Baingio Pinna What is the Meaning of Shape? 1. On the Shape The shape of an object is a primary condition fundamental for our lives. Shape is the primary visual attribute among others (color, shade, lighting) that elicits unambiguous identification due mainly to its constancy. Another relevant perceptual property is its uniqueness. Indeed, it is unique and much more informative than any other object properties, i.e. color, shading (depth) and lighting (illumination). Shapes are not usually regarded as a creation of our brain but appear veridically, as part of the physical world. As a matter of fact, the core meaning of shape is one of the main interests and targets of mathematics (from topology and mathematical analysis to trigonometry and geometry) aimed to describe and study the main properties of shapes and the relationship among them. No other property has been studied from so many different perspectives and so deeply as shape (see Palmer, 1999; Pizlo, 2008). It is useful to distinguish between shape in the mathematical sense (i.e. as an ideal object) and shape as encoded in the physical world. In the former sense, objects are ontologically neutral and not always perceptually possible and relevant. 1.1. The Invention of the Square Among all the known shapes, the square is a unique and special one. The emergence of the square and its geometrical/phenomenal components (sides and angles) is the consequence of the way four segments go together according to the Gestalt grouping and organization principles. Phenomenally, its singularity, homogeneity, regularity and symmetry are among the strongest of all the known shapes. The circle also shows unique properties, but unlike the square it is present in nature (e.g. the full moon and the sun). The square is instead a human invention. It is a pure creation of the human mind. The invention of the wheel (i.e. the circle) is likely one of the most important inventions of all time. It was at the root of the Industrial Revolution. The oldest known wheel was attributed to the ancient Mesopotamian culture of Sumer around 3500 B.C., but it is supposed to have been invented much earlier. If the potter’s wheels were the very first wheels, the invention of the square was GESTALT THEORY © 2011(ISSN 0170-057 X) Vol. 33, No.3/4, 383-422 GESTALT THEORY, Vol. 33, No.3/4 likely as important as the wheel. The square is, in fact, a basic shape used to measure any kind of object, shape or space. Every shape either regular or irregular is measured in squares (m2) or in the 3-D version of the square, cubes (m3). The square is the unit and, more generally, the ‘brick’ of all the other shapes. By moving around the gaze and focusing the attention on the shapes, one notices that almost everything has a square shape. Most of the human artifacts are made up of squares or its variations. For instance, houses are composed of windows, floors, tables, televisions and doors that are squares or square-like shapes. As concerns these special phenomenal properties, we will study the meaning of shape starting from the square. 1.2. The Shape before the “Shape”: Grouping and Figure-Ground Segregation Gestalt psychologists were the first to study and develop a theory of shape, considered as an emergent quality. They studied the shape mostly in terms of grouping and figure-ground segregation. (Other Gestalt approaches to shape perception will be discussed in section 3.3.) Rubin (1915, 1921) studied the problem of shape formation in terms of figureground segregation, by asking what appears as a figure and what as a background. He discovered the following general figure-ground principles: surroundedness, size, orientation, contrast, symmetry, convexity, and parallelism. Rubin also suggested the following main phenomenal attributes, belonging to the figure but not to the background. (i) The figure takes on the shape traced by the contour, implying that the contour belongs unilaterally to the figure (see Nakayama & Shimojo, 1990; Spillmann, 2012; Spillmann & Ehrenstein, 2004), not to the background. (ii) Its color/brightness is perceived full like a surface and denser than the same physical color/brightness on the background that appear instead transparent and empty. (iii) The figure appears closer to the observer than the background. Wertheimer (1923, see also Spillmann, 2012) approached this problem in terms of grouping. The questions he answered is: how do the elements in the visual field ‘go together’ to form an integrated percept? How do individual elements create larger wholes? He studied some basic grouping principles useful to answer the previous questions. They are: proximity, similarity, good continuation, closure, symmetry, convexity, prägnanz, past experience, common fate, and parallelism. It is reasonable to consider that figure–ground segregation must operate before grouping (Hoffman & Richards, 1984; Palmer, 1999). For example, dot elements on which grouping acts must be already segregated as a figure from the background, otherwise the visual system would not know which elements to group. Nevertheless, the same elements do not possess the figural properties of holistic organized and segregated figures; rather, they appear as elementary 384 Pinna, What is the Meaning of Shape? components necessary to create boundaries. They are not surfaces, but something similar to perceptual ‘bricks’ necessary to create something more holistic. In spite of the apparent differences between figure-ground segregation and grouping, what is phenomenally clear is that both dynamics are so intimately intertwined that a sharp distinction is likely impossible and maybe useless from a scientific point of view. Within Rubin’s and Wertheimer’s works, the problem of shape formation is approached in terms of the main conditions operating in two of the processes (grouping and figure-ground segregation) underlying but preceding the formation of the shape. For example, the unilateral belongingness of the boundaries can be considered as a shape issue before the “shape” meaning. It talked about shape but it did not explain its meaning. Similarly, even if the closure principle can describe the perception of a square, it cannot say anything about its properties and about the way its properties assign the special meanings we have previously described. Furthermore, it cannot explain the square variations described in the next sections. Even if Gestalt grouping and figure-ground principles are part of the problem of shape perception, they do not face directly this problem and, more importantly, they do not answer basic questions like: what is shape? What is its meaning? 2. General Methods 2.1. Subjects Different groups of 12 undergraduate students of architecture, design, linguistics participated in the experiments. Subjects had some basic knowledge of Gestalt psychology and visual illusions, but they were naive both to the stimuli and to the purpose of the experiments. They were male and female with normal or corrected-to-normal vision. 2.2. Stimuli The stimuli were the figures shown in the next sections. The overall sizes of the visual stimuli were ~3.5 deg visual angle. The figures were shown on a computer screen with ambient illumination from a Osram Daylight fluorescent light (250 lux, 5600° K). Stimuli were displayed on a 33 cm color CRT monitor (Sony GDM-F520 1600x1200 pixels, refresh rate 100 Hz), driven by a MacBook Pro computer with an NVIDIA GeForce 8600M GT. Viewing was binocular in the frontoparallel plane at a distance of 50 cm from the monitor. 2.3. Procedure Two methods, similar to those used by Gestalt psychologists, were used. 385 GESTALT THEORY, Vol. 33, No.3/4 Phenomenological task: The task of the subjects was to report spontaneously what they perceived by providing a complete description of the main visual property. The descriptions were provided by at least 10 out of 12 subjects and were reported concisely within the main text to aid the reader in the stream of argumentations. The descriptions were judged by three graduate students of linguistics, naive as to the hypotheses, to get a fair representation of the ones given by the observers. Subjects were allowed to make free comparisons, confrontations, afterthoughts, to see in different ways, distance, etc.; to match the stimulus with every other one. Variations and possible comparisons occurring during the free exploration were noted down by the experimenter. The selection of the stimuli with opposite conditions and controls and the possible comparisons among the stimuli prevent the problem of generating biased experiences. This is clearly shown by the differences in the results (see next sections). Scaling task: The subjects were instructed to rate (in percent) the descriptions of the specific attribute obtained in the phenomenological experiments. New groups of 12 subjects were instructed to scale the relative strength or salience (in percent) of the descriptions of the phenomenological task: “please rate whether this statement is an accurate reflection of your perception of the stimulus, on a scale from 100 (perfect agreement) to 0 (complete disagreement)”. Throughout the text we reported descriptions whose mean ratings were greater than 80. As concerns these tasks and procedure see Pinna, (2010a, b; Pinna & Albertazzi, 2011; Pinna & Sirigu, in press; Pinna & Reeves, 2009). 3. Squares, Rotated Square and Diamonds 3.1. Non-Square Shapes that Appear Like Squares Shape illusions are only apparently in contrast with the properties previously described: unambiguous identification, constancy, uniqueness and veridicality. These illusions are, in fact, considered to be exceptions visible under specific and rare conditions and, thus, ineffective for real life. The strong shape illusion, illustrated in Fig. 1a, was described like a large square with concave and convex sides. This description reveals a “distortion” that does not change the basic meaning of the square shape. In fact, the main shape even if distorted is still perceived like a square. Moreover, paradoxically the distortion reinforces and strengthens the perception of the square. In fact, the square is amodally seen as the whole shape supporting the perceived distortion. Conversely, the distortion is what elicits the amodal wholeness of the square (see Pinna, 2010b). This kind of phenomenal dynamics also occurs when the perceived distortion is not illusory but “real”, as shown in Fig. 1b. 386 Pinna, What is the Meaning of Shape? " ! # $ % ) ( ' & Fig. 1 Non-square shapes that appear like squares In more intense conditions in terms of distortion (see Figs. 1c-i), where the square and its sides or angles appear beveled, broken, crashed, gnawed, deliquescing, deformed, protruding, the main shape is again perceived as a square, while those specific descriptions reveal what happens to each square. They appear like “happenings” of a square (Pinna, 2010b; Pinna & Albertazzi, 2011). These changes and happenings can be seen as depending on or related to specific and !"#$%&'()''!"#$%#&'(#$$" “invisible” but perceptible causes affecting the shape and the material properties *(!+,'-,+(%,.%!/'/),0&,-(!1%2 of the square. They add visual meanings but do not really change the shape of the square, which is perceived like the amodal invariant shape supporting all those happenings (see also section 5.6). From a geometrical point of view, these are non-square shapes that appear like squares. These results suggest the following questions: Why do we perceive a square plus a happening in each of these cases, instead of a set of irregular shapes, one different from the other? What is the role of the happening and of other possible shape 387 GESTALT THEORY, Vol. 33, No.3/4 attributes in shape formation? Which properties influence and determine the meaning of shape? An answer to the first question was previously reported by Pinna (2010b). In the next sections, possible responses to the other questions will be proposed. We will first start by showing opposite conditions, where squares are perceived like nonsquare shapes, to understand the ways and under which conditions a square shape can be influenced and changed. 3.2. Squares that Appear Like Non-Square Shapes 3.2.1. Square Fig. 2a shows a square. The figure, here illustrated, appears like a “true” square, i.e. a shape that appears like a square tout court, a square without anything else. This one-word description, “square”, does not reveal any happening or any other relevant emerging attribute. Shape properties, like orientation, size and position, are left off, because, under these conditions, they are “invisible” or unnoticeable like the background. These omitted properties are superfluous. The word “square” seems to contain, in fact, everything to recreate exactly the same figure and, thus, does not need any further information. This square appears like the best example and the model of every “square”. It is worthwhile noticing that the omissions are important information useful to understand the phenomenology of shape perception. Related to our square, we can state that the more numerous are the omissions (invisible attributes), the better is the appearance as a model of this shape, or, conversely the less is the information described, the better is the squareness of the shape. We define as “phenomenal singularity” the instance of a shape that does not need to be defined by attributes and that correspond to a one-word description. In other words, the phenomenal singularity is the best instance of a specific shape. By asking naive subjects “draw a square” and, afterwards, “choose the square that is the most ‘square’ among those illustrated” (see Figs. 2a-c), we found that most of them (99%) represented the square exactly like the one of Fig. 2a and chose this figure as the best example of square among the three. These results suggest the following questions: What is the relationship between the descriptive and the phenomenal notion of shape? More particularly, what is the meaning of the term “square” when it denotes a singularity like the shape of the object perceived in Fig. 2a? By complementation, what is the meaning of the same term when it does not refer to a phenomenal singularity but emerges with visible attributes? What is the visual meaning of the square? What does this shape convey, express or reveal in the way it appears? 388 Pinna, What is the Meaning of Shape? 3.2.2. Rotated Square Fig. 2b represents an intermediate but crucial step in answering the previous questions. This figure is mostly described as a rotated square. Under these conditions, subjects introduced spontaneously information about orientation, thus, creating a two-word description. The rotation becomes now visible, noticeable like a figure. The exact orientation is, instead, not specified spontaneously in words. Only after asking them to describe the apparent direction and degree of rotation, our subjects reported ~10° anticlockwise. These results suggest a twofold perception: a “true” square plus something that happens to it, namely, the rotation. In other words, unlike Fig. 2a the square is, now, not only a square, but also a square with a “happening” (Pinna, 2010b) defined in terms of rotation. The anti-clockwise rotation suggests some kind of minimum rotation pathway starting from the “true” square of Fig. 2a. Structurally, this happening is similar to those described for Figs. 1c-i. Linguistically, the rotation is an adjective that describes the noun, which is the square. Phenomenally, it is what happens to the shape. The primary role of the shape (square) in relation to the adjective (rotation) can be clearly perceived by comparing the two following possible descriptions: “a rotated square” and “a rotation with a square shape”. The second description appears meaningless and odd. A rotation cannot have a shape, while the shape can have a rotation. This suggests a clear asymmetrical hierarchy between the two terms. The shape is primary, earlier in time and order than the rotation. Therefore, the shape is a noun and as such it is a word generally used to identify a class of elements. As a noun, the shape is like “a thing”, which can appear in many different ways, and the rotation is one of this ways of being of the shape, i.e. the attribute of that specific thing. These phenomenal observations suggest the following methodological note: the asymmetrical descriptions represent a useful method of understanding the primary role of one visual component over another, e.g. of the shape over the rotation and, more generally, of something that becomes the primary thing over another perceived like its attribute. Another example useful to understand the effectiveness of this method is represented by the relation between shape and color: we say “a red square” and not “a square-shaped red”. The distinction between things and attributes can also be demonstrated through the position of the words one relative to the other and through the phenomenal invisibility, i.e. an attribute (way of being of a thing) can be invisible or unnoticed like a background much more than a thing. Despite this asymmetry, rotation and square define themselves reciprocally. The rotation is defined by the shape, i.e. the rotation can be perceived if and only if the square as a singularity is also perceived. Conversely, the rotation defines 389 GESTALT THEORY, Vol. 33, No.3/4 the shape, i.e. without the rotation the square as a singularity could not be perceived. As soon as they are defined, square and rotation organize themselves asymmetrically as suggested by the two previous descriptions. ! " # Fig. 2 A square (a), a rotated square (b) and a diamond (c) 3.2.3. Diamond By increasing the rotation of Fig. 2b up to 45° as shown in Fig. 2c, both the happening (rotation) and the square are replaced by another one-word description: a diamond. This outcome is unexpected, if compared with the square of Fig. 2a. It represents a hard problem for an invariant features hypothesis. In fact, if shapes are defined by virtue of attributes invariant over rotations, then the two shapes of Figs. 2a and 2c should be perceived as having the same shape. Therefore, the square and the diamond demonstrate that different shape rotations cannot be perceived as having the same shape. Figs. 2a and 2c show the so-called Mach’s square/diamond illusion (Mach, 1914/1959; Schumann, 1900), according to which the same geometrical figure is perceived as a square when its sides are vertical and horizontal, but as a diamond when they are diagonal. From a phenomenal point of view, it is more correct to state that the square is perceived when the sides are vertical and horizontal, while a diamond is seen when its angles or vertices are vertical and horizontal. This description is more appropriate if we consider what emerges more strongly in the two!"#$%&'()''!"#$%#&'(#$$" conditions: the sides in the case of the square, and the angles/vertices in the case$%!&'()'&%*'+*!,(,-'./')%!0*1 of the diamond. We will see in section 5 some important consequences of these phenomenal observations for a better understanding of the meaning of shape. One main effect related to Mach’s square/diamond illusion is the fact that the diamond appears larger than the square. Schumann (1900) suggested that this is related to the fact that visual attention is placed on the vertical-horizontal axes, which are clearly longer in the diamond condition. This explanation is supported by the results of a simple control experiment according to which, by focusing the attention on one side of the diamond rather than on one angle, during the comparison of the size of Fig. 2a and 2c, the apparent size difference between the square and the diamond is strongly reduced or even annulled. 390 Pinna, What is the Meaning of Shape? 3.3. The Role of the Frame of Reference in Shape Perception More recent and complex explanations of the square/diamond illusion are based on object-centered reference frames. Rock (1973, 1983; see also Clément & Bukley, 2008), starting from previous Gestalt studies (Asch & Witkin, 1948a, 1948b; Koffka, 1935; Metzger, 1941, 1975), suggested that the perceived shape is a description relative to a perceptual frame of reference, i.e. the visual system prefers gravitational axes over retinal or head axes. In other words, Rock considered Mach’s square/diamond illusion as a clear evidence that a shape is perceived in relation to an environmental frame of reference where gravity defines the reference orientation, at least in the absence of intrinsic axes in the object itself. If the environmental orientation of the figure changes with respect to the two figures, the description of one shape does not match the description stored in memory for the other shape, therefore the observer fails to perceive the equivalence of the two figures. The stimulus factors important in determining the intrinsic reference frame are: gravitational orientation; directional symmetry (Pinna, 2010b; Pinna & Reeves, 2009); axes of reflectional symmetry, configural orientation (Attneave, 1968; Palmer, 1980) and axes of elongation (Marr & Nishihara, 1978; Palmer, 1975a, 1983, 1985; Rock, 1973). These factors rule the relation between shape and orientation as it happens in other phenomena (e.g., the rod-and-frame and Kopfermann’s effects; Davi & Profitt, 1993; Kopfermann, 1930; see also Marr & Nishihara, 1978; Palmer, 1975b, 1989, 1999; Witkins & Asch, 1948). These explanations contain some serious limits especially within the context of phenomenology. More particularly, they cannot account for the reason why we perceive a square, a diamond or a rotated square without invoking names and descriptions stored in memory. More specifically, they do not say anything about what changes phenomenally inside the shape properties when axes of reflection, gravitation and other factors change and about which shape properties switch when a square switches to a diamond. These limits are accompanied by the following questions: why are two names/ descriptions (square and diamond) stored so differently? Are they stored as different names because they are perceived differently or are they perceived differently because they are stored in memory with different names/descriptions? These last questions are not trivial because they are related to the important problem of the primary role of visual perception over the higher cognitive processes (see Kanizsa, 1980, 1985, 1991). This implies that the difference between square and diamond can be accounted for within the domain of vision alone and in terms of perceptual organization of shape attributes. In addition to these issues, the previous hypotheses cannot explain what shapes, such as squares, diamonds or rotated squares, are, and, even more generally, they 391 GESTALT THEORY, Vol. 33, No.3/4 do not say anything about what a shape is. They only state that in the case of the square/diamond illusion some factors influence the switch from one shape to another. Even if these factors are likely really effective, they cannot explain the meaning of shape. As a consequence, on the basis of these factors what determines the perception of a square and a diamond is not accounted for. 4. Doubts about the Role of Frame of Reference 4.1. On the Second Order Square/Diamond Illusion The limits of these hypotheses can be highlighted even more effectively through some new phenomenal conditions useful to understand the meaning of shape. Their rationale is the following: if the perceived shape is a description relative to a perceptual frame of reference, then results analogous to those achieved with the square/diamond illusion are expected to be attained through second order variations of squares and diamonds. In Fig. 3a, the square and the diamond of Figs. 2a and 2c and the rotated square of Fig. 2b are changed by making the sides concave. Under these conditions the two main effects previously described, i.e. the square/diamond switch and the size difference between the horizontal and vertical conditions, are strongly reduced or even absent. They appear more easily like the same figure with different amount of rotation. 392 Pinna, What is the Meaning of Shape? ! " # $ % & ' ( ) * Fig. 3 Second order variations of a square, a rotated square and a diamond In!"#$%&'()''!"#$%#&'(#$$" Fig. 3b, the angles are now rounded. The two main effects of the square/ +(!,-).-,(%-/%!0)0'-1&-.(!2%3 diamond illusion are clearly absent. They are also absent in the further conditions illustrated in Figs. 3c-g, where the changes involve the whole shapes. In Figs. 3hj, only one angle of each shape has been changed, but again the square/diamond 393 GESTALT THEORY, Vol. 33, No.3/4 and the size difference effects are very weak or absent. These results demonstrate that under these conditions the vertical/horizontal and gravitational axis do not define the reference orientation and, thus, do not influence shape perception. 4.2. The Square/Diamond Illusion with Polygons A second set of conditions that weaken the previous hypotheses and, at the same time, contribute to an understanding that the meaning of shape is related to the orientation of polygons. If the rotation of a square by 45 deg induces the square/ diamond illusion, similar results are expected by rotating polygons. In Fig. 4, several polygons in two orientations with a different number of sides are illustrated. The polygons do not show any kind of difference in the two orientations. Furthermore, they do not have different names stored in memory and, finally, they do not show a clear size change like the one reported in the square/diamond illusion. Fig. 4 Polygons and the square/diamond illusion Why does only the square induce this kind of illusion, while other polygons do not? The octagon, shown in two orientations, with the sides or with the angles 394 Pinna, What is the Meaning of Shape? along the vertical/horizontal axis (see Fig. 5), is useful when answering this question. Under these conditions, the two figures appear different: one flattened and the other pointed. Sides or angles emerge more strongly in one but not in the other condition and vice versa. The vertical/horizontal alignments strengthen the salience of the sides and the angles. (It is worthwhile clarifying that, among the previous polygons, the one geometrically and phenomenally closer to the octagon is the hexagon, where sides and angles are as well placed both on the vertical and on the horizontal axis.) Although the two octagons show the difference previously described, they do not have different names stored in memory and do not show a clear size difference like the square/diamond illusion. Fig. 5 Flattened and pointed octagons A new effect emerging in these figures is an illusion of numerosity: the number of angles and sides is perceived higher in the octagon with the angles along the vertical and horizontal axes. This phenomenon is likely related to the phenomenal asymmetry between the emergence of the sides and the angles. This asymmetry will be dealt in greater depth in the next section. 5. Inside the Shape: What is a Shape? 5.1. What are Squares and Diamonds? Sidedness and Pointedness To understand why the second order variations illustrated in Fig. 3 are not influenced in the two main properties of the square/diamond effect, it is necessary to go back to the properties emerging in the two octagons, which help the understanding of the meaning of the square and the diamond. In geometry, a square is defined as a regular quadrilateral, namely a shape with four equal sides and four equal angles. Sides and angles are the components of a square that emerge more easily within the gradient of visibility, i.e. the gradient of phenomenal vividness of different visual attributes that do not pop out with the same strength (Pinna, 2010a). If a square shape is made up of sides and angles, then it shows phenomenal properties such as “sidedness” and “pointedness” related to these components. These two properties are only apparently equipollent. The square/diamond illusion demonstrates the vividness asymmetry between these properties. In the square the sidedness appears stronger than the pointedness, !"#$%&'()''!"#$%#&'(#$$" while the diamond shows more strongly the pointedness. The perceived strength !"#$%&'%$"(%)(#*&*+%,-%'"#.(/ 395 GESTALT THEORY, Vol. 33, No.3/4 of one or of the other property is influenced by the vertical/horizontal and gravitational axis that plays by accentuating the sidedness against the pointedness in the square and, vice versa, the pointedness against the sidedness in the diamond. On the basis of these properties, it appears clear why the second order variations of Fig. 3 are not involved in the square/diamond illusions. In fact, in all the conditions illustrated sidedness and pointedness are not in contrast but either the sidedness or the pointedness are attenuated or emphasized, thus weakening only one of the two effects. This entails that one of the two singularities is weakened, therefore appearing as a rotation of the other. The two properties can also account for the reason why we perceive a rotated square in Fig. 2b. This is due to the strength of the sidedness being higher than the one of the pointedness. Similarly, the numerosity illusion of Fig. 5 can be considered as related to the shape attribute that defines the number of elements in the octagon. We suggest that this figure, similarly to the other polygons, is mostly defined by the sidedness and thus by the number of sides. More specifically, to answer a question like “what polygon is this?” spontaneously we count at a glance the number of sides but not the number of vertices. The importance of the two properties in defining the shape appears in fact asymmetrical. Therefore, because in the pointed octagon of Fig. 5 the sidedness is weakened while the vertices are perceived with a stronger vividness, the numerosity of the sides is determined taking into account or starting from the angles or vertices, which induce an increasing of number of sides or a summation effect due to the numerosity fuzziness of the sides together with the angles. The calculation at a glance of the number of sides can include also some vertices that pop out more strongly than the sides. These phenomenal reports suggest that, all else being equal, the perceived shape can change or switch from one shape to another by accentuating the sidedness or the pointedness independently from the vertical/horizontal and gravitational axes. A demonstration of this expectation is illustrated in Fig. 6, where, despite the configural orientation effects (i.e. the perception of local spatial orientation determined by the global spatial orientational structure) studied by Attneave (1968) and Palmer (1980), rows of figures are perceived as rotated squares or as diamonds according to the position of the small circle placed near the sides or near the angles of the figures (see also Pinna, 2010a, 2010b; Pinna & Albertazzi, 2011). While in Figs. 6a and 6c, the geometrical diamonds are phenomenally perceived as rotated squares, in Figs. 6b and 6d, the geometrical diamonds are perceived more strongly than in the control (Fig. 6e) as diamonds. 396 Pinna, What is the Meaning of Shape? # 2 0 1 ( Fig. 6 Rotated squares or diamonds? 5.2. On the Difference between a Square and a Rotated Square It is worthwhile clarifying that a diamond and a square rotated by 45 deg as shown !"#$%&'()''!"#$%#&'(#$$" in Fig. 6 are different shapes, not only because they have two different names, but, !"#$%&'%$"(%)(#*&*+%,-%'"#.(/ mostly, because they show opposite phenomenal properties: pointedness in the diamonds and sidedness in the rotated squares. This shape switch is not a minor difference but a variation of the perceptual meaning of shape (see Pinna, 2010b). Pointedness and sidedness are like the underlying shapes of the shape, a second level shape (meta-shape), i.e. the meanings of the perceived shapes, and, more 397 GESTALT THEORY, Vol. 33, No.3/4 particularly, of the diamond and square or of the two octagons illustrated in Fig. 5. These phenomenal remarks are corroborated by the results of Fig. 7, where the inner rectangles accentuate the sidedness or the pointedness of both the checks and the whole checkerboards, thus eliciting respectively the perception of rotated squares or diamonds in the same geometrical figures. This result demonstrates local and global effects of the accentuation. Fig. 7 Rotated squares or diamonds in both the checks and the whole checkerboards 398 !"#$%&'()''!"#$%#&'(#$$" !"#$%&'%$"(%)(#*&*+%,-%'"#.(/ Pinna, What is the Meaning of Shape? Sidedness and pointedness can also be accentuated in the two grids with the same geometrical shape as shown in Fig. 8. Again, the single elements of the grid (each single inner diamond shape) and the global shape of the grid are perceived as rotated squares or diamonds by virtue of the accentuation of sidedness or pointedness. Fig. 8 Rotated squares or diamonds in both the components and the whole grids These results suggest that the shape of an object depends on its inner properties, on their accentuation due to other elements (disk or empty circles) present in !"#$%&'()''!"#$%#&'(#$$" !"#$%&'%$"(%)(#*&*+%,-%'"#.(/ 399 GESTALT THEORY, Vol. 33, No.3/4 the visual field. Therefore, shape perception is the result of the organization of its inner attributes, whose gradient of visibility can be changed according to accents placed in a spatial position that enhances the vividness of one shape attribute against the other. It is worthwhile showing Kopfermann’s effect demonstrating the dependence of an object shape on the frame of reference (Kopfermann, 1930; see also Antonucci et al., 1995; Gibson, 1937; Wikin & Asch, 1948). The effect is shown in Fig. 9 in the four classical versions. Under these conditions, the square and the diamond of Figs. 9a-b, when included within a rectangle obliquely oriented are perceived respectively as a diamond and as a rotated square (see Figs. 9c-d). # 0 1 2 Fig. 9 Kopfermann’s effect Figs. 10a and 10b demonstrate the stronger role of the accentuation of the sidedness or the pointedness over the larger reference frame. Due to the black dot and to the inner small rectangle, the geometrical shapes are now restored, i.e. the diamond and the rotated square perceived in Figs. 9c-d are switched into a rotated square and a diamond demonstrating the ineffectiveness of the larger frame of reference. !"#$%&'()''!"#$%#&'(#$$" !"#$%&'%$"(%)(#*&*+%,-%'"#.(/ 400 Pinna, What is the Meaning of Shape? # 0 Fig. 10 Kopfermann’s effect annulled 5.3. On the Accentuation of Shape Properties Sidedness and pointedness can be accentuated in many ways (see Pinna, 2010a, 2010b; Pinna & Albertazzi, 2011). A powerful accentuation factor is the reversed contrast shown in Fig. 11. Due to this factor, the same geometrical octagons appear rotated in opposite directions, clockwise or anticlockwise (Figs. 11a-b). They are also perceived pointed with different strength and at different locations of!"#$%&'()*''!"#$%#&'(#$$" the figures depending on the position of the white components (Figs. 11c-d). By!"#$%&'%$"(%)(#*&*+%,-%'"#.(/ comparing Figs. 11a-b and 11c-d, the visual differences between the sidedness and the pointedness emerge very clearly. The difference in salience of sides and angles is seen very clearly also in Figs. 11e-f, where a slightly concave and convex effect of the sides can be perceived. These differences are also accompanied by the illusion of numerosity described in section 4.2. It is worthwhile noticing that it is not the geometrical orientation which defines the numerosity, in fact it is kept constant, but the emergence of the sidedness or of the pointedness due to their accentuation. 401 GESTALT THEORY, Vol. 33, No.3/4 # 1 0 2 ( - Fig. 11 Accentuation of sidedness and pointedness in octagons In Fig. 12, the accentuation of the sidedness and pointedness through the !"#$%&'(()''!"#$%#&'(#$$" reversed contrast induces diamond-shaped (Fig. 12a) or grand piano-like (Fig. !"#$%&'%$"(%)(#*&*+%,-%'"#.(/ 12b) figures in the same geometrical objects. 402 Pinna, What is the Meaning of Shape? # 0 Fig. 12 Diamond-shaped or grand piano-like figures in the same geometrical objects In Fig. 13, the accentuation, due to the arrangement of black and white sides of each !"#$%&'()*''!"#$%#&'(#$$" square, produces a directional symmetry and elicits several phenomena: (i) a global !"#$%&'%$"(%)(#*&*+%,-%'"#.(/ and local rectangle illusion, i.e. the geometrical squares, both locally (each single square) and globally (the square made up of squares), are perceived like rectangles elongated in the direction perpendicular to the black sides; (ii) the orientation of each element appears polarized (upwards in Fig. 13a and downwards in Fig. 13b); (iii) the elements are grouped in columns and rows and a global waving (up & 403 GESTALT THEORY, Vol. 33, No.3/4 down or left & right) apparent motion is clearly perceived when the gaze follows the tip of a pen moved across the patterns illustrated in Figs. 13c and 13d. These results are likely related to the fact that the black side not only enhances the salience of the sidedness, but also defines the base of each check. This suggests that the phenomenal accentuation of one shape property manifests vectorial properties. More particularly, the accent placed on the black side appears, under these conditions, as the starting point of the oriented direction. The white side of each check, opposite to the black one, is perceived as the tip of the arrow or as the terminal point of the oriented direction induced by the accent. Finally. the magnitude of the vector depends on the magnitude of the accent, here kept constant. Briefly, the accents behave like Euclidean vectors considered in the same acceptation used in physics. # 0 1 2 Fig. 13 The accentuation, due to black sides, produces a directional symmetry and manifests vectorial properties 404 !"#$%&'()*''!"#$%#&'(#$$" !"#$%&'%$"(%)(#*&*+%,-%'"#.(/ Pinna, What is the Meaning of Shape? These results demonstrate that the accentuation of one shape property against the other can induce different kinds of dimensional, direction and even motion effects, which suggest a theory of shape, considered like an overall holder containing many shape attributes that compete or cooperate and whose strength can be changed or accentuated in many ways. Other effects induced by the accentuation and by its vectorial properties are the tilt and straighten up effects of Fig. 14. The dot seems to tilt further the shape by pulling the top left-hand corner of the parallelogram in Fig. 14-left and to push the whole figure in the right-vertical direction, thus, straightening up the parallelogram in Fig. 14-right. Fig. 14 Tilt and straighten up effects Another kind of accentuation is induced by the missing parts or cuts of sides and angles shown in Fig. 15, thus inducing the switch from the diamond to the rotated square shape both in the 2D and 3D conditions. It is worthwhile noticing that the 3D appearance of the cube with the missing corner is weaker than the one of the cube with the cut side (see also Fig. 16). This is likely due to the directional symmetry induced by the cut, which favors the vertical organization of lines that camouflages the whole 3D perception. !"#$%&'()*''!"#$%#&'(#$$" !"#$%&'%$"(%)(#*&*+%,-%'"#.(/ 405 GESTALT THEORY, Vol. 33, No.3/4 Fig . 15 Diamond and the rotated square shapes both in the 2D and 3D conditions By introducing white sides or white dots within the same shape near the corner or next to one side, the cube appearance can be either weakened or optimized (cf. the control at the bottom) as shown in Fig. 16. !"#$%&'()*''!"#$%#&'(#$$" !"#$%&'%$"(%)(#*&*+%,-%'"#.(/ 406 Pinna, What is the Meaning of Shape? Fig. 16 The vertical organization weakens the 3D appearance of the cubes 5.4. Other Shape Properties: The Pointing !"#$%&'()*''!"#$%#&'(#$$" !"#$%&'%$"(%)(#*&*+%,-%'"#.(/ The shape properties are not restricted to the sidedness and pointedness. Given the vectorial attributes previously described and the relations between sides and angles and also between what appears as the base of a shape and its height, the pointing is another significant shape property, which can be strongly influenced by the accentuation. If the pointing is a shape attribute, then it is expected to create and define the perceived shape. In Fig. 17a, the horizontal alignment of equilateral triangles induces the pointing 407 GESTALT THEORY, Vol. 33, No.3/4 of the triangles in the direction of their alignment. This is due to the configural orientation effect studied by Attneave (1968), Palmer (1980, 1989) and Palmer & Bucher (1981). Figs. 17b-c demonstrate that the pointing of the triangles can be deviated or redirected by the small rectangles and circles placed inside each triangle, respectively in the top left and bottom left-hand directions. These results are unexpected on the basis of the configural orientation effect (see also Pinna, 2010a, 2010b). # 2 0 1 ( Fig. 17 The pointing and the shape of triangles can be influenced by the accentuation 408 !"#$%&'()*''!"#$%#&'(#$$" !"#$%&'%$"(%)(#*&*+%,-%'"#.(/ Pinna, What is the Meaning of Shape? More important than these conditions are the following ones of Figs. 17d-e, where the pointing clearly influences the shape of the triangles, thus demonstrating that the pointing is a shape property. Geometrically the triangles are isosceles, nevertheless due to the pointing induced by the two kinds of accentuation (rectangles and circles), they are perceived like scalene triangles. More in details, because the perceived pointing is not in the direction of the angle created by the two longer sides, this induces an asymmetrical effect that propagates and determines the whole shape of each triangle making it appear as scalene. These results suggest that the pointing and all the other meta-shape attributes here studied are the main attributes responsible for the shape formation. They can explain what a shape is. Variations in the pointing of sides or vertices, due to the accentuation, clearly influence the shape of figures as shown in Fig. 18. Under these conditions, the rows of irregular quadrilaterals are perceived as different shapes, difficult to recognize as the same figures. By determining the shape, the accent determines also the orientation of each specific shape and therefore the shape-related information about its rigidity and surface bending in the 3D space. The bending region is easily and immediately perceivable and its location changes in relation to the accent position within the figure. These results suggest the kind of visual organization and the new conditions illustrated in the following section. 409 GESTALT THEORY, Vol. 33, No.3/4 Fig. 18 Rows of irregular quadrilaterals are perceived as different shapes 5.5. The Headedness and the Organic Segmentation There is a special kind of shape formation never studied before, which subsumes a meta-shape property that we call “headedness”. This property is shown in the irregular wiggly object of Fig. 19a that assumes an organic appearance similar to !"#$%&'()*''!"#$%#&'(#$$" an amoeba or to some kind of living creature with a head and upper and lower !"#$%&'%$"(%)(#*&*+%,-%'"#.(/ limbs, moving in the direction defined by the shape component perceived as the head of the organism. The object shapes up slowly and appears reversible, i.e. the same component can assume different roles (head, limb), therefore changing the whole organic segmentation and, as a consequence, the direction of the perceived motion, the structure, the weight and all the other static and dynamic characteristics of the organism. This organic segmentation can be reshaped, similarly to the ways previously 410 Pinna, What is the Meaning of Shape? shown in the case of the squares, through the accentuation of one component against the others in the function of head, thus favoring the emergence of the headedness shape property. Figs. 19b-e demonstrate that by changing the spatial position of the small circle the organism changes its shape, appearing each time as a different creature. The component defined by the circle becomes the head. As such, all the organic properties change accordingly to what is perceived as the head, i.e. to the headedness property. For instance, the organisms of Figs. 19bc or 19d-e are perceived moving in opposite directions. The limbs appear also totally different and so on. # 1 0 2 ( - + Fig. 19 Different organic segmentations of undulated figures 411 !"#$%&'()*''!"#$%#&'(#$$" !"#$%&'%$"(%)(#*&*+%,-%'"#.(/ GESTALT THEORY, Vol. 33, No.3/4 Figs. 19f-c demonstrate that not all the components can assume the function of head. The accentuation of the bottom components cannot induce so strongly as in Figs. 19b-e the headedness property. This likely depends on the position of the head, usually placed sideways or at the top of a living being. However, the term “usually” does not necessarily mean that the position of the head is totally due to past experience, but that the head should be structurally located in certain spatial components and not in others in order to show the strongest headedness property necessary to influence at best the entire shape. Against the headedness and organic segmentation, it can be argued that these results are due to the fact that the filled circle behaves or is reminiscent of an eye, thus eliciting cognitive processes that have nothing to do with the shape formation within the visual domain. The counter-arguments to this issue are illustrated in the conditions of Fig. 20, where the positions of the small circle and the different shapes of the accentuation reject this objection in favor of the spontaneous organic segmentation as part of the problem of shape formation within the perceptual domain and depending on the headedness property. Figs. 20f-g shows how different shapes of the inner components can create organic segmentation by putting together different wiggly components that create not only a head within a body but also a face with different components (nose, mouth and so on). 412 Pinna, What is the Meaning of Shape? 0 # 1 2 ( - + Fig. 20 The positions of the small circle and the different shapes of the accentuation change the headedness of the undulated figures It is!"#$%&'()*''!"#$%#&'(#$$" worthwhile noticing that this kind of segmentation is related to those !"#$%&'%$"(%)(#*&*+%,-%'"#.(/ previously described, where the accentuation popped out some inner meta-shape attributes. Furthermore, like in the previous conditions, these attributes can be spontaneously highlighted through our own gaze and the focus of attention without the need of external accents. This free and subjective visual highlight can be easily demonstrated in Fig. 19a by switching spontaneously the headedness from one wiggly component to another, therefore addressing the organic segmentation in different ways. 413 GESTALT THEORY, Vol. 33, No.3/4 5.6. The Happening as a Further Shape Property In the light of these results, we can now go back to the conditions illustrated in Fig. 1, by reviewing the phenomenal notion of “happening”. It can, in fact, be considered as another meta-shape attribute among the others. Every happening is a discontinuity that accentuates one or more properties of the main shape. This discontinuity gives a meaning to the shape in the same way as we have shown in the previous sections, or like, for example, in the diamond and the rotated squares of Fig. 15. The missing portion of the side or of the angle imparts different meanings to the shape by eliciting a diamond or a rotated square shape. Furthermore, in the same way as the happening (the geometrical discontinuity) imparts a meaning to the shape, the shape imparts a meaning to the discontinuity. For instance, the object illustrated in Fig. 1c is the result of a complex kind of shape formation and meaning assignment that we spontaneously define “a beveled square”. Geometrically, there is neither a “square”, nor a “beveling”, or an “a” but two vertical, two horizontal and one oblique segment forming a closed figure with the oblique segment placed in the top right-hand portion of the figure connecting the horizontal and vertical segments, shorter than the other two. This complex geometrical description is strongly simplified by giving a visual meaning to that shape, i.e. a beveled square. Differently from these phenomenal results, good continuation, prägnanz and closure principles group the sides of the figure to form a pentagon. The discontinuous component, i.e. the oblique segment, gives a meaning to the other sides, that become a square, and, at the same time, the square assigns a meaning to the discontinuity that appear like a beveling (see also Pinna, 2010a, 2010b). The notion of happening also suggests a more interesting aspect of the meaning of shape. Shape not only implies boundary contour formation or geometrical organization like square vs. diamond. It also contains more complex properties as suggested by Rubin introducing depth and chromatic attributes (see section 1.2). Figs. 1c-i clearly demonstrate that there are also material properties that can influence and assign different meanings to the shape. In fact, when, for example, it is broken, the material properties strongly determine its shape. If a square is made up of glass, when its shape is broken, it will be different from a square made up of pottery or fabric. The shape of the break changes according to the material property. Conversely, the shape of the broken square suggests its material properties. The beveled square indicates only a small number of material attributes (paper, metal, etc.) and, at the same time excludes many others. They are reciprocally determined in the same way we have seen in the case of the diamond and the rotated square. For a more exhaustive analysis of the notion of “happening” see Pinna (2010a, 2010b) and Pinna & Albertazzi (2011). 414 Pinna, What is the Meaning of Shape? 6. Discussion and Conclusions In the previous sections, following the methods traced by Gestalt psychologists, we studied the meaning of shape perception starting from the square/diamond illusion, which represents a problem for the invariant features hypothesis and for any model of shape formation. Theories based on the role of frame of reference in determining shape perception were discussed and largely weakened or refuted in the light of a high number of new effects, demonstrating the basic phenomenal role of inner properties in defining the meaning of shape. On the basis of these effects, several shape properties were demonstrated. They are: (i) the sidedness and the pointedness, related to the sides and angles in the case of squares, diamonds and polygons; (ii) the pointing involved mostly in the triangles; (iii) the headedness, i.e. the appearance like a head of a particular component within an irregular shape, in the case of a new kind of visual organization that we called “organic segmentation”; finally, (iv) the happening, i.e. the something that happens to a figure. Many other shape properties remain to be studied. These shape properties were demonstrated to underlie the whole notion of shape and to appear like second level shape meanings. They can be considered like transversal or elemental meta-shapes common to a large number of shapes both regular and irregular. They are like meaningful primitives, phenomenally relevant, of the language of shape perception. This suggests that the meaning of shape can be understood on the basis of a multiplicity of meta-shape attributes. Therefore, the notion of shape can be phenomenally represented like a whole visual “thing” that contains a specific set of phenomenal primitive properties. In other words, the shape can be considered like the holder of shape attributes. As a holder it expresses and manifests the state of organization of the inner meta-shapes. Within the shape like a holder, the shape attributes are not placed all at the same height within the gradient of visibility, i.e. some emerge more strongly than others depending on a number of factors that can influence their vividness and thus their visibility. Among them, we studied some known factors like the horizontal/vertical axes, the gravitational orientation, the configural orientation and the large reference frame. We also demonstrated their limits and showed the reason of their effectiveness under specific conditions. Within the hypothesis of the shape like a holder, their effectiveness depends on the accentuation of one specific meta-shape attribute. Therefore, in the case of a square, the horizontal/ vertical organization of the sides accentuates the sidedness, while in the case of the diamond the pointedness is accentuated by the same factor. This entails that a rotated square is perceived when the sidedness is stronger than the pointedness; otherwise we would have perceived a rotated diamond. 415 GESTALT THEORY, Vol. 33, No.3/4 This suggests that all the shape attributes are present at the same time but some or only one emerges, due to specific factors, as the winner that imparts the basic meaning to the shape. It follows that the shape attributes can compete and cooperate and, above all, they are all present at the same time, placed along the gradient of visibility and in a dynamic state of equilibrium that can be changed by accentuating the opposite or competing attribute. Several ways to accentuate the shape attributes were demonstrated in most of the figures illustrated. It was also demonstrated that the accentuation operates like Euclidean vectors. The organization of the shape attributes can create conditions of singularity where one specific attribute emerges much more than others. This is the case of the square of Fig. 2a and of the diamond of 2c. Under these conditions, the perceived shape manifests a unique and a special meaning similar to the one assumed by the term “Prägnanz” within the Gestalt literature. This term was related to a special phenomenal property belonging to certain gestalts but not to others. This property makes some objects appear as unique, preferred, singular and distinguished (Ausgezeichnet). This is the case of the circle and the square (Metzger, 1963; 1975a; 1975b; Wertheimer, 1912a; 1912b; 1922, 1923). Wertheimer (1923) introduced a second interesting meaning, aimed at describing not only a property but also a process: Prägnanz refers to a process bringing to a stable result and with the maximum of equilibrium. This is the case of Prägnanz as a grouping principle (see also Metzger, 1963) directed to create the best Gestalt (Tendenz zur Resultierung in guter Gestalt; gute Fortsetzung) with an inner necessity and with the minimum of requiredness (innere Notwendigkeit, Köhler, 1938). As regards the need to distinguish between the two meanings see Hüppe (1984) and Kanizsa and Luccio (1986, 1989). The third meaning of the term “Prägnanz” is the most controversial and states that Prägnanz refers to self-organization processes aimed at the formation of an ordered, singular (Einzigartigkeit), and distinguished (Ausgezeichnet) outcome (Goldmeier, 1937; Köhler, 1920; Metzger, 1963; 1982; Rausch, 1952, 1966; Wertheimer, 1912a, 1912b, 1922). For an interesting discussion on the meanings of Prägnanz see Kanizsa (1975, 1991) and Kanizsa & Luccio (1986, 1989), who criticized and rejected the third meaning as part of perception and suggested distinguishing sharply the first two meanings to avoid any possible confusion. Pinna (1993, 1996, 2005) introduced a fourth meaning going beyond and solving Kanizsa and Luccio’s critiques to the third meaning. It states that a tendency toward Prägnanz does not necessarily concern the modal realization of a singular perceptual result but it usually implies the amodal formation of the most distinguished and singular result (amodal prägnanz). This idea is in agreement with the meaning of shape introduced in this work. In fact, the perception of a rotated square implies the amodal prägnanz. This is all 416 Pinna, What is the Meaning of Shape? the more reason for the notion of happening. In fact, in the case of the beveled square, the square appears as the amodal whole object and the beveling as the modal part of it. The square is the result of the amodal wholeness completion of something perceived as its visible modal portion. The square is perceived and not perceived at the same time and its amodal whole completion occurs “beyond” the beveling. This implies that the amodal completion can be considered as a subset or as an instance of the more general problem of amodal wholeness. In the case of the beveled square, the amodal wholeness corresponds to the amodal prägnanz. This suggests that every shape manifests an ideal condition where one meta-shape attribute emerges much more than others. In other words, each shape indicates amodally its starting or converging point of singularity. Therefore, we are able to perceive how a figure can be changed or accentuated to obtain the best condition under which the shape becomes a singularity. It is worthwhile noticing that, on the basis of our results, the gradient of visibility of the shape attributes indicates that, when one attribute emerges, the others remain invisible or in a second plane of visibility. In conclusion, the meaning of shape, here suggested, allows its extension to conditions never included in the notion of shape so far. They are, for example, the material properties, previously considered as shape attributes (see section 5.6), but also figures like those illustrated in Fig. 21, known as “Maluma-Takete” (Köhler, 1929, 1947; see also Ramachandran & Hubbard; 2001), where two opposite attributes are perceived, curviness and pointedness, and where a large set of further opposite properties – smoothness and sharpness, jaggedness and roundedness – are related to these ones. Fig. 21 Maluma and Takete 417 GESTALT THEORY, Vol. 33, No.3/4 Summary The aim of this work is to answer the following questions: what is shape? What is its meaning? Shape perception and its meaning were studied starting from the square/ diamond illusion and according to the phenomenological approach traced by gestalt psychologists. The role of frame of reference in determining shape perception was discussed and largely weakened or refuted in the light of a high number of new effects, based on some phenomenal meta-shape properties useful and necessary to define the meaning of shape. The new effects studied are based on the accentuation of the following meta-shape attributes: sidedness and pointedness (in the case of squares, diamonds and polygons); the pointing (in the triangles); the headedness (in irregular shapes); the happening (in deformed shapes), i.e. the something that happens to a figure. Every happening is a discontinuity that accentuates one or more properties of the main shape and gives a meaning to the shape. The phenomenal results demonstrated that the accentuation of the meta-shape properties operates like Euclidean vectors. On the basis of these results we suggested that the meaning of shape could be understood on the basis of a multiplicity of meta-shape attributes that operate like meaningful primitives of the complex language of shape perception. Therefore, the notion of shape can be represented like a whole visual “thing/holder” that contains a specific organized set of phenomenal primitive properties, i.e. the state of organization of the inner meta-shapes. Keywords: Shape perception, Gestalt psychology, perceptual organization, visual meaning, visual illusions. Zusammenfassung Ziel der vorliegenden Arbeit ist die Beantwortung folgender Fragen: Was ist Form und was ist deren Bedeutung? Die Wahrnehmung von Form und Bedeutung wurde erstmals anhand einer Quadrat-Rauten-Täuschung (Pinna) mit Hilfe der von der Gestaltpsychologie entwickelten phänomenologischen Methode untersucht. Die Rolle des Bezugssystems für die Wahrnehmung einer Form wird diskutiert, jedoch angesichts zahlreicher neuer Effekte größtenteils herabgestuft oder gar widerlegt. Diese neuen Effekte gehen auf einige für die Definition der Form-Bedeutung förderliche und notwendige phänomenale Meta-Form-Eigenschaften zurück. Sie beruhen auf der Akzentuierung folgender Eigenschaften: anschauliche Erstreckung von Kanten und Ecken (im Fall von Quadraten, Rauten und Polygonen); anschauliche Ausrichtung (bei Dreiecken); anschauliche Gerichtetheit (bei unregelmäßigen Formen); Bezogenheit auf ein dynamisches Ereignis (bei deformierten Formen), also auf das Etwas, das mit einer Form geschieht. Jedes Ereignis stellt eine Störung dar, die eine oder mehrere (implizite) Eigenschaften der zugrunde liegenden Form isoliert und verstärkt und dadurch der Form eine Bedeutung zuweist. Die Beobachtungen zeigen, dass die Meta-Form-Eigenschaften sich wie euklidische Vektoren verhalten. Aufgrund der Ergebnisse vertreten wir die Auffassung, dass man die Bedeutung einer Form auf der Grundlage einer Vielzahl von Meta-Form-Eigenschaften verstehen kann, die sich ihrerseits wie bedeutungshaltige Primitiva der komplexen Sprache der Formwahrnehmung verhalten. Der Begriff der Form kann daher wie ein holistischer “Ding-Träger” aufgefasst werden, der eine spezifisch organisierte Anzahl grundlegender 418 Pinna, What is the Meaning of Shape? phänomenaler Eigenschaften enthält, nämlich den Zustand der Organisation der inneren Meta-Formen. Schlüsselwörter: Formwahrnehmung, Gestaltpsychologie, Wahrnehmungsorganisation, visuelle Bedeutung, Wahrnehmungstäuschung. References Antonucci, G., Fanzon, D., Spinelli, D., & Zoccolotti, P. (1995): Visual factors affecting the rod- and-frame illusion: the role of gap size and frame components. Perception, 24, 1119-1130. Asch, S. E, & Witkin, H. A. (1948a): Studies in space orientation: I. Perception of the upright with displaced visual fields. Journal of Experimental Psychology 38, 325-337. Asch, S. E., & Witkin, H. A. (1948b): Studies in space orientation: II. Perception of the upright with displaced visual fields and with body tilted. Journal of Experimental Psychology 38, 455-477. Attneave, F. (1968). Triangles as ambiguous figures. American Journal of Psychology 81, 447-453. Clément, G., & Bukley, A. (2008): Mach’s square-or-diamond phenomenon in microgravity during parabolic flight. Neuroscience Letters 447, 179-182. Davi, M., & Proffit, D.R. (1993): Frames of reference and distinctive figural characteristics affect shape perception. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance 19, 867-877. Gibson, J.J. (1937): Adaptation, after-effect and contrast in the perception of tilted lines: II. Simultaneopus contrast and the areal restriction of the after-effect. Journal of Experimental Psychology 20, 553-569. Goldmeier, E. (1937): Über Ähnlichkeit bei gesehenen figuren. Psychologische Forschung 4, 146-208. Hoffman, D.D., & Richards, W.A. (1984): Parts of recognition. Cognition 18, 65-96. Huppe, A., (1984): Prägnanz. Ein gestalttheoretischer Grund-begriff. Munchen, Profil Verlag. Kanizsa, G. (1975): The role of regularity in perceptual organization. In Flores D’Arcais, G.B (eds.), Studies in Perception, Festschrift for Fabio Metelli, Firenze, Giunti-Martello, 48-66. Kanizsa, G. (1980): Grammatica del vedere. Bologna, Il Mulino. Kanizsa, G. (1985): Seeing and thinking. Acta Psycologica 59, 23-33. Kanizsa, G. (1991): Vedere e pensare. Bologna, Il Mulino. Kanizsa, G., & Luccio, R. (1986): Die Doppoldeutigkeiten der Prägnanz. Gestalt Theory 8, 99-135. Kanizsa, G., & Luccio, R. (1989): Fenomenologia della formazione di un ordine autonomo della percezione. Rivista di Psicologia 3, 28-46. Koffka, K. (1935): Principles of Gestalt Psychology. Routledge and Kegan Paul, London, UK. Köhler, W. (1920): Die physischen Gestalten in Ruhe und im stationären Zustand. Eine naturphilosophische Untersuchung. Vieweg, Braunschweig. Köhler, W. (1929): Gestalt Psychology. New York: Liveright. Köhler, W. (1938): The place of value in a world of facts. New York, Liveright. Köhler, W. (1947): Gestalt Psychology, 2nd Ed. New York: Liveright. Kopfermann, H. (1930): Psychologische Untersuchungen über die Wirkung zweidimensionaler Darstellungen körperlicher Gebilde. Psychologische Forschung 13, 293-364. Mach, E. (1914/1959): The Analysis of Sensation. Chicago, Open Court USA. Marr, D., & Nishihara, H. K. (1978): Representation and recognition of the spatial organization of three-dimensional shapes. Proceedings of the Royal Society of London 200, 269-294. Metzger, W. (1941): Psychologie: die Entwicklung ihrer Grundannhamen seit der Einführung des Experiments. Dresden, Steinkopff. Metzger, W. (1963): Psychologie. Darmstadt, Steinkopff Verlag. Metzger, W. (1975a): Gesetze des Sehens. Kramer, Frankfurt-am-Main. Metzger, W. (1975b): Die Entdeckung der Prägnanztendenz. Die Anfänge einer nicht-atomistischen Wahrnehmungslehre. In Flores D’Arcais, G.B (eds.), Studies in Perception, Festschrift for Fabio Metelli, Firenze, Giunti-Martello, 3-47. Metzger, W. (1982): Möglichkeiten der Verallgemeinerung des Prägnanzprinzips. Gestalt Theory 4, 3-22. Nakayama, K., & Shimojo, S. (1990): Towards a neural understanding of visual surface representation. Cold Spring Harbor Symposia on Quantitative Biology LV, 911-924. Palmer, S. E. (1975a): The effects of contextual scenes on the identification of objects. Memory & Cognition 3(5), 519-526. Palmer, S.E. (1975b): Visual perception and world knowledge: Notes on a model of sensory-cognitive interaction. In D. A. Norman & D. E. Rumelhart (Eds.), Explorations in cognition, 279-307. San Francisco: W. H. Freeman. 419 GESTALT THEORY, Vol. 33, No.3/4 Palmer, S.E. (1980): What makes triangles point: Local and global effects in configurations of ambiguous triangles. Cognitive Psychology 12, 285-305. Palmer, S.E. (1983): The psychology of perceptual organization: A transformational approach. In J. Beck, B. Hope, & A. Baddeley (Eds.), Human and machine vision, 269-339. New York: Academic Press. Palmer, S.E. (1985): The role of symmetry in shape perception. Special Issue: Seeing and knowing. Acta Psychologica 59(1), 67-90. Palmer, S.E. (1989): Reference frames in the perception of shape and orientation. In B. E. Shepp & S. Ballesteros (Eds.), Object perception: Structure and process, 121-163. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum. Palmer, S.E. (1999): Vision Science: photons to phenomenology, Cambridge, Massachusetts, London, England, The MIT press. Palmer, S.E., & Bucher, N.M. (1981): Textural effect in perceiving pointing of ambiguous triangle. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception & Performance 8(5), 693-708. Pinna, B. (1993): La creatività del vedere: verso una Psicologia Integrale. Padova, Domenighini Editore. Pinna, B. (1996): La percezione delle qualità emergenti: una conferma della ”tendenza alla pregnanza”. In Boscolo P., Cristante F., Dell’Antonio A. e Soresi S., (eds.), Aspetti qualitativi e quantitativi nella ricerca psicologica, Padova, Il Poligrafo, 261-276. Pinna, B. (2005): Riflessioni fenomenologiche sulla percezione delle qualità emergenti: verso una riconsiderazione critica della teoria della Pregnanza. Annali della Facoltà di Lingue e Letterature Straniere dell’Università di Sassari 3, 211-256. Pinna, B. (2010a): What Comes Before Psychophysics? The Problem of ‘What We Perceive’ and the Phenomenological Exploration of New Effects. Seeing & Perceiving 23, 463-481. Pinna, B. (2010b): New Gestalt principles of perceptual organization: An extension from grouping to shape and meaning. Gestalt Theory 32, 1-67. Pinna, B., & Albertazzi, L. (2011): From grouping to visual meanings: A new theory of perceptual organization, 288-344. In L. Albertazzi, G. van Tonder, D. Vishwanath, (eds.), Information in Perception, MIT Press. Pinna, B., & Reeves, A. (2009): From Perception to art: How the brain creates meanings. Spatial Vision 22, 225-272. Pinna, B., & Sirigu, L. (in press): The Accentuation Principle of Visual Organization and the Illusion of Musical Suspension. Seeing & Perceiving. Pizlo, Z. (2008): 3D shape: its unique place in visual perception. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Ramachandran, V.S., & Hubbard, E.M. (2001): Synaesthesia: A window into perception, thought and language. Journal of Consciousness Studies 8(12), 3-34. Rausch, E. (1952): Struktur und Metrik figural-optischer Wahrnehmung. Frankfurt, Kramer. Rausch, E. (1966): Das Eigenschaftsproblem in der Gestalttheorie der Wahrnehmung. In W. Metzger, & H. Erke (hrsg.), Wahrnehmung und Bewußtsein, “Handbuch der Psychologie”, Bd 1/1, 866-951, Hogrefe, Göttingen. Rock, I. (1973): Orientation and form. New York: Academic Press. Rock, I. (1983): The logic of perception. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Rubin, E. (1915): Synsoplevede Figurer. Kobenhavn, Glydendalske Boghandel. Rubin, E. (1921): Visuell wahrgenommene Figuren. Kobenhavn, Gyldendalske Boghandel. Schumann, F. (1900): Beiträge zur Analyse der Gesichtswahrnehmungen. Zur Schätzung räumlicher Grössen. Zeitschrift für Psychologie und Physiologie der Sinnersorgane 24, 1-33. Spillmann, L. (Eds.) (in press): Max Wertheimer: On Motion and Figure-Ground Organization. MIT Press. Spillmann, L., & Ehrenstein, W.H. (2004): Gestalt factors in the visual neurosciences. In L. Chalupa & J. S. Werner (eds.). The Visual Neurosciences. Cambridge, MA, MIT Press, 1573-1589. Wertheimer, M. (1912a): Über das Denken der Naturvölker. Zeitschrift für Psychologie 60, 321-378. Wertheimer, M. (1912b):Untersuchungen über das Sehen von Bewegung. Zeitschrift für Psychologie 61, 161265. Wertheimer, M. (1922): Untersuchungen zur Lehre von der Gestalt. I. Psychologische Forschung 1, 47-58. Wertheimer, M. (1923): Untersuchungen zur Lehre von der Gestalt II. Psychologische Forschung 4, 301-350. Witkin, H.A., & Asch, S.E. (1948): Studies in space orientation, IV. Further experiments on perception of the upright with displaced visual fields. Journal of Experimental Psychology 38, 762-782. 420 Pinna, What is the Meaning of Shape? Acknowledgments Supported by Finanziamento della Regione Autonoma della Sardegna, ai sensi della L.R. 7 agosto 2007, n. 7, Fondo d’Ateneo (ex 60%) and Alexander von Humboldt Foundation. Baingio Pinna, born 1962, since 2002 Professor of Experimental Psychology and Visual Perception at the University of Sassari. 2001/02 Research Fellow at the Alexander Humboldt Foundation, Freiburg, Germany. 2007 winner of a scientific productivity prize at the University of Sassari, 2009 winner of the International “Wolfgang Metzger Award to eminent people in Gestalt science and research for outstanding achievements”. His main resaerch interests concern Gestalt psychology, visual illusions, psychophysics of perception of shape, motion, color and light, and vision science of art. Address: Facoltà di Lingue e Letterature Straniere, Dipartimento di Scienze dei Linguaggi, University of Sassari, via Roma 151, I-07100 Sassari, Italy. E-Mail: baingio@uniss.it 421 Announcements - Ankündigungen On the occasion of the 100th anniversary of the pivotal publication by Max Wertheimer on the phi-phenomenon in 1912, Wertheimer’s symposium at the convention of the German Society of Psychology Bielefeld, 24th to 27th September 2012 will take place. The symposium will be hosted by Viktor Sarris (University of Frankfurt) and Horst Gundlach (University of Würzburg) in cooperation with the GTA – Society for Gestalt theory and its applications. The preliminary agenda contains contributions by Michael Wertheimer (University of Colorado at Boulder), Lothar Spillmann (Neurocentrum, University medical center Freiburg), Riccardo Luccio (University of Trieste), and Jürgen Kriz (University of Osnabrück). eeeee Aus Anlass des 100jährigen Jubiläums der entscheidenden Publikation von Max Wertheimer zum Phi-Phänomen im Jahre 1912 findet ein Wertheimer-Symposium auf dem Kongress der Deutschen Gesellschaft für Psychologie Bielefeld, 24. – 27. September 2012 statt. Das Symposium wird in Kooperation mit der GTA - Gesellschaft für Gestalttheorie und ihre Anwendungen, von Viktor Sarris (Universität Frankfurt) und Horst Gundlach (Universität Würzburg) veranstaltet. Vorgesehen sind Beiträge von Michael Wertheimer (University of Colorado at Boulder), Lothar Spillmann (Neurocentrum, Universitätsklinikum Freiburg), Riccardo Luccio (University of Trieste) und Jürgen Kriz (Universität Osnabrück). 422 GTA – Symposium Helsinki 29. September 2012 In the anniversary year of Gestalt Theory, the GTA – Society for Gestalt Theory and its Applications – hosts a scientific symposium in Finland for the first time. Interacting with Finnish academics, various topics focusing on Gestalt Theory will be covered. Contributions on the following topics are planned: Gestalt Theory History and Modern, Gestalt Theory in Finland, Gestalt Theory in Art and Culture, Gestalt Theory in Education, Gestalt Theory in Psychotherapy, Gestalt Theory and Design. eeeee Im Jubiläumsjahr der Gestalttheorie veranstaltet die GTA - Gesellschaft für Gestalttheorie und ihre Anwendungen, erstmals ein wissenschaftliches Symposium in Finnland. Gestalttheoretische Schwerpunkte aus verschiedenen Themenbereichen werden in Interaktion mit finnischen Wissenschaftlern behandelt. Geplant sind Beiträge u.a. zu folgenden Themen: Gestalttheorie - Geschichte und Aktualität, Gestalttheorie in Finnland, Gestalttheorie in Kunst und Kultur, Gestalttheorie in Bildung und Erziehung, Gestalttheoretische Psychotherapie, Gestalttheorie und Design. 423 The International SOCIETY FOR GESTALT THEORY AND ITS APPLICATIONS invites submissions for the WOLFGANG METZGER AWARD 2013 This award is named after Wolfgang Metzger, a student of Max Wertheimer and one of the leading members of the second generation of the Berlin Gestalt School. In the first period of this award it was granted by decision of the board of directors of the GTA to eminent people in Gestalt science and research for outstanding achievements. In 1987, the award went to Gaetano Kanizsa and Riccardo Luccio (Italy), in 1989 to Gunnar Johansson (Sweden). Since 1999 the award has been granted every second or third year by the board of directors of the GTA based on an international public award contest and a screening and review of the submittals by an international scientific Award Committee. The first prize winners since 1999 were: Giovanni Bruno Vicario, Italy, and Yoshie Kiritani, Japan; Peter Ulric Tse, USA; Fredrik Sundqvist, Sweden; Cees van Leeuwen, NL/Japan; Baingio Pinna, Italy. Applicants for the Metzger Award 2013 must submit a scientific paper (in English or German) inspired by Gestalt theory and that contributes to the research or the application of Gestalt theory in the physical sciences, the humanities, the social sciences, the economic sciences, or any other field of human studies. Hence, the paper could deal with a subject from psychology, philosophy, medicine, arts, architecture, linguistics, musicology or other fields of research or application of research as long as it is inspired by a Gestalt theoretical approach. The first prize winner will receive € 1000, will be invited as the award speaker to the 18th international Scientific Convention of the GTA in 2013, and the paper will be published in the international multidisciplinary journal Gestalt Theory (www.gestalttheory.net/ gth/) in the submitted version or in an adapted form. Members of the Award Committee for the 2013 contest are: Geert-Jan Boudewijnse (Montreal/Canada; chair), Silvia Bonacchi (Warsaw/Poland), Hellmuth Metz-Göckel (Dortmund/FRG), Baingio Pinna (Sassari/Italy), Fiorenza Toccafondi (Parma/Italy), N.N. Submittals for the Metzger Award 2013 are due by September 2012. The submission must be sent as a Word or a PDF document to the Metzger Award committee at: metzger-award@gestalttheory.net. More information about the international Society for Gestalt Theory and its Applications as well as the Wolfgang Metzger Award 2013 can be found on the website of the Society: www.gestalttheory. net/ 424 Die internationale GESELLSCHAFT FÜR GESTALTTHEORIE UND IHRE ANWENDUNGEN lädt ein zu Einreichungen für den WOLFGANG-METZGER-PREIS 2013 Dieser Preis ist nach Wolfgang Metzger benannt, Schüler von Max Wertheimer und führendem Vertreter der zweiten Generation der Berliner Schule der Gestalttheorie. In einer ersten Periode wurde der Preis über Beschluss des Vorstandes der GTA an verdiente Persönlichkeiten für herausragende Beiträge zur Anwendung der Gestalttheorie in Wissenschaft und Forschung verliehen: 1987 ging der Metzger-Preis in diesem Sinn an Gaetano Kanizsa und Riccardo Luccio (Italien), 1989 an Gunnar Johansson (Schweden). Seit 1999 wird der Preis international öffentlich ausgeschrieben und vom GTA-Vorstand auf Grundlage der Begutachtungsergebnisse und Empfehlungen eines internationalen wissenschaftlichen Preis-Komitees vergeben. Die ersten Preise gingen seither an Giovanni Bruno Vicario (Italien) und Yoshie Kiritani (Japan), Peter Ulric Tse (USA), Fredrik Sundqvist (Schweden), Cees van Leeuwen (NL/Japan), Baingio Pinna (Italien). Für Bewerbungen um den Metzger-Preis 2013 ist ein wissenschaftlicher Beitrag (in Englisch oder Deutsch) einzureichen, der zur Überprüfung und Weiterentwicklung der Gestalttheorie in Forschung oder Anwendung in den Naturwissenschaften, den Humanwissenschaften, den Sozial- und Wirtschaftswissenschaften oder auf einem anderen Gebiet beiträgt. Einreichungen können also beispielsweise aus der Psychologie, Philosophie, Medizin, Kunst, Architektur, den Sprachwissenschaften, der Musikwissenschaft oder auch aus anderen Fachgebieten kommen, solange sie sich in der Behandlung ihres Themas kompetent auf die Gestalttheorie beziehen. Die Gewinnerin bzw. der Gewinner des Metzger-Preises 2013 erhält ein Preisgeld von € 1000 und wird zum Preisträgervortrag bei der 18. internationalen Wissenschaftlichen Arbeitstagung der GTA im Jahr 2013 eingeladen. Die eingereichte Arbeit oder der Preisträgervortrag wird in der internationalen multidisziplinären Zeitschrift Gestalt Theory (www.gestalttheory.net/gth/) veröffentlicht. Mitglieder des Metzger-Preis-Komitees 2013 sind: Geert-Jan Boudewijnse (Montreal/ Kanada; Vorsitz), Silvia Bonacchi (Warschau/Polen), Hellmuth Metz-Göckel (Dortmund /D), Baingio Pinna (Sassari/Italien), Fiorenza Toccafondi (Parma/Italien), N.N. Einsendeschluss für den Metzger-Preis 2013 ist September 2012. Einreichung als Word- oder PDF-Dokument an das Preis-Komitee: metzger-award@ gestalttheory.net. Weitere Informationen über die GTA und den Wolfgang-MetzgerPreis: www.gestalttheory.net/ 425 Gestaltpsychologie und Person Entwicklungen der Gestaltpsychologie Herausgegeben von Giuseppe Galli 154 Seiten, € 18,-ISBN 978 3 901811 43 2 Das vorliegende Buch beschreibt die Beziehungen zwischen Gestalttheorie und Person und ist die Frucht der Arbeit einer Gruppe von Psychologen, die sich mit folgenden Aspekten der Person befassten: die Person und ihr Ich; die Person in Aktion; die Person in Beziehung; die Entstehung der Person; die Person in Dialog; die Person und die Zentrierung. Der hauptsächliche Zugang zur Untersuchung dieser Aspekte ist ein relationaler oder feldtheoretischer, dem zufolge die Faktoren, die das Verhalten bestimmen, nicht nur aus dem innerpersonalen System abgeleitet werden können, sondern auch von den Beziehungen zwischen Individuum und der konkreten Situation, in das es eingebettet ist, abhängen. In der Person-Umwelt-Beziehung haben die Gestalttheoretiker besonders die Ausdrucks- und Wesensqualitäten aufgewertet, die aus dem Objekt-Pol das Ego anzielen. Die Theorie des psychischen Feldes konnte seine Fruchtbarkeit sowohl in den Untersuchungen zur Allgemeinen und Sozial-Psychologie zeigen, als auch in jenen zur Entwicklungspsychologie. In den letzten Jahrzehnten setzte sich das Feldmodell auch im psychoanalytischen Umfeld durch. Das Buch ist sowohl für Studierende als auch für Forschende und Therapeuten von Interesse. Fax: + 43 1 985 21 19-15 | Mail: verlag@krammerbuch.at