Case Report Psychopathology 2003;36:218–220 DOI: 10.1159/000072793 Received: August 28, 2002 Accepted: April 10, 2003 Delusional Paralysis: An Unusual Variant of Cotard’s Syndrome Andreas Reif Waldemar M. Murach Bruno Pfuhlmann Department of Psychiatry and Psychotherapy, University of Würzburg, Würzburg, Germany Key Words Coenaesthesic hallucination W Cotard’s syndrome W Delusional disorder W Electroconvulsive therapy W Nihilistic ideas W Nosology W Psychotic depression Abstract Cotard’s syndrome, a highly impressive psychopathological condition, occurs mainly in depressive disorders and entails nihilistic delusions concerning the body and the non-existing of the self as outstanding features, accompanied by hypochondriacal delusions and ideas of guilt as well as immortality. We here report on a female patient presenting with an unusual variant of the syndrome: most prominently, she had the delusion to be paralysed, although displaying psychomotor agitation, and that neuroleptic agents had devoured her nerve ganglia. Upon ECT, symptoms rapidly improved. Psychopathological implications and the nosological position of Cotard’s syndrome are discussed. Copyright © 2003 S. Karger AG, Basel Introduction Among the generally astonishing uncommon psychiatric syndromes, Cotard’s syndrome (which he himself termed ‘le délire de négation’, coming close to the English translation ‘delusional nihilism’) is one of the most fascinating disorders in both psychological and philosophical terms. Cotard listed the following symptoms of the syn- ABC © 2003 S. Karger AG, Basel 0254–4962/03/0364–0218$19.50/0 Fax + 41 61 306 12 34 E-Mail karger@karger.ch www.karger.com Accessible online at: www.karger.com/psp drome: anxious melancholy, ideas of damnation or possession, a tendency for self-mutilation or suicide, hypochondriac ideas about the non-existence or destruction of inner organs or the whole body, and the idea that one cannot die [1]. The key feature, however, is the delusional belief that parts of the patient’s body or organs are missing or malfunctioning. This is often described with bizarre comparisons, which can extent to the conviction of one’s own death or non-existence. How can a person deny his own existence? This question reflects the intriguing enigma of Cotard’s delusion, resembling an existentialist variant of Epimenides’s paradoxon (Epimenides was the Cretan who coined the famous sentence ‘All Cretans are liars’). Thus, Cotard’s delusion is not the only self-verifying delusion as Pearn at al. [2] suggested, but in fact a self-falsifying delusion and therefore a paradoxon. Cotard’s syndrome can present in many and astonishing clinical pictures, and there is even a manic variant incorporating megalomaniac ideas with bodily illusions of enormity [3]. Depressive ideas, apart from the nihilistic delusion of being dead, include the patients’ denial of the world’s existence, the plea to be buried because the patients believe they are a rotting corpse, the conviction that their bowels and stomach are lacking or that even most parts of their body do not work (examples taken from Enoch and Ball [3]). Here we present a remarkable case of delusional paralysis, which has so far not been described in the literature to this extent and once more demonstrates the amazing multi-facetted appearance of Cotard’s syndrome. Andreas Reif Department of Psychiatry and Psychotherapy University of Würzburg, Füchsleinstrasse 15 DE–97080 Würzburg (Germany) Tel. +49 931 201 76000, Fax +49 931 201 77550, E-Mail a.reif@gmx.net Case Report Discussion Ms P., a 71-year-old retired teacher, had no history of psychiatric illness until the age of 69. Following a suicide attempt, she had been admitted to hospital; she complained of sleep disturbances, restlessness and hypochondriac ideas, and she was described as lamenting. A diagnosis of adjustment disorder and histrionic-anancastic disorder was applied. Following anti-depressant and neuroleptic treatment, she was discharged as almost recovered, however, she soon had to be readmitted due to somatoform symptoms (mainly concerning pollakisuria), which she again described in an anxious and lamenting manner. Furthermore, she worried about stiffness (which could not be objectified), attributed by her to neuroleptic treatment, connected with the fear that her hands had to be amputated and that medical insurance would not pay for treatment. During in-patient treatment, she attempted suicide twice (by means of intoxication and attempted drowning), albeit rather demonstrative. As her condition did not resolve following treatment with lorazepam, risperidone, mirtazapine and trimipramine, she was referred to our department for further diagnostic evaluation. On admission, we saw a well-nourished lady with no prominent cognitive-mnestic deficits or major physical disease apart from severe presbyacusis. Her family history was positive in that her brother had suffered from depression and committed suicide. She complained constantly that both her legs and arms were paralysed, resulting in an inability to move, so that she feared that her extremities had to be amputated and that thereafter she would be damned to live as a ‘helpless torso’. She claimed that the cause for this were neuroleptics still circulating in her blood vessels and devouring her nerve cells, which she could sense in her arms; she stated that she was no longer sure whether she was still alive. The only treatment possible would be instant dialysis. These delusional beliefs were held with unshakable conviction; in a letter, she wrote: ‘My feet and legs, my hands, my cervical vertebra head and my back are paralysed by drugs. Paralysis of the back of the head is yet sensible. If the paralysis progresses, I fear my hands, feet and legs will have to be amputated.’ In striking contrast to her complaints, she was psychomotorically agitated and far from being paralysed. Further psychopathological symptoms were logorrhea, lamenting and depressive mood, although she stated not to suffer from depression. Other depressive ideas were present, e.g. that she had to be imprisoned because of tax fraud and that she was afraid of being entombed alive with a plug in her mouth. Extended laboratory tests, including auto-antibodies, GAD-IIantibodies and amphyphysine-antibodies (to rule out stiff-man syndrome), did not reveal gross abnormalities, neither did ECG, EEG, SEP and cranial MRI. The patient refused lumbar puncture and PET scanning. We initiated treatment with amitryptiline and olanzapine, which slightly relieved her agitation but brought about no change with respect to her delusions of being paralysed. Thus electroconvulsive therapy (ECT) was applied, which was well tolerated and proved to be effective: following 8 treatments, Ms P. stated not to suffer any longer from paralysis, and other delusional contents or depressive ideas had also disappeared. Her mood was well, and she proved to be a witty and charming lady, sharply contrasting her personality on admission. She received maintenance therapy with olanzapine and mirtazapine after ECT discontinuation, and her situation had not deteriorated by the 5-week follow-up. Slight cognitive deficits could be observed, such as affective lability, loss of distance and mental rigidity, so we applied the ICD-10 diagnosis of organic affective disorder. To the best of our knowledge, this is the first report on delusional paralysis in medical literature. Strikingly, the delusion was held with unshakable belief against all overt evidence, i.e. psychomotor agitation. We feel that it is justified to regard the symptomatology of Ms P. as a variant of Cotard’s syndrome: the delusional content was of the nihilistic and hypochondriacal type (she thought that parts of her body did not function well, feared to be buried alive, and was at times not sure whether she was still living or not), accompanied by ideas of guilt and agitated depression. Characteristically, the syndrome had been of sudden onset, without a previous history of psychiatric disorder but a typical period of initial anxiety. Thus our patient featured the most frequent symptoms of Cotard’s syndrome as reported by Berrios and Luque [4]. A predominance of women in their later years has been reported [3], as was Ms P., and she presented with clinical evidence of the organic substrates suggested to play a role in Cotard’s delusion [5]. As suggested by other authors [6–8], ECT proved to be an efficient and well-tolerated treatment with sustained efficacy. There is considerable debate whether Cotard’s delusion is syndromal in nature or a distinct nosological entity. Based on a literature survey of 100 cases, Berrios and Luque [4] reported three basic factors of nihilistic delusion by means of a factor analysis, arguing for nosological unspecificity: psychotic depression, Cotard type I (which resembles a pure form of the syndrome, closer to delusional than to affective disorder) and Cotard type II (which constitutes a mixed group, displaying symptoms of the schizophrenic spectrum as well as of affective psychoses). Following this factor-analytic approach, our patient most likely belongs to the ‘psychotic depression’ type. The authors agree with Enoch and Ball [3] that Cotard’s delusion, defined narrowly, represents a highly specific and clear-cut syndrome, not a distinct nosological entity. However, the most challenging question concerns the neurobiological underpinnings of nihilistic delusions. There are two psychopathological key symptoms that might help to elucidate this. First, there appears to be a connection between Cotard’s syndrome (in its narrower definition) and depression, which is primarily a disorder of the thymopsyche. Depressive patients often claim to feel nothing at all, a condition which bears some similarity to the negation of one’s own existence; furthermore, depression often goes along with somatic symptoms. Second, Cotard’s delusion is accompanied by erroneous beliefs about the own body, often including inner organs, Delusional Paralysis Psychopathology 2003;36:218–220 219 but – as our case demonstrates – also extremities and thus visible body parts. These misperceptions do not seem to be of the coenaesthetic-hallucinatory type seen in schizophrenic disorders: the patient states that his organs do not function, have disappeared, etc., but usually he does not claim to actually feel this, which raises the question whether the patient suffers from wrong perceptions or from wrong judgements about his somatic state. This very specific symptom of Cotard’s syndrome differentiates it from coenaesthetic schizophrenia, and it suggests that the biological substrate of the delusion does not primarily involve the sensory perception of the body. Rather, it seems to involve a disordered somatopsyche, a term coined by Wernicke [9] to designate the concept of an integrating self-consciousness of the body. This prompts the question which associations between malfunctions of the somatopsyche and thymopsyche exist, and if and how both play a part in Cotard’s syndrome. An interesting, albeit highly speculative hypothesis to resolve this issue is based on Damasio’s theory of emotion and consciousness [10, 11]. Briefly (and very much simplified), Damasio proposes that sensory input from the body is represented in neuronal maps which are inter alia the basis for emotions, which, in turn, assist in generating what Damasio terms ‘extended consciousness’. Damasio pointed out a remarkable functional cross-over of the brain stem and cingulate cortex in regulating homeostasis, body perception, emotion, arousal, learning and consciousness. According to his theories, any disturbance of those second-order neuronal maps of body perception – the functional basis of the ‘somatopsyche’ – will lead to specific changes in the subject’s emotions (the ‘thymopsyche’) and, eventually, in the person’s consciousness or self-awareness. In terms of classic psychopathology (along the lines of Wernicke) one could here postulate a specific association between the somatopsyche and the auto- psyche representing the consciousness of one’s body and personal integrity – in contrast to the allopsyche, which represents the consciousness of the external world. We thus hypothesise that, in Cotard’s syndrome, the primary defect is a functional disturbance in sensory second-order neuronal maps or their integration, i.e. a somatopsychic disturbance, leading to emotional disorder and, in severe cases, to specific changes in consciousness – which psychopathologically imposes as the conviction to be nonexisting. Therefore, the most interesting anatomical target structure for Cotard’s delusion would be, in our opinion, the cingulate gyrus, integrating input from visceral organs and the musculoskeletal system as well as playing a role in emotions and consciousness. Independently of the postulated neurobiological correlates, Cotard’s syndrome seems to be a nosologically inconsistent condition. In the majority of cases, it could be interpreted as a form of depressive delusional ideas associated with other depressive symptoms. In some cases, an association with megalomaniac ideas (délire d’énormité) is described, where the megalomaniac ideas are typically of a very extreme character, including absurdities like the merging of one’s body with the whole universe [3]. Such symptoms can typically be seen in specific forms of schizophrenic psychoses, e.g. phantastic paraphrenia according to Leonhard’s differentiated nosology [12]. On the other hand, in anxiety psychosis, a subform of Leonhard’s cycloid psychoses, states of extreme anxiety, with ideas of threat and annihilation, may occur, leading to transient nihilistic delusions. Thus Cotard’s syndrome, in our opinion, represents a symptomatologically highly impressive and interesting but nosologically non-specific condition. However, its investigation should be pursued as it could yield important insights into the psychobiological underpinnings of psychopathological symptoms. References 1 Cotard J: Du délire des négations. Arch Neurol (Paris) 1882;6:209–295. 2 Pearn J, Gardner-Thorpe C: Jules Cotard (1840–1889): His life and the unique syndrome which bears his name. Neurology 2002;58: 1400–1403. 3 Enoch D, Ball H: Uncommon Psychiatric Syndromes, ed 4. London, Arnold, 2001. 4 Berrios GE, Luque R: Cotard’s syndrome: Analysis of 100 cases. Acta Psychiatr Scand 1995;91:185–188. 220 5 Joseph AB, O’Leary DH: Brain atrophy and interhemispheric fissure enlargement in Cotard’s syndrome. J Clin Psychiatry 1986;47: 518–520. 6 Petracca G, Migliorelli R, Vazquez S, Starkstein SE: SPECT findings before and after ECT in a patient with major depression and Cotard’s syndrome. J Neuropsychiatry Clin Neurosci 1995;7:505–507. 7 Lohmann T, Nishimura K, Sabri O, Klosterkotter J: Successful electroconvulsive therapy of Cotard syndrome with bitemporal hypoperfusion. Nervenarzt 1996;67:400–403 [in German]. Psychopathology 2003;36:218–220 8 Yamada K, Katsuragi S, Fujii I: A case study of Cotard’s syndrome: Stages and diagnosis. Acta Psychiatr Scand 1999;100:396–398. 9 Wernicke C: Grundriss der Psychiatrie in klinischen Vorlesungen, ed 2. Leipzig, Thieme, 1906. 10 Damasio AR: The Feeling of What Happens: Body and Emotion in the Making of Consciousness, ed 1. London, Heinemann, 2000. 11 Damasio AR: Descartes’ Error: Emotion, Reason, and the Human Brain, ed 1. New York, Putnam, 1994. 12 Leonhard K: The Classification of Endogenous Psychoses, ed 5. New York, Irvington, 1979. Reif/Murach/Pfuhlmann