. The fact that a majorityof the Courtwas prepared(if only temporarily)to recastthat doctrinein a way that would strip it of most of its significance hardlysuggests that the Courtwas comfortable with Chevron'sinnovations. Other disputes over Chevronfundamentalssoon followed. Althoughless dramaticthan Cardoza-Fonseca,on balancethey too suggestedthatthe Court was not preparedto accept the full implicationsof the decision. With respect to one issue-what type of agency decision is entitled to Chevrondeference-the Courthas been faithfulto Chevron'slogic. In Adams Fruit Co. v. Barrett,75the Court held that Chevron applies only to agency decisions that are an exercise of delegatedauthority.Thus, a statementby the Departmentof Labor about the scope of private judicial remedies available under a federal statute was entitled to no deferencebecause the agency was given no authorityto regulatethis matter.Althoughthis decision cuts back on the potential scope of the Chevrondoctrine,it is consistentwith the language and rationale of Chevron,with its focus on the delegation of interpretative authorityimplicit in the delegationof decisional authority. With respect to other issues, however, the Court has departed from Chevron'slogic. For example, the Courthas held that Chevrondeferencedoes not apply to legal interpretationsadvancedfor the first time in appellatebriefs filed on behalf of an agency.76This conclusionis consistent with established tenets of administrativelaw.77But unlikethe propositionrecognizedin Adams Fruit,a general"posthoc rationalizationof counsel"exceptionis not consistent with Chevron.If Congress has delegatedauthorityto an agency to enforce a particularstatute,andtherefore(perChevron)hasimpliedlydelegatedinterpretative authorityto the agency,it shouldnot matterif the agency announcesits interpretationthrougha brief as opposed to, for example, an opinion letter writtenby the generalcounsel or an informaladjudication(bothof which have been held to be entitled to Chevrondeference78).Indeed, Justice Scalia has recognizedin a law review articlethatthe "posthoc rationalization"of counsel exception is at odds with Chevron.79Whateverthe implicationsof Chevron 75. 494 U.S. 638 (1990). The holdingin AdamsFruitwas foreshadowedby JusticeScalia's concurring opinion in Crandonv. United States, 494 U.S. 152, 168-84 (1990), where he arguedthat legal opinions of the Office of Legal Counsel of the Departmentof Justice were not entitled to Chevrondeference because they dealt with mattersover which that office had no enforcementresponsibility. 76. Bowen v. GeorgetownUniv. Hosp., 488 U.S. 204, 212 (1988). 77. See SEC v. Sloan, 436 U.S. 103, 117-18 (1978); InvestmentCo. Inst. v. Camp,401 U.S. 617, 628 (1971); SEC v. Chenery Corp., 318 U.S. 80 (1943). 78. See PensionBenefit Guar.Corp.v. LTVCorp., 110 S. Ct. 2668 (1990) (Chevrondeferenceto prior opinion letters); Mead Corp. v. Tilley, 490 U.S. 714 (1989) (same); JapanWhaling Ass'n v. American CetaceanSoc'y, 478 U.S. 221 (1986) (Chevrondeferenceto CommerceDepartmentcertificationof national compliance with treaty obligations);Young v. CommunityNutrition Inst., 476 U.S. 974 (1986) (Chevron deference to FDA notices setting "tolerancelevels"). 79. Scalia, supra note 39, at 517-18. 988 The Yale Law Journal [Vol. 101: 969 might be for this issue, however,it is clear that the Courtis not aboutto start deferring to governmentlegal briefs. Anotherissue that has resultedin a potentiallyimportantqualificationof the Chevronframeworkconcernsthe statusof canonsof statutoryconstruction. Chevronitself does not mentioncanons, and it is unclearwhere they fit under the framework.Althoughthe canons clearly qualify as a "traditionaltoo[l] of it is odd to think of a court concludingon the basis statutoryconstruction,"80 of a canon that Congress had an intention"on the precise question at issue." Canons are maxims or rules of thumbthat allow courts to imputeanswersto interpretativequestionswhen it is not possibleto discernby moredirectmeans what the legislatureintended. Thus, one would expect that if a court could interpreta statuteonly by invokinga canon,it would be forcedto acknowledge that the issue is one to which Congresshas not clearly spoken and that,under Chevron,it must thereforedefer to a reasonableinterpretationby the administrativeagency. Conceivably,the court would considerthe canons at step two, in asking whether the agency interpretationis reasonable.81But again, if an agency interpretationis consistentwith the languageand purposeof a statute, it is hard to see how it could be condemnedas unreasonablesimply because a judicial canon would suggest a contraryresult. The Court first directly confrontedthe issue of canons and Chevronin EdwardJ. DeBartolo Corp. v. Florida Gulf Coast Building & Construction Trades Council.82 The Court acknowledged that the relevant provision of the National Labor Relations Act was ambiguous and that the National Labor RelationsBoard(NLRB)hadinterpretedthe provisionto prohibitcertaintypes of handbilling.But the Courtalso thoughtthe NLRB'sconstructionwouldraise serious constitutionalquestions.Relying on the canon of avoidinginterpretations that raise serious constitutionalquestions,83the Courtin effect held that the result suggested by Chevronwas trumpedby the result suggested by the canon.Thus,insteadof integratingthe canoninto step one-on the groundthat it was indicative of congressionalintent-or step two-on the groundthat it illuminatedthe question of reasonableness-the Courtused the canon to oust the Chevronframeworkaltogether. The implications of this decision for the future of Chevronare hard to assess. On the one hand, DeBartolo could mean that Chevronitself is just another canon, as Professor Cass Sunstein has argued.84If true, this would raise a whole host of unanswered-and probablyunanswerable-questions aboutwhich canons overrideChevronand which are subordinateto Chevron. 80. ChevronU.S.A., Inc. v. National ResourcesDefense Council, 467 U.S. 837, 843 n.9 (1984). 81. Cf. Note, Chevron and Canons of StatutoryConstruction,58 GEO.WASH.L. REV.829 (1990) (arguingthat "statutedefining" canons should apply at step one while "statuteapplying"canons should apply at step two). 82. 485 U.S. 568 (1988). 83. See NLRB v. Catholic Bishop, 440 U.S. 490 (1979). 84. Sunstein, supra note 4, at 2113. 1992] Executive Precedent 989 On the other hand, in Rust v. Sullivan,85 the Court applied Chevron and re- fused to follow DeBartoloin circumstanceswherethreeJusticesfoundthatthe thus establishingthat it raised agency interpretationwas unconstitutional,86 "seriousconstitutionaldoubts."Rust could mean thatDeBartolo will be confined to its facts.87In any event, in holding that at least one canon trumps Chevronon at least one occasion, the Courthas furthercalled into doubt its commitmentto the stricturesof the Chevrondoctrine.88 A thirddevelopmentconcernsagency interpretationsthatare at odds with prior judicial precedent.Chevronholds that statutoryambiguities are to be resolved, if possible, by agencies not courts.Thus, if a court has construedan ambiguousstatute one way (without the benefit of an agency view), and an agency later has occasion to read the statutedifferently,the logic of Chevron would seem to indicatethat the court shouldfollow the agency interpretation, rather than the earlier judicial pronouncement.Indeed, the D.C. Circuit in Chevronhadinvalidatedthe EPA'sinterpretationof "stationarysource"largely becauseit was contraryto priorD.C. Circuitprecedent,and the Courtheld that this did not justify a departurefrom deference.89 Nevertheless, the SupremeCourt,in Maislin Industries,U.S. v. Primary Steel, Inc.,90emphaticallyrejectedthe idea that an agency might disregarda previousjudicial constructionof a statute,at least when it is a precedentof the Supreme Court: "Once we have determineda statute's clear meaning, we adhereto that determinationunderthe doctrineof stare decisis, and we judge an agency's later interpretationof the statuteagainst our prior determination of the statute'smeaning."91It is difficult to quarrelwith this conclusion, for there would be somethingunsettlingabouta worldin which executive branch administratorscould "overrule"SupremeCourtdecisions.Again, however,the 85. 111 S. Ct. 1759 (1991). 86. See id. at 1780-86 (Blackmun,J., dissenting,joined by Marshall& Stevens, JJ.). 87. Chief Justice Rehnquist'sopinion for the majoritywas less than illuminatingon the question of why the constitutionalissues did not raise a "seriousquestion."He simply statedthatpetitioners'constitutional arguments,although"not withoutsome force,"were not enough to "carrythe day."Id. at 1771. The opinion arguablycan be read as limiting the DeBartolo canon to cases in which the agency interpretation would be unconstitutional,as opposed to merely raising a "serious question"of constitutionality. 88. Othercases havepresentedquestionsinvolvingthe interactionof Chevronandthe canons,buthave not shed much light on the issue. In EEOCv. ArabianAm. Oil Co., 111 S. Ct. 1227, 1230 (1991), the Court relied heavily on the canon thatstatutesarepresumednot to applyoutsidethe territoriallimitsof the United States, and refusedto defer to the contraryjudgmentof the EEOC.But the Courtdid not applythe Chevron framework,so the decision does not say anythingaboutthe relationshipbetween Chevronand the canons. In Michigan Citizens for an Indep. Press v. Thornburgh,868 F.2d 1285, 1292-93 (D.C. Cir. 1989), aff'd, 493 U.S. 38 (1989), the D.C. CircuitreasonedthatChevronsupersedescanons based on substantivepolicy considerations,such as the canonrequiringthatexceptionsto the antitrustlaws be narrowlyconstrued.The Court granted certioraribut affirmed by an equally divided vote, and thus wrote no opinion. 89. Chevron U.S.A., Inc. v. National Resources Defense Council, 467 U.S. 837, 841-42 (1984); see also Mesa VerdeConstr.Co. v. NorthernCal. Dist. Council of Laborers,861 F.2d 1124, 1129-31 (9th Cir. 1988) (en banc) (interpretingChevronto permitagency to change interpretationnotwithstandingSupreme Court affirmance of prior view). 90. 110 S. Ct. 2759 (1990). 91. Id. at 2768. 990 The Yale Law Journal [Vol. 101: 969 outcome does not follow from the logic of Chevronand must be counted as yet anotherqualificationon that doctrine. In short, the post-Chevrondecisions explicatingthe meaning of Chevron reveal much that calls into questionthe Court'sfidelity to the doctrine.In one instance-Cardoza-Fonseca-the Court adopted,albeit only temporarily,an exception that would swallow the rule. Other decisions reveal a pattern of qualifyingor compromisingthe doctrinewith otherprinciplessuggestingthat Chevronrests at best uneasily in the largerbody of administrativelaw. C. The RevolutionTransformed Perhaps the most significant post-Chevrondevelopment,however, is a subtlebutimportantmodificationin the statementof the relevantinquiryat step one. As we have seen, Chevronformulatedthatinquiryin termsof whetherthe court could "clearly"discern that Congress"hadan intentionon the precise question at issue."92If this thresholdrequirementwere faithfully followed, there is little doubt that it would mark a majorshift of interpretativepower towardthe executive branch:it is a rarecase wherea courtcan fairly say that Congressthoughtabout,let alone formulateda clear view on, the preciseissue in controversy.The "specific intentions"formulationthereforeoperatesas an engine of judicial deference. By the same token, however, if the threshold determinationfor independentjudicial resolutionat step one were described differently-for example, if courts were instructedto ask whetherthe statute has a general meaning thatresolves the controversy,even if Congresshas not specifically addressedthe issue at hand-then the balance might shift back towardindependentjudgment.In short,underthe two-stepChevronframework, everythingturnson the theory of judicial interpretationadoptedat step one.93 Post-Chevroncases have in fact begun to change the formulationof the step-oneinquiry.The first sign of changewas whenopinionsbeganto dropany referenceto "specific intentions"or whetherCongresshad"clearlyspokento" the issue at hand and instead describedthe thresholdinquirysimply in terms of whether the statute was "ambiguous"or "unclear."94 Then, beginning in 1988 with the K Mart Corp. v. Cartier,Inc decision,95a more dramaticchange emerged: the Court began to describe the inquiry at step one in terms of whetherthe statute has a "plainmeaning."96This rubric,an offspring of the 92. 467 U.S. at 843 n.9. 93. See Anthony,supra note 7, at 18-25. 94. See, e.g., Mobil Oil Exploration& ProducingSoutheastInc. v. United DistributionCos., 111 S. Ct. 615 (1991); PittstonCoal Groupv. Sebben,488 U.S. 105 (1988); Honig v. Doe, 484 U.S. 305 (1988); Young v. CommunityNutrition Inst., 476 U.S. 974 (1986). 95. 486 U.S. 281 (1988). The K Mart approachwas anticipatedin Bethesda Hosp. Ass'n v. Bowen, 485 U.S. 399 (1988), Justice Kennedy'sfirst opinion for the Court. 96. See, e.g., Demarestv. Manspeaker,l l S. Ct. 599 (1991) (offering no deferenceto administrative construction that is contrary to plain language of statute); Sullivan v. Stroop, 110 S. Ct. 2499 (1990) (upholding agency interpretationas being compelled by plain meaning of statute); Public Employees 1992] Executive Precedent 991 "new textualism"espoused more generallyby Justices Scalia and Kennedy,97 has not been followed uniformly.Some opinionscontinueto quotethe language of Chevron about whether Congress has spoken to the precise question at issue.98The trend,however,has been stronglyaway fromthe originalChevron formulationof step one. Whatare the consequencesof substitutingtextualismfor intentionalismat step one? By itself, such a shift does not necessarilyreducedeference.Indeed, if the inquiry at step one is formulatedin terms of whetherthe statutorytext discloses that Congresshas spokento the precisequestionat issue, this results in even greater deferenceto agency views, becauseCongresshas undoubtedly "spoken to" fewer issues in text than it has throughsome combinationof textualand nontextualsources.But at the same time thatthe Courthas dropped the languageof intentandsubstitutedthe languageof plainmeaning,it has also droppedthe referenceto "theprecisequestionat issue." In K Mart, for example, Justice Kennedy's opinion stated that in ascertainingwhetherthere is a plainmeaning,"thecourtmustlook to the particularstatutorylanguageat issue, as well as the language and design of the statuteas a whole." 99 In this fashion, the "plain meaning" inquiry has tended in practice to devolve into an inquiry about whether the statute as a whole generates a clearly preferred meaning.10? The movement from "specific intention"to "plain meaning"to "plain meaningconsideringthe design of the statuteas a whole"is butone shortstep away from "best meaning."In other words, with a shift at step one from the "specificintentions"rubricto the "plainmeaning"rubric,the Courthasmoved the thresholdinquirya long way towardthe exercise of independentjudgment. Justice Scalia has candidlyadmittedthat the use of textualismat step one has this consequence: One who finds more often (as I do) that the meaning of a statuteis apparentfromits text andfromits relationshipwith otherlaws, thereby finds less often that the triggeringrequirementfor Chevrondeference exists. It is thus relativelyrarethat Chevronwill requireme to accept an interpretationwhich, though reasonable,I would not personally adopt. Contrariwise,one who abhorsa "plainmeaning"rule, and is willing to permit the apparentmeaning of a statuteto be impeached RetirementSys. v. Betts, 492 U.S. 158, 171 (1989) ("[N]odeferenceis due to agency interpretationsat odds with the plain language of the statute itself."). 97. See generallyWilliamN. Eskridge,Jr.,TheNew Textualism,37 UCLA L. REV.621 (1990); Patricia M. Wald, The Sizzling Sleeper: The Use of LegislativeHistory in ConstruingStatutesin the 1988-89 Term of the United States SupremeCourt, 39 AM. U. L. REV.277, 281 (1990). 98. See, e.g., Pension Benefit Guar.Corp. v. LTVCorp., 110 S. Ct. 2668 (1990); MeadCorp. v. Tilley, 490 U.S. 714 (1989). 99. 486 U.S. at 291 (emphasisadded).FourJusticesjoined this portionof JusticeKennedy'sopinion, making it the opinion of the Court. 100. For examples of this trend,see Dole v. United Steelworkers,110 S. Ct. 929 (1990); Sullivan v. Zebley, 110 S. Ct. 885 (1990); Public Employees RetirementSys. v. Betts, 492 U.S. 158 (1989). The Yale Law Journal 992 [Vol. 101: 969 by the legislative history,will more frequentlyfind agency-liberating ambiguity, and will discern a much broaderrange of "reasonable" interpretationthatthe agency may adoptand to which the courtsmust pay deference. The frequencywith which Chevronwill require that judge to accept an interpretationhe thinks wrong is infinitely greater.101 In short, the mergerof the two-step Chevronframeworkand Justice Scalia's "plainmeaning"approachto statutoryconstruction,if consistentlyfollowed, would dramaticallytransformChevronfroma deferencedoctrineto a doctrine of antideference. Table 3, which collects the results from Table 1 into two time periods, suggests that the K Mart reformulationmay mark the beginning of such a transformation.The first period spansthe 1985 and 1986 Terms.Chevronwas reasonablywell establishedby this time; it had been expressly reaffirmedin Chemical Manufacturers Ass'n v. National Resources Defense Council102in the previousyear,andhadnot yet encounteredany significantcontroversy.The second period covers the 1988 to 1990 Terms-after the Cardoza-Fonseca episode and afterthe plain meaningreformulationof step one in K Mart.Table 3 indicatesthatthe Chevronframeworkwas usedmorefrequentlyin the second period than in the first (going from 32% of deferencecases to 52%). This is perhapswhat one would expect, given the prominenceaccordedChevronby the controversiesthat eruptedin Cardoza-Fonsecaand othercases. However, the rate of acceptanceof the agency constructionwent down betweenthe two periods (from 66% to 50%),as indeeddid the acceptancerate in all deference cases (from 72% to 59%). TABLE 3. Post-Chevron Terms in Two Periods A TERM B C D E F CASES TOTAL CHEVRON CHEVRON INVOLVING CHEVRONFRAMEWORK: FRAMEWORK: CASESCIrIN DEFERENCE AGENCY VIEWFRAMEWORK AGENCY VIEW DECIDED AT TRADITIONAL FACTORS QUESTION ACCEPIED APPLIED ACCEPTED STEPTwo 1988-90 34 20 (59%) 18 (51%) 9 (50%) 5 (30%) 16 (47%) 1985-86 25 18 (72%) 8 (32%) 6 (66%) 5 (62%) 8 (35%) 101. Scalia, supra note 39, at 521. Note that Justice Scalia's explanationfor why textualismwould resultin less deferenceis quite differentfrom mine. He seems to believe thattextualismleads to determinate results in most cases and that introducingevidence of intentto "impeach"the text muddiesthings up and thus requiresdeference. My argumentis that textualismwill answer the "precisequestion"at issue in so few cases that it leads courts to abandonthe quest for specific congressional answers, thus allowing a dramaticallyexpandedjudicial role at step one. 102. 470 U.S. 116 (1985). Executive Precedent 1992] 993 Again, the shift is producedby changesin only a handfulof cases, and the precisepercentagesare not thatmeaningful.But it is possible thatwhatwe are seeing here is at least caused in partby the emergenceof the new plain meaning approachto step one associated with K Mart. Some confirmationof this is supplied by the numberof cases reachingstep two of the Chevronframework. The more expansive the theory of the judicial role is at step one, the fewer occasions thereare to move on to step two. Althoughthe Courthas not given much considerationto step two at any time throughoutthe post-Chevron period,it is interestingto note thatthe frequencydeclinedeven furtherbetween the earlier and later periods. III. WHAT'S WRONG WITH CHEVRON? Chevron'sadoptionof a generaltheoreticalframeworkfor structuringthe choice betweenindependentjudgmentanddeferencewas an importantadvance over the formlessnessof the previousera. Unfortunately,evidence is mounting that the Court picked the wrong framework.I have already described the primarysymptomof dysfunction:the lack of congruencebetweenChevronand the actual practice of the SupremeCourt in determiningwhetheror to what extent to deferto administrativeinterpretationsof statutes.Theoryandpractice diverge in many ways: the failure to apply Chevronin at least half the cases in which, by its own terms, it shouldgovern;the continuinguse of traditional factors of deferencewhich Chevronappearsto renderirrelevant;the creation of numerousexceptions to Chevronthat do not seem to cohere with the decision's rationale;the developmentof a differentversionof the Chevrondoctrine that greatly expands the judicial role at step one. It is possible to arguethatthese manifolddeviationssimply reflect lapses of judgmenton the partof the Court,and thatthe properresponseis to identify the "true"version of Chevronand exhortthe Justicesto follow it consistently. But the divergences between theory and practicecanvassed in Part II are so pervasivethatit is difficultto attributethe problemsimply to judicialbacksliding. SupremeCourtJusticesarepracticalindividuals,sensitiveto the traditions of American constitutionalism,and the Court'spersistentrefusal to abide by the narrowstricturesof Chevronsuggests thattheremust be somethingwrong with eitherChevron'simplicittheoryof deference,or its practicalimplications, or both. In this part, I will attemptto spell out why Chevronis incompatible with fundamentaltenets of American public law, and why the framework proves to be so unsatisfactoryin practice. A. ChevronTheory Chevronraises issues thatgo the heartof our understandingof the judicial role undera system of separationof powers. In terms of formal separationof 994 The Yale Law Journal [Vol. 101: 969 powers theory,103 interpretationof law is often said to be the exclusive province of the judiciary.104 This raises the "Marburyproblem":if it is the role of courts to "to say what the law is,"105then how can courts defer to the views of another branch of governmenton the meaning of the law?l06In termsof a functionaltheoryof separationof powers,the purposeof an independentjudiciaryis often describedin termsof its capacityfor checkingarbitrariness and aggrandizementby the other branchesof government.107 This raises the problemof agency accountability:how can we structurejudicialreview of agency action so that agencies have enough discretionto implementcomplex regulatoryprograms, and yet assure that they do not become a tyrannical "FourthBranch"of government,immunefrom popularcontrol? One of the strengths of the Chevron doctrine is that it offers, if only implicitly, answers to the Marburyand agency accountabilityproblems.The answers it provides,however,are radicallydifferentfrom those that were put forthin the past, and are difficult to squarewith other,moreenduringcommitments about the properrole of the courts in a system of separatedpowers. In the early days of modernadministrativelaw, the Marburyand agency accountabilitydilemmaswereusuallyresolvedby borrowingfromlongstanding notions about the relationshipbetweenjudges and juries. Courtswould defer to agency findings of fact, but would decide all question-sof law de novo.108 Under such a division of labor,courts would clearly retain final authorityto "say what the law is." And by independentlyascertainingthe meaningof the agency's statutoryauthorityin all cases, courts would provide a powerful constraintagainst arbitrarinessand aggrandizement. This solution was short lived, however. The comparativeadvantageof agencies is not limited to finding facts (or applying the law to facts), but extends to resolving many questionsof law as well. And if courts decide all questions of law de novo-even where the meaning of the law is uncertain-then the price of containingagency aggrandizementis very likely to be judicial aggrandizement.In response to these shortcomings,the Court abandonedthe judge-jurymodel soon after the AdministrativeProcedureAct 103. On the distinctionbetween formal and functionaltheories of separationof powers, see Rebecca L. Brown, Separated Powers and OrderedLiberty, 139 U. PA. L. REV. 1513, 1522-31 (1991); Cass R. Sunstein, ConstitutionalismAfter the New Deal, 101 HARV.L. REV.421, 493-96 (1987); Peter L. Strauss, Formal and Functional Approaches to Separation-of-PowersQuestions-A Foolish Inconsistency?,72 CORNELLL. REV. 488 (1987). 104. Waymanv. Southard,23 U.S. (10 Wheat.) 1, 46 (1825). 105. Marburyv. Madison, 5 U.S. (1 Cranch) 137, 177 (1803). 106. See Monaghan,supra note 6, at 2; Eric M. Braun,Note, Coring the Seedless Grape:A ReinterL. REV.986, 988-89, pretationof ChevronU.S.A., Inc. v. National ResourcesDefense Council, 87 COLUM. 994-95 (1987). 107. RichardH. Fallon, Jr.,Of LegislativeCourts,AdministrativeAgencies,and Article111,101 HARV. L. REV.916, 978 (1988); see also Farina,supra note 6, at 467-99. 108. See Crowell v. Benson, 285 U.S. 22 (1932); JAFFE,supra note 13. 1992] Executive Precedent 995 was enacted,graduallydevelopingthe multifactoredcontextualapproachthat, as we have seen, dominatedthe pre-Chevronera.-09 Chevron in effect advances a third solution to the Marburyand agency accountabilityproblems. The Marburyproblem is resolved by a theory of congressionallymandateddeference.Courtsreconciletheir duty to "say what the law is" with the practiceof deferringto agency interpretationsof law by positing that Congress, in conferringauthorityon an agency to administera statute, has implicitly directed courts to defer to the agency's legal views. Accountability is achieved under Chevron by reducing the role of judicial review and relying instead on Presidentialoversight. Both halves of the Chevronsolutionareproblematicat best. The mandatory deference solution to the Marburyproblemrests entirely on the presumption thatwhen Congressdelegatesthe authorityto administera statuteto an agency, it wants courts to defer to that agency's interpretationsof law. The evidence that would supportsuch a presumptionis weak. Congress has never enacted a statutethat containsa generaldelegationof interpretativeauthorityto agencies. The very practiceof enactingspecific delegationsof interpretativeauthority suggests that Congress understandsthat no such general authorityexists. Moreover,the one generalstatuteon point, the AdministrativeProcedureAct, directs reviewing courts to "decide all relevantquestions of law."110If anything, this suggests that Congress contemplatedcourts would always apply independentjudgmenton questionsof law, reservingdeferencefor administrative findings of fact or determinationsof policy. The strongestevidence in supportof the Court'spresumptionis the fact that Congress knows about the practiceof judicial deferenceto agency interpretationsand has not acted to prohibitit."' But in order to establish that Congress has mandatedthe practiceof deference,the Courtshould be able to point to more than a debatableinferencefrom congressionalinaction.12Chev109. See supra notes 7-29 and accompanyingtext. I describe how the contextual approachcan be squaredwith the Marburyand agency accountabilityconcernsat infratext accompanyingnotes 175-76 and accompanyingtext. 110. 5 U.S.C. ? 706 (1988) (emphasisadded). 111. For a number of years, Senator Dale Bumpers gatheredconsiderablesupport for a proposed amendmentto the APA thatwould have affirmativelyprohibitedanyjudicialdeferenceto agencyinterpretations of law. See generally James T. O'Reilly, Deference Makes a Difference:A Studyof Impacts of the Bumpers Judicial Review Amendment,49 U. CIN. L. REV.739 (1980). Failure to enact the Bumpers Amendment may suggest congressional ratificationof the deference doctrine. Drawing inferences from unenactedlegislation is always hazardous,however,and here more so than usual. Although the Bumpers Amendmentwas never enacted, it drew consistent (and overwhelming)support-hardly suggesting that Congress is in fact strongly committed to the deference doctrine. Instead,Congress may have failed to approvethe amendmentout of inertia, because of timing problems,or because the impact of deferenceis too diffuse to generatethe concentratedpolitical supportneeded to producelegislative action. See Farina, supra note 6, at 473-74. 112. A recent decision dealing with judicial deference to an agency's interpretationsof its own regulationssought to explain the practice of deference in terms of a presumptionof congressionalintent based on the agency's "historicalfamiliarity"with the issue and its "policymakingexpertise."Martinv. OccupationalSafety & Health Review Comm'n, 111 S. Ct. 1171, 1177 (1991). In Martinthe argumentin favor of the presumptionof intent is based on policy argumentsin favor of deferring to executive views, 996 The Yale Law Journal [Vol. 101: 969 ronitself, in definingthejudicialrole in the interpretationof statutes,suggested that courts have no authorityto impose decisionalrules that cannotbe traced to an authoritativejudgment of Congress. Yet the Court could point to no statuteindicatingthat Congresshas requiredthatagencies, ratherthan courts, A decisionalframeworkthatrests interpretambiguitiesand gaps in statutes.'13 on two foundations,one of which contradictsthe other,is difficult to regard as sound. Chevron'ssolutionto the agencyaccountabilityproblemis also unsatisfactory. Unlike previousdiscussionsof the accountabilityproblem,which tended to assume that popular control comes about only through the election of representativeswho pass statutes that are then enforced by courts, Chevron perceives a dual channelof popularcontrol:one operatingthroughthe election of representativeswho pass statutes;the other through the election of the President who directs the agents who implementthose statutes. The Court sought to forge a formulathat would allow both channelsof popularcontrol to operate by limiting courts to the enforcementof unambiguouslegislative directives,leaving all discretionarydecisions to be disciplinedby Presidential oversight. The Court'sperceptionthatthereis a dual channelof controlis an important insight."4But Presidentialoversighthas inherentlimitations.Many administrative entities-including the "independent"regulatoryagencies and "legislative"or Article I courts-enjoy variousdegreesof statutoryimmunity from direct Presidentialcontrol."1Several prominentseparationof powers decisions handed down since Chevronhave legitimized these immunities,116 diluting the power of the Presidentto assureoverall directionof those agents who administer the law. But even without the Court's sanction for these immunities,it is simplyunrealistic,given the vastnessof the federalbureaucracy, to expect that the Presidentor his principal lieutenants can effectively monitor the policymaking activities of all federal agencies.117Nor does it the assumption being that if the Court finds these policies persuasive then Congress must too. Again, however, the Court cited no direct evidence that Congress has in any context actually endorsed these policies. 113. See Michael Hertz, Textualismand Taboo: Interpretationand Deferencefor Justice Scalia, 12 L. REV. 1663, 1665-68 (1991). CARDOZO 114. See Harold Bruff, Legislative Formality,AdministrativeRationality,63 TEX.L. REV.207, 217 (1984); Lloyd Cutler& David Johnson,Regulationand the Political Process, 84 YALEL.J. 1395, 1410-12 (1975); RichardJ. Pierce, Jr.,TheRole of the Judiciaryin Implementingan Agency Theoryof Government, 64 N.Y.U. L. REv. 1239 (1989). 115. See Miller, supra note 44; Peter L. Strauss,The Place of Agencies in Government:Separation L. REV.573 (1984). of Powers and the Fourth Branch, 84 COLUM. 116. See Freytag v. Commissioner, 111 S. Ct. 2631 (1991) (suggesting that it is constitutionally permissiblefor Congress to create an Article I courtoutside both the executive and the judicial branches); Mistretta v. United States, 488 U.S. 361 (1989) (upholding statute creating a commission exercising rulemakingpower as partof thejudicial branch);Morrisonv. Olson, 487 U.S. 654 (1988) (upholdingstatute creating independentprosecutorinsulatedfrom removal by the Presidentor Attorney Generalexcept for good cause). 117. See Strauss, supra note 115. 1992] Executive Precedent 997 seem wise or appropriateto leave controlof agency behaviorto congressional In the end, the primaryprotectionagainst arbitraryor oversight hearings.118 action aggrandizing by agencies must remainthe fundamentalconstitutional limitation on all executive action-that it "comportwith the terms set in And the only effective institutionalmechanism for legislative directives."119 this is judicial review. constraint preserving To be sure, Chevrondoes not eliminate all judicial enforcementof legal limitations on executive action. But by restrictingcourts to enforcementof "specificintentions"or "clearandunambiguous" statutorydirectives,it seriousweakens the while offering no adequate check on abuses ly primary agency alternativein its place. Of particularconcern here is the matterof enforcing boundarylimitations.Overthe years,the SupremeCourthaspermittedincreasingly broaddelegationsof discretionaryauthorityto agencies, but only on the understandingthat the exercise of this delegatedauthoritywould be subjectto To the extent that broaddelegationsare often independentjudicial review.120 Chevron undermines this understandingby suggestingthat courts ambiguous, must defer to an agency's interpretationof the scope of its own authority.'21 As ProfessorCynthiaFarinaputs it: [A key assumptionof Chevron-] that Congress may give agencies primaryresponsibilitynot only for makingpolicy within the limits of their organic statutes,but also for defining those limits wheneverthe text andsurrounding legislativematerialsareambiguous-is fundamentally incongruouswith the constitutionalcourse by which the Court came to reconcile agencies and separationof powers.122 A possible solution to this particulardifficulty would be to carve out yet anotherexception to Chevron,this time for decisions that implicatethe scope of the agency's own jurisdiction.In fact, three Justicesendorsedjust such an exception in Mississippi Power & Light Co. v. Mississippi ex rel. Moore.'23 The difficulty with the proposedexception,as JusticeScalia pointedout in his concurringopinion, is that virtually any decision about the meaning of the 118. See Richard J. Lazarus, The Neglected Question of Congressional Oversight of EPA: Quis CustodietCustodes(WhoShall Watchthe WatchersThemselves)?,LAW& CONTEMP. PROBS.205 (Autumn 1991) (describing multiple difficulties associated with congressionaloversightof EPA). 119. HaroldJ. Krent,Separatingthe Strandsin Separationof Powers Controversies,74 VA. L. REV. 1253, 1256 (1988). 120. See Touby v. United States, 111 S. Ct. 1752, 1757-58 (1991), where the Court rejected a nondelegationdoctrinechallenge to regulationsnot subjectto judicialreview, butonly afterconcludingthat the regulationscould be reviewedin individualenforcementactions.JusticeMarshall'sconcurringopinion expressly statedthatthe availabilityof judicial review was critical to the conclusionthatthe delegationwas constitutional.Id. at 1758 (Marshall,J., concurring);see also Skinnerv. Mid-AmericaPipeline Co., 490 U.S. 212, 218-19 (1989); Yakus v. United States, 321 U.S. 414, 426 (1944). 121. Farina, supra note 6, at 487-88; Cass R. Sunstein,InterpretingStatutesin the RegulatoryState, 103 HARV.L. REV.407, 446 (1989). 122. Farina, supra note 6, at 487-88. 123. 487 U.S. 354, 386-87 (1988) (Brennan,J., dissenting,joined by Marshall& Blackmun,JJ.). The Yale Law Journal 998 [Vol. 101: 969 substantivetermsof a statutecan be viewed as eitherexpandingor contracting an agency's "jurisdiction."'24 The questionat issue in Chevronitself, concernthe definition of a ing proper "stationarysource"of air pollution,has implications for the scope of the EPA'sregulatorypower. So a "jurisdictionalquestions"exception to Chevronwould eitherswallow the rule or lead to arbitrary decisions based on explication of a notoriousformalism("jurisdiction"). In sum, Chevronseeks to resolve the centraltheoreticalproblemsof the modernadministrativestateby adoptinga dubiousfiction of delegatedauthority and by reducingthe role of the courts to a point that threatensto undermine the principal constitutionalconstrainton agency misbehavior.Given these failings, it is small wonder that the Court often seems wary of the Chevron doctrine, applying it inconsistentlyat best. B. ChevronPractice The Court'sgeneralfailureto abideby the teachingsof Chevron-whether acts of omissionor commission-also suggeststhatthe frameworkfrequentby ly generates unwantedresults. There are a numberof reasons why Chevron does not functionwell as a guide to determiningthe relativeweightto be given to judicial and agency views. 1. The SequentialInquiry Perhapsthe most basic problemstems from the fact thatChevroncasts the relevantdeterminantsin a sequentialhierarchy:considerationof judicialcompetence first, considerationof administrativecompetencesecond. By sequencing the inquiry in this fashion, Chevronalmost guaranteesthat in every case the independentviews of the judiciarywill be given either too much or too little weight, and concomitantly,that the views of the agency will be given either too little or too much deference.If the issue is resolved at step one, then the court gives no considerationto the views of the executive and decides the matterindependently.If the issue is resolvedat step two, then the courtregards the agency view as dispositive,unlessit can say thatit is unreasonable.In other words, Chevron inevitably generates "one-sided"decisions. In those cases where the Courtfeels that one-sidednessis appropriate,Chevronwill do fine. But if the Courtperceives that a more refinedapproachis called for, Chevron is a source of awkwardness.The predominantsolution in the latter situation appearsto be to ignore Chevron. For example, Chevronseems to rule out the previouslycommon practice of using executive interpretationsas a "comfortfactor"to confirm a judicial 124. Id. at 381 (Scalia, J., concurring). 1992] Executive Precedent 999 If all cases interpretationbased primarilyon the text and legislative history.125 fell into neat piles-unambiguous statutesin one pile, ambiguousstatutesin the other-this would entail no loss. Realistically,however, there is a broad gray areawherethe existence of an administrativeinterpretationmighthelp tip the balance.Surelyit makesno sense to forbidcourtsto drawuponthe consensus of the two branchesin assuringthe public that the correctresult has been reachedin such a case. Similarly,it was possible underthe pre-Chevronregime to look to executive interpretationsto disconfirma conclusionbasedon an independentanalysis of text and history.Thus, even if the courtfound thatjudicialprecedentor the text suggested one answer,it mightfind this tentativejudgmentoutweighedif, say, a contraryadministrativeinterpretationhadbeen consistentlyfollowed for many years, and this executive view had been ratified by a subsequentCongress.126Chevron'ssequentialinquiryrendersit impossible to reach this kind of result.Althoughallowingadministrative to overcomeindepeninterpretations dent analysis in this fashionis morecontroversial,it is really not thatdifferent fromthe commonpracticeof allowingjudicialprecedentto overcomea conclusion drawn from an independentexaminationof text and history.127 Indeed, allowing especially strongexecutive interpretationsto dominatejudicialreadings provides a way of injecting a dynamic or evolutionary element into statutoryinterpretation-in a way that is far more consistentwith democratic theory than permittingcourts to do the updating.128 The other half of the one-sidednessproblem,of course, is that Chevron eliminatesany significantjudicialinputat step two. In practice,this has proved to be less of a problem because a court that is convinced that judicial input would be desirablehas ways of avoiding the conclusion that the case should be decidedat step two: it can "rig"the inquiryat step one, eitherby overstating the evidence that Congress had a specific intentionor, more likely today,by finding that the meaning of the statuteis "plain."Thereare several examples 125. See supra text accompanyingnote 9. 126. See, e.g., GuardiansAss'n v. Civil Serv.Comm'n,463 U.S. 582, 591-93 (White, J.); id. at 619-20 (Marshall,J., dissenting)(statingthatlongstandingagencyinterpretationratifiedby Congressshouldprevail over contraryinterpretationsuggested by priorSupremeCourtopinion);Bob Jones Univ. v. United States, 461 U.S. 574, 599 (1983) (relying on agency interpretationratified by Congress to bolster conclusion supportedonly weakly by statutorytext and history);see also John P. Dwyer, The Pathology of Symbolic Legislation,17 ECOLOGY L.Q. 233,284-315 (1990) (arguingthatcourtsshoulddeferto agencyinterpretation mitigating the extreme consequencesof "symbolic"environmentallaws). 127. See Pattersonv. McLean CreditUnion, 491 U.S. 164, 173 (1989). 128. Judicialupdatingnot only violates normsof democraticlegitimacy,but is also inconsistentwith the concept of judicial "interpretation"as conventionallyunderstood.See Steven D. Smith, Law Without Mind,88 MICH.L. REV.104 (1989) (criticizingT. AlexanderAleinikoff, UpdatingStatutoryInterpretation, 87 MICH.L. REV.20 (1987)); see also William N. Eskridge,Jr.,DynamicStatutoryInterpretation,135 U. PA. L. REV.1479 (1987) (advocatinginterpretationof statutesin light of evolving societal, political, and legal context). 1000 The Yale Law Journal [Vol. 101: 969 Alternativeamong recently decidedcases that I would put in this category.129 ly, the courtcan simply ignorethe Chevronframework,following the Supreme Court'smost common avoidancedevice. But both techniquesrest on misapplication of supposedly controllinglaw and representan unhappysolution to a problemthat should not exist. It would seem far betterto devise a methodfor courts to articulatetheir misgivings directly. 2. The Dividing Line A second set of problemsis generatedby the methodfor determiningthe dividingline betweenthe two steps in the sequentialinquiry.As we have seen, the balance is determinedby the theory of interpretationadoptedat step one. As originallyformulated,Chevrondescribedthe judicialinquiryin sucha way that it would almost certainlyproduceroutine deferenceto agency views. Chevron'stheory of the judicial role at step one is the statutoryanalogue of what in constitutionallaw has been called "strictintentionalism."As Dean PaulBresthas put it, "Strictintentionalismrequiresthe interpreterto determine how the adopterswould have applieda provisionto a given situation,and to The problemwith such a theory of interpretationis apply it accordingly."130 thatno matterhow precisethe meaningof the text, unanticipatedquestionswill invariablyarise about how the text is to apply in differentcircumstances.13 129. See, e.g., Dole v. United Steelworkers,494 U.S. 26 (1990) (rejectingOffice of Managementand Budget's construction of the PaperworkReductionAct largely on the basis of structuralargumentsand canons of construction);Sullivan v. Zebley, 493 U.S. 521 (1990) (rejectingthe Secretaryof Health and Human Service's interpretationof the Social Security Act based on inferencesdrawn from reading two provisionstogetherand equitableconsiderations);PublicEmployeesRetirementSys. v. Betts, 492 U.S. 158 (1989) (findingan agencyinterpretationof the Age Discriminationin EmploymentAct contraryto the "plain meaning"of the statute,even thoughdeterminingthe precise meaning of the Act was a "somewhatmore difficult task"). 130. Paul Brest, The MisconceivedQuestfor the Original Understanding,60 B.U. L. REV.204, 222 (1980). Such a theoryof interpretationis vulnerableto attackfor all the reasonstextualistslike JusticeScalia attackintentionalismgenerally:Congressenacts texts, not intentions,see, e.g., Pennsylvaniav. Union Gas Co., 491 U.S. 1, 29 (1989) (Scalia, J., concurringin part and dissenting in part);In re Sinclair,870 E2d 1340 (7th Cir. 1989) (Easterbrook,J.) (holding that where conflict exists, languageof statuteprevailsover USINGANDMISUSING LEGISLATIVE A REEVALUATION HISTORY: legislative history);U.S. DEP'TOFJUSTICE, HISTORY OFLEGISLATIVE IN STATUTORY INTERPRETATION (1989); reconstructinghistorical intentionsis very difficult given the limited informationwe have available; see, e.g., Wisconsin Pub. Intervenorv. Mortier,111 S. Ct. 2476, 2488 (1991) (Scalia, J., concurring)(statingthat committeereportsare unreliable as a "genuineindicatorof congressionalintent");and heavyrelianceon legislative historyleads to strategic manipulationby legislative insiders, see, e.g., Blanchardv. Bergeron,489 U.S. 87, 97 (1989) (Scalia, J. concurring) (suggesting that references to district court decisions were inserted in committee report by staffers "to influence judicial construction").But it is not my purpose here to take sides in the debate between intentionalism(whetherof the strict or generalvariety) and textualism.The only point is thatthe particularbrandof intentionalismendorsedby Chevron-strict intentionalism-results in a very small role for courts at step one. 131. See REEDDICKERSON, THEINTERPRETATION ANDAPPLICATION OF STATUTES (1975); Frank Easterbrook,The Role of OriginalIntentin StatutoryConstruction,11 HARV.J.L. & PUB.POL'Y59, 62-63 (1988). The point has been recognized in a variety of contexts. See, e.g., Robert Bennett, Objectivityin ConstitutionalLaw, 132 U. PA. L. REV.445 (1984); MarthaField, Sourcesof Law: The Scope of Federal CommonLaw, 99 HARV.L. REV.881, 942-45 (1986). 1992] Executive Precedent 1001 In the familiar example,'32if the statute says "no vehicles are permittedin the park,"does this languageapplyto bicycles?Or,if the legislatureanticipates this application,and provides that "no motor vehicles are permitted in the park,"does this version apply to motorizedwheel chairs?Given the limits of human imagination,it is virtually impossiblefor the legislatureto formulate a specific intentionabouthow a provisionshouldbe appliedto all or even most situations.The process of application,especially over time, will always outrun the understandingof even the most farsightedlegislature.For this reason, to ask the interpreterto "ascertai[n]thatCongresshadan intentionon the precise question at issue," as Chevrondemands,'33is to ask a question that will yield an affirmativeanswer-at least an honest affirmativeanswer-in only a tiny numberof cases.134 Underthe Chevronframework,thereis only one way to expandthe small judicial role contemplatedby the specific intentionstheory-reformulate the natureof the inquiryat step one. The cure,unfortunately,may be as bad as the disease. As we have seen, recent decisions have begun to drop the specific intentions requirementin favor of a "plainmeaning"formulation.35But this leaves unansweredseveralcriticalquestionsaboutwhatkindsof interpretative aids courtsmay consult at step one. Mustthe courtfind the statuteplain on its face? Or may it be plain after consulting extrinsic sources, like dictionary definitions, definitions contained(explicitlyor implicitly)in otherstatutes,or considerationsof the structureof the act? In its more latitudinarianversions, where the court looks to considerationsof structureand purposein deciding whetherthe meaning is "plain,"the plain meaning inquirytends to converge with a "clearlypreferredmeaning"approach.136If this happens,then Chevron would suffer from the exact opposite of the problemthatplaguedthe original formulation:if step one does not completely swallow step two, at least it will have dramaticallyexpanded-perhaps too far-in the opposite direction. On other occasions the Court has not committed to either a "specific intentions"method,or to a textualistmethod,buthas statedthe relevantinquiry simply in terms of whether the statute is "ambiguous"or "unclear."137This formulationleaves even more questionsunanswered.To what extent may the courtresolve the meaningof the statuteat step one basedon inferencesdrawn from legislative history or considerationsof statutorypurpose? May it use canons of constructionbasedon linguisticusage?Canonsbasedon substantive 132. See. e.g., H.L.A. HART,THECONCEPT OFLAW(1961); Brest, supra note 130, at 209-10. 133. ChevronU.S.A., Inc. v. National ResourcesDefense Council, 467 U.S. 837, 843 n.9 (1984). 134. The Court has recognized this point outside the Chevroncontext. See Moskal v. United States, 111 S. Ct. 461, 467 (1990) ('This Courthas never requiredthat every permissibleapplicationof a statute be expressly referredto in its legislative history.");Diamond v. Chakrabarty,447 U.S. 303, 315 (1980) ("ThisCourtfrequentlyhas observedthata statuteis not to be confinedto the 'particularapplication[s]... contemplatedby the legislators.'") (quoting Barr v. United States, 324 U.S. 83, 90 (1945)). 135. See supra text accompanyingnote 99. 136. See supra text accompanyingnote 100. 137. See cases cited supra note 94. 1002 The Yale Law Journal [Vol. 101: 969 policy considerations?Given the wide range of possible answers to these questions,the Chevronframeworkbecomes at best unpredictable,and at worst a vehicle for complete substitutionof judicialjudgmentfor the views of the agency. In short, the reformulationof the judicial inquiryat step one will have at least one of two consequences.First, it will result in a considerablesacrifice of the formality of the original Chevronstructure,and with it, much of the simplicityand predictabilitythatmadethe two-stepprocedureseem attractive. Moreproblematically,if the reformulationresultsin a greatlyenlargedjudicial role at step one-as recent cases suggest may be happening-then it would have the paradoxicaleffect of elevating the courtsratherthan agencies to the role of primarypolicymaker.The originalrationalefor Chevron-the need to have statutorygaps filled by the most democraticallyaccountabledecisionmaker-would be turnedon its head. Thereare severalreasonswhy we shouldview the potentialtransformation of Chevroninto a doctrineof antideferencewith alarm.The practiceof deferring to executive interpretationsof statutesperformsmany valuablefunctions: it allows policy to be made by actorswho are politically accountable;it draws upon the specialized knowledge of administrators;it injects an element of flexibility into statutoryinterpretation;and it helps assurenationallyuniform constructions.138 As statutes become increasinglycomplex, and courts tend to be increasinglyformalistic in their approachto statutoryinterpretation,a robustmeasureof deferenceto agencyinterpretations may be, if anything,more than In ever if before. courts do the fact, imperative gap filling at step one underthe "plainmeaning"nostrumby applyingdictionarydefinitions,rulesof grammar,and canons of construction,then the contentof nationalpolicy will be determinedby courts without any considerationof the substantivevalues at issue in the policy disputes-either those that animatedCongressor those articulatedby the agency chargedwith administrationof the statute. Finally, there is a more fundamentaldifficulty with the focus on judicial interpretationat step one. The Chevronframeworkmakesthe decisionto defer turn on some conception,either explicit or implicit, of what kind of judicial interpretationis legitimate. But there is no a priori reason why the sphereof deferenceshould always be the exact mirrorimage of whatevera majorityof the Court believes on any given day is permissible in the name of judicial interpretation.Surely there are other variables-such as the degree of the agency's expertise and the existence of reliance interests implicated by the 138. See generally Diver, supra note 11, at 585-92 (discussing a variety of utilitarianargumentsfor deference to administrativeinterpretations,includingagency expertise and flexibility); RichardJ. Pierce, TheRole of Constitutionaland Political Theotyin AdministrativeLaw, 64 TEX.L. REV.469, 520-21 (1985) (arguingthat deferenceto agency interpretationspromotespolitical accountability);Silberman,supra note 44 (deferenceserves ends of democratictheoryand uniformity);PeterL. Strauss,OneHundredFifty Cases Per Year: Some Implicationsof the SupremeCourt'sLimitedResourcesfor Judicial Review of Agency Action, 87 COLUM.L. REV. 1093 (1987) (deferencerequiredto assure uniformityin interpretation). 1992] Executive Precedent 1003 agency's interpretation-that also ought to have some bearingon the decision to defer.By makingthe transitionfromindependentjudgmentto deferenceturn solely on the amenabilityof the issue to independentjudicial resolution,the Chevronframeworkexcludes these considerations. C. A New and ImprovedChevron? Could the Courtimproveon the presentstate of affairs by tinkeringwith the Chevronframework?No doubtsome beneficial reformsare possible. For example, the Courtcouldreformulatethe inquiryat step one in termsof degree of judicialcertitudeaboutstatutorymeaning,ratherthanin termsthatimplicate Thus, it could ask whetherthe statuteadmitsof only interpretativemethod.139 "one possible meaning,"ratherthan posing the question in terms of whether Congress had a "specific intention"on the point or whetherthe text of the statuteis "plain."Such a reformmight offer a "compromise"position on the judicial role that would provide a more robustcheck on agency misbehavior thanthe originalChevronwithoutgoing to the oppositeextremeof encouraging judicial substitutionof judgment. But no matter how much tinkeringis done with the formulationof the inquiry at step one, a numberof serious and irremediableproblems would remain.The frameworkwould still provideno logical role for the traditional deferencefactors;it would still generateone-sideddecisions;and it would still requirethe deference decision to be based exclusively on a considerationof judicial competenceto exerciseindependentjudgmentto the exclusionof other factors. Moreover,it is unclear that any formulationof the properjudicial inquiry at step one can-over a wide range of cases-satisfactorily reconcile the desire to drawuponthe comparativeadvantagesof agencies as interpreters with the desire thatcourtscontrolagencyarbitrarinessand aggrandizement.In light of the manifold problemsassociatedwith the Chevrondoctrine,and the persistentgulf between theory and practice,it is time to considerwhetheran alternativeframeworkmight do better. IV. THE EXECUTIVE PRECEDENT MODEL In this part, I offer an alternativeto Chevron-the executive precedent model. The basic idea assimilates the deference doctrine into the general judicial practiceof following precedent.The differenceis thatthe "precedent" the courts would be asked to follow is generatedby a different branch of government. Just as courts generally adhere to interpretationsof statutes 139. See JAFFE, supra note 13, at 572 (suggestingthat the relevantinquiryis whether"thejudges are themselves convinced that [a] certain reading, or application,of the statute is the correct-or the only faithful-reading or application");Sunstein,supra note 4, at 2092 ("If the court has a firm conviction that the agency interpretationviolates the statute,that interpretationmust fail."). 1004 The Yale Law Journal [Vol. 101: 969 embodiedin judicial precedents,so they wouldgenerallyfollow the interpretations of statutesembodiedin prior decisions by executive branchagencies. A. ExecutiveInterpretationof Law The executiveprecedentmodelbeginswith the premisethatentitiescharged with the execution of the law, includingthe President,executive departments, and independent regulatory agencies, have an inherent power to interpret enactedlaws. Eventhoughthe Presidentandthe entitiesthatassistthe President in the execution of law have no inherentpower to "makelaw,"'40once Congress has delegated authorityto executive actors under law, the executive agencies must determinewhat that law means, and need not await a further delegation of interpretativeauthorityfrom Congress to do so. The constitutionalbasisfor an inherentexecutivepowerto interpretthe law is straightforward.The Constitutionexpresslygrantsthe President"executive power,"and directs the Presidentto see that the laws are "faithfullyexecuted."141The conferral of these powers would seem to presuppose that the Presidentandthose who serve underhis directionhavethe capacityto ascertain the meaningof the law.Indeed,law interpretation is an inevitableandnecessary of the of the constitutional functionsof the executive byproduct performance branch.142 as courts Just must interpretthe law in orderto resolve cases and controversiesthat arise within their jurisdiction,so executive officials must interpretthe law in orderto promulgateregulations,bringenforcementactions, instructemployees how to carry out programs,or perform any of the other myriadtasksentrustedto agencies.In fact, becauseonly a fractionof executive actionsend up in court,administrativeactorsengage in law interpretationwith greater frequencyand over a wider range of cases than courts do.'43If only the courts had the capacityto interpretlaw, our system of governmentcould not continue to function. Moreover,althoughexecutive interpretationsoccur in a variety of "formats,"'44they share much in common with judicial precedent.145Executive interpretationsare usuallywritten,aregenerallyaccompaniedby statementsof 140. See YoungstownSheet & Tube Co. v. Sawyer, 343 U.S. 579, 585 (1952) (steel seizure case); Thomas W. Merrill, The Judicial Prerogative, 12 PACEL. REV.(forthcoming 1992). 141. U.S. CONST.art. H, ?? 1, 3. 142. See Bowsher v. Synar, 478 U.S. 714, 733 (1986) ("Interpretinga law enacted by Congress to implementthe legislative mandateis the very essence of 'execution' of the law.");United States v. Nixon, 418 U.S. 683, 703 (1974) ("In the performanceof assigned constitutional duties each branch of the Governmentmust initially interpretthe Constitution,and the interpretationof its powers by any branchis due great respect from the others.");FrankH. Easterbrook,PresidentialReview,40 CASEW. RES.L. REV. 905 (1989-90). 143. See, e.g., JERRY L. MASHAW, BUREAUCRATIC JUSTICE 186 (1983) (judicial review touches less than one percent of the Social Security disabilitycaseload). 144. See Anthony,supra note 7, at 7-14. 145. See FrederickSchauer,Precedent, 39 STAN.L. REV.571, 572 (1987) (noting that reliance on precedentnot limited to courts of law but "is part of life in general"). 1992] Executive Precedent 1005 reasons,'46and often respondto argumentsby affected entities supportingor opposingthe interpretation.Furthermore,the writtenstatementsof reasonsthat accompanyexecutive interpretationsserve many of the same functionsas do the written opinions that accompanyjudicial decisions. They establish the thatthe executiveconstruction legitimacyof the interpretation by demonstrating has a sound basis in law and policy.147 They clarify the scope of the interpretation so that similar issues that arise in the futurecan be quickly resolved without having to "reinventthe wheel."'48They offer instructionsto subordinate employees for applyingthe interpretationin analogous but nonidentical circumstances.Finally,they explain to membersof the public the position the governmenthas taken so that they can make appropriateadjustmentsin their behaviorand plan for the future.149 Thus, it seems highly appropriateto speak of executive interpretationsas a separate system of precedent-executive precedent.150 B. The Judicial Systemof Following Precedent Given that both the executive branch and the judicial branch generate interpretationsof statutesthatcan be regardedas "precedent,"whatis the basis for the judicial practice of deferring to executive precedent?The executive 146. In this respect at least, it is more naturalto speak of executive branchdecisions as "precedent" than it would be to speak of congressional legislation as precedent.Administrativeagencies, like courts, typically vote to approveofficial explanationsgiven for their actions, such as agency adjudicatoryorders or Federal Register notices. Congress, in contrast, usually does not incorporatestatementsexplaining particularrules set forth in statutes.Explanationsmay be found in legislative history,but Congress does not as a whole vote to approvelegislative history,nor is it sent to the Presidentfor his signatureor veto. Still, the Court has on occasion treatedcongressional legislation as "precedent"supportinga particular interpretationof the Constitution.See Field v. Clark, 143 U.S. 649, 690-91 (1892) (treatingprior statutes delegatingdiscretionto executive as precedentsupportingthe constitutionalityof delegation).See generally James B. Thayer,The Origin and Scope of the AmericanDoctrineof ConstitutionalLaw,7 HARV.L. REV. 129 (1893) (arguing that courts should defer to legislative interpretationsof ambiguous constitutional provisions). 147. See Henry P. Monaghan,StareDecisis and ConstitutionalAdjudication,88 COLUM. L. REV.723, 749-55 (1988). 148. See RICHARD THEJUDICIAL DECISION 72-73 (1961); Schauer,supra note 145, WASSERSTROM, at 599. 149. See MELVIN A. EISENBERG, THENATURE OFTHECOMMON LAW10-12 (1988) (discussing the requirementthat judicial decisions be "replicable"by private parties and their advisors);Schauer,supra note 145, at 597-98; WASSERSTROM, supra note 148, at 66-69. 150. Indeed,certaintypes of administrativedecisions-adjudications-have legal consequenceslargely indistinguishablefrom judicial decisions. Executive agencies can enter ordersfor the paymentof money (damages) and cease and desist orders(injunctions).See CommodityFuturesTradingComm'n v. Schor, 478 U.S. 833 (1986) (agency may adjudicatecommon law claim for money damages);AmericanAirlines v. North Am. Airlines, 351 U.S. 79 (1956) (Civil AeronauticsBoard may properlyissue cease and desist order).Failure to abide by an agency ordercan result in sanctions for contempt. Regal KnitwearCo. v. NLRB, 324 U.S. 9 (1945). And courts "have long favored applicationof the common-lawdoctrines of collateral estoppel (as to issues) and res judicata (as to claims) to those determinationsof administrative bodies that have attained finality." Astoria Fed. Sav. & Loan Ass'n v. Solimino, 111 S. Ct. 2166, 2169 (1991). Although I would not confine the notion of executive precedent to statements of reasons in adjudicatorydecisions, the parallel to judicial precedenthere is especially striking. 1006 The Yale Law Journal [Vol. 101: 969 precedentmodel locates thatpracticein the courts'inherentpowersto develop We know that the "judicial principlesfor resolving cases and controversies.151 in III the Article of following precedescribed practice power" encompasses dent, even though this practice is not expressly authorizedin any source of positive law.152Indeed, the norm of following precedentis ubiquitousin the Anglo-Americanlegal system.Theexecutiveprecedentmodelwouldassimilate the judicial practiceof deferringto executive interpretationsinto this system of following precedent.Courtswould be deemedto have inherentauthorityto develop guidelinesfor deferringto executiveprecedentsin appropriatecircumstances. This inherentauthority,like otherproductsof judicialself-governance(such as common law rules of procedure153), would be subject to congressional modification.154 Thus, if Congresswere expresslyto instructcourtsto deferor not to defer to particular agency interpretations,these instructions would supersedethe norms of following precedent.But absent express instructions fromCongressaboutthe allocationof authority,courtswoulddeveloptheirown standardsfor determiningwhen to defer to priorexecutive interpretationsof law. In determiningwhereexecutiveprecedentmightfit into the judicialsystem of following precedent,it is useful to considerbriefly the variousways courts treat different types of judicial precedent.None of these understandingsis compelled by any statutoryor constitutionalprovision. Rather, they have emerged over the years througha gradualprocess of judicial self-definition. Decisions of superiorcourtsarethe mostpowerfulformof precedent.They are regardedas legally binding on lower courts.155A court's own previous 151. See generally Chambersv. NASCO, Inc., 111 S. Ct. 2123, 2132 (1991) ("It has long been understoodthat '[c]ertain implied powers must necessarilyresult to our Courts of justice from the nature of their institution,'powers 'which cannot be dispensedwith in a Court,becausethey are necessaryto the exercise of all others."') (quoting United States v. Hudson, 11 U.S. (7 Cranch)32, 34 (1812)). 152. Therecan be no doubtthatthe Framersof the Constitutionunderstoodthatthe normof following No. 78, at 471 precedent was an integral element of the functioning of courts. See THEFEDERALIST (AlexanderHamilton)(J. Cooke ed., 1961) ("Toavoidan arbitrarydiscretionin the courts,it is indispensable that they should be bounddown by strictrules and precedents.").For example, Blackstone,a familiarlegal source to the Framers,pronouncedthat precedentmust be followed "unless flatly absurdor unjust."1 WILLIAM COMMENTARIES ONTHELAWSOFENGLAND 70 (Facsimile ed. 1979). BLACKSTONE, 153. See Sibbachv. Wilson & Co., 312 U.S. 1, 9-10 (1941); Waymanv. Southard,23 U.S. (10 Wheat.) 1, 43 (1825). 154. In the contextof constitutionaladjudication,ProfessorMonaghanhasquestionedwhetherCongress would have the authorityto direct the Courtto disregardthe principle of stare decisis. Monaghan,supra note 147, at 754-55. But given Congress' acknowledgedpower to legislate standardsof review of agency action underdelegated statutoryauthority,there can be little doubt that Congress could direct the courts to decide questions of statutoryinterpretationde novo, or (short of constitutionalviolation) to deem an agency's interpretationauthoritative-or anythingin between. 155. See, e.g., ThurstonMotorLines v. JordanK. Rand,Ltd.,460 U.S. 533, 535 (1983); Huttov. Davis, 454 U.S. 370, 375 (1982). It is not plausible to view this norm as simply grounded in an empirical generalizationthat a lower court will get reversedby a superiorcourt if it fails to follow superiorcourt precedent.The U.S. SupremeCourt,for example,does not begin to have the institutionalcapacityto review all decisions of the federalcourtsof appealsto ensurethatthey remainfaithfulto SupremeCourtprecedent. See Peter Strauss, One Hundred Fifty Cases Per Year, 87 COLUM.L. REV. 1093 (1987). The same is 1992] Executive Precedent 1007 decisions are not as binding as decisions of superior courts. But their own opinions are also accordedmore than deference;underthe doctrine of stare decisis, they are regardedas enjoying a very strong presumptionof correctness.156 In practice, this means they will be followed unless they are overruled, and generally speaking they will be overruledonly if there is a very strongjustification for doing so.'57 A third type of precedentis made up of prior decisions of tribunalsof coordinatejurisdiction.The most familiarexample is when one federal court of appealsconfrontsan issue thathas been decidedpreviouslyby anothercourt of appeals. Here the judicial attitudeis more uncertain.English courts and nineteenth-centuryAmericancourtsdevelopedthe doctrineof the "controlling decision," whereby the precedentof a court of coordinatejurisdiction was regardedas binding as a matterof comity.'58After the creationof the federal courts of appeals in 1891, and the reconceptualizationof the role of the SupremeCourtas being devotedlargelyto the resolutionof conflicts betweenthe courtsof appeals,the attitudeof the federalcourtsof appealsrelaxedconsiderably.159Some courts came to speak of a duty of following the precedentof another circuit unless it could be said to be "clearly erroneous."'60Others stressed that such precedentis not "binding,"and implied that intercircuit precedentwould be followed only to the extent it is "persuasive"-suggesting that it is entitled to no deferenceat all.161Perhapsthe most accuratesynthesis of the contemporaryunderstandingis thatone courtof appealswill "give most respectful considerationto the decisions of the other courts of appeals,"162 probablytrue in many of the large state court systems. 156. California v. FERC, 110 S. Ct. 2024, 2028-30 (1990); Pattersonv. McLean Credit Union, 491 U.S. 164, 172 (1989); Square D Co. v. Niagara FrontierTariff Bureau, Inc., 476 U.S. 409, 424 (1986) (referringto "the strong presumptionof continuedvalidity that adheresin the judicial interpretationof a statute"). 157. Patterson,491 U.S. at 172. It has even been arguedthatin the statutorycontext, the presumption of correctness should be absolute. See LawrenceC. Marshall, "Let Congress Do It": The Case for an AbsoluteRule of StatutoryStare Decisis, 88 MICH.L. REV.177 (1989). 158. See Alan D. Vestal, RelitigationBy Federal Agencies: Conflict, Concurrenceand Synthesisof Judicial Policies, 55 N.C. L. REV.123, 129-40 (1977). 159. Id. at 140-66. Professor Vestal concluded his comprehensive 1977 survey by noting that "the doctrine of controllingdecision may not have the vitality it once had,"although he thoughtmany of the departuresfrom the doctrine were unexplained,and"the underlyingprinciplesthat have been the basis for the doctrine of controllingdecision have lost none of theirvitality."Id. at 166. For an interestingargument in supportof applyinga rule of staredecisis to intercircuitprecedent-based largelyon the desirableeffects on the SupremeCourt's workload-see WalterV. Schaefer,ReducingCircuitConflicts,69 A.B.A. J. 452 (1983); Walter V. Schaefer,Reliance on the Law of the Circuit-A Requiem, 1985 DUKEL.J. 690. 160. See, e.g., Homan v. United States, 279 F.2d 767, 773 (8th Cir.) ("We have in a long line of opinionsdeclaredthat,on an unsettledquestionof federallaw, while a decision by anotherCourtof Appeals is not compulsively bindingupon us, we will, in the interestof judicial uniformity,accept it as persuasive and follow it, unless we are clearly convinced that it is wrong."(citationsomitted)),cert. denied, 364 U.S. 866 (1960). 161. See, e.g., City Storesv. LernerShops,410 F.2d 1010, 1014(D.C. Cir. 1969) ("Decisionsof district courts and other courts of appeals are, of course, not binding on us and are looked to only for their persuasive effect."). 162. Colby v. J.C. Penney Co., 811 F.2d 1119, 1123 (7th Cir. 1987) (Posner,J.). 1008 The Yale Law Journal [Vol. 101: 969 or there especially where the prior interpretationis a "reasoneddecision"163 In effect, a legal interpretationof another is an "accumulationof authority."164 circuit is regardedas prima facie correct,and is given more or less deference dependingon contextualfactorssuch as the extent of considerationgiven the issue by the other circuit and how long its precedenthas been followed. Finally, there are precedentsof inferiorjudicial tribunals.A court will nearly always take note of the view of the tribunalwhose decision is under review; it is regardedat the very least as an interesting datum. Generally speaking,however,the superiorcourtwill resolve all questionsof law de novo; the views of the inferior court will be followed only to the extent they are regardedas persuasive.165The decisions of inferior tribunalsother than the one underreview are noted only sporadically.166 Thus,the generalunderstandis that lower court is not entitled to any measureof deference ing precedent the tribunal. by superior Which of the four attitudestoward differenttypes of judicial precedent should provide the relevantbenchmarkfor determiningthe attitudeof courts toward executive precedent?We can quickly dismiss the possibilities that executive precedentshould be treatedlike the decisions of superiorcourtsor like a court's own prior decisions. Part of our received understandingof the "judicialpower"is thatcourtshave final say in articulatingthe meaningof the law in cases broughtbefore them.167It would seem to follow from this that courtsare not legally boundby executiveinterpretationsof statutes.Forsimilar reasons,it would seem to be inconsistentwith ourunderstandingof the judicial power to posit thatcourtsare boundby executiveprecedentsthe way they must follow their own precedents. The two most plausiblemodels for executive precedentare the treatment of decisions by courtsof coordinatejurisdictionand the treatmentof decisions by inferiorcourts. For a variety of reasons,I think that the treatmentof decisions by courts of coordinatejurisdictionprovidesthe best analogy. Some of these reasonswill unfold only as the full implicationsof the model are spelled 163. Aldens, Inc. v. Miller, 610 F.2d 538, 541 (8th Cir. 1979), cert. denied, 446 U.S. 919 (1980). 164. 1B JAMESW. MOOREET AL., MOORE'SFEDERALPRACTICE? 0.402, at 15 (2d ed. 1984). 165. See generally Salve Regina College v. Russell, 111 S. Ct. 1217 (1991) (federal court of appeals should not defer to district court's interpretationof state law in diversity suits). 166. Occasionallyone will find the suggestionthata widespreadconsensusamonglower tribunalsover a long period of time is entitled to some deference.Reves v. Ernst & Young, 494 U.S. 56, 74-76 (1990) (Stevens, J., concurring) (Court should defer to unanimousconsensus among courts of appeals about meaning of Securities Act exemption);United States v. Ryan, 284 U.S. 167 (1931) (Courtshould hesitate to set aside uniformconstructiongiven to statuteby lower courtsfor more than 60 years). And from time to time, courts will rely on argumentsor insights containedin particularlower court decisions, especially if the judge is widely respected. See, e.g., InterstateCommerceComm'n v. Brotherhoodof Locomotive Eng'rs, 482 U.S. 270, 293 n.8 (1987) (Stevens, J., concurring)("JudgeFriendly'sdiscussionon the general issue of denials of petitions to reopen continues to merit our respect."). 167. See United States v. Nixon, 418 U.S. 683, 705 (1974) (rejectingclaim of unreviewableexecutive authorityto determinewhen executive communicationsare legally privileged);Marburyv. Madison,5 U.S. (1 Cranch) 137, 170 (1803) (courts have power to compel executive officers to perform legal duty as determinedby court). 1992] Executive Precedent 1009 out. One overarchingreasonfor selecting the precedentof courtsof coordinate jurisdictionas the properlodestar,however,bears emphasisat the outset. In comparingthe situationof superiorcourts and inferior courts as law interpreters,the comparativeadvantageresidesalmostentirelywith the superior court.'68Thus, there is no reason for a superiorcourt to defer to the judgments of a trial court on questions of law. But when we comparecourts and agencies, there are strengths and weaknesses on both sides of the ledger. Executiveinterpretershavegreaterexpertiseon mattersthatarehighlytechnical or complex;they have morefamiliaritywith the overallstructureof a statutory program,and with the policies followed underthose programs;and they are more accountableto the public. On the other hand, courts are more insulated from political pressuresthan agencies; their membersare more likely to be selected for theirlegal abilitiesthanare agencyheads;they may be able to hire better law clerks; and they may have more time to do research and write opinions, if only because they are exempt from the statutorydeadlinesoften imposed on agencies. The point is not thatagenciesare always betterinterpretersthancourtsare or vice versa, but simply that there are advantagesand disadvantageson both sides. This suggests that, at least as a first approximation,the treatmentof precedentof courtsof parallelauthorityappearsto supplythe best benchmark for establishingthe judicial attitudetowardexecutive precedent.'69Of course, this is just an analogy. There are a numberof aspects in which the treatment of executive precedentshould differ from that of intercircuitprecedent.The analogy is useful, however,for it demonstratesthatit is possible to groundthe deference doctrine in the practice of following precedent.As we shall see, moreover,the treatmentof the precedentof courtsof parallelauthorityappears 168. See Salve Regina College, 111 S. Ct. at 1221; Dan T. Coenen,ToDefer or Not to Defer: A Study of Federal Circuit Court Deference to District CourtRulings on State Law, 73 MINN.L. REV.899, 923 (1989). 169. If courts should treatthe interpretationsof executive agencies like the precedentof a tribunalof coordinate jurisdiction, then should agencies treat the opinions of courts the same way, i.e., as only presumptivelycorrectandentitledto moreor less weightdependingon contextualfactors?This is a variation on the problem of agency "nonacquiescence"in judicial interpretationsof law. See Samuel Estreicher& RichardRevesz, Nonacquiescenceby Federal AdministrativeAgencies, 98 YALEL.J. 679 (1989); Vestal, supra note 158. My answer would be that, as a matterof theory,agencies must give judicial precedentno more deference than courts must give executive precedent.Courtsrenderjudgmentsthat bind the parties before them (includingagencies) and suchjudgmentsmust of coursebe obeyed. They also issue statements of reason-opinions-that help readers(includingagencies)predicthow they will resolve futurecontroversies. But they do not issue edicts that bind all the world, as the Constitution,a statute, or an agency regulationdoes. See John Harrison,TheRole of the Legislativeand ExecutiveBranchesin Interpretingthe L. REV.371 (1988); Edwin Meese, III, The Law of the Constitution,61 TUL. Constitution,73 CORNELL L. REV.979 (1987). In theory, therefore,agencies could regardjudicial precedentthe same way courts regardagency precedent. At a practical level, however, the fact that courts review agencies ratherthan vice versa may well dictate a more accommodatingattitudeby agencies. Thus, agencies may wish to "acquiesce"in judicial opinions for futurecases even if those opinions are not bindingas a matterof law, and even if the agency, as a matter of interbranchprecedent-following,is not convinced by the court's analysis. 1010 The Yale Law Journal [Vol. 101: 969 to sharemany of the main featuresof the administrativedeferencedoctrineas it has been historicallypracticedand understood. C. The Model Stated If we view the deferencedoctrineas partof the system of precedent,then the decision whether or to what extent to defer to executive interpretations would in each case entail a three-partinquiry:(1) Is therean executive precedent?(2) How strongis thatprecedent?(3) Given the strengthof the executive precedent,does an independentjudicialexaminationof the questionof statutory interpretationcompel a differentresult? 1. Is Therean ExecutivePrecedent? Not every interpretationof law by an executive agency shouldbe regarded as a "precedent,"at least for purposes of determiningthe judicial response. Here, I would suggest that the relevantdistinctionis betweenan interpretation initially advancedwhen the agency is acting as an independentdecisionmaker and an interpretationfirst advancedwhen the agency is acting as a party to judicial proceedings.Insofaras the agency adoptsan interpretationwhen it is wearing its independentdecisionmakerhat, its views should be regardedas "precedent."Includedin this categorywould be any interpretationembodied in a decision by an agency thatis legally bindingon actorsoutsidethe agency itself, such as the promulgationof legislativerules, the issuanceof administrative orders,or the awardof licensesandgrants.In addition,any legal interpretation embodied in an official statement of agency position that predates a particularjudicial controversywould count as precedent. Examples would includeinterpretativerules, policy statements,agency enforcementguidelines, and previous opinion letters. When an agency initially advancesan interpretationwhile it is wearingits judicial litigant hat, however, the interpretationshould not be regardedas precedent.This is not because the agency loses any comparativeadvantageit may have as an interpreterwhen it changeshats. Instead,judicial normsabout impartialadjudicationprecludegiving the interpretationprecedentialweight. When there are two parties before a court contestingthe meaning of the law, it is generally understoodthat the court should decide the matterimpartially and independently,without giving one party's views greater weight simply because of that party's status.170 Thus, insofar as the agency view is not embodied in a previous authoritativeexpression of its views, the agency view shouldbe treatedas no differentfromthe positionof any otherparty.Examples 170. See Fishgold v. Sullivan Drydock & RepairCorp., 154 F.2d 785, 789 (2d Cir.), aff'd, 328 U.S. 275 (1946); Anthony,supra note 7, at 60 ("Itwould exceed the boundsof fair play to allow an institutionally self-interestedadvocacyposition, which 'may properlycarry a bias,' to controlthe judicial outcome."). 1992] Executive Precedent 1011 of agency action that fall into this categoryand thus shouldnot be regardedas precedentwould includean interpretationimplicitin the decision of a prosecutor to file criminal charges, an interpretationreflected in the decision of an agency to institute judicial enforcement proceedings, or an interpretation advancedfor the first time in legal briefs filed in courtdefendinga previously taken agency action. 2. How StrongIs the ExecutivePrecedent? Once it is determinedthatthereis an executiveprecedenton point,the next step would be to ascertain how "strong"it is. This inquiry, which would necessarily be fairly judgmental,would entail two distinct components. The first componentturns on the level in the executive hierarchyfrom which the intepretationemanates.Under the executive precedentmodel, the authorityof executive agencies to interpretlaw derives not from a delegation of interpretativeauthorityfrom Congress,but from the President'sexecutive power and constitutionalobligationto see thatthe laws are faithfullyexecuted. Thus,the more directlyaccountablethe interpreteris to the President,the more the decision would partakeof the President'sconstitutionalauthorityand the an stronger it would be regarded as executive precedent. To illustrate:171 interpretationcontainedin a letter from a regionaloffice of the Departmentof Health and Human Services (HHS) would not be as strong as one contained in a "programinstruction"adopted by the general counsel of HHS, which would not be as strong as one reflected in a policy directive issued by the Secretaryof HHS, which would not be as strong as an interpretationdirectly approvedby the President. This hierarchyof authority,of course, directly parallelsthe understandingof the strengthof precedentin thejudicialhierarchy, wherethe SupremeCourtpartakesof the "judicialpower"by directgrantfrom the Constitution,andlowercourtspossess thejudicialpoweronly in accordance with their position in relationto the SupremeCourt.172 The second componentof the strengthof executive precedentis derived by analogy to the treatmentof precedentof courts of coordinatejurisdiction within the system of judicial precedent.Considersome of the factors that a courtmightlook to in determiningwhetherto follow the precedentof a judicial tribunal of coordinate authority:How long has the precedentof the other tribunalbeen followed? Has it been criticizedby laterdecisions, or is it inconsistent with anotherprecedentof equal status?Has the public come to rely on 171. The illustrationis derived from Miller v. Youakim,440 U.S. 125, 144 n.25 (1979). 172. Unlike the Chevrondoctrine,the executiveprecedentmodeldoes notrequirethattherebe a unitary executive branch.See supra note 44. Everythingelse being equal, however,the greaterthe "independence" of an executive entity from Presidentialoversightand control, the weakerits precedent.Thus, a statutory interpretationadopted by the Securities and ExchangeCommission-an "independent"regulatoryagency-would be entitled to less deference than would an interpretationadoptedby a Cabinetofficer such as the Attorney General or the Secretaryof HHS, both of whom are removableby the Presidentat will. 1012 The Yale Law Journal [Vol. 101: 969 the interpretation?Does the interpretationconcern a matteras to which the othertribunalhas particularfamiliarityor expertise?Wasthe issue fully briefed and arguedin the othertribunal,and is the othertribunal'sdecision supported of the othertribunal by a thoroughandreasonedopinion?Has the interpretation been ratified by subsequentcongressional action? As developed more fully below, these factors bear an uncannyresemblanceto the contextual factors courts developed in the pre-Chevronera in orderto determinewhether,or to what extent, to defer to executive interpretations.The analogy to intercircuit precedenthelps to sharpen our understandingof why many of these factors should be relevant and which ones are most importantin particularsettings. 3. Does an IndependentJudicial JudgmentCompela DifferentResult? Once the courthas establishedthatthereis an executive precedentand has determined (roughly) how strong that precedent is, then it must make an independentinquiryto determinewhetherthereis sufficientreasonto overcome the presumptionof correctnessthatsucha precedentenjoys.In undertakingthis inquiry, the court could call upon any and all of the "traditionaltools of that would be relevant in interpretingthe statute statutoryinterpretation"173 de novo. The conclusionsreachedthroughthis kindof analysis-ranging from a judgmentthatthe statutecan haveonly one possible meaningto a conclusion that it is utterlyopaque-would then be consideredin light of the conclusions reachedaboutthe strengthof the executiveprecedent.A strongprecedent-such as an interpretationadopted by the Secretary of HHS in a well reasoned decisionconsistentlymaintainedovera long periodof time-would be rejected only if the courtwere firmly convincedit was wrong.A weak precedent-such as a recent letter from a regionaloffice of HHS assertingthe interpretationin a conclusoryfashion-would be disregardedif the courthada fair doubtabout its correctness. This is an admittedlyimprecisedecisional formula.But there are simply too many relevantvariablesto reducethe inquiryto a simple algorithm.Nor is it particularlysurprisingthatthis shouldbe the case. Afterall, the same must be said of the role of judicial precedentin statutoryinterpretation:no single formula can capturethe process by which courts determinethe competing claims of priorjudicialprecedentanda de novojudicialexaminationof statutory languageand legislative intent.The only differencewhereexecutive precedent is involved is thatthe precedentcomes from a differentbranchof government.174 173. ChevronU.S.A., Inc. v. National ResourcesDefense Council, 467 U.S. 837, 843 n.9 (1984). 174. An alternativebasis for a model not groundedin presumeddelegationis suggestedby the doctrine of practical construction:administrativedecisions could be seen as a form of "conduct"that is evidence of the practicalconstructionof a statuteby the partychargedwith its implementation.See Annotation,Effect of practical or administrativeconstructionof a statuteon subsequentjudicial construction,73 L. Ed. 322 (1929). The doctrine of practicalconstructionis often encounteredin cases construingtreaties,see Eastern 1992] Executive Precedent 1013 V. THE MODELSCOMPARED The proposedexecutive precedentmodel sharesmany of the strengthsof the Chevron doctrine in that it strives to encourage courts to defer to the judgments of political actors who have greater public accountabilityand specialized knowledge.Yet, I will contend,it avoids Chevron'smajortheoretical and practicalfailings. Moreover,the model is not radical,unless perhaps one assumes (contraryto fact) that the full-blown Chevrondoctrine actually defines the statusquo. Indeed,a majorpart of the justificationfor the model is that it coheresbetterwith both existing and historicalpracticethan does the Chevronformulation.Finally, the executive precedentidea has consequences for judicial, administrative,and congressionalbehaviorthat, on balance, are superiorto the effects of Chevron. A. OvercomingChevron'sTheoreticaland Practical Problems Any theory of deferencemust come to terms with the Marburyproblem and the problemof agency accountability.We can now see thatthere are three general strategies for accomplishingthese ends.'75 The first-which prevailedfleetinglywhenmodernadministrativelaw was taking form-is to allow courts to review all questions of law de novo. This solution totally eliminates the Marburyproblem and provides a powerful potentialcheck on agency abuse.But it deprivesus of any comparativeadvantage agencies may have as interpreters,and it gives the courts too much discretionarypower over the formulationof policy. The second strategy-that of Chevron-is grounded in the notion of mandatorydeference.Courtsseek to remainfaithfulto theirdutyto "saywhat the law is" while deferringto executive interpretationsby positing that Congress has mandatedthatthey defer.Agency accountabilityis securedby having courtsenforceclearstatutorydirectivesandby relyingon Presidentialoversight. As we have seen,'76this strategy, as pursued by Chevron, falls victim to several difficulties, includingthe need to adopta doubtfulfiction of delegated interpretativeauthority,and to abandona good partof the only effective check on the abuse of power by agencies. Airlines, Inc. v. Floyd, 111 S. Ct. 1489, 1499 (1991); Air France v. Saks, 470 U.S. 392, 403 (1985), and traces its origins to the doctrine of practicalconstructionin the law of contracts.See SAMUEL WILLISTON, A TREATISE ON THELAWOFCONTRACTS ? 623 (3d ed. 1961). As suggested by these origins, however, the doctrineultimatelyrestson the idea of mutualassent-if bothpartiesto an agreementconcurin a certain practicalimplementation,thenthis suggeststhatbothpartieshave assentedto this construction.The absence of anythingresemblinga conventional bilateralagreementin the agency setting may make this particular analogy problematicas a basis for a model of deference to administrativedecisions. 175. See Stephen Breyer,Judicial Review of Questionsof Law and Policy, 38 ADMIN.L. REV.363, 368-69 (1986). 176. See supra text accompanyingnotes 7-29. 1014 The Yale Law Journal [Vol. 101: 969 The third strategy-that pursuedby the executive precedentmodel-is groundedin discretionarydeference.Courtsremainfaithful to the duty to say what the law is, but in exercising this duty they conclude as a matterof selfgovernancethat the best guide to the meaningof the law is often to follow the prior interpretationsof a coordinatebranchof government.At the same time, courts hold agencies accountableby upholdingonly the exercise of sound executive discretion:they affirmdecisionsthatpresenta combinationof strong precedentand/orcongruencewith congressionalintent, but they reversedecisions thatpresenta combinationof weakprecedentand/ortensionwith congressional intent.This approachthereforeallows courtsto continueto act as a check on abuse of delegated power. 1. TheoreticalFailings By groundingthe practiceof deferencein normsof judicial comity rather than legislative compulsion,the executive precedentmodel avoids Chevron's most glaring weakness:the need to posit a fictitious delegationof power from Congress to executive agencies. Instead,the practiceof deferenceis derived from two relatively uncontroversialconstitutionalpropositions:(1) executive entities have an inherentpower to interpretthe laws they are chargedwith enforcing, and (2) the courts have an inherentpower to develop norms for followingprecedentthatcan be extendedto encompassthe practiceof deferring to executive precedent. Because the executive precedentmodel grounds deference in inherent powers,it is unaffectedby the ambiguityoverCongress'trueintentionsregarding the allocation of interpretativeauthority.Chevronfails in the face of this uncertaintybecause ambiguitydoes not add up to a mandatorydirective to defer.But if courtshave inherentpowerto decide when to defer,an ambiguous congressional attitude simply means Congress has done nothing that would requirecourts to desist from their existing practiceof deference. In addition,the model harmonizesbetterwith establishedunderstandings of constitutionalstructure.At a formallevel, Chevronrecognizesan omnipotent Congress,which is envisionedas not only establishingsubstantivelegal norms, butalso as directingthe allocationof interpretativeauthoritybetweenexecutive agencies and courts. But in practice,because of its fiction that Congresshas delegatedthe resolutionof all ambiguitiesto the agencieschargedwith enforcement of a statute, Chevronsanctions the exercise of vast executive powers uncheckedby meaningfuljudicial review. The executive precedentmodel, like Chevron,posits that Congress has ultimatepower over the adoptionof substantivelegal norms.But the allocation of interpretativeauthoritybetweenagencies and courts-at least for purposes of judicial review-is determined by the courts themselves, absent some supersedinginstructionfromCongress.By groundingthe practiceof deference 1992] Executive Precedent 1015 in the discretionarypowers of courts, the executive precedentmodel permits courtsto continueto performan importantcheckingfunctionin reviewingthe exercise of delegated power by agencies. In particular,courts would not be requiredto identify a clear statutoryviolation before they could decline to follow executiveprecedent.Otherabusesof agencypower-including decisions thatupset settledexpectations,decisionsthatreflectagency bias, and decisions that seek to expand agency power beyond the sphere contemplatedbut not expresslyspelledoutby Congress-would also be subjectto judicialcorrection. 2. Practical Failings The executive precedentmodel, with its greaterflexibility and openness to a wider range of potentiallyrelevantconsiderations,also avoids the major practicalfailings of Chevron.By retainingflexibilityaboutthe relativeweights to be given executive precedent and independentjudgment, the executive precedentmodel avoids the extremes of Chevron,whereby the views of the executive are given eithertoo little or too muchweight in virtuallyevery case. In particular,the model ensuresthatthe executive branchview will always be considered,ratherthan become relegatedto a subset of cases in which courts do not feel confident aboutexercisingindependentjudgment.At a minimum, therefore,the executiveprecedentmodelguaranteesthatthe entitywith the best graspof practicalconsequences-the executive agency-at least gets its views on the table in every case. The executiveprecedentmodelalso sidestepsthe needto adoptany particular theory of judicial interpretationin orderto fix the point at which the court will defer to executivejudgment.The model can be weddedto any of the rival methods of interpretation.It is based on a contextual assessment of the "strength"of the executive precedenttogetherwith an independentjudicial assessment of statutorymeaning, with no a priori specification of a single legitimate method for ascertainingmeaning. Finally,the model is open to a wide rangeof contextualfactorsthatcourts continue to regard as important.Under Chevron,the court is instructedto decide whetherto defer after looking at only one variable:whetherthe court is entitled to exercise independentjudgment. Other variables related to the agency's authorityand its performanceare ignored. In effect, the decision whether to defer is made with blinders on. Under the executive precedent model, in contrast,the courtlooks at both sides of the equation:measuringfirst the strengthof the executive precedentand then consideringthis measurement against an independentassessmentof the clarity of the statute. 1016 The Yale Law Journal [Vol. 101: 969 B. Congruencewith Practice Perhapseven more impressiveis the capacity of the executive precedent model to explainvariousfeaturesof the deferencedoctrine,both the traditional pre-Chevronunderstandingand the recent exceptions recognized under the Chevronregime. 1. The Status of Pre-ChevronFactors Under the Executive Precedent Model Quite a numberof the featuresof the deferencedoctrineas it existed in the pre-Chevronera-features thatwere apparentlybanishedby Chevron,butseem to persistin the actualpracticeof the Court-suddenly becomeexplicableonce we view the practiceof deferenceas a form of following precedent.In particular, most of the deference factors have direct analogues in the practice that courtsobservewhendecidingwhetherto followjudicialprecedent.And the few factorsthatlack directanalogueshave a commonsensebasis andcan be readily accommodatedto the executive precedentmodel. (a) DeferenceAs a Sliding Scale. Pre-Chevronpractice,as we have seen, treateddeference as existing along a sliding scale,177whereas Chevrontends to make deferencean all-or-nothingproposition.Viewing deferenceas a form of following precedentmakessense of the traditionalapproach.Wherejudicial precedentis concerned,courts typically do not resolve questions of statutory interpretationsolely on the basis of precedentfrom courtsof coordinatejurisdiction. Some nonbindingprecedentsare consideredweightierthanothers,and considerationsdrawnfrom the precedentof othercourtsare typicallyweighed Simiagainstthe court'sindependentanalysis of the meaningof the statute.178 under the executive deference to executive views would model, larly, precedent fall along a continuum,dependingon the strengthof the executive precedent and the degree of confidence the court has in its independentview of the statute'smeaning. (b) Express Delegations. Pre-Chevroncases also distinguishedbetween "legislative rules" and "interpretativerules." This construct has no direct analogue in the realm of judicial precedent,no doubt because it is rare for 177. See supra text accompanyingnote 8. 178. See Colby v. J.C. Penney,Inc., 811 F.2d 1119, 1123 (7th Cir. 1987) (circuit court does not give automaticdeference to decisions of other circuits, but recognizes that "withinreason, the parties to cases before us are entitled to our independentjudgment.");HaberleCrystal SpringsBrewing Co. v. Clarke,30 F.2d 219, 222 (2d Cir. 1929), rev'd on other grounds, 280 U.S. 384 (1930) ("Much as we respect the considered decisions of other circuits, we conceive that our duty requires us to form an independent judgmentin cases of first impressionin our own court,and forbidsus blindlyto follow othercircuits,when our minds are not persuadedby the argumentsadvanced."). 1992] Executive Precedent 1017 Nevertheless, Congress expressly to delegate rulemakingpower to courts.179 the basic insight of the legislative/interpretativerule distinctionis sound and shouldbe adoptedto the executiveprecedentframework.Any expressdirective from Congressaboutthe allocationof interpretativeauthoritywould supersede the internalnorms.But such directivesare rare.Shortof an express allocation of interpretativeroles, a specific congressionalgrant of authorityto agencies in a particularareashouldbe viewed as a congressionaljudgmentof the superior competenceof the agencyto developlegal normsin the areaunderconsideration,andthus shouldalso resultin greaterdeferenceto agencyinterpretations. I would, however, reject one feature of the pre-Chevronapproachto legislative rules. Pre-Chevroncase law tendedto speakin all-or-nothingterms. Eitheran agency interpretationwas a "legislativerule"entitledto greatdeference, or it was an "interpretativerule" entitled only to whateverpersuasive effect it might have.'80Unfortunately,this dichotomytended to break down in practice. Statutes granting general substantive rulemaking authority to agencies,ratherthanspecific authorityto definea particularterm,wereparticuI would avoid crudedichotomiesby makingthe specificilarly problematic.81' ty of any expresscongressionaldelegationof regulatoryauthorityone contextual factor to be consideredin determiningthe strengthof the executive precedent.The specificity of the grantfromCongress,however,wouldnot necessarily override or negate other considerations. (c) AgencyExpertise.Pre-Chevroncase law variedthe degreeof deference accordingto whetherthe issue was one thatimplicatedagency"expertise."This idea is encounteredless often in the realm of judicial precedent,but it is not unheardof. For example, courtsof appealswill occasionallygive extradeference to decisionsof othercircuitsthathavegreaterfamiliaritywith the substantive body of law in question.'82And courtsquite commonlydefer to interpre- 179. The principalexception is the Rules EnablingAct, which authorizesthe SupremeCourtto adopt rules of civil procedureand evidence. 28 U.S.C. ? 2072 (1988). This delegation,however,concernsmatters of judicial self-governance,over which courts would presumablyhave inherentauthorityin the absenceof a legislative delegation. See ThomasMerrill, The CommonLaw Powers of Federal Courts, 52 U. CHI.L. REV. 1, 46-47 (1985). Anotherarguableexception is the SentencingCommission,on which three federal judges sit. In Mistrettav. United States, 488 U.S. 361 (1989), the SupremeCourtheld that it was constitutionally permissible for Congress to constitute the SentencingCommissionas part of the judicial branch, even though it exercises substantiverulemakingauthority. 180. See Battertonv. Francis,432 U.S. 416, 424-25 & n.9 (1977); 1 DAVIS,supra note 6, at 421-22. 181. Some pre-Chevroncases suggested that interpretationsadoptedpursuantto general rulemaking authoritywere entitled to less weight than interpretationsmore specifically authorizedby Congress.See, e.g., United States v. Vogel FertilizerCo., 455 U.S. 16 (1982); Rowan Cos., Inc. v. United States, 452 U.S. 247,253 (1981). Othercases suggestedthatinterpretationsadoptedpursuantto generalrulemakingauthority were no differentfrom specific authorizations.See, e.g., FCCv. WNCN ListenersGuild, 450 U.S. 582, 594 (1981). 182. See City of Westfield v. Federal Power Comm'n, 551 F.2d 468 (1st Cir. 1977) (views of D.C. Circuit, which reviews great bulk of Federal Power Commission orders, carry great weight when case involving similar issue comes before other circuit);Watsonv. Allen, 254 F.2d 342, 347 (D.C. Cir. 1958) ("substantialweight" given to views of Court of Customs and PatentAppeals "as to technical or highly specialized patent matters"). 1018 The Yale Law Journal [Vol. 101: 969 tations of state law or procedural law by other courts that have greater experience with these localized legal regimes.183 The notion that specialized competence warrants deference naturally plays a more prominent role in the executive precedent context because of the specialized nature of administrative agencies. Common sense suggests that the views of those with specialized knowledge about a subject are generally more valuable than the views of those without such knowledge. Because agencies are specialists, it follows that additional deference should be given to their judgments within the area of their specialization. Thus, pre-Chevron case law accorded extra deference to an agency's interpretations of the specific statute it was charged with administering, but did not give any special deference to other types of agency interpretations, such as constructions of common law terms, constitutional principles, or prior judicial precedents,184 or to interpretations of statutes the agency did not ordinarily administer.'85The executive precedent model would carry this general distinction forward, treating the presence or absence of specialized agency knowledge as one of the factors to be considered in determining the strength of agency precedent. (d) Longstanding Interpretations. Pre-Chevron cases put great stress on whether an agency interpretation was longstanding and consistent. This has a direct analogue in practice regarding judicial precedent. Here too, the longevity of the precedent is clearly an important factor in determining how much weight it will be given.'86 The case for giving greater weight to old precedents is based primarily on two considerations. First, the fact that an interpretation has survived for a long period of time is some evidence that it is sound, in the sense that it is workable.'87 Unworkable interpretations generate discontent that may result in congressional overruling, or modification or repudiation by the court that initially offered the interpretation. The fact that none of this has occurred is circumstantial evidence that the interpretation does not impose undue costs on regulated entities or frustrate the basic objectives of the proponents of the legislation.'88 Second, longstanding interpretations give rise to 183. See Bishop v. Wood, 426 U.S. 341, 345-46 n. 10 (1976) (SupremeCourtdefers to interpretation of state law adoptedby lower federal courts that are "familiarwith the intricaciesand trendsof local law and practice");PanduitCorp. v. All States Plastic Mfg. Co., 744 F.2d 1564, 1574-75 (Fed. Cir. 1984) (FederalCircuit adopts policy of following law of regionalcircuits with respect to proceduralquestions). 184. See, e.g., Piper v. Chris-CraftIndus., Inc., 430 U.S. 1, 41 n.27 (1977); Texas Gas Transmission Corp. v. Shell Oil Co., 363 U.S. 263, 268-70 (1960); SEC v. CheneryCorp., 318 U.S. 80, 89 (1943). 185. See, e.g., NLRB v. Bildisco & Bildisco, 465 U.S. 513, 529 n.9 (1984); Alaska S.S. Co. v. United States, 290 U.S. 256, 261-64 (1933). 186. See, e.g., Californiav. FERC, 110 S. Ct. 2024, 2029 (1990) (referringto "thedeferencethis Court must accord to long-standing and well-entrencheddecisions, especially those interpretingstatutes that underliecomplex regulatoryregimes");SquareD Co. v. NiagaraFrontierTariff Bureau,Inc., 476 U.S. 409, 421-22, 424 (1986) (refusing to overrule precedentfollowed for six decades notwithstandingextensive changes in statutoryframeworkand relateddoctrine). 187. See Commissionerv. Fink, 483 U.S. 89, 102-03 (1987) (Stevens, J., dissenting). 188. Similar points have been advancedin the literatureseeking to explain why common law rules tend to be efficient. See William M. Landes & RichardA. Posner,Legal Precedent:A Theoreticaland EmpiricalAnalysis, 19 J. LAW& ECON.249 (1976); George L. Priest, The CommonLaw Process and the 1992] Executive Precedent 1019 relianceintereststhatwarrantjudicialprotection.One of the primaryjustifications for the practiceof followingjudicialprecedentsis to promotestabilityin the legal system by protectingthese reliance interests.'89Of course, the presumption in favor of old precedentsis not irrefutable.Generally speaking, however,the longer and more consistentlya precedenthas been followed, the higherthe burdenis on the partyseekingto overcomethe precedentto explain why it is infirm.'90 Given these judicial understandings,it is not surprisingthat the duration of an executive interpretationis the most frequentlyencounteredfactorin the pre-Chevroncase law (and for that matterin the post-Chevroncases as well). The rationalefor giving weight to longstandingagency precedentis identical to that for giving weight to judicial precedent:age is indicativeof soundness (in the sense of workability),andolderinterpretations generaterelianceinterests It is also true that deservingprotection.'9l longstandingagency precedent,like longstandingjudicialprecedent,can be overruled.Courtscan accommodatethe need for change by imposing a higher burdenof explanationon an agency reversingits own longstandingprecedentthan otherwisewould be the case.192 (e) Well-ReasonedDecisions. Beginning with Skidmorev. Swift & Co.,193 the SupremeCourt'spre-Chevroncases also gave greaterdeferenceto "wellreasoned" agency decisions. In determiningwhether to follow nonbinding precedentsin the judicial context, such as decisions of courts of coordinate jurisdiction, courts frequentlyconsider how persuasive the reasoning of the other courtis: whetherit has consideredall relevantarguments,supportedthe Selection of Efficient Rules, 6 J. LEGALSTUD.65 (1977); Paul H. Ruben, Why is the CommonLaw Efficient?, 6 J. LEGALSTUD.51 (1977). 189. See United States v. Mason, 412 U.S. 391 (1973) (stare decisis requiresthat people rely on the Court's decisions and that they should not be penalized for such reliance);cf. Payne v. Tennessee, 111 S. Ct. 2597, 2610 (1991) ("[C]onsiderationsin favor of stare decisis are at their acme in cases involving propertyand contractrights, where reliance interestsare involved."). 190. See Fink, 483 U.S. at 89, 103 (Stevens, J., dissenting);WestinghouseElec. & Mfg. Co. v. Formica Insulation Co., 266 U.S. 342 (1924) (Court will not lightly disturbrule settled by 45 years of judicial constructionwith respect to rights arising underpatent law). 191. The need to protectreliance interestshas long been recognized as an importantreason to defer to longstandingexecutive interpretations.As the Court observed in one case: [G]overnmentis a practicalaffair intendedfor practicalmen. Both officers, law-makersand citizens naturallyadjust themselves to any long-continuedaction of the Executive Department-on the presumptionthat unauthorizedacts would not have been allowed to be so often repeatedas to crystallize into a regularpractice.Thatpresumptionis not reasoningin a circle but the basis of a wise and quieting rule that in determiningthe meaning of a statute or the existence of a power, weight shall be given to the usage itself-even when the validity of the practice is the subject of investigation. United States v. Midwest Oil Co., 236 U.S. 459, 472-73 (1915); see also Brewsterv. Gage, 280 U.S. 327, 336 (1930); Logan v. Davis, 233 U.S. 613, 627 (1914); United States v. Burlington& Mo. RiverR.R., 98 U.S. 334, 341 (1879). 192. See American Hosp. Ass'n v. NLRB, 111 S. Ct. 1539, 1546 (1991) ("Giventhe extensive notice and commentrulemakingconductedby the Board,its carefulanalysis of the commentsthatit received,and its well-reasonedjustificationfor the new rule, we would not be troubledeven if therewere inconsistencies between the currentrule and priorNLRB pronouncements.");SEC v. CheneryCorp., 318 U.S. 80 (1943). See generally STEPHEN G. BREYER & RICHARD B. STEWART, ADMINISTRATIVE LAWANDREGULATORY POLICY 416-26 (2d ed. 1985). 193. 323 U.S. 134 (1944). 1020 The Yale Law Journal [Vol. 101: 969 conclusion with a thorough explanation, and so forth.19 This is perfectly sensible. Because the precedentof a coordinatetribunalis not binding,it must compete with the court's independentanalysis of the issue. Althoughthereis a general bias in favor of uniformity,and thus the precedentwill be regarded as prima facie correct,a poorlyreasonedprecedentobviously commandsless respect and requiresthatthe secondcourtdig moredeeply in orderto ascertain for itself what the correct answer should be. The same patternis followed in the executive precedentcontext. Here, the pre-Chevroncase law could, if anything, have done more to emphasize the importanceof careful agency reasoning.Whereagency factfindingand policy judgmentsare concerned,courtshavecome to insist thatagenciestake a "hard look" at the relevant variables and options.195There is no reason why the preferencefor rigor should not extend to legal interpretations. (f) InteragencyAgreement.Pre-Chevroncase law reducedthe degree of deferencewheretwo agencieswerein disagreementaboutthe properinterpretation of a statute.This practicealso makes sense if we think of deferenceas a form of following precedent.Wherea court faces conflicting precedentsfrom differentjurisdictions,it is muchless likely to defer to one of those interpretations than it would where the precedentfrom other jurisdictions is unanimous.196Here too, we see how the executive precedentmodel can rationalize pre-Chevronpracticeand integrateit with generalnormsof judicial self-governance. A particularlyvenerablepre-Chevron (g) Contemporaneous Interpretations. factor laid stress on whetherthe agency interpretationwas contemporaneous with the enactment of the statute. Because courts are generally not active participantsin the processof formulatinglegislation,the views of a contemporary court are not necessarily probativeof the thinking of the draftersof a statute.Thereis, however,a moredirectanaloguein constitutionallaw: the idea thatcourtsshouldgive deferenceto the views of the first Congresswith respect to the meaning of the Constitution.197 The views of the first Congress are to be because so many of the membersof that thought especially revealing were active in the Congress participants framingandratificationof the Consti194. See, e.g., Richardsv. Local 134, Int'l Bhd. of Elec. Workers,790 F.2d 633, 636 (7th Cir. 1986); City Stores Co. v. Lerner Shops of D.C., Inc., 410 F.2d 1010, 1014 (D.C. Cir. 1969); see also Oneida County Fair Bd. v. Smylie, 386 P.2d 374, 391 (Idaho 1963) (state supremecourt will select and apply decisions from other jurisdictions that reflect soundestreasoning.) 195. The general tenets of the "hardlook" doctrine have been said to be: (1) agencies must offer detailedexplanationsfor theirdecisions;(2) they mustexplaindeparturesfrom pastpractices;(3) they must allow effective participationby affectedinterests;and(4) they mustgive considerationto possiblealternative measures.Cass R. Sunstein, Deregulationand the Hard Look Doctrine, 1983 SUP.CT. REV.181-82. For examples of "hardlook" review in the SupremeCourt,see Bowen v. AmericanHosp. Ass'n, 476 U.S. 610, 627 (1986); Motor Vehicles Mfrs. Ass'n v. State Farm MutualAuto Ins. Co., 463 U.S. 29, 41-44 (1983); Baltimore Gas & Elec. Co. v. National ResourcesDefense Council, 462 U.S. 87, 105-06 (1983). 196. See Vestal, supra note 158, at 163-65. 197. See Bowsher v. Synar, 478 U.S. 714, 723-24 (1986); Marsh v. Chambers,463 U.S. 783, 790 (1983). 1992] Executive Precedent 1021 tution,and thus presumablyhadspecial insightinto the originalunderstanding. In effect, the decisions of the first Congressare viewed as one form of legislative branch"precedent"entitled to deferenceby the courts. constructionfactorin administrative The rationalefor the contemporaneous law is similar to that in the constitutionalcontext. It has been observedthat agency officials are often "thedraftsmenof the laws they are afterwardscalled Even if agency actorsdid not participatedirectlyin the upon to interpret."198 formulationof the legislation, their contemporaneousinterpretationcan be regarded as indicative of the prevailing views about policy, given that the administrativeagency often shares the same assumptionsthat animate the Like its constitutionalcousin, the administrativedoctrine has legislature.199 somewhatlimited value, and goes moreto the judicialdiscernmentof congressional intent than to ascertainingthe "strength"of the executive precedent. Moreover,I suspectthatmanyof the referencesto contemporaryconstructions, especially in the earlier cases, are synonyms for longstandingconstruction. Nevertheless,even when used in its correctsignification,there is no harmin incorporatingit as one factorin the decisional matrix,as long as its rationale is clearly perceived. (h) RatifiedInterpretations.Finally,pre-Chevroncases often placedweight on evidence thatCongresshadratifiedthe executiveconstruction.The ideathat interpretationsare entitled to greaterdeferenceif they have been ratified by Congressalso has a preciseparallelin the worldof judicialprecedent.Congress is presumedto be aware of the way statuteshave been interpretedby courts. If one court adoptsa particularinterpretation,and Congresslaterreenactsthe statute without substantively changing the interpretedlanguage, then it is presumedthat Congress has approvedthe interpretation.20The doctrinecan be explained by a kind of "squeakywheel" theory of the legislative process similar to that which underlies(in part)the longstandinginterpretationfactor. If the initial interpretationgeneratesdiscontent-in the sense that it imposes large costs on particularinterest groups-then we can presume that those groups will bring it to the attentionof Congress;if Congress agrees, it will amendthe statuteto overturnthe interpretation.By the same token,if Congress reenacts a statuteafterjudicial interpretationwithoutchangingthe language, thatis some evidence thatthe interpretationhas notgeneratedgreatdiscontent. Because the doctrinemakes some ratherheroic assumptions,it should be used with caution. One problemrelates to the assumptionthat Congress is awareof judicial interpretationsof statutes.This may be contraryto fact if the interpretationaffects large and diffuse intereststhathave difficulty organizing 198. United States v. Moore, 95 U.S. 760, 763 (1888). 199. See, e.g., SEC v. Sloan, 436 U.S. 103, 126 (1978) (Brennan,J., concurring). 200. See, e.g., Pierce v. Underwood,487 U.S. 552, 566-68 (1988); Lorillardv. Pons, 434 U.S. 575, 580 (1978). See generally William N. Eskridge,Jr., InterpretingLegislative Inaction, 87 MICH.L. REV. 67, 70-84 (1988). 1022 The Yale Law Journal [Vol. 101: 969 for legislative action.201 Anotherproblemis presentedby those cases that find congressionalratificationbased on the failure of Congress to enact proposed legislation. Legislative inaction is always inherentlyambiguous and could reflect nothingmore thana crowdedlegislative agenda.But as long as ratification is limited to cases where at least the relevant committees have been informed of an interpretation,and Congressreenactsthe relevant legislation without change, it is probablya useful doctrine. The administrativeratification doctrine-a staple of pre-Chevroncase law-has exactly the same logic and limitations as the judicial ratification doctrine. Administrativeinterpretationscan be just as importantto interest andwe can expectthatthe interpretations that groupsas judicialinterpretations, make well-organizedinterest groups unhappywill come to the attentionof Congress. Thus, subject to the caveats noted about the judicial ratification version, congressionalratificationis a permissiblefactor for courts to use in ascertainingthe weight of executive precedent. 2. The Post-ChevronExceptionsUnder the ExecutivePrecedentModel The executive precedentmodel also makes sense of some of the disputes over Chevronfundamentalsthathaveeruptedin recentyears. In each case, the model suggests that there are sound reasons to deviate from the logic of Chevron. (a) InterpretationsBeyond Agency Authority. In Adams Fruit Co. v. the Courtheld that agency interpretationsare entitled to no deferBarrett,202 ence if they concern a topic that the agency has not been empoweredto regulate. In effect, Adams Fruit carries Chevron'spresumeddelegationtheory to its ultimateconclusion.Since the delegationof regulatoryauthoritygives rise to the duty to defer, where there is no delegatedpower there is no deference. Pre-Chevroncase law was more refined. When an agency spoke abouta matteras to which it had no power to regulate,its views were still entitledto considerationby courts,providedthey boreotherindiciathatwouldentitlethem to respect. This was the holding of Skidmore.203 The executive precedent model would adhereto this pre-Chevronunderstanding,ratherthan to Adams Fruit. If an agency's interpretationqualifies as executive precedentand has other attributesthat suggest it is entitledto deference,there is no reasonwhy it shouldnot be given appropriateweight as a form of precedent.For example, agencies often have specializedknowledgeaboutthe operationsof a particular industry and the way it is affected by a statutoryscheme. If the agency has issued an interpretativeregulationor policy statementthatprovidesa reasoned 201. See MANCUR ACTION OLSON,THELOGICOFCOLLECTIVE (1971); Bruce A. Ackerman,Beyond Carolene Products,98 HARV.L. REV.713 (1985). 202. 494 U.S. 638, 649-50 (1990). 203. Skidmorev. Swift & Co., 323 U.S. 134, 139-40 (1944). 1992] Executive Precedent 1023 analysis of the way the statuteshould be read, its views should be entitledto some weight, even if does not have day-to-dayregulatoryauthorityover the matter in contention. Adams Fruit is the wooden product of a conceptual scheme that all too often forecloses potentiallyvaluablelines of inquiry,and it should be rejected. (b) Post hoc Rationalizations.In contrast,the Court'sdecision to exclude "post hoc rationalizations"of counsel from Chevrondeference04is not consistent with the logic of Chevron.As long as the question concerns a matter delegated to the agency, Chevronsuggests it should not matterhow or when the agency announcesits interpretation. The "posthoc rationalization"exception,however,conformsto pre-Chevron case law,205and can be explained by the executive precedentmodel. As noted above, post hoc rationalizationsare simply not "precedents."They are interpretationsfirst advancedby an agency in its capacityas a party litigant, not in its capacity as an independentdecisionmaker.Thus, any deferenceto agency views in this context would offend ideals of judicial impartiality. (c) Canons of Construction.The Court has also suggested that certain canonsof construction-most notably,the canonthatinterpretations of doubtful constitutionalityare to be avoided-may trumpthe Chevrondoctrine.20Chevron itself supplies no rationalefor such a holding.Underthe executive precedentmodel, in contrast,courtsmay consultany traditionaltool of interpretation in arriving at an assessmentof the clarity of statutorymeaning. Canonsthat serve as defaultrules in the absenceof more directevidence of congressional intent should not play a majorpartin this exercise. If thereis no bettermeans of resolving a questionof interpretationthan calling upon such a canon, then, as a general rule, the executive interpretationshould not be set aside. On the otherhand,canons groundedin considerationsof constitutionallaw and structure207 may supply a strongerbasis for overcomingexecutive precedent. (d) Judicial Precedent.In Maislin Industries,U.S. v. PrimarySteel, Inc., the Courtheld that an agency cannot change its mind aboutthe meaningof a statuteif by doing so it "casts doubton [the Court's]prior interpretation"of the statute.208 This conclusion remains a mystery underChevron,but makes perfect sense underthe executive precedentmodel. It is useful here to return to the judicial analogy. Althoughone court of appeals shouldtreata decision of anothercourtof appealsas primafacie correct,the precedentof the second 204. Bowen v. GeorgetownUniv. Hosp., 488 U.S. 204, 212 (1988) (quoting BurlingtonTruckLines v. United States, 371 U.S. 156, 168 (1968)). 205. See, e.g., SEC v. Sloan, 436 U.S. 103, 117-18 (1978); InvestmentCo. Inst. v. Camp, 401 U.S. 617, 628 (1971); SEC v. CheneryCorp., 318 U.S. 80, 87-88 (1943). 206. EdwardJ. DeBartolo Corp. v. FloridaGulf Coast Bldg. & Constr.TradesCouncil, 485 U.S. 568, 574-75 (1988). 207. See, e.g., Gregoryv. Ashcroft, 111 S. Ct. 2395, 2403-06 (1991) (adoptingcanon that statutewill not be construed to interfere with traditionalstate governmentalfunctions absent clear congressional statementindicating intent that it be so applied). 208. Maislin Indus., U.S. v. PrimarySteel, Inc., 110 S. Ct. 2759, 2770 (1990). 1024 The Yale Law Journal [Vol. 101: 969 court-however well reasonedandconsistentlyfollowed-cannot overcomethe force of the court'sown precedent.209 Staredecisis prevailsover the deference to of other circuits. given precedents Similarly, an executive precedentcannot outweigh a directly applicable judicial precedent.Of course, the executive view may providean occasion for the courts to reconsidertheir own precedent,just as contrarydecisions from other circuits may often trigger en banc reconsiderationby courts of appeals.210But such a change at best constitutesan appeal to the discretionof the court to overrule its prior precedentunderthe criteria of stare decisis; it does not impose an obligationon the courts to change their views or even to engage in a reconsideration.Thus,the executiveprecedentrendersthe outcome in Maislin perfectly explicable. (e) Decisions ImplicatingAgency Jurisdiction.In Mississippi Power & Light Co. v. Mississippiex rel. Moore,21JusticesBrennanand Scalia engaged in an inconclusive debate over whether an exception to Chevronshould be createdfor interpretationsthatimplicatethe limits of an agency'sjurisdiction. This issue is particularlyill suited to sweeping, either/or solutions. A rule precludingdeference on issues that implicate an agency's jurisdictionwould accomplish indirectly what Cardoza-Fonsecasought to do directly:it would eliminate any deferenceon "pure"questions of statutoryinterpretation.This is becausealmostany purelylegal questionwill haveimplicationsfor the scope of an agency's authority.At the same time, courts have long operatedwith a kind of unwrittenunderstandingthat deferenceto agency views is not appropriate, at least not to the same degree, where the agency view is likely to be influencedby institutionalbias.212 For example, courtsdo not defer to agency views on whetheragency decisions are judiciallyreviewable,whetheragency action falls within the termsof the FederalTortsClaimsAct, whetheragencies are liable to pay attorney'sfees, or whetheragency documentsmust be disclosed underthe Freedomof InformationAct.213For similarreasons, at least a lesser degree of deference may be warrantedwhen an agency decides to regulatea new area:the decision to regulatemay be motivatedby designs for agency aggrandizementratherthan by a disinterestedassessmentof statutory authorityand appropriatepolicy. The executive precedentmodel permits courts to give effect to concerns aboutinstitutionalbias in determiningwhetherdeferenceis appropriate.In the 209. E.g., FederalSav. & LoanIns. Corp.v. Bonfanti,826 F.2d 1391, 1394 n.3 (5th Cir. 1987), vacated sub nom. Zohdi v. Federal Sav. & Loan Ins. Corp., 490 U.S. 1001 (1989). 210. See FED.R. APP.P. 35. 211. 487 U.S. 354 (1988). 212. See Braun,supra note 106, at 1005-07; Sunstein,supra note 4, at 2101. 213. See, e.g., United States v. Fausto, 484 U.S. 439 (1988) (judicial review); Pierce v. Underwood, 487 U.S. 552 (1988) (attorney'sfees); CIA v. Sims, 471 U.S. 159 (1985) (Freedomof InformationAct); United States v. S.A. Empresade Viacao Aerea Rio Grandense(Varig Airlines), 467 U.S. 797 (1984) (FederalTorts Claims Act). 1992] Executive Precedent 1025 most egregious cases of agency bias-for example, wherethe issue is whether an agency decision is subjectto judicial review-there may well be no executive precedentsince the issue arises only when the agency is engagedin its role as a judicial litigant. In the moredifficult case wherean agency has concluded thatits statutorymandatepermitsa new industryor activity to be regulated(or deregulated),the executiveprecedentmodelpermits-as is appropliate-a more modulatedresponse.The concernwith possible agency bias justifies reducing the degree of deference without disregardingagency views and arguments altogether.In contrast,the rigid Chevrondoctrinedemandsthat courts either defer or not defer,permittinga courtto disregardan agency's conclusionsonly if it can identify a clear statutorymandatethat has been violated. Again, the more flexible approachbetter serves the separationof powers concerns furthered by the practice of independentjudicial review. All in all, the executive precedentmodel makes sense of a great deal of learningpreviouslyregardedas an unconnectedhodgepodgeof factorswith no unifying theme or rationale.The persistenceof these traditionalfactorsin the face of an official doctrinethat is hostile to their survival suggests that there is value in this conventionalwisdom. The congruencebetween the executive precedentmodel and observationsof conventionalpracticeprovidespowerful supportfor the model's validity. C. Consequencesfor Judicial and Agency Performance Finally, it is importantto give some considerationto the systemic effects that the executive precedentmodel might have relative to the Chevronmodel. Of course, in undertakingany such inquiry,one must bear in mind that the Chevronmodel operatesquite differentlyin practicethan it does on paper. 1. Consequencesfor Courts Proponentsof the Chevrondoctrineare attractedalmostexclusively by the prospect that its formal or rulelike qualities will confine judicial discretion. Restrictingjudicial discretionis thoughtto be desirablein this contextfor both instrinsic and extrinsic reasons. The intrinsic reason is that restrictionson judicial discretionare thought to be necessary if we are to speak of courts as being bound by "law."214 Whateverthe theoreticalor practicalfailings of Chevron,or its discontinuities with past (andpresent)judicialpractice,it at least has the appearanceof a legal rule ratherthan an "all things considered"standard.Justice Scalia, probably 214. See Antonin Scalia, The Rule of Law as a Law of Rules, 56 U. CHI.L. REv. 1175 (1989). For a general discussion, see FrederickSchauer,Formalism,97 YALEL.J. 509 (1988). 1026 The Yale Law Journal [Vol. 101: 969 the foremost championof the Chevrondoctrine,215 is clearly attractedto this featureof Chevron.Fromthis perspective,the executiveprecedentmodel is not sufficiently rulelike: it importsso many factorsthat the practiceof deference would degenerateinto an ad hoc inquirythat would allow courtsto reachany result they wanted to. Moreover,with so many factorsfrom which to choose, effective review or oversight by the SupremeCourt would be impossible.216 While thereis clearly some meritto this criticism,I would offer severalpoints by way of response. First, although my proposedexecutive precedentmodel is clearly more open texturedthan Chevron,I do not think that it can fairly be describedas "lawless." Unlike the pre-Chevronregime that it resembles, the executive precedent model endorses neither ad hockery nor an open-ended "list of factors"approach.Instead,it offers a theory thatexplains the respectiveroles of the executive and judicial branches,tells us which deference factors are relevant and why, and provides an account,in general terms at least, of how the courtis to considerthe executive view relativeto its own assessmentof the interpretativequestion.The modelmaybe complex-too complexto be reduced to a simple Chevron-likeformula-but it is not "unprincipled."Nor can it be said thatthe modelprescribesan ad hoc balancingtest. Suchtests requirecourts to engage in a "head-to-headcomparison"of competing interests.217The executive precedentmodel, in contrast,is groundedin analogical reasoning, whereby various factorsbecome relevantin determiningwhethera particular case approximatesa particularparadigm.In this sense, it is simply a variant on what is perhapsthe most universaltool of legal reasoning.218 Second, to a considerableextent, the case for legal formalism is much strongerwhererules of primarybehaviorare concernedthanit is when we are dealing with rules of legal method.Whencourtsadopt"all things considered" tests for the governanceof primarybehavior,serious questionscan be raised about whether similarly situatedpersons are in fact treatedalike.219But it is hardto see how the equalitynormis offended,at least to anythingapproaching the same degree, when an issue of statutoryinterpretationis resolved in one case using one set of interpretativetools and a different issue of statutory interpretationis resolved in anothercase using other interpretativetools. As long as the outcome of each exercise of statutoryinterpretationis applied 215. See NLRB v. United Food & CommercialWorkersUnion, 484 U.S. 112, 133-34 (1987) (Scalia, J., concurring)(applaudingthe Courtfor abandoningthe limiting approachof Cardoza-Fonseca);Scalia, supra note 39. 216. See Scalia, supra note 214, at 1178-82 (criticizing multifactortests for transformingquestions of law into questions of fact and for insulatinglower courts from effective appellatereview). 217. T. Alexander Aleinikoff, ConstitutionalLaw in the Age of Balancing, 96 YALEL.J. 943, 945 (1987). 218. See EDWARD H. LEVI,AN INTRODUCTION TOLEGALREASONING 1-2 (1949). 219. Scalia, supra note 214. at 1178. 1992] Executive Precedent 1027 consistently,the individualsprimarilyaffectedwill generallyperceivethatthey are being treatedequally. Third, the claim that Chevronallows the SupremeCourt to control the behaviorof lower courts, whereasthe executive precedentmodel would not, cannot be based on the Chevrondoctrineas we currentlyknow it-where the two-step frameworkis ignoredas often as it is followed, and when followed, is applied in several differentversions. But even if the Courtwere to adhere to a "pure"version of Chevron,there would still be ample opportunitiesfor manipulation,most prominentlythroughspuriousidentificationsof "specific intentions"or "plain"statutorymeanings.Thus,even thoughChevronis more formalisticthanthe executive precedentmodel, it too cannotconstrainwillfulness in the lower courts. To be sure, there is no basis for believing that the executive precedentmodel would impose greater constraintson lower courts than would a rigorously and consistentlyapplied Chevron.But I do think it likely thatthe decision to deferunderthe executive precedentmodel would be made in a more candid manner,with more revealingreasonsgiven in support of judicial outcomes. The relevant choice, therefore, may not be between constrainedand unconstrainedjudicial decisions, but between more or less judicial candor. Finally, I seriously doubt whetherit would ever be possible to decide all deference questions without being drawn into some type of contextual or multivariateinquiry,call it "pragmatism" or "practicalreasoning"or whatever.220As Judge Stephen Breyer has observed, "thereare too many different types of circumstances,includingdifferentstatutes,differentkinds of application, differentsubstantiveregulatoryor administrativeproblems,and different legal posturesin which cases arrive, to allow 'proper'judicial attitudesabout The questions of law to be reducedto any single simple verbal formula."221 fact that the Courtis now creatingvarious ad hoc exceptions and alternative formulationsof the Chevron doctrine suggests the beginnings of a process whereby the apparentsimplicity of Chevronis tempered with a variety of qualifyingrules. Whenwe startwith the two-stepChevronframeworkandthen create these exceptions, we end up with a crazy patchworkthat lacks any internalcoherence.Theexecutiveprecedentmodel,by admittinga widervariety of variablesin a more contextualizedrelationshipat the outset, can avoid the need for this kind of improvisedstructure. The extrinsic reasonfor wantingto constrainjudicial discretionby formal rules is that this would enhancethe ability of agencies to change the law. It is no accidentthatmanyof the principaldefendersof Chevron-including Justice 220. See RICHARD THEPROBLEMS A. POSNER, OFJURISPRUDENCE 286-309 (1990) (urgingpragmatic approachto statutoryinterpretation);William N. Eskridge,Jr.& Philip P. Frickey,StatutoryInterpretation as Practical Reasoning, 42 STAN.L. REV.319 (1990). 221. Breyer,supra note 175, at 373. 1028 The Yale Law Journal [Vol. 101: 969 Scalia and Judges Starrand Silberman222-allserved in the first Reagan Administration, when an aggressively conservative executive branch sought widespreadchange in the law and encounteredresistancefrom both Congress and the judiciary.These defendersendorseChevronas a tool for translatingthe electoral mandateof the Presidentinto legal reform,therebyovercomingthe resistance of the other two branchesof government. This rationale for Chevron,however,is obviously limited to a particular set of historicalcircumstances-circumstancesthat have alreadybeen at least in partsupersededby the appointmentof increasingnumbersof federaljudges by PresidentsReaganandBush. Whatis neededis a formulathatstrikesa more enduringbalancebetweenexecutive, legislative,andjudicialperspectives,and between the forces of change and stability. The executiveprecedentmodelenvisionsa largerrole for thejudiciarythan does the original version of Chevron.However,as previouslyindicated,this largerrole is necessary if courts are to performtheir traditionalfunction of On the other hand, I do not think checking administrativeabuses of power.223 that the discretionarynatureof the executive precedentmodel would cause courts to engage in wholesale substitutionof judgmentfor agency interpretations. Otherrules groundedin judicial self-governance,most prominentlythe understandingthat courts must follow precedentsof superiorcourts and the doctrineof staredecisis, exert a powerfulinfluence over the mannerin which courts resolve legal controversies. There is no reason why the deference doctrine, understoodas a form of respect given to legal interpretationsby anotherbranchof governmentof coordinateconstitutionalstatus, should not also exert an importantinfluence over judicial behavior. To be sure, by stressing the importanceof reliance factors such as longstandingandconsistentagencyinterpretation,contemporaneousinterpretation, and congressional ratification, the executive precedentmodel is also more resistant to rapid change in law than is Chevron.But again, I think this is healthy.Chevronis a doctrinefor Jacobeans:the resultsof a single Presidential election are a sufficient cause for wholesale modificationsin the law, with no offsetting incentive for stabilityor protectionof relianceinterests.Surely,it is ratherodd for Whiggishconservativeslike JusticeScalia-who speakglowingly of legal formalism because it promotespredictabilityin the law,224and who eloquently defend a strict separationof powers in order to prevent undue concentrationsof power that pose a threatto liberty and private rights225-to endorse Jacobeanmeasures. 222. See Scalia, supra note 39; Silberman,supranote44; Starr,supra note 34; see also JudicialReview of AdministrativeAction in a ConservativeEra, 39 ADMIN.L. REV.353 (1987) (paneldiscussion including Judge Starr and RichardWillard,a Justice Departmentofficial in the Reagan Administration). 223. See supra text accompanyingnotes 117-22. 224. Scalia, supra note 214, at 1179. 225. Morrison v. Olson, 487 U.S. 654, 697 (1988) (Scalia, J., dissenting). 1992] Executive Precedent 1029 The executive precedent model would strike a better balance between stabilityand change.By giving greaterdeferenceto longstanding,contemporaneous, and ratified agency interpretations,it would introducea bias in favor of stability,and would give a measureof protectionto the relianceintereststhat But this model would not rule out these interpretationshave generated.226 reasons for that the change,provided changeareclearlyarticulatedandthe new with is consistent the interpretation statutoryframework.Thus, it would not "freeze"the law or precludelegal developmentin responseto changedperceptions of policy, whethercaused by Presidentialelections or otherwise. 2. Consequencesfor Agencies When we turn from the consequencesfor judicial behaviorto the effects on agency behavior,the balance sheet wholly favors the executive precedent model. The Chevronframeworkessentially providesno incentives for agency behavior.It focuses at both steps one and two almost exclusively on variables relevant only to judicial functioning.The executive precedentmodel, in contrast,pays equal attentionto the caliberand qualityof the agency's precedent, and by making the weight of the agency's precedentrelevant to the decision to defer,providesincentivesfor agenciesto engage in certaintypes of behavior ratherthan others.Three incentives,in particular,would be introducedby the executive precedentapproach. The first is the incentive to maintain a consistent position over time. Consistency is desirableinsofar as it promotesequalityof treatmentbetween similarlysituatedparties,protectsrelianceinterests,andrendersadministrative actionmorepredictable,therebyallowingprivatepartiesto engagein meaningful planning.227 Consistency may also reduce "rentseeking" in the form of of expenditures resources designed to influence agencies to change their interpretationsof the law.228 On the other hand, a rigid rule of "first in time, first in right" would eliminate one of the advantages of using agencies to implement law: the possibility of modifying policy over time as experience accumulates and conditionsand publicperceptionschange.And a rule makingthe first interpretation controllingmight induce excessive expendituresto influence the initial constructionof the law. The executive precedentmodel strikes an appropriate 226. See Monaghan,supra note 147, at 751-52 (practice of judicial adherenceto precedentfosters conservative values). 227. It is no coincidence that these are some of the same values served by formal rules of law. See Scalia, supra note 39. For traditionaladministrativelaw statementsendorsinggreateragency consistency, & STEWART, see, e.g., BREYER supra note 192; 4 DAVIS,supra note 6, ? 20:11. 228. This point was suggested to me by my colleague Keith Hylton. See Keith Hylton, Doctrinal Efficiency and LaborLaw (Aug. 1991) (unpublishedmanuscripton file with author)(discussingpossible rent-seekingresponses to frequentchanges in National LaborRelations Board doctrine). 1030 The Yale Law Journal [Vol. 101: 969 balance between these concernsby demandingeither agency consistency or a persuasive explanationfor change as a condition for deference. The second relevantincentive is the attemptto strive for harmonyamong differentagencies. It is always difficultto maintaincoherencein oursprawling bureaucraticstate. Variousmechanismsfor centralizedcontrolexist, including and preclearanceof regulationsby the Office of Managementand Budget229 of the Solicitor General.230 But the preclearance judicial appealsby centripetal forces tend always to overpowerthe centrifugal.The idea thatagencyinterpretations that conflict with other agency interpretationswill lose a measureof judicial deference adds anothersmall incentive for internalcoherence. The third is the incentive to providereasonedexplanationsfor statutory thatagency factfindingand policymaking interpretations.It is "anomalous"231 is today subject to searchingreview underthe "hardlook" doctrine, which requiresa carefulconsiderationof relevantfactorsand an answerto prominent UnderChevron,however,agency interpretaobjections by affected parties.232 tions of law are subjectto automaticdeferenceunless the court finds that the matterhas been clearlyresolvedby Congress.Paradoxically,therefore,official doctrine requires more searchingjudicial review on questions of fact and policy-where agenciesare traditionallythoughtto enjoya comparativeadvantange-than on questionsof law,wherethe traditionalview was thatcourtsheld the edge.233 One of the promisingfeaturesof the executive precedentmodel is that it would tend to incorporatesome of the featuresof "hardlook"review into the process of consideringwhetherto give deferenceto executive interpretations of statutes.The strengthof an agency precedentwould to a significantextent be a functionof how carefullythe agencyconsideredthe questionof interpretation, respondedto objections,and offeredreasonsin supportof the interpretation adopted.In effect, an agency that has given a "hardlook" at a question of interpretationwill be entitled to greaterdeferencethan an agency that has given only cursoryconsiderationto the issue. 3. Consequencesfor Congress Finally, it is worth speculating briefly about what sorts of incentives a rigorously enforced Chevron would create for Congress. It is unlikely that Congresswould standidly by in responseto a majorrealignmentin the division of powers that enhanced the executive branch's ability to institute policy 229. As requiredby Exec. OrderNo. 12,291, 3 C.F.R. 127 (1981), reprintedin 5 U.S.C. ? 601 (1982). See ChristopherC. DeMuth& Douglas H. Ginsburg,WhiteHouse Reviewof AgencyRulemaking,99 HARV. L. REV. 1075 (1986). 230. See 28 C.F.R. ? 0.20(b) (1991). 231. Breyer,supra note 175, at 397. 232. See sources cited supra note 195. 233. See Diver, supra note 11, at 574. 1992] Executive Precedent 1031 changesandminimizedthe role of the courtsin checkingadministrativeabuses. One would expect some combinationof threeresponsesfrom Congress,none of which in my view would be desirable. congressionalresponsewouldbe to enact Perhapsthe most straightforward If longer and more detailed statutes.234 the only things courts will enforce are specific directives,then Congresswould try to supplyas many specific directives as possible. While some mighthail this developmentas a healthyreasserthere is tion of the "legislative power" by its constitutionalinstrument,235 reason to believe that an upsurgein the specificity of legislation would lead There can to bad policy236and more influence by private interestgroups.237 be little doubt that it would add to the complexity-and incomprehensibility-of the legal system. Anotherpossiblecongressionalresponsewouldbe to seek greaterinfluence over administrativeagencies.This mighttake the formof directrestrictionson Presidentialauthorityover agency heads. Morelikely, it would manifestitself in the formof moreintensiveoversighthearingsandcontactsbetweencongresThe result, again, would be an erosion sional staff and agency personnel.238 of coherence and greaterinterestgroup influence.239 Third, Congress might attemptto overrule Chevrondirectly,perhapsby As previouslyindicated, enacting some form of the BumpersAmendment.240 I think that Congresshas the constitutionalpower to directcourtsto adandon the Chevronapproach.But such a responsewould very likely take the form of an overreaction-as the BumpersAmendmentsurelywouldbe-and at the very least would create a troubling precedent for congressional interventionin matterstraditionallyleft to evolutionaryjudicial development. Of course, the chance of these responsesoccurringwill be reducedif the Courtcontinues to create exceptions to the Chevrondoctrineand to ignore it altogether.Nevertheless,therecan be little doubtthat the executive precedent approach-which is more consistent with historic practice and promises to resultin a morebalancedjudicialrole-would provideeven greaterassurances against undesirablecongressionalreactions. 234. Hertz, supra note 113, at 1675. 235. See, e.g., JOHNH. ELY,DEMOCRACY AND DISTRUST131-33 (1980) (criticizing excessive delegation of legislative authorityon democratictheory grounds);J. Skelly Wright,BeyondDiscretionary Justice, 81 YALEL.J. 575, 584-86 (1972) (urgingrevival of nondelegationdoctrine). 236. See BRUCEA. ACKERMAN & WILLIAM T. HASSLER, CLEANCOAL/DIRTY AIR(1981) (arguing that highly detailed provisions in 1977 Clean Air Act Amendmentsimpeded EPA's ability to develop effective policy). 237. See JerryL. Mashaw,Prodelegation:WhyAdministratorsShouldMakePolitical Decisions, 1 J.L. ECON.& ORGANIZATION 81 (1985) (public choice theory suggests that interestgroups will have greater influence in legislative arena than in administrativearena). 238. See Lazarus,supra note 118. 239. See HaroldH. Bruff,LegislativeFormality,Administrative Rationality,63 TEX.L. REV.207 (1984) (discussing interest group influence exerted throughcongressionaloversight process). 240. See supra note 111. 1032 The Yale Law Journal [Vol. 101: 969 VI. CONCLUSION From the perspective of this Article, the long controversyover judicial deferenceto administrativeinterpretationsof statutescan be seen as a rivalry between two competing models: the mandatorydeference model and the discretionary deference model. The rivalry has been largely unconscious becausethe assumptionsof the mandatorydeferencemodel are often unstated, and the theoreticalbasis for the discretionarydeferencemodel has neverbeen previously articulated.Still, we can see these ideas strugglingfor dominance in judicial practice. In the pre-Chevronera, the two models coexisted uneasily.Courtsapplied the mandatorydeferencemodelto interpretations backedby expressdelegations of regulatoryauthorityfromCongress.But in the absenceof an expressdelegation, they appliedsomethingthatin retrospectlooks very muchlike the discretionary deferencemodel-examining variouscontextualfactorsthat could be appliedjust as easily to a precedentof a court of coordinatejurisdictionas to the constructionof an executive branchagency. The Chevronera on paper representsa rejectionof the discretionaryapproachand an embraceof a pure mandatoryregime.Now, however,the realmof mandatorydeferencehas vastly expandedto include a presumptionof delegationin all cases where a federal statute is ambiguous or unclear.As we have seen, however, in practice the discretionaryapproachhas lived on, in the shadowsof Chevron,and in considerable tension with its expandeddelegationtheory. Chevron's many failings are largely those of the mandatorydeference model that it incorporates.Althoughthe idea of expressdelegationis straightforwardenough,the conceptof an implieddelegationof interpretativeauthority is difficultto characterizeas a congressionalcommand.The focus on delegation also makes the decision about whetherto defer subordinateto the resolution of a questionof judicialinterpretation: Did Congress(constructively)delegate, or did it not? In this fashion, considerationof the executive view becomes ensnaredin controversiesover the legitimate scope of judicial interpretation. Finally, the idea of delegationrequiresthat deferencebe viewed in either/or terms:eitherCongressdelegatedauthority,or it did not; no intermediatepossibilities make sense. The either/ornatureof the mandatorydeference theory based on delegated power pushes the doctrinetowardextremes of either too little or too much deference. I have argued that a better solution to the uneasy mixture of the pre-Chevronperiod would have been to move to a pure discretionaryregime, whatI havecalled the executiveprecedentmodel.The idea of delegationwould not disappearin such a regime. It would simply revertto its original scope of express delegation, and it would become one of several factors that courts would examine in determiningthe "strength"of an executive precedent.Becausethe practiceof deferenceunderthe executiveprecedentmodelis grounded 1992] Executive Precedent 1033 in a conception of the judicial power ratherthan in a fiction of delegation,it avoids the major theoreticalfailings of the Chevrondoctrine. In addition,it allows courtsto considervariousattributesof the executive decisionthatseem undeniablyrelevant to the question of how much weight it should be given: such as whetherthe agency's interpretationis supportedby carefulreasoning, whetherits interpretationhas generatedrelianceintereststhatshouldbe protected, andwhetherits constructionhas been approvedby Congress.The executive precedentmodel also permitsa flexible responseto the questionof deference, allowingcourtsto give variousdegreesof deferenceto executiveinterpretations, dependingon the strengthof the contextualfactorsinvolved and on the court's conviction about the clarity of the statuteas an original matter. Like its close cousin, the doctrine of judicial precedent,the model of executive precedentdoes not admitof easy or pat answers.But this does not mean it has nothing to say about what variablesare relevant to its operation and why they are significant. In this respect,one of the significantbenefits of the executive precedentmodel is that it might teach us somethingabout the practiceof followingjudicialprecedent,of whichlegal academicshaveunfortunately had far too little to say. [Vol. 101: 969 The Yale Law Journal 1034 APPENDIX Agency Deference Cases in the Supreme Court 1981-1990 Terms Case Chevron Agency Step 1 Interpretion Framework or Accepted? Followed? Step 2 Traditional Factors 1990 TERM 1. Pauley v. Bethenergy Mines, Inc., 111 S. Ct. 2524 (1991) Y Y 2. Gregory v. Ashcroft, N N N/A None 3. LittonFin. PrintingDiv. v. NLRB, 111 S. Ct. 2215 (1991) Y N N/A Expertise 4. Rustv. Sullivan, 111 S. Ct. 1759 (1991) Y Y S2 Longstanding Well-reasoned 5. AmericanHosp. Ass'n v. NLRB, 111 S. Ct. 1539 (1991) Y Y S1 Well-reasoned 6. CottageSav. Ass'n v. Commissioner,111 S. Ct. 1503 (1991) Y N N/A Longstanding Ratification 7. Norfolk& WesternRy. Co. v. American TrainDispatchersAss'n, 111 S. Ct 1156 (1991) Y Y S1 None 8. International Union,UAWv. Johnson Controls,Inc., 111 S. Ct. 1196 (1991) Y N N/A None 9. EEOCv. ArabianAm. Oil Co., 111 S. Ct. 1227 (1991) N N N/A Legis./Interp. S2 Expertise Longstanding 111 S. Ct. 2395 (1991) Longstanding Contemporaneous Well-reasoned 10. Demarest v. Manspeaker, 111 S. Ct. 599 (1991) N Y S1 Ratification 11. Mobil Oil Exploration & Producing Southeast Inc. v. United Dist. Cos., Y Y S1 None N Y S1 None Y Y S2 None 111 S. Ct. 615 (1991) 1989 TERM 12. Maislin Indus., U.S. v. Primary Steel, Inc., 110 S. Ct. 2759 (1990) 13. PensionBenefit Guar.Corp.v. LTV Corp., 110 S. Ct. 2668 (1990) 1992] 1035 Executive Precedent 14. Sullivanv. Stroop, 110 S. Ct. 2499 (1990) Y Y S1 None 15. Fort StewartSch. v. FederalLabor RelationsAuth.,495 U.S. 641 (1990) Y Y S1 None 16. Davis v. United States, 495 U.S. 472 (1990) Y N N/A Longstanding Contemporaneous Ratification 17. Departmentof Treasuryv. Federal LaborRelationsAuth.,494 U.S. 922 (1990) N Y S1 None 18. NLRBv. CurtinMathesonScientific, Inc., 494 U.S. 775 (1990) Y N N/A Longstanding 19. AdamsFruitCo. v. Barrett, 494 U.S. 638 (1990) N Y S1 None 20. Crandonv. United States, 494 U.S. 152 (1990) N N N/A None 21. Sullivanv. Everhart, 494 U.S. 26 (1990) Y Y S2 None 22. Dole v. UnitedSteelworkers, 494 U.S. 26 (1990) N Y S1 None 23. Sullivanv. Zebley, 493 U.S. 521 (1990) N Y S1 Ratification 24. United Statesv. GoodyearTire& RubberCo., 493 U.S. 132 (1990) Y Y N/A None 25. Chesapeake& Oh. Ry. Co. v. Schwalb,493 U.S. 40 (1990) y N N/A Longstanding 26. PublicEmployeesRetirementSys. v. Betts, 492 U.S. 158 (1989) N Y S1 Contemporaneous 27. PublicCitizenv. UnitedStatesDept. of Justice,491 U.S. 440 (1989) N N N/A Contemporaneous 28. MeadCorp.v. Tilley, 490 U.S. 714 (1989) Y Y S2 Longstanding 29. Robertsonv. MethowValleyCitizens Council,490 U.S. 332 (1989) Y N N/A Longstanding 30. Marshv. OregonNaturalResources Council,490 U.S. 360 (1989) Y N N/A None 31. Massachusettsv. Morash, 490 U.S. 107 (1989) y N N/A Longstanding 32. Coit IndependenceJointVenture v. FederalSav. & LoansIns. Corp., 489 U.S. 561 (1989) N N N/A None 1988 TERM Well-reasoned 1036 [Vol. 101: 969 The Yale Law Journal 33. Bowen v. Georgetown Univ. Hosp., 488 U.S. 204 (1989) N N N/A Longstanding 34. Pittston Coal Group v. Sebben, 488 U.S. 105 (1989) N Y S1 None 35. Communications Workers v. N N N/A Longstanding 36. Mississippi Power & Light Co. v. Mississippi ex rel. Moore, 487 U.S. 354 (1988) Y N N/A None 37. Huffman v. Western Nuclear, Inc., 486 U.S. 663 (1988) Y N N/A 38. K Mart Corp. v. Cartier, Inc., 486 U.S. 281 (1988)241 Y/N Y S2/S1 None 39. FERC v. Martin Exploration Management Co., 486 U.S. 204 (1988) Y N N/A None 40. EEOC v. Commercial Office Prods. Co., 486 U.S. 107 (1988) Y N N/A None 41. Edward J. DeBartolo Corp. v. Florida Gulf Coast Bldg. & Constr. Trades Council, N N N/A None Y N N/A None 43. Traynor v. Turnage, 485 U.S. 535 (1988) Y N N/A Longstanding Ratification 44. Federal Labor Relations Auth. v. N N N/A None 45. Bethesda Hosp. Ass'n v. Bowen, 485 U.S. 399 (1988) N Y S1 None 46. Etsi Pipeline Project v. Missouri, 484 U.S. 495 (1988) N Y S1 None 47. Honig v. Doe, 484 U.S. 305 (1988) Y Y S2 None 48. NLRB v. United Food & Commercial Y Y S2 Longstanding N N/A None 1987 TERM Beck, 487 U.S. 735 (1988) Post hoc rationalization 485 U.S. 568 (1988) 42. Regents of the Univ. of Cal. v. Public Employment Relations Bd., 485 U.S. 589 (1988) Aberdeen Proving Ground, 485 U.S. 409 (1988) Workers Union, Local 23, 484 U.S. 112 (1987) 1986 TERM 49. Utah Div. of State Lands v. N United States, 482 U.S. 193 (1987) 241. For purposes of tabulation,this case has been counted as "Y" and "S2." 1992] 1037 Executive Precedent 50. Bowen v. Yuckert, 482 U.S. 137 (1987) Y N N/A Ratification 51 Fall RiverDyeing & FinishingCorp. v. NLRB,482 U.S. 27 (1987) Y N N/A None Bhd. of Elec. 52. NLRBv. International Workers,Local 340, 481 U.S. 573 (1987) N N N/A None 53. Lukhardv. Reed, 481 U.S. 368 (1987) Y N N/A None 54. INS v. Cardoza-Fonseca, 480 U.S. 421 (1987) N Y S1 Longstanding 55. Clarkev. SecuritiesIndus.Ass'n, 479 U.S. 388 (1987) Y Y S2 None 56. Wrightv. City Of Roanoke Redev.& Hous.Auth., 479 U.S. 418 (1987) Y N N/A None 57. AnsoniaBd. of Educ.v. Philbrook, 479 U.S. 60 (1986) N N N/A None 58. CommodityFuturesTradingComm'n v. Schor,478 U.S. 833 (1986) Y N N/A Expertise Longstanding Ratification 59. Local 28 of Sheet MetalWorkers' Int'l Ass'n v. EEOC, 478 U.S. 421 (1986) Y N N/A Longstanding Contemporaneous 60. JapanWhalingAss'n v. American CetaceanSoc'y, 478 U.S. 221 (1986) Y Y S2 None 61. UnitedStatesDep't Of Transp. v. ParalyzedVeteransof Am., 477 U.S. 597 (1986) Y Y S1 Longstanding 62. Atkinsv. Rivera, 477 U.S. 154 (1986) Y N N/A None 63. MeritorSav. Bankv. Vinson, 477 U.S. 57 (1986) Y N N/A None 64. Youngv. CommunityNutritionInst., 476 U.S. 974 (1986) Y Y S2 Longstanding Ratification 65. Bowen v. AmericanHosp. Ass'n, 476 U.S. 610 (1986) N N N/A None 66. FTCv. IndianaFed'n of Dentists,476 U.S. 447 (1986) Y N N/A None 67. FDICv. PhiladelphiaGearCorp., 476 U.S. 426 (1986) Y N N/A Longstanding Ratification 1985TERM 1038 [Vol. 101: 969 The Yale Law Journal 68. United States v. City of Fulton, 475 U.S. 657 (1986) Y Y S2 None 69. NLRB v. Financial Inst. Employees, Local 1182, N N N/A None N Y S1 None Y Y S2 Ratification N N/A Expertise 475 U.S. 192 (1986) 70. Board of Governors of the Fed. Reserve Sys. v. Dimension Fin. Corp., 474 U.S. 361 (1986) 71. United States v. Riverside Bayview Homes, Inc., 474 U.S. 121 (1985) 1984 TERM 72. Pattern Makers' League of N. Am. v. NLRB, 473 U.S. 95 (1985) Y 73. Jean v. Nelson, 472 U.S. 846 (1985) Y N N/A None 74. Cornelius v. Nutt, 472 U.S. 648 (1985) Y N N/A None 75. Central States S.E. & S.W. Areas Y N N/A None 76. Western Air Lines v. Criswell, 472 U.S. 400 (1985) Y N N/A Longstanding 77. Mountain States Tel. & Tel. Co. Y N N/A Longstanding Longstanding Pension Fund v. Central Transp., Inc., 472 U.S. 559 (1985) v. Pueblo of Santo Ana, 472 U.S. 237 (1985) Contemporaneous 78. Lowe v. SEC, 472 U.S. 181 (1985) N N N/A None 79. Connecticut Dep't of Income Maintenance v. Heckler, 471 U.S. 524 (1985) Y N N/A Longstanding 80. INS v. Rios-Pineda, 471 U.S. 444 (1985) Y N N/A None 81. Tony & Susan Alamo Found. v. Secretary of Labor, 471 U.S. 290 (1985) Y N N/A Longstanding 82. United States v. Locke, 471 U.S. 84 (1985) Y N N/A None 83. Bennett v. Kentucky Dep't of Educ., 470 U.S. 656 (1985) Y N N/A None 84. Heckler v. Turner, 470 U.S. 184 (1985) Y N N/A Longstanding Ratification 85. NAACP v. Hampton County Election Comm'n, 470 U.S. 166 (1985) Y N N/A None 1992] Executive Precedent 1039 86. ChemicalMfrs. Ass'n v. NationalResourcesDefense Council 470 U.S. 116 (1985) Y Y S2 Longstanding 87. NLRBv. Action Automotive,Inc., 469 U.S. 490 (1985) Y N N/A None 88. Alexanderv. Choate, 469 U.S. 287 (1985) y N N/A None 89. LawrenceCountyv. Lead-Deadwood Sch. Dist., 469 U.S. 256 (1985) Y N N/A None 90. UnitedStatesv. Boyle, 469 U.S. 241 (1985) Y N N/A None 91. IrvingIndep,Sch. Dist. v. Tatro, 468 U.S. 883 (1984) Y N/A N/A None 92. SecuritiesIndus.Ass'n v. Board of Governorsof Fed. ReserveSys., 468 U.S. 207 (1984) Y N/A N/A Longstanding Legis./Interp. 93. SecuritiesIndus.Ass'n v. Board of Governorsof Fed. ReserveSys., 468 U.S. 137 (1984) N N N/A Longstanding Post hoc rationalization 94. Sure-tan,Inc. v. NLRB, 467 U.S. 883 (1984) Y N/A N/A None 95. ChevronU.S.A., Inc. v. NationalResourcesDefenseCouncil 467 U.S. 837 (1984) Y Y S2 Expertise 96. UnitedStatesv. Morton, 467 U.S. 822 (1984) Y N/A N/A Legis./nterp. 97. SEC v. JerryT. O'Brien,Inc., 467 U.S. 735 (1984) Y N/A N/A Longstanding 98. CapitalCities Cable,Inc. v. Crisp,467 U.S. 691 (1984) Y N/A N/A None 99. AluminumCo. of Am. v. Central LincolnPeoples'Util. Dist., 467 U.S. 380 (1984) Y N/A N/A Expertise Contemporaneous 100. ICCv. AmericanTruckingAss'ns, Inc., 467 U.S. 354 (1984) Y N/A N/A None 101. EscondidoMut.WaterCo. v. La Jolla Band of MissionIndians, 466 U.S. 765 (1984) N N/A N/A Longstanding 102. NLRBv. City DisposalSys., Inc., 465 U.S. 822 (1984) Y N/A N/A Longstanding Expertise 1983Term Ratification 1040 [Vol. 101: 969 The Yale Law Journal 103. Consolidated Rail Corp. v. Darrone, 465 U.S. 624 (1984) Y N/A N/A Contemporaneous Ratification 104. NLRB v. Bildisco & Bildisco, 465 U.S. 513 (1984) N N/A N/A Expertise 105. Grove City College v. Bell, 465 U.S. 555 (1984) Y N/A N/A Longstanding Ratification 106. Dickman v. Commissioner, 465 U.S. 330 (1984) Y N/A N/A None 107. Commissioner v. Engle, 464 U.S. 206 (1984) N N/A N/A None 108. INS v. Phinpathya, 464 U.S. 183 (1984) N N/A N/A None 109. Bureau of Alcohol, Tobacco & Firearms v. FLRA, N N/A N/A None 464 U.S. 89 (1983) 1982 TERM 110. Rice v. Rehner, 463 U.S. 713 (1983) Y N/A N/A Contemporaneous 111. Guardians Ass'n v. Civil Serv. Y N/A N/A Longstanding Comm'n of N.Y., 463 U.S. 582 (1983) Contemporaneous 112. Belknap, Inc. v. Hale, 463 U.S. 491 (1983) N N/A N/A None 113. Public Serv. Comm'n v. N N/A N/A None Y N/A N/A Longstanding 115. NLRB v. Transportation Management Corp., 462 U.S. 393 (1983) Y N/A N/A Longstanding 116. Bell v. New Jersey, 461 U.S. 773 (1983) Y N/A N/A None 117. Bill Johnson's Restaurants, Inc. N N/A N/A Expertise Mid-Louisiana Gas, 463 U.S. 319 (1983) 114. National Ass'n Of Greeting Card Publishers v. United States Postal Serv., 462 U.S. 810 (1983) v. NLRB, 461 U.S. 731 (1983) 118. Morrison-Knudsen Constr. Co. v. Longstanding Y N/A N/A Longstanding Y N/A N/A Ratification Director, Office of Workers' Compensation Programs, 461 U.S. 624 (1983) 119. Bob Jones Univ. v. United States, 461 U.S. 574 (1983) 1992] Executive Precedent 1041 120. Heckler v. Campbell, 461 U.S. 458 (1983) Y N/A N/A Legis./Interp. 121. American Paper Inst, Inc. v. American Elec. Power Serv. Corp., Y N/A N/A Contemporaneous 122. Commissioner v. Tufts, 461 U.S. 300 (1983) Y N/A N/A Contemporaneous 123. Metropolitan Edison Co. v. NLRB, 460 U.S. 693 (1983) Y N/A N/A None 124. Bowsher v. Merck & Co., 460 U.S. 824 (1983) N N/A N/A Longstanding 125. Fidelity Fed. Sav. & Loan Ass'n v. De La Cuesta, 458 U.S. 141 (1982) Y N/A N/A Longstanding 126. Schweiker v. Hogan, 457 U.S. 569 (1982) Y N/A N/A None 127. Blum v. Bacon, 457 U.S. 132 (1982) Y N/A N/A None 128. North Haven Bd. of Educ. v. Bell, 456 U.S. 512 (1982) Y N/A N/A Longstanding Ratification 461 U.S. 402 (1983) 1981 TERM Interagency disagreement 129. Herwig v. Ray, 455 U.S. 265 (1982) Y N/A N/A Legis./Interp. 130. United States v. Vogel Fertilizer Co., 455 U.S. 16 (1982) N N/A N/A Longstanding Ratification Legis./Interp. 131. United States v. Clark, 454 U.S. 555 (1982) Y N/A N/A Longstanding 132. Charles D. Bonnano Linen Serv. Y N/A N/A Longstanding Well-reasoned N/A N/A Longstanding v. NLRB, 454 U.S. 404 (1982) 133. NLRB v. Hendricks County Rural Elec. Membership Corp., V 454 U.S. 170 (1981) Ratification 134. Ridgway v. Ridgway, 454 U.S. 46 (1981) V N/A N/A None 135. Federal Election Comm'n v. V N/A N/A Longstanding Well-reasoned Democratic Senatorial Campaign Comm., 454 U.S. 27 (1981) Expertise