A:\Waite.art.doc Printed On: 5/6/99 4:19:00 PM 81 Agostini v. Felton: Thickening the Establishment Clause Stew Jason M. Waite* Liberty finds no refuge in a jurisprudence of doubt. 1 I. INTRODUCTION 2 In Agostini v. Felton, the United States Supreme Court reversed its controversial 1985 decision in Aguilar v. Felton, 3 holding that a federally funded program providing supplemental, remedial instruction by government employees to disadvantaged children, on a neutral basis on school premises, including sectarian schools, is not invalid under the Establishment Clause.4 In Aguilar, the Court had held that a local government’s use of federal Title I funds to provide remedial educational services by public school teachers in parochial schools violated the First Amendment’s Establishment Clause.5 On remand following Aguilar, the district court enjoined the Board of Education of the City of New York “from using public funds for any plan or program under [Title I] to the extent that it requires, authorizes or permits public school teachers and guidance counselors to provide teaching and counseling services on the premises of sectarian schools within New York City.”6 Associate, Grunfeld, Desiderio, Lebowitz & Silverman, LLP, Atlanta, Georgia; J.D., with distinction, Emory University School of Law, Atlanta, Georgia; B.A., cum laude, Middlebury College, Middlebury, Vermont. 1. Planned Parenthood of Southeastern Pa. v. Casey, 505 U.S. 833, 844 (1992) (O’Connor, J.). 2. 117 S. Ct. 1997 (1997), rev’g, Aguilar v. Felton, 473 U.S. 402 (1985). 3. 473 U.S. 402 (1985). 4. 117 S. Ct. at 2006-17. 5. 473 U.S. at 414. 6. Agostini, 117 S. Ct. at 2005 (quoting Application to Petition for Certiorari at A25-A26, Aguilar v. Felton, 473 U.S. 402 (1985) (No. 96-533)). * 81 A:\Waite.art.doc 82 Printed On: 5/6/99 4:19:00 PM NEW ENGLAND LAW REVIEW [Vol. 33:1 The effect of this injunction, often forcing a seemingly artificial movement of special education programs from parochial school premises to costly mobile instructional units adjacent to the schools,7 highlights the rationality of the Court’s decision in Agostini from a policy standpoint.8 Indeed, Aguilar had been condemned as overly rigid and the product of delusions of a popish plot.9 Surely, critics charged, it is sound policy to “give economically disadvantaged children a better chance at success in life,”10 regardless of whether they attend public or parochial schools. In Agostini, the Court reconsidered the constitutionality of Title I of the Elementary and Secondary Education Act of 1965,11 which channels federal funds through the states to “local educational agencies” (LEAs).12 LEAs spend the funds to provide remedial education, guidance, and job counseling to eligible students,13 defined as those: “(i) who reside within the attendance boundaries of a public school located in a low-income area;14 and (ii) who are failing, or at risk of failing, the State’s student performance standards.”15 Title I requires that funds be made available on an equitable basis to children attending private as well as public schools.16 However, Congress saw fit to place limitations on LEAs provision of services to children enrolled in private schools. In particular, the Title I services themselves must be “secular, neutral, and non-ideological,”17 and according to federal regulations, must “supplement, and in no case supplant, the level of services” already provided by the private school.18 Agostini reaches the Court as an appeal from a denial of petitioners’ Federal Rule of Civil Procedure 60(b)(5) motion for relief from the Agui7. See Linda Greenhouse, Court Eases Curb on Providing Aid in Church Schools, N.Y. TIMES, June 24, 1997, at A1. 8. See Agostini, 117 S. Ct. at 2013. But see id. at 2022 (Souter, J., dissenting) (defending the off-premises logic). When Aguilar was handed down, it was estimated that some 20,000 economically disadvantaged children in New York City alone would experience a decline in Title I services. See Aguilar, 473 U.S. at 431 (O’Connor, J., dissenting). 9. See Bruce Fein, Even Handed Aid Where Needed?, W ASH. TIMES , November 12, 1996, at A20. Indeed, the Agostini decision was praised by many, including the Clinton Administration and New York City Mayor Rudolph Giuliani, as undoing a wrongheaded case. See Greenhouse, supra note 7, at A1. 10. Agostini, 117 S. Ct. at 2018. 11. 20 U.S.C. §§ 6301-38 (1994). 12. Id. at §§ 6311-12. 13. See id. at § 6315(c)(1)(A)-(H). 14. Id. at § 6313(a)(2)(B). 15. Id. at § 6315(b)(1)(B). 16. See id. at § 6321(a). 17. 20 U.S.C. § 6321(a)(2) (1994). 18. 34 C.F.R. § 200.12(a) (1996). A:\Waite.art.doc Fall, 1998] Printed On: 5/6/99 4:19:00 PM ESTABLISHMENT CLAUSE 83 lar-based injunction.19 Joined by Chief Justice Rehnquist and Justices Scalia, Kennedy and Thomas, Justice O’Connor’s majority opinion asserted that because a court may recognize subsequent changes in both statutory and decisional law, the “threshold issue” in reviewing the denial of the Rule 60(b)(5) motion in Agostini is “whether the factual or legal landscape has changed since Aguilar [was decided].”20 Because of the lack of any factual change, the success of petitioners’ Rule 60(b)(5) motion is predicated on whether the law of the Establishment Clause had changed since Aguilar, or, in Justice O’Connor’s words, whether subsequent Establishment Clause cases “have so undermined Aguilar that it is no longer good law.”21 Despite the lower courts’ straightforward denial of the 60(b)(5) motion because Aguilar had not been overruled, the majority in Agostini concluded that Establishment Clause law had changed since the original decision in Aguilar and its companion case, School District of Grand Rapids v. Ball. 22 Justice O’Connor’s opinion addressed several assumptions underpinning the reasoning of both Aguilar and Ball, and concluded that none of them remain valid under the Court’s current understanding of the Establishment Clause.23 The majority opinion relied heavily on its interpretation of two post-Aguilar decisions, Zobrest v. Catalina Foothills School District24 and Witters v. Washington Department of Services for the Blind. 25 Based on these interim cases, the Court found that the “understanding of the criteria used to assess whether aid to religion has an impermissible effect” has changed.26 Justice Souter delivered a vigorous dissent defending the constitutional reasoning of Aguilar and challenging the Court’s interpretations of Zobrest and Witters. Souter assailed the Court’s claims that Zobrest and Witters effected changes in Establishment Clause law, and specifically attempted to refute the argument that those cases altered the salience of the assumptions upon which Aguilar and Ball were based. In short, Souter emphasized that the Court may disagree with the assumptions and the holdings of Aguilar and Ball, but that “its disagreement is fresh law.”27 Justice Ginsburg’s separate dissent criticizes the Court’s decision effecAgostini v. Felton, 117 S. Ct. 1997, 2000 (1997). Id. at 2007. Id. at 2000. See id. at 2000-01 (citing School Dist. of Grand Rapids v. Ball, 473 U.S. 373 (1985)). 23. See id. at 2010. 24. 509 U.S. 1 (1993). 25. 474 U.S. 481 (1986). 26. Agostini, 117 S. Ct. at 2010. 27. Id. at 2023 (Souter, J., dissenting). 19. 20. 21. 22. A:\Waite.art.doc 84 Printed On: 5/6/99 4:19:00 PM NEW ENGLAND LAW REVIEW [Vol. 33:1 tively to reconsider Aguilar under the guise of reviewing a denial of a Rule 60(b)(5) motion.28 Ginsburg surveyed decisional law on this procedural rule and concluded that such a motion does not present the opportunity for relitigation of the legal or factual claims underlying a prior judgment.29 According to Ginsburg, the sole question presented on an appeal of a decision to deny a 60(b)(5) motion is whether “the District Court abuse[d] its discretion when it concluded that neither the facts nor the law had so changed as to warrant alteration of the injunction.”30 Indeed, Aguilar, until it was overruled by the decision in Agostini, remained the governing Establishment Clause law. Therefore, denial of petitioners’ 60(b)(5) motion by the lower courts was proper.31 For Ginsburg, the Court’s acknowledgment that the lower court denials of the motion were proper, while then proceeding with its own reconsideration of Aguilar, transformed Rule 60(b)(5) into a license for collateral attack on a previous decision and undermined the integrity of the Court as a non-agenda setting body.32 Students of the Establishment Clause will likely be unable to find any doctrinal clarification in this highly unconventional decision. To the contrary, the case leaves open questions about the continued significance of the three-part Lemon v. Kurtzman33 test, as well as the future of Justice O’Connor’s oft-articulated “endorsement test,” which had been picked by many as the successor-in-waiting to Lemon. 34 Moreover, after analyzing the procedural method by which Agostini reached the Supreme Court, this Article will argue that the Court’s paradoxically declaring a change in Establishment Clause law while simultaneously finding that the law had already changed for purposes of Rule 60(b)(5) undermines the weight and integrity of the decision.35 At the least, the Court’s willingness in Agostini to give capacious readings to its own precedents, while at the same time claiming that it is simply recognizing changes in Establishment Clause law that have already occurred, reifies the often whimsical, even capriSee id. at 2026-28. See id. at 2027 (Ginsburg, J., dissenting) (citing 11 W RIGHT ET AL., FEDERAL PRACTICE AND PROCEDURE § 2863 (2d ed. 1995)). 30. Id. at 2027. 31. See id. 32. See Agostini, 117 S. Ct. at 2028. 33. 403 U.S. 602 (1971). 34. See, e.g., Steven D. Smith, Symbols, Perceptions, and Doctrinal Illusions: Establishment Neutrality and the ‘No Endorsement’ Test, 86 M ICH. L. REV. 266, 267 (1987) (“O’Connor’s ‘no endorsement’ test seems at the moment to be the heir apparent. By offering her proposal as a ‘clarification’ of the Lemon test, O’Connor has facilitated a smooth transition to the no endorsement approach.”). 35. See Agostini, 117 S. Ct. at 2027-28 (Ginsburg, J., dissenting). 28. 29. A:\Waite.art.doc Fall, 1998] Printed On: 5/6/99 4:19:00 PM ESTABLISHMENT CLAUSE 85 cious, nature of establishment jurisprudence. First, Part II of this Article will place Agostini in the context of the relevant Establishment Clause precedents of the Court.36 Part III will analyze closely the reasoning of the three opinions generated in the case.37 Part IV will argue that the decision is jurisprudentially suspect and unlikely to elucidate further the meaning of the Establishment Clause.38 Finally, this Article suggests a few legal principles or trends that the case may evince.39 II. THE LAW OF ESTABLISHMENT CLAUSE: FROM AGUILAR TO AGOSTINI The main paradigm for Establishment Clause analysis has been Lemon v. Kurtzman. 40 In that case, Chief Justice Burger synthesized “the cumulative criteria developed by the Court over many years . . . .”41 First, [that a] statute must have a secular legislative purpose; second, that its principal or primary effect must be one that neither advances nor inhibits religion; [and] finally, that the statute does not foster an excessive government entanglement with religion.”42 A. Aguilar In Aguilar v. Felton, 43 taxpayers challenged the New York City Board of Education’s use of federal Title I funds to pay the salaries of public employees teaching secular remedial education classes to needy children in both private and parochial schools.44 Remedial and enhancement instruction was being provided at public expense to classes comprised of statutorily eligible parochial school students in their private school buildings.45 Of the students eligible to receive funds in 1981-1982, 13.2% were enrolled in private schools; of that group, 93% attended religious schools.46 In Aguilar, it was the individual student focus of the Title I program that might have weighed against a finding of unconstitutionality, as funds See infra notes 40-155 and accompanying text. See infra notes 156-237 and accompanying text. See infra notes 237-82 and accompanying text. See infra notes 283-317 and accompanying text. 403 U.S. 602 (1971). Id. at 612. Id. (citations omitted). 473 U.S. 402 (1985). See id. at 404-06; see also supra notes 10-17 and accompanying text (discussing the administration of Title I programs). 45. See id. at 409. 46. See id. at 406. 36. 37. 38. 39. 40. 41. 42. 43. 44. A:\Waite.art.doc 86 Printed On: 5/6/99 4:19:00 PM NEW ENGLAND LAW REVIEW [Vol. 33:1 were arguably given to eligible students via the LEAs, not directly to any school, private or public.47 In addition to having strict rules for the participating publicly-employed teachers to avoid contact with the religious school’s personnel and programs and ban all religious materials from their classrooms, New York City adopted a system for monitoring the religious content (or lack thereof) of publicly funded Title I classes held in religious schools.48 Nevertheless, the Second Circuit in Felton v. Secretary, Department of Education reversed the district court’s decision that the Title I program was constitutional, holding that the Establishment Clause “constitutes an insurmountable barrier to the use of federal funds to send public school teachers and other professionals into religious schools to carry on instruction, remedial or otherwise.”49 In 1985, when the Supreme Court decided Aguilar, the Lemon test was the controlling analytical framework.50 Under the three-part test from Lemon, 51 failure under any one of the prongs renders consideration of the others unnecessary.52 The Court in Aguilar rested its decision of unconstitutionality primarily on the excessive entanglement of church and state created by the monitoring system and did not directly address whether the program was violative of the Establishment Clause because of its primary effect.53 The Court articulated the logic inherent in the excessive entanglement prong of Lemon, stating “that neither the State nor Federal Government shall promote or hinder a particular faith or faith generally 47. See supra notes 11-18 and accompanying text; see also Witters v. Wash. Dept. of Serv’s for the Blind, 474 U.S. 481, 487-88 (1986) (finding that disbursement of aid provided directly to a student who then chose to use the funds for religious education is permissible under the Establishment Clause). 48. See Aguilar, 473 U.S. at 406-07. 49. Felton v. Sec’y, Dept. of Ed., 739 F.2d 48, 49-50 (citing Meek v. Pittenger, 421 U.S. 349, 367-72 (1975)); see also Wolman v. Walter, 433 U.S. 229 (1977). 50. Only after 1985 did the first indications of the Court’s dissatisfaction with the Lemon test surface and several refinements of the test, as well as alternative conceptions of the Establishment Clause, begin to appear in the opinions of different Justices. See Daniel O. Conkle, Lemon Lives, 43 CASE W. RES. L. REV. 865, 865-66 (1993); see also discussion infra notes 127-44 and accompanying text (regarding dissatisfaction with the Lemon test). 51. See supra notes 33-35 and accompanying text (discussing the three-part Lemon inquiry). 52. See Lemon, 403 U.S. at 612-13. 53. See Aguilar, 473 U.S. at 413 (“This pervasive monitoring by public authorities in the sectarian schools infringes precisely those Establishment Clause values at the root of the prohibition of excessive entanglement.”). Excessive entanglement is, again, the third prong of the test set forth in Lemon: “(i) the statute must have a secular legislative purpose; (ii) its principal or primary effect must be one that neither inhibits nor advances religion; and (iii) it must not foster an excessive government entanglement with religion.” Id. A:\Waite.art.doc Fall, 1998] Printed On: 5/6/99 4:19:00 PM ESTABLISHMENT CLAUSE 87 through the advancement of benefits or through the excessive entanglement of church and state in the administration of those benefits.”54 However, it is worth noting that before resting its holding strictly on excessive entanglement, the Court commented on the monitoring system that appellants had argued immunized their administration of Title I programs. “At best, the supervision in this case would assist in preventing the Title I program from being used, intentionally or unwittingly, to inculcate the religious beliefs of the surrounding parochial school.”55 This analysis by the Court in Aguilar suggests that, aside from the entanglement problem, the Court could have found the program at issue in Aguilar to have the primary effect of advancing or inhibiting religion, thus violating the second prong of Lemon and being equally constitutionally impermissible. More broadly, this suggests that the Establishment Clause prevents more than simply the intentional or obvious confluence of church and state. Indeed, much of the Court’s case law has recognized the preventive role of the establishment guarantee and the circumspection that is warranted.56 B. Ball In School District of Grand Rapids v. Ball,57 the companion case to Aguilar, the School District of Grand Rapids was challenged for hiring public school teachers to teach remedial subjects in a special Shared Time Program offered in non-public schools.58 Simultaneously challenged was a similarly administered program called Community Education, through which various courses were offered to all members of the community and taught at non-public schools, mostly by sectarian school teachers hired by the Board of Education.59 While the programs took place on the premises of the private schools, unlike in Aguilar, the school district in Ball set up a leasing system whereby the private school classrooms used for the programs were “leased” from the private schools by the district.60 However, the Court discounted any mitigating effect of this arrangement.61 Overall, forty of the forty-one schools at which the programs challenged in Ball operated were sectarian in character, an even greater proportion of paroId. at 414. Id. at 409. See infra notes 64-81 and accompanying text (including quotations from Lemon, Meek, and Bowen). 57. 473 U.S. 373 (1985). 58. See id. at 375-76. 59. See id. at 375-77. 60. See id. at 377-78. 61. See id. 54. 55. 56. A:\Waite.art.doc 88 Printed On: 5/6/99 4:19:00 PM NEW ENGLAND LAW REVIEW [Vol. 33:1 chial school involvement than in Aguilar. 62 Unlike its handling of Aguilar, in Ball the Court fully applied the effects prong of the Lemon test and expressly affirmed the salience of the threepart test noting that, “[w]e therefore reaffirm that state action alleged to violate the Establishment Clause should be measured against the Lemon criteria.”63 However, the reasoning of Justice Brennan’s majority opinion did not rest solely on a straightforward application of Lemon. First, discussing one of the long competing principles of the Establishment Clause, the no-funding principle, Brennan wrote early in his analysis of Ball that, “[t]he Establishment Clause primarily proscribes ‘sponsorship, financial support, and active involvement of the sovereign in religious activity.’”64 Another element present in the Ball analysis is the Court’s focus on the nature of the religious schools in which the programs were operating. Based on the findings of the district court, the Court in Ball concluded that at these religious schools, “the secular education . . . goes hand in hand with the religious mission that is the only reason for the schools’ existence. Within the institution, the two are intertwined.”65 In its application of Lemon, the Court summarily concluded that the programs passed the first prong of the test.66 The purpose of the programs was “manifestly secular.”67 Thus, the question presented was whether the primary effect of the challenged programs was to advance or inhibit religion.68 Given the “pervasively sectarian” nature of the schools where the programs were operating,69 the Court concluded that the challenged programs may have impermissibly advanced religion in three ways: (i) the participating teachers may inculcate particular religious beliefs; (ii) the programs may provide a symbolic link between government and religion, especially in the eyes of impressionable youngsters; and (iii) the programs may directly promote religion by impermissibly providing a subsidy to the primary religious mission of the institutions affected.70 The Court assessed each of these potential constitutional infirmities and concluded that See id. at 379. School Dist. of Grand Rapids v. Ball, 473 U.S. 383 (1985). See id. at 381 (citing Comm. for Pub. Educ. & Religious Liberty v. Nyquist, 413 U.S. 756, 772 (1973); see also Zorach v. Clauson, 343 U.S. 306, 314 (1952) (“Government may not finance religious groups nor undertake religious instruction nor blend secular and sectarian education . . . .”). But see Rosenberger v. University, 515 U.S. 819, 843 (1995). 65. Ball, 473 U.S. at 383 (quoting Lemon, 403 U.S. at 657). 66. Id. at 383. 67. See id. 68. See id. 69. Id. at 385. 70. Id. 62. 63. 64. A:\Waite.art.doc Fall, 1998] Printed On: 5/6/99 4:19:00 PM ESTABLISHMENT CLAUSE 89 there is at least a risk of all three problems, thus rendering the programs unconstitutional.71 In the Court’s discussion of the potential inculcation of religious beliefs by teachers, the prophylactic nature of the Establishment Clause mandate is illustrated. Declaring one of the absolutes of the Establishment Clause to be the prohibition on “government-financed or government-sponsored indoctrination into the beliefs of a particular religious faith,”72 the Court cited Lemon’s admonition that “[t]he State must be certain . . . that subsidized teachers do not inculcate religion.”73 Similarly, the Court refers to Meek v. Pittenger,74 where it was held that a program of loaning state-paid instructors to sectarian schools was impermissible.75 As the Court in Ball made clear, the holding in Meek was not because the publicly employed teachers were inculcating religious beliefs, but because they potentially could, and this constituted “an unacceptable risk.”76 When applying these rationales to the programs under challenge in Ball, the Court simply found that, despite a presumption of good faith on the part of the publicly employed teachers in both programs, “there is a substantial risk that programs operating in this environment [of sectarian schools] would be used for religious educational purposes.”77 However, the Court failed to articulate any powerful reasoning for the acceptance of this risk-averse rationale as applied to the Shared Time Program. While the Community Education Program under challenge employed mostly professional religious school teachers with whom the risk of inadvertent inculcation during the teaching of secular subjects seemed legitimate, with the Shared Time Program teachers, usually teaching in public schools but enlisted to teach remedial subjects to parochial school students, the risk, if any, seemed far from “substantial.”78 Regardless of whether the Court’s circumspection appropriately rose to this level, because the inculcation problem was simply one of the ways that the challenged programs may have impermissibly advanced religion, the failure to solidify the basis for finding a risk of inculcation in the Shared Time Program would not alone Ball, 473 U.S. at 387, 392, 396. Id. at 385. Id. (quoting Lemon, 403 U.S. at 619) (emphasis added). 421 U.S. 349 (1975). Ball, 473 U.S. at 384-85 (quoting Meek, 421 U.S. at 370). Id. Id. at 388. See id. at 398-400 (O’Connor, J., concurring in the judgment in part and dissenting in part) (agreeing that the Community Education Program is unconstitutional but arguing that the Shared Time Program is not because there is no reason to believe that public school teachers coming into parochial schools will violate orders and inculcate religion). 71. 72. 73. 74. 75. 76. 77. 78. A:\Waite.art.doc 90 Printed On: 5/6/99 4:19:00 PM NEW ENGLAND LAW REVIEW [Vol. 33:1 have allowed the program to overcome the constraints of the Establishment Clause. Like the concern over the risk of inculcation, the Court’s analysis of the potential symbolic union of church and state created by the programs reflected a degree of circumspection.79 The symbolic union inquiry is necessarily focused on the potentially harmful effect of appearances. As the Court in Ball notes: Government promotes religion as effectively when it fosters a close identification of its powers and responsibilities with those of any—or all—religious denominations as when it attempts to inculcate specific religious doctrines. If this identification conveys a message of government endorsement or disapproval of religion, a core purpose of the Establishment Clause is 80 violated. As the Court reasoned, the scrutiny applied to a union when assessing its symbolic impact is logically heightened when the symbolic union will directly reach children of tender years.81 By its very nature, the symbolic union query has the potential to render seemingly inane distinctions in the administration of a government program constitutionally dispositive. Indeed, the Court in Ball recognized this when it compared McCollum v. Board of Education, 82 (which held religious instructors coming onto public school premises unconstitutional) to Zorach v. Clauson83 (which held a similar religious instruction program conducted off the premises of public schools constitutional). “The difference in the symbolic impact helps to explain the difference between the cases.”84 Applying these concerns over symbolism to both of the programs under challenge in Ball, the Court concluded that because the classes take place in parochial school buildings, “the students would be unlikely to discern the crucial difference between the religious school classes and the ‘public school’ classes, even if the latter were successfully kept free of religious indoctrination.”85 79. See generally Bowen v. Kendrick, 487 U.S. 589, 648 (1988) (Blackmun, J., dissenting) (“[The Establishment Clause] calls for fundamentally conservative decisionmaking: our cases do not require a plaintiff to demonstrate that a government action necessarily promotes religion, but simply that it creates such a substantial risk.”) (emphasis in original). 80. Ball, 473 U.S. at 389. See also Lynch v. Donnelly, 465 U.S. 668, 688 (1984) (O’Connor, J., concurring). (“Endorsement sends a message to nonadherents that they are outsiders, not full members of the political community, and an accompanying message to adherents that they are insiders, favored members of the political community.”). 81. Ball, 473 U.S. at 390. 82. 333 U.S. 203 (1948). 83. 343 U.S. 306 (1952). 84. Ball, 473 U.S. at 391. 85. Id. A:\Waite.art.doc Fall, 1998] Printed On: 5/6/99 4:19:00 PM ESTABLISHMENT CLAUSE 91 Thus the young students would witness “a powerful symbol of state endorsement and encouragement of the religious beliefs” that are taught in the same classroom at other times.86 Accordingly, the programs were deemed to have an unconstitutional effect.87 The final way in which the challenged programs in Ball may have had the impermissible effect of advancing religion could have been the easiest to ascertain. However, while it is unconstitutional for a government program effectively to provide a subsidy to the religious mission of sectarian schools, “[t]he Court has never accepted the mere possibility of subsidization . . . as sufficient to invalidate an aid program.”88 With this problem, the Court is not concerned with risk, as it is with the inculcation pitfall, or with the amorphous effect of symbolism. As the Court in Ball made clear, if the effect of the proffered aid is direct and substantial it is impermissible, whereas if the effect is “indirect and incidental” the program will pass constitutional muster.89 After reiterating its recognition of the dual function of sectarian schools to provide secular education while promoting a religious perspective,90 the Court reasoned that the programs challenged in Ball were the “kind of direct aid to the educational function of the religious school [that] is indistinguishable from the provision of a direct cash subsidy to the religious school that is most clearly prohibited under the Establishment Clause.”91 The Court rejected the argument that the challenged aid was provided directly to the students rather than to the religious schools,92 concluding that where “no meaningful distinction can be made between aid to the student and aid to the school,” the concept of aid “to individuals is a transparent Id. at 392. See id. Id. at 394. Ball, 473 U.S. at 394. Cf. Bd. of Ed. v. Allen, 392 U.S. 236 (1968) (upholding program providing loans of secular textbooks to nonpublic school students) with Comm. for Pub. Educ. & Religious Liberty v. Nyquist, 413 U.S. 756, 780-94 (1973) (striking down state tax schemes providing for tuition grants and tax benefits for parents whose children attend religious schools). 90. Ball, 473 U.S. at 395. See also supra notes 58-62 and accompanying text (discussing the importance of the secular nature of the schools where the programs operated). 91. Ball, 473 U.S. at 395. For another formulation of the direct/indirect inquiry, see Wolman v. Walter, 433 U.S. 229, 259 (1977) (Marshall, J., concurring in part and dissenting in part) (arguing that a “line . . . should be placed between [acceptable] general welfare programs that serve children in sectarian schools because the schools happen to be a convenient place to reach the programs’ target populations and [unacceptable] programs of educational assistance.”). See also Allen, 392 U.S. 236, 252-54 (1968) (Black, J., dissenting) (arguing for the same type of distinction between direct and indirect aid as Justice Marshall in Wolman). 92. See Ball, 473 U.S. at 396. 86. 87. 88. 89. A:\Waite.art.doc 92 Printed On: 5/6/99 4:19:00 PM NEW ENGLAND LAW REVIEW [Vol. 33:1 fiction.”93 Finally, the Court rejected the petitioners’ argument that the subsidy provided by these programs could not be substantial because the courses offered were supplemental, “not previously offered in the schools . . . and not required by school rule or state regulation.”94 The Court reasoned that “there . . . [was] no way of knowing whether the religious schools . . . [may] have offered” these types of courses in the absence of the programs, and then commented that the general subject matter of these supplemental subjects was indeed similar to that offered in the religious schools.95 Moreover, according to the Court, “[t]o let the genie out of the bottle in this case would be to permit ever larger segments of the religious school curriculum to be turned over to the public school system . . . .”96 Therefore, by concluding that the challenged programs had the primary effect of advancing religion in three different ways, the Court held both of them violative of the Establishment Clause.97 Adhering to the Lemon test and giving a lengthy second prong effects analysis upon which the decision could rest, the Court found it unnecessary to engage in the third prong of the Lemon inquiry—whether the programs impermissibly entangled religion and government.98 C. Witters Decided the term after Aguilar and Ball, Witters v. Wash. Dept. of Serv’s. for the Blind99 addressed the challenge of a blind man who had applied for and been denied, because of state interpretation of Establishment Clause requirements, special educational assistance under a Washington statute that authorized financial aid for qualified blind persons seeking to further themselves educationally.100 The Court, applying the three-part Lemon test, held that the Establishment Clause was not a bar to the state issuing a tuition grant to petitioner who planned to use the money to attend a Christian college.101 As in Ball, there was no dispute over the Id. at 396 (citing Wolman v. Walter, 433 U.S. at 264). Id. Id. Id. at 397. See id. See Ball, 473 U.S. at 397 n.14; but see Aguilar v. Felton, 473 U.S. 402 (1985). 99. 474 U.S. 481 (1986). 100. See id. at 483-84. 101. See id. at 484-85. Interestingly, the Court declined to address petitioner’s argument that the Free Exercise Clause would bar a more stringent interpretation of the Washington State Establishment Clause forbidding petitioner's receipt of aid. See id. at 489-90. 93. 94. 95. 96. 97. 98. A:\Waite.art.doc Fall, 1998] Printed On: 5/6/99 4:19:00 PM ESTABLISHMENT CLAUSE 93 secular purpose of the aid statute, and the Court focused on the second prong of Lemon—whether the primary effect of the provision of financial aid to petitioner was to advance religion. Witters addressed arguments similar to those presented in Aguilar and Ball. Specifically, the Court’s analysis of the effect inquiry was similar to that in Ball because it framed the question as whether the aid to petitioner would be a permissible indirect transfer to a religious institution, or an impermissible direct subsidy.102 Justice Marshall, writing for the majority, emphasized that the tuition money was paid directly to the student and only flowed to religious institutions by virtue of the independent choices of aid recipients.103 Moreover, the Court reasoned that there was nothing to indicate that any significant portion of the aid expended by the state, as a whole, would flow to religious institutions.104 The Court further concluded that the petitioner’s use of neutrally available state aid to help pay for his religious education did not confer any message of state endorsement of religion, thus there was no symbolic union with the potential to have the impermissible effect of advancing religion.105 D. Bowen The Court applied the same accommodating approach of Witters in Bowen v. Kendrick106 the following term. In Bowen, the Court considered a challenge to a federal grant program that provided funding to public or non-profit private organizations, including religious organizations, for services relating to adolescent sexuality and pregnancy.107 In the statute, Congress specifically recognized the benefits of having such services provided by religious and charitable organizations, among others.108 The District Court held that the program was unconstitutional both on its face and as applied because it had the impermissible effect, under Lemon, of advancing religion.109 First, the Court once again affirmed the Lemon test as the proper framework in which to assess the constitutionality of the program.110 As with Aguilar, Ball, and Witters, the Court concluded easily that the first prong of Lemon was satisfied.111 In assessing the issue of whether the Act 102. 103. 104. 105. 106. 107. 108. 109. 110. 111. See id. at 487. See id. See id. at 488. See Witters, 474 U.S. at 489. 487 U.S. 589 (1988). See id. at 593. See id. at 595; see also 42 U.S.C. § 300z(a)(8)(B) (1982). See Bowen, 487 U.S. at 598-600. See id. at 602. See id. at 602-04. A:\Waite.art.doc 94 Printed On: 5/6/99 4:19:00 PM NEW ENGLAND LAW REVIEW [Vol. 33:1 had the primary effect of advancing religion, the Court put forth two reasons why the statute on its face could be deemed to have such an impermissible effect: (i) because the statute expressly enlists the involvement of religious organizations in a federal program, it endorses religious solutions to the problems addressed by the Act or creates a symbolic union between church and state; or (ii) because it authorizes direct federal funding of religious organizations and the Act’s purpose may coincide with a religious grantee’s purpose, the Act results in an impermissible inculcation of religious beliefs.112 As to the first argument against the Act, the Court reasoned that nothing prevents Congress from making considered judgments about the role religious organizations may play in solving certain secular problems.113 The Court referred to congressional findings that supported such a judgment and concluded that, at most, this congressional recognition would only incidentally and remotely advance religion.114 The Court rejected the argument that this scheme creates an impermissible symbolic link between government and religion by reasoning that the consequence of such a holding would be to forbid any government aid program that provides funding to religious organizations in areas in which the religious organizations and government have congruent interests.115 As for the second argument against the program, because it is premised on the notion that public funding of religious organizations leads to inculcation of belief and advances religion, the Court addressed many of the same issues as Ball and Witters. First, the Court emphasized the neutral nature of the funding scheme and reasoned that when aid is made available neutrally and generally in a public funding scheme, religious institutions are not prohibited from participating.116 The Court then qualified this pronouncement by reasoning that even neutral programs may have the primary effect of advancing religion if, for example, aid is given to a “pervasively sectarian” institution and may advance the institution’s “religious mission.”117 The Court discussed the emphasis in Ball given to the nature of the institutions receiving aid in that case,118 but distinguished See id. at 605-06. See id. at 606. See id. at 607. See Bowen, 487 U.S. at 613-14. See id. at 608-09 (citing Bradfield v. Roberts, 175 U.S. 291 (1899)). Id. at 609-10. But see id. at 630-31 (Blackmun, J., dissenting) (assailing the “misplaced focus” on the pervasively sectarian nature of institutions receiving aid). 118. See Bowen v. Kendrick, 487 U.S. 589, 610 (1987); see also supra notes 6065 and accompanying text (discussing the importance of the sectarian nature of the involved institution). 112. 113. 114. 115. 116. 117. A:\Waite.art.doc Fall, 1998] Printed On: 5/6/99 4:19:00 PM ESTABLISHMENT CLAUSE 95 Ball because the aid program in Bowen was not directed to pervasively sectarian institutions. The Court reasoned that the challenged aid scheme was permissible on its face because, “of the eligible religious institutions, many will not deserve the label ‘pervasively sectarian.’”119 The Court also rejected the argument that the challenged grant program will have the primary effect of advancing religion because religiously affiliated grantees counseling adolescents presents the risk of inculcation of religious beliefs.120 While the Court accepted the logic of Ball—that programs entailing an unacceptable risk of inculcation by the grantee institution must be struck down—it then reasoned that no presumption against the religious institutions receiving aid while carrying out their functions under the Act in a secular manner is warranted.121 Thus, if a nonpervasively sectarian institution is the grantee, it is entitled to a presumption by the Court that it will handle the funds in accordance with the secular directives of the funding agency.122 After concluding that the Act met the primary effects prong of Lemon, the Court turned to the entanglement inquiry; however, not without severely criticizing this third prong.123 The Court recognized the “catch-22” that is often presented by Lemon and is illustrated by Aguilar. That is, state supervision of aid to ensure it is used in a way that comports with the Establishment Clause can itself render a program constitutionally invalid because it fosters excessive entanglement between church and state. “For this and other reasons, the entanglement prong of the Lemon test has been criticized over the years.”124 Despite its obvious dissatisfaction with this third prong, if not the entire Lemon test, the Court again hinged its conclusion on the fact that because the grantee institutions were not pervasively sectarian, the less intensive monitoring that was necessary would not “cause the government to intrude unduly in the day-to-day operations of the religiously affiliated AFLA grantees.”125 Therefore, the federal grant program was held not to violate the Establishment Clause.126 E. The Lemon Debate The frustration with the Lemon test articulated by the Court in Bowen 119. Id. at 610. But see id. at 631 (Blackmun, J., dissenting) (“The majority first skews the Establishment Clause analysis by adopting a cramped view of what constitutes a pervasively sectarian institution.”). 120. See id. at 611. 121. See id. at 612. 122. See id. 123. See id. at 615-16. 124. Bowen v. Kendrick, 487 U.S. 589, 616 (1987). 125. Id. at 616. 126. See id. at 618. A:\Waite.art.doc 96 Printed On: 5/6/99 4:19:00 PM NEW ENGLAND LAW REVIEW [Vol. 33:1 has resonated through other cases, especially in the form of criticism of the entanglement prong. Even in Lemon itself, Justice White, in concurrence, criticized the “catch-22” created by the entanglement inquiry.127 Another example is Justice O’Connor’s dissent in Aguilar, where she wrote, “I question the utility of entanglement as a separate Establishment Clause standard. . . . To a great extent, the anomalous results in our Establishment Clause cases are ‘attributable to [the] entanglement prong.’”128 However, criticisms and attempts to refine the Lemon test have not been limited solely to the third prong.129 Justice O’Connor has argued for clarification of the Lemon test by focusing the analysis on “endorsement or disapproval of religion.”130 Under her reformulation, “the proper inquiry under the purpose prong of Lemon would be whether government intends to convey a message of endorsement or disapproval of religion.”131 As for the effects prong, O’Connor argues that the actual effect of a government practice is unimportant, rather what is dispositive is whether the practice has the effect of communicating a message of government “endorsement or disapproval of religion.”132 This conception of the Establishment Clause has been invoked approvingly by a majority opinion invalidating a Louisiana statute requiring balanced treatment of evolution and creationism in public schools,133 and countenanced by the Court in a case involving a public display of a creche.134 However, it has not been immune to vociferous criticism.135 Justice Kennedy has assailed the endorsement test and criticized the primary effects prong of Lemon from which it is derived, as reflecting “an unjustified hostility toward religion.”136 To be sure, Justice Kennedy does not demean Lemon without suggesting his own framework for analysis. Kennedy interprets the Establishment Clause as forbidding government 127. See Lemon, 403 U.S. at 668 (White, J., concurring); see also Wallace v. Jaffree, 472 U.S. 38, 108 (Rehnquist, J., dissenting) (referring to the “insolvable paradox” created by the entanglement prong). 128. Aguilar v. Felton, 473 U.S. 402, 430 (O’Connor, J., dissenting) (quoting Jesse Choper, The Religion Clauses of the First Amendment: Reconciling the Conflict, 41 U. PITT. L. REV. 673, 681 (1980)). 129. See, e.g., Edwards v. Aguillard, 482 U.S. 578, 636-40 (1987) (Scalia, J., dissenting) (advocating elimination of the secular purpose prong of the Lemon test). 130. Lynch v. Donnelly, 465 U.S. 668, 689 (1984). 131. Id. at 691 (emphasis added). 132. Id. at 692 (emphasis added). 133. See Edwards v. Aguillard, 482 U.S. 578 (1987). 134. See Allegheny County v. Greater Pittsburgh ACLU, 492 U.S. 573 (1989). 135. See, e.g., Smith, supra note 34; Mark Tushnet, The Constitution of Religion, 18 C ONN. L. REV. 701, 711-12 (1986). 136. Allegheny, 492 U.S. at 655 (Kennedy, J., dissenting). A:\Waite.art.doc Fall, 1998] Printed On: 5/6/99 4:19:00 PM ESTABLISHMENT CLAUSE 97 coercion of anyone to support or participate in religion or its exercise.137 Justice Souter has fundamentally disagreed with Justice Kennedy’s theory and has advanced a view of the Establishment Clause that he believes embraces the meaning of the second prong of Lemon which “compels the state to pursue a course of neutrality toward religion,138 favoring neither one religion over others nor religious adherents collectively over nonadherents.”139 Overall, dissatisfaction with Lemon has resulted in multiple approaches being advanced by different Justices, as well as a plethora of scholarly criticism and proposals for refinement of Establishment Clause jurisprudence.140 Indeed, to reach desired results, the Court has been able to manipulate the words of the test to the point where they have lost whatever definitive meaning they once held.141 However, the famous three-prong test, formally at least, remains law.142 Assessing the effects of the Lemon test, Justice Rehnquist once wrote, The three-part test has simply not provided adequate standards for deciding Establishment Clause cases . . . . Even worse, the Lemon test has caused this See id. at 660; see also Lee v. Weisman, 505 U.S. 577, 587 (1992). Comm. for Pub. Ed. & Religious Liberty v. Nyquist, 413 U.S. 756, 792-93 (1973). 139. See Board of Ed. of Kiryas Joel Village School Dist. v. Grumet, 512 U.S. 687, 696 (1994) (Souter, J., concurring) (citing Epperson v. Arkansas, 393 U.S. 97, 104 (1968)). 140. See, e.g., Michael Stokes Paulsen, Lemon is Dead, 43 C ASE W. R ES. L. REV. 795, 800-01 (1993) (advocating adoption of Justice Kennedy’s coercion test, and arguing: “Each of Lemon’s three ‘prongs’ for evaluating the constitutionality of government action challenged under the Establishment Clause . . . had some major analytical flaw or ambiguity. . . . The ambiguity of the test left the Court leeway to interpret each prong in varying ways, producing a bewildering patchwork of decisions as the justices engaged in a tug-of-war over the interpretation of the test.”). 141. See id.; see also, e.g., Lynch v. Donnelly, 465 U.S. 668 (1984) (weakly enforcing the Lemon test to uphold a government sponsored creche); see also Philip Kurland, The Religion Clauses and the Burger Court, 34 C ATH. U. L. REV. 1, 1213 (1984) (criticizing Lynch as “disingenuous” and “sleazy”). One commentator has blamed the uncertain nature of the primary effects prong of Lemon for the disparate treatment of indirect and direct aid to religious schools, calling primary effect more of a label than a framework for analysis. Thomas C. Berg, Religion Clause Anti-Theories, 72 NOTRE DAME L. REV. 693, 696 n.15 (1997). 142. Interestingly, during his last term on the bench, Justice Blackmun wrote a concurrence in which he advocated adherence to the principles of Lemon despite rumblings on the Court over adopting a new analytical framework for the Establishment Clause. See Board of Ed. of Kiryas Joel Village School Dist. v. Grumet, 512 U.S. 687, 710 (1994) (Blackmun, J., concurring) (“I write separately only to note my disagreement with any suggestion that today’s decision signals a departure from the principles described in Lemon . . . I remain convinced of the general validity of the basic principles stated in Lemon . . . ”). 137. 138. A:\Waite.art.doc 98 Printed On: 5/6/99 4:19:00 PM NEW ENGLAND LAW REVIEW [Vol. 33:1 Court to fracture into unworkable plurality opinions . . . . The results of our school services cases show the difficulty we have encountered in making the 143 Lemon test yield principled results. Given these clear misgivings about the utility of Lemon, it is no surprise that when authoring the Court’s opinion in Zobrest v. Catalina Foothills School Dist.,144 the Chief Justice avoided expressly using the three prong framework. F. Zobrest In Zobrest, a deaf petitioner appealed a Ninth Circuit decision which held that the provision under a federal act of a sign language interpreter to aid him at his Catholic school would violate the Establishment Clause.145 The circuit court, basing its decision on the effects prong of Lemon and the reasoning of Ball, concluded that placement of a government employee in a sectarian school would create an impermissible symbolic union between government and religion.146 After overcoming the objection of four dissenting Justices that, prudentially, the Court should not pass on the constitutionality of an Act of Congress if a construction of the Act is possible by which the constitutional question can be avoided,147 the Court assessed the merits of petitioner’s Establishment Clause claim.148 Relying on Witters and Bowen, the Court in Zobrest began with the premise that “government programs that neutrally provide benefits to a broad class of citizens defined without reference to religion are not readily subject to an Establishment Clause challenge just because sectarian institutions may receive an attenuated financial benefit.”149 Therefore, because any aid flowing to petitioner’s sectarian school under the statute did so as a result of a private decision by a beneficiary of a federal entitlement, the Establishment Clause was not violated.150 The Court further reasoned that if an interpreter were provided to petitioner under the Act, his sectarian school would only receive the indirect economic benefit of petitioner’s Wallace v. Jaffree, 472 U.S. 38, 110 (1984) (Rehnquist, J., dissenting). 509 U.S. 1 (1993). See id. at 3. See id. at 5. See id. at 14 (Blackmun, J., dissenting, joined by Justices Souter, Stevens, and O’Connor) (disagreeing with the Court’s decision to reach the constitutional question). 148. See id. at 8. Notably, Petitioner not only challenged the circuit court’s interpretation of the Establishment Clause, he asserted that the Free Exercise Clause required provision of an interpreter under the Act. See id. at 4. 149. Id. 150. See Zobrest, 509 U.S. at 10; see also Witters v. Wash. Dep’t. of Serv’s for the Blind, 474 U.S. 481, 487 (1985). 143. 144. 145. 146. 147. A:\Waite.art.doc Fall, 1998] Printed On: 5/6/99 4:19:00 PM ESTABLISHMENT CLAUSE 99 tuition, and even this proposition required the assumption that, without the interpreter, petitioner would have gone to school elsewhere and the school would have been unable to fill his spot.151 Respondent argued that the Ball prohibition against government provision of educational services on the premises of sectarian schools applied with equal force to the provision of a single interpreter to petitioner.152 However, the Court rejected this argument by explaining Ball and distinguishing it from Zobrest. First, the Court announced that in Ball, the challenged programs “in effect subsidized the religious functions of the parochial schools by taking over a substantial portion of their responsibility for teaching secular subjects.”153 The Court, perhaps subtly addressing the concerns of inculcation and symbolic union, further asserted that “the task of a sign language interpreter seems to us quite different than that of a teacher or guidance counselor [which were being provided in Ball and Aguilar] . . . . [T]he Establishment Clause lays down no absolute bar to the placing of a public employee in a sectarian school.”154 Accordingly, the Constitution did not prohibit petitioner from having a sign language interpreter provided for by federal law aid him at his sectarian school.155 III. INTERPRETATION OF P RECEDENT: CREATIVE CONSISTENCY IN AGOSTINI These are the precedents and principles which the Supreme Court confronted in Agostini, a case involving a federally funded program of remedial instruction provided to eligible children on a neutral basis by publicly employed teachers on the premises of schools, including sectarian ones. In Agostini, the Court, while overruling one of those precedents, Aguilar, does not claim to evaluate and then choose among the various, sometimes competing, approaches to the Establishment Clause. Rather, because the case reached the Court as a review of the lower courts’ denials of petitioner’s Rule 60(b)(5) motion, the decision in Agostini is framed as a straightforward application of one line of precedents that is announced to have overruled Aguilar. Petitioners in Agostini sought relief from the Aguilar-based injunction under Federal Rule of Civil Procedure 60(b)(5) which states: On motion and upon such terms as are just, the court may relieve a party . . . Id. at 10-11 (1993). See id. at 11. Id. at 12 (quoting School Dist. of Grand Rapids v. Ball, 473 U.S. 373, 397 (1985)). 154. Id. at 13 (emphasis added). 155. See id. at 14. 151. 152. 153. A:\Waite.art.doc 100 Printed On: 5/6/99 4:19:00 PM NEW ENGLAND LAW REVIEW [Vol. 33:1 from a final judgment [or] order . . . [when] the judgment has been satisfied, released, or discharged, or a prior judgment upon which it is based has been reversed or otherwise vacated, or it is no longer equitable that the judgment 156 should have prospective application. This standard has been interpreted to mean that a grant of Rule 60(b)(5) relief is appropriate when the party seeking relief can show a “significant change either in factual conditions or the law.”157 The district court and the court of appeals both denied the petitioners relief from the Aguilarbased injunction because, although “there may be good reason to conclude that Aguilar’s demise is imminent, [it has] not yet occurred.”158 In short, those courts reasoned that because a grant of relief is conditioned on a significant change in law, and because the law [Aguilar] which led to the injunction remained intact, relief under Rule 60(b)(5) would be improper.159 Interestingly, the Court’s quotation of Rule 60(b)(5) omits the reference to the reversal or vacation of the prior judgment.160 Instead, Justice O’Connor’s majority opinion elaborated on the standard for relief under Rule 60(b)(5), accepting the need for a showing of a significant change in fact or law.161 Justice O’Connor then asserted the simple premise that “a court may recognize subsequent changes in either statutory or decisional law.”162 Therefore, the Court presented the “threshold issue” in reviewing the denial of the Rule 60(b)(5) motion in Agostini as “whether the factual or legal landscape has changed since Aguilar was decided.”163 First, the Court rejected petitioners’ arguments that the costs of complying with the injunction constituted a significant factual change.164 The argument that the statements of five Justices in another case calling for the overruling of Aguilar165 constituted a change in Establishment Clause law FED. R. C IV. P. 60(b)(5). Rufo v. Inmates of Suffolk County Jail, 502 U.S. 367, 384 (1992). Agostini, 117 S. Ct. at 2006 (citations omitted). See id. See id. See id. (citations omitted). Id. (citing Railway Employees v. Wright, 364 U.S. 642, 652-53 (1961)). Id. at 2007. Agostini, 117 S. Ct. at 2006 (“petitioners have failed to establish the significant change in factual conditions required by Rufo.”). 165. See Board of Ed. of Kiryas Joel Village School Dist. v. Grumet, 512 U.S. 687, 718 (1994) (O’Connor, J., concurring in part and concurring in the judgment); id. at 731 (Kennedy, J., concurring in the judgment); id. at 750 (Scalia, J., dissenting, joined by Thomas, J., and Rehnquist, C.J.). See generally Basilios E. Tsingos, Forbidden Favoritism in the Government Accommodation of Religion: Grumet and the Case for Overturning Aguilar, 18 HARV. J.L. & PUB . POL’Y 867, 868 (1994). 156. 157. 158. 159. 160. 161. 162. 163. 164. A:\Waite.art.doc Fall, 1998] Printed On: 5/6/99 4:19:00 PM ESTABLISHMENT CLAUSE 101 was also dismissed.166 Thus, O’Connor hinges the success of petitioners’ Rule 60(b)(5) motion on whether the law of the Establishment Clause had changed since Aguilar, or, in O’Connor’s words, whether subsequent Establishment Clause cases “have so undermined Aguilar that it is no longer good law.”167 Ultimately, the Court expressly overruled Aguilar because it concluded that assumptions upon which Aguilar and Ball were based have been undermined.168 In essence, although Aguilar was based primarily on the entanglement prong of Lemon, 169 the Court found that the “understanding of the criteria used to assess whether aid to religion has an impermissible effect” had changed.170 In analyzing the holdings of Aguilar and Ball, 171 Justice O’Connor reduced these decisions to resting on four, what she called, “assumptions.”172 Three of these are from Ball, and thus related to the effects prong of Lemon, while the last, from Aguilar, stems from the entanglement inquiry. In Justice O’Connor’s rendering, the four assumptions upon which Aguilar and Ball together relied are: (i) any public employee who works on the premises of a religious school is presumed to inculcate religion in her work; (ii) the presence of public employees on private school premises creates a symbolic union between church and state; (iii) any and all public aid that directly aids the educational function 166. Agostini, 117 S. Ct. at 2007 (“But the question of Aguilar’s propriety was not before us. The views of five Justices that the case should be reconsidered or overruled cannot be said to have effected a change in Establishment Clause law.”). 167. Id. 168. Id. 169. See supra notes 53-56 and accompanying text. 170. Agostini, 117 S. Ct. at 2010. 171. See id. at 2008. 172. Id. at 2010; but see supra notes 64-65 and accompanying text (discussing other rationales expressly mentioned by the Court in Ball). It is worth noting that, contrary to the impression left by Agostini, these, in Agostini language, “assumptions” did not collectively form the basis of the decision in Ball. Rather, in Ball, if any of the three “assumptions” were accepted, the challenged programs would be deemed to have an impermissible effect on religion. The Court in Ball accepted all three “assumptions” en route to finding an impermissible effect; however, rejection of one or even two of these propositions would not render the decision flawed. See Ball, 473 U.S. at 385. The first premise in Ball, that publicly-employed teachers participating in the remedial program at a parochial school may inculcate particular religious beliefs was perhaps wrongly influenced by the Court’s consideration of two different programs, one of which employed mostly parochial school teachers to teach secular remedial subjects. See supra notes 77-78 and accompanying text (discussing the distinction between the two programs that may have been overlooked by the majority in Ball). Indeed, application of this conclusion as to a program whereby public school teachers are employed to teach secular subjects to parochial school students is convincingly assailed by the Court in Agostini. A:\Waite.art.doc 102 Printed On: 5/6/99 4:19:00 PM NEW ENGLAND LAW REVIEW [Vol. 33:1 of religious schools impermissibly subsidizes religious indoctrination; and (iv) that because of (i) above, the Title I program necessitated preventive monitoring which itself was an impermissible government entanglement with religion.173 The Court provided an analysis of the Ball opinion to support its distillation of the above-listed dispositive “assumptions” made in the case.174 Justice O’Connor’s summary account of the Ball opinion neglects some of the factors involved in the reasoning of that case, notably, Justice Brennan’s emphasis on the pervasively sectarian nature of the parochial schools involved in the program challenged in Ball. 175 The Court, however, correctly focused on the critical analysis in Ball of whether the Title I program had the primary or principal effect of advancing or inhibiting religion. Accordingly, Agostini undertakes to address the continuing salience of these four dispositive assumptions. A. Inculcation In Agostini, the Court reasoned that the Court in Zobrest properly refused to presume that a publicly employed interpreter would inculcate any religious beliefs absent evidence to the contrary.176 Zobrest “expressly rejected the notion . . . that, solely because of her presence on private school property, a public employee will be presumed to inculcate religion in the students.”177 This is a most expansive reading of Zobrest, in which the issue was whether placement of a publicly employed sign-language interpreter in a parochial school classroom would have an unconstitutional effect.178 Justice O’Connor disregarded Chief Justice Rehnquist’s express distinction in Zobrest between interpreters and teachers. She further dismissed Justice Souter’s outcries in his dissent in Agostini over this “mistaken reading.”179 Instead, she concluded for the Court that “there is no genuine basis upon which to confine Zobrest’s underlying rationale—that public employees will not be presumed to inculcate religion—to sign-language Agostini, 117 S. Ct. at 2010. Id. at 2008-10. Compare Ball, 473 U.S. at 384, with Lemon, 473 U.S. at 657. See Agostini, 117 S. Ct. at 2010-11. Id. at 2011. See Zobrest, 509 U.S. at 13 (“[T]he task of a sign-language interpreter seems to us quite different from that of a teacher or guidance counselor . . . ethical guidelines require interpreters to ‘transmit everything that is said in exactly the same way it was intended.’”); see also supra note 154 and accompanying text. 179. Compare Agostini, 117 S. Ct. at 2011 with Agostini, 117 S. Ct. at 2022 (Souter, J., dissenting). 173. 174. 175. 176. 177. 178. A:\Waite.art.doc Fall, 1998] Printed On: 5/6/99 4:19:00 PM ESTABLISHMENT CLAUSE 103 interpreters.”180 According to the Court, Zobrest made “fresh law” that removed the presumption of inculcation of religion by public employees.181 B. Symbolic Union Agostini also concluded that the impermissible symbolic union assumption from Ball had been undermined. This conclusion also depended on the Court’s inventive interpretation of Zobrest. “Zobrest also implicitly repudiated . . . [the assumption] . . . that the presence of a public employee on private school property creates an impermissible symbolic link between government and religion,”182 Justice O’Connor wrote. In an apparent attempt to support this reasoning, she then went on to challenge Justice Souter’s opposing view that Title I services must be provided to sectarian school students in off-campus locations because placing public school teachers in parochial schools generally creates an impermissible symbolic union between church and state.183 According to the majority in Agostini, there is no “perceptible difference in the degree of symbolic union between a student receiving remedial instruction” on or off the premises of a parochial school, and the Court in Zobrest also rejected this distinction.184 C. Financial Subsidy Despite the fact that the Court in Ball spoke clearly on the issue of “whether the effect of the proffered aid [to religion] is direct and substantial,”185 the Court in Agostini rejected the rationale of Ball which had led to finding an impermissible effect. Ball recognized the inherently intertwined secular and religious function of parochial schools,186 and then reasoned that, because of this intertwining of functions, the provision of teachers and instructional materials, unlike the provision of general welfare services to children in parochial schools, was a form of impermissible “direct aid to the educational function of the religious school.”187 In defiId. at 2011. Id. Id. at 2011 (emphasis added). Id. at 2012. Id. Ball, 473 U.S. at 394 (quoting Comm. for Pub. Ed. & Religious Liberty v. Nyquist, 413 U.S. 756, 785 n.39 (1973)). 186. See id. at 395; see also supra note 65 and accompanying text (discussing the relevance of the sectarian nature of the schools involved). 187. Ball, 473 U.S. at 395. The Court cited Wolman v. Walter, 433 U.S. 229, 243 (1977) to demonstrate the distinction between impermissible direct aid and neutral general welfare benefits that just happen to be administered through schools. See also supra note 83 and accompanying text. 180. 181. 182. 183. 184. 185. A:\Waite.art.doc 104 Printed On: 5/6/99 4:19:00 PM NEW ENGLAND LAW REVIEW [Vol. 33:1 ance of this prior reasoning, the Court in Agostini concluded that Witters and Zobrest rendered Title I aid to sectarian schools a permissible subsidy.188 Though the grant at issue in Witters was issued directly to a recipient who would use the money for religious education, the Court in Agostini reasoned that because the statutory grant in Witters was based on neutral criteria and any money ultimately flowing to a religious institution did so only as the result of a private choice, “we have departed from the rule relied on in Ball that all government aid that directly aids the educational function of religious schools is invalid.”189 The Court summarily rejected the possible distinctions that could be drawn between state grants to individual students and the Title I program. Moreover, Agostini rejected the concern of Ball that even indirect aid may “impermissibly finance religious indoctrination.”190 The Court reasoned that, like the statutory scheme in Zobrest under which disabled individuals received aid, the Title I scheme under challenge made aid available neutrally to eligible recipients and provided services that were supplemental.191 Therefore, the Court concluded that, like providing an interpreter to the petitioner in Zobrest, Title I services did not “relieve sectarian schools of costs they otherwise would have borne in educating their students.”192 Again, to support its contention that the Title I aid scheme did not impermissibly subsidize the religious mission of institutions, the Court attacked Justice Souter’s competing view by emphasizing the seemingly illogical alternative of off-campus instruction.193 In short, the Court found no difference in the financial benefit or subsidy that a religious school receives between the on-premises and off-premises provision of Title I services; therefore, the on-premises instruction did not provide an impermissible subsidy.194 D. Entanglement The Court addressed the entanglement problems presented by the Title I program upon which Aguilar was based.195 While implicitly affirming the continued relevance of this third prong of the Lemon test, the Court recog188. 189. 190. 191. 192. 193. 194. 195. See Agostini, 117 S. Ct. at 2011. Id. Id. at 2012. See id. Id. at 2013. See id. at 2013-14. See Agostini, 117 S. Ct. at 2013-14. See id. at 2014-15. A:\Waite.art.doc Fall, 1998] Printed On: 5/6/99 4:19:00 PM ESTABLISHMENT CLAUSE 105 nized that the purpose of the prong may render it simply “an aspect of the inquiry into a statute’s effect.”196 After emphasizing the need for an entanglement to be excessive before rising to the level of constitutional infirmity, the Court set forth the three grounds upon which Aguilar rested its finding of entanglement: “(i) the program . . . require[s] ‘pervasive monitoring’ . . . to ensure that Title I employees do not inculcate religion; (ii) the program require[s] ‘administrative cooperation’ between the Board and parochial schools; and (iii) the program might increase the dangers of ‘political divisiveness.’”197 The Court rejected the latter two considerations because “they are present no matter where Title I services are offered.”198 The first consideration was also discarded because it rested on the presumption that the public employees would inculcate religion, and because that presumption was abandoned by Zobrest, there was no reason to assume that pervasive monitoring was required.199 E. Prudential Determinations Finally, the Court offered some brief arguments about how neither the doctrine of stare decisis nor the law of the case doctrine prevented its decision, as well as a few defenses, aimed at Justice Ginsburg’s dissent, of its procedural decision to reconsider Aguilar.200 Then, while disavowing any suggestion that it recognized the overruling of two cases by the implications of subsequent cases, the Court expressly overruled Ball and Aguilar. 201 The trial court was correct, the Court counseled, “to recognize that the [60(b)(5)] motion had to be denied unless and until this Court reinterpreted its binding precedent.”202 However, “we see no reason to wait for a ‘better vehicle’ in which to evaluate the impact of subsequent cases on Aguilar’s continued validity.”203 F. The Dissenters Justice Souter’s dissent defended the Aguilar decision, not so much for 196. Id. at 2015; see also Marsa v. Wernick, 86 N.J. 232, 242-43 (1981). The New Jersey Supreme Court, in interpreting and applying the Lemon test, has examined the practical significance of the entanglement prong, noting that “where the conduct itself is undertaken directly by government officials or personnel, the third element of the tripartite test, excessive government entanglement, is effectively embraced by the other standards of the test.” Id. 197. Agostini, 117 S. Ct. at 2015. 198. Id. 199. See id. at 2015-16. 200. See id. at 2017-18. 201. See id. at 2017. 202. Id. 203. Agostini, 117 S. Ct. at 2018. A:\Waite.art.doc 106 Printed On: 5/6/99 4:19:00 PM NEW ENGLAND LAW REVIEW [Vol. 33:1 the entanglement ground upon which it rested as for its adherence to the principles that the State may neither subsidize religion directly nor act in ways that could be reasonably viewed as religious endorsement.204 After providing a historical justification for both principles,205 Souter assessed the practical effect of the Court’s reasoning. “If a State may constitutionally enter the schools to teach in the manner in question, it must in constitutional principle be free to assume, or assume payment for, the entire cost of instruction provided in any ostensibly secular subject in any religious school.”206 Souter also directly addressed the majority’s repeated reference to the distinction between Title I instruction occurring on and off the premises of sectarian schools. Though the issue was not before the Court, even offpremises aid could prove to be an impermissible subsidy to religious schools, he argued, if it saves the schools money they would have had to spend on similar programs and therefore, “makes it easier for them to survive and concentrate their resources on their religious objectives.”207 However, even if this argument proved insufficient to bar off-premises aid, the on and off premises line remains a sensible one for two reasons.208 First, if Title I services are provided off-campus, they are less likely to provide an impermissible subsidy or to cause a shifting of resources by the school.209 Second, “the difference in the degree of reasonably perceptible endorsement is substantial.”210 In short, if the state keeps its distance from these parochial schools, the likelihood of observers perceiving state approval of the schools’ missions is reduced.211 For Souter, the symbolic union concern necessitates drawing of constitutional lines, and “on one side of every one of them is an otherwise sympathetic case that provokes impatience with the Constitution and with the line. But constitutional lines are the price of constitutional government.”212 Justice Souter’s dissent is perhaps most significant for its alternative reading of Zobrest and Witters upon which the Court relies so heavily. As for the Court’s announcement that Zobrest abandoned the presumption that placing public employees on parochial school grounds results in an See id. at 2020 (Souter, J., dissenting). See id. Id. at 2021-22 (Souter, J., dissenting). Id. at 2022. See id. The possibility that the off-premises aid might be deemed the perfect free exercise accommodation in the face of an establishment prohibition of onpremises aid was not raised. 209. See Agostini, 117 S. Ct. at 2022. 210. Id. 211. See id. 212. Id. at 2026. 204. 205. 206. 207. 208. A:\Waite.art.doc Fall, 1998] Printed On: 5/6/99 4:19:00 PM ESTABLISHMENT CLAUSE 107 impermissible symbolic union,213 Souter accepted that Zobrest rejected a per se presumption but only because the nature of the employee’s job in Zobrest (sign-language interpreter) rendered him “more like a hearing aid than a teacher, and the signing could not be understood as an opportunity to inject religious content in what was supposed to be secular instruction.”214 The majority’s rendering of Zobrest, for Justice Souter, blatantly extended Zobrest beyond its holding.215 Souter also rejected the Court’s claim that Zobrest implicitly repudiated the risk of symbolic union arising from public employees being placed in parochial schools.216 Zobrest simply did not address the symbolic effect of public school teachers entering parochial schools. Rather, on the issue of symbolic union, “the lesson of Zobrest is merely that less is less.”217 As for the concern over the possible financial subsidy to religious schools, Justice Souter’s dissent not only assailed the Court’s interpretation of Zobrest and Witters, it also recognized that the majority’s characterization of the propositions upon which Ball rested may be flawed.218 Contrary to the majority’s claim, Ball did not establish that “any and all” public aid that directly aids the educational function of religious schools impermissibly finances religious indoctrination.219 Rather, Ball emphasized that the determining factor is “whether the effect of the proffered aid was direct and substantial.”220 Contrary to the majority’s understanding then, Witters and Zobrest were substantially different from Ball in that they involved single beneficiaries and, therefore, in those cases, only limited aid would flow to religious schools and only as a result of individual private choices.221 In addition, Witters found it significant that the program as a whole did not result in a significant amount of aid flowing to sectarian institutions.222 For Justice Souter, the Title I scheme under consideration was fundamentally different from the programs in Zobrest and Witters because, instead of aiding individual grantees whose independent choices direct where the aid will flow, it serves some 22,000 students at religious schools See supra note 175 and accompanying text. Agostini, 117 S. Ct. at 2023. See id. See id. Id. See id. at 2023-24. Id. at 2024. Agostini, 117 S. Ct. at 2024; see also supra notes 89-90 and accompanying text (discussing the distinction between permissible indirect aid and impermissible direct aid). 221. See Agostini v. Felton, 117 S. Ct. 1997, 2024 (1997). 222. See id.; see also supra notes 104-05 and accompanying text. 213. 214. 215. 216. 217. 218. 219. 220. A:\Waite.art.doc 108 Printed On: 5/6/99 4:19:00 PM NEW ENGLAND LAW REVIEW [Vol. 33:1 who “may not apply directly for Title I funds,”223 and instead of serving blind or deaf students, it funds instruction in core subjects.224 In short, “[t]he Title I services necessarily relieved a religious school of ‘an expense that it otherwise would have assumed.’”225 Souter’s dissent is significant because, in his analysis of precedent, the Court was indeed making “fresh law” in Agostini. 226 If correct, this conclusion leaves the Court defenseless against the dissent of Justice Ginsburg, who argues that the Court misapplied Federal Rule of Civil Procedure 60(b)(5) because, “nothing can disguise the reality that, until today, Aguilar had not been overruled. Good or bad, it was in fact the law.”227 In Justice Ginsburg’s opinion the Court’s hearing of Agostini is an unprecedented use of Rule 60(b)(5) that goes beyond the recognized power of appellate courts to modify decrees.228 As conventionally used, Rule 60(b)(5) allows modification of an injunction if a party can show “‘a significant change either in factual conditions or in law’ that renders continued operation of the judgment inequitable.”229 However, as Ginsburg asserted, Rule 60(b)(5) has never been thought to “‘allow relitigation of issues that have been resolved by the judgment.’”230 Justice Ginsburg logically assailed what the majority effectively accomplished by hearing Agostini. The rule anounced in Rodriguez de Quijas v. Shearson/American Express, Inc. 231—that lower “courts must follow the Supreme Court case which directly controls, leaving to [the] Court the prerogative of overruling its own decisions”232—is the majority’s basis for its assertion that the lower courts were correct to reject petitioners’ motion.233 However, Ginsburg sees this reasoning as the creation of a license for the Court to “bend Rule 60(b) to a purpose—allowing an ‘anytime’ rehearing”234 by the Supreme Court. This possibly disingenuous use of Rule 60(b)(5) to effectively allow an appellate court to rehear Aguilar becomes more apparent, Ginsburg argues, if one recognizes that appellate courts may only review denials of Id. at 2025. Id. at 2024. Id. Agostini, 117 S. Ct. at 2023. Id. at 2028 (Ginsburg, J., dissenting). Id. at 2026-27. Id. at 2026. Id. at 2027 (quoting 11 W RIGHT ET AL., FEDERAL PRACTICE AND PROCEDURE , § 2863 (2d ed. 1995)). 231. 490 U.S. 477 (1989). 232. Agostini, 117 S. Ct. at 2027 (Ginsburg, J., dissenting). 233. Id. at 2028; see also id. at 2018 (majority opinion). 234. Id. at 2028. 223. 224. 225. 226. 227. 228. 229. 230. A:\Waite.art.doc Fall, 1998] Printed On: 5/6/99 4:19:00 PM ESTABLISHMENT CLAUSE 109 Rule 60(b) motions for abuse of discretion.235 No such abuse is evident here. Since Aguilar had not been overruled at the time, the district court properly denied petitioners’ motion without any abuse of discretion. Justice Ginsburg thus concluded that the Court should have waited for another case in which substantive Supreme Court review of the underlying case law would be appropriate.236 The need for such careful adherence to the Federal Rules of Civil Procedure and their traditional application is based “in the maintenance of integrity in the interpretation of procedural rules, preservation of the responsive, non-agenda-setting character of this Court, and avoidance of invitations to reconsider old cases based on speculations on chances from changes in the Court’s membership.”237 IV. PERPETUATING A JURISPRUDENCE OF DOUBT Agostini suffers from three related infirmities. The first, and most arguable, is the Court’s substantive interpretation of Witters and Zobrest. The Court announces that those cases stand for what amounts to several significant shifts in Establishment Clause law. However, it is not the Court’s conclusions in this regard that are troubling, because those two cases can easily be argued to create the logical roots for an adjustment in the rigidity of Establishment Clause analysis. Unfortunately, the reasoning behind the Court’s assertions about the changes in law effected by Witters and Zobrest are not fully borne out. While a significant amount of the supportive reasoning offered is a rebuttal to the off-premises option that the Court paints Justice Souter as championing, much of the changes in law are stated in a conclusory fashion. Of course, if the substantive analysis leaves something to be desired, it is not without a reason. The procedural context of the case (appeal from a denial of a 60(b)(5) motion) in a way forces the Court to limit its supporting rationale for the ultimate outcome, and perhaps, to cajole more out of Witters and Zobrest than they actually hold so that it can be said that the law of Aguilar had already changed prior to Agostini. Indeed, this See id. Agostini, 117 S. Ct. at 2028. Id. (citing Illinois Central R. Co. v. Illinois, 184 U.S. 77, 92 (1902)). Notably, the Court’s membership is one way of explaining the change from Aguilar to Agostini. The former decision was written by Justice Brennan and joined by Justices Blackmun, Powell, Marshall, and Stevens. See Aguilar v. Felton, 473 U.S. 402 (1985). Justices Burger, Rehnquist, White, and O’Connor dissented. See id. at 419-31. The latter decision was written by Justice O’Connor and joined by Justices Rehnquist, Scalia, Kennedy, and Thomas. See Agostini v. Felton, 117 S. Ct. 1997 (1997). Justices Souter, Stevens, Ginsburg, and Breyer dissented. See id. at 2019. 235. 236. 237. A:\Waite.art.doc 110 Printed On: 5/6/99 4:19:00 PM NEW ENGLAND LAW REVIEW [Vol. 33:1 jurisprudentially suspect claim by the Court is the most puzzling aspect of the case. Because of Rule 60(b)(5), the Court, in effect, simultaneously declares that Aguilar had been overruled and that it is thus overruled by Agostini. A. Jurisprudential Cooking “Among the stupendous powers of the Supreme Court of the United States . . . is the power, through an articulate search for principle, to interpret history . . . [and] the power, through the disposition of cases, to make it.”238 This observation of Mark DeWolfe Howe is amply evidenced by the Court in Agostini. Unable to grant petitioners’ 60(b)(5) motion based on the inequity of Aguilar having prospective application, because constitutional requirements must supersede equitable claims, the Court makes history by simply declaring that prior judgments, which themselves had announced what the Constitution requires, were now vacated.239 Justice O’Connor reasoned that Aguilar had been overruled, as a practical matter, by two subsequent cases, despite the fact that those cases did not themselves question the validity of Aguilar. Justice Souter delivers a convincing argument that, through its interpretation and application of precedent, the Court is making fresh law in Agostini under the guise of finding a change in law sufficient to satisfy Rule 60(b)(5). Indeed, even the Court expressly declared that “we therefore overrule Ball and Aguilar,”240 without addressing whether by this declaration the law is being established or, as the Court at times postures, Agostini is simply acknowledging that those earlier cases “are no longer good law.”241 The Court is forced to adhere to the fiction that the law had significantly changed since Aguilar in order to grant Rule 60(b)(5) relief, despite the fact that the actual change in law arguably did not occur until the gavel struck in Agostini. 242 In rejecting petitioners’ earlier argument that the statements of five Justices in another case calling for the reconsideration of Aguilar constituted the requisite change in law for grant of a 60(b)(5) motion, Justice O’Connor wrote, “[b]ut the question of Aguilar’s propriety was not before us. . . .”243 That is perfectly logical. If the question of Aguilar’s (or Ball’s) propriety is not before the Court, then the law it proM ARK DEW OLFE HOWE, THE GARDEN AND THE W ILDERNESS 3 (1965). See FED. R. C IV. P. 60(b)(5); see also supra notes 167-69 and accompanying text (discussing Rule 60(b)(5)). 240. Agostini, 117 S. Ct. at 2017. 241. Id. at 2016. 242. See LON L. FULLER , THE M ORALITY OF LAW 51 (2d ed., 1964)(discussing the declarative function of law). 243. Agostini, 117 S. Ct. at 2007. 238. 239. A:\Waite.art.doc Fall, 1998] Printed On: 5/6/99 4:19:00 PM ESTABLISHMENT CLAUSE 111 nounced can not be said to have changed, let alone “significantly changed.” The paradox that the Court creates by at once declaring fresh law and finding a change in prior law stands in considerable tension with elementary principles of the rule of law. Despite the Court’s declaration that the law had changed to render Aguilar invalid, Agostini was the first instance in which such changes in law were announced and deemed sufficient to overrule Aguilar. Only Agostini makes the parties and the public privy to this change in law. As Professor Lon L. Fuller recognized, laws must be given adequate publication so that they may be subject to public criticism . . . . It is also plain that if the laws are not made readily available, there is no check against a disregard of them by those charged with their application and enforcement . . . . The requirement that laws be published does not rest on any such absurdity as an expectation that the dutiful citizen 244 will sit down and read them all. In Agostini, the Court neglects this principle of the rule of law leaving even the most learned citizens guessing as to what the Constitution might tomorrow be held to have mandated. If Aguilar can be implicitly overruled by Zobrest and Witters, whose pronouncements are only analogously applicable, then any majority of Justices is able to recognize or effect a change in law without actually having to justify its decision to overrule the prior case on the merits. The Court can avoid the responsibility that comes with changing the law by simply saying that it has already changed. Competing interpretations of precedents in an area of law such as the Establishment Clause are understandable because in such a sensitive area of law it is impossible “to find any set of principles that reconciles all standing statutes and precedents.”245 However, because of the Rule 60(b)(5) context of the case, the Court in Agostini effectively is forced to assert that the “gravitational force”246 of Aguilar silently disappeared. This silent disappearance is particularly disconcerting because, as Professor Ronald Dworkin has written, when recognizing mistakes in prior decisions, “consistency requires justification, not explanation, and the justification must be plausible and not a sham. If the justification . . . makes distinctions that are arbitrary and deploys principles that are unappealing, then it cannot count as justification at all.”247 Agostini, because of its procedural context, fails to provide an adequate justification for change in the law. After a careful See FULLER, supra note 241, at 51 (emphasis added). R ONALD DWORKIN, TAKING R IGHTS SERIOUSLY 119 (1977). Id. at 113. Dworkin uses the term “gravitational force” to refer to the authority of precedent. Id. “[T]he force of a precedent escapes the language of its opinion.” Id. 247. Id. at 119. 244. 245. 246. A:\Waite.art.doc 112 Printed On: 5/6/99 4:19:00 PM NEW ENGLAND LAW REVIEW [Vol. 33:1 and genuine reading of Zobrest and Witters, it remains difficult to understand how Aguilar ever lost the status of law without proper justification in the form of a fresh new case directly challenging its precepts. If it were deciding whether Title I programs are constitutionally permissible in general, the Court would be correct to consider the meaning of Aguilar and Ball and then examine whether subsequent cases may “have so undermined” those cases that they were “no longer good law,”248 or no longer had gravitational force. This type of straight constitutional analysis, rather than the Court’s analysis of the programs under the guise of reviewing the denial of a Rule 60(b)(5) motion, would hold more weight and provide a clearer source for discerning what the Establishment Clause requires. Nevertheless, even in the Rule 60(b)(5) context, the Court could have examined only the continuing validity of the actual holding in Aguilar, that the monitoring scheme was an unconstitutional excessive entanglement between church and state.249 The Court would have thus limited the meaning of Agostini to a recognition of a more universally accepted change in Establishment Clause law—the reduction of the rigidity of the entanglement prong of Lemon. 250 The Court does assert that the entanglement prong has increasingly been seen as nothing more than “an aspect of the inquiry into the statute’s effect.”251 However, the Court maintains the formal relevance of the third prong of Lemon, and, for that matter, of the much maligned Lemon test altogether.252 Simple repudiation of this prong would have left for another day the articulation of the proper current analysis for determining whether a program such as Title I has an unconstitutional effect. Undoubtedly, this would not have solved the jurisprudential infirmity of at once declaring and recognizing a change in law. However, that the entanglement prong is no longer a relevant part of Establishment Clause analysis seems much more plausible than reading Zobrest and Witters as encompassing paradigmatic shifts in law. Moreover, this option might have been preferable because the nature of the effects inquiry is so controlling in Establishment Clause cases that its articulation is deserving of maximum clarity. By forcing future litigants to argue the controlling nature of Ball, instead of resorting to the transparent fiction necessary in the Rule 60(b)(5) context, Agostini, 117 S. Ct. at 2007. See supra notes 54-55 and accompanying text (discussing the finding of excessive entanglement in Aguilar). 250. See supra notes 128-29, 194-98 and accompanying text (discussing the potential demise of entanglement). 251. Agostini, 117 S. Ct. at 2015. See also supra note 195 and accompanying text. 252. For criticism of the test set forth in Lemon, see, for example, BERG , supra note 142, at 696. 248. 249. A:\Waite.art.doc Fall, 1998] Printed On: 5/6/99 4:19:00 PM ESTABLISHMENT CLAUSE 113 that Aguilar had practically or impliedly been overruled by subsequent cases, the Court would have had the opportunity to overrule Aguilar using the proper justification that is incumbent in straight constitutional analysis. B. Interpretative Cooking The Court’s substantive analysis of the inculcation, symbolic union and financial subsidy problems that may arise under the primary effects prong of Lemon is somewhat tenuous. Rejection of the presumption that public employees will inculcate religion to religious school students is the most acceptable of the Court’s conclusions. Indeed, this presumption created in Ball may have been improperly applied to the Shared Time Program which employed public employees in parochial schools.253 Nevertheless, the reasoned and perhaps overdue rejection of the presumed inculcation presumption as applied to the Title I programs cannot alone guarantee the program’s constitutionality. Despite the Court’s summary treatment of it,254 Ball’s symbolic union assumption was based on reasoning and a broader constitutional principle which preceded Ball. Agostini’s firm rejection of this assumption required more than merely citing the implied repudiation of this assumption by Zobrest. Ball discussed at length the principle that when the powers of government become closely identified with those of any religion it may have an unconstitutional effect.255 This is never of more concern to the Court than when impressionable young children are the first-hand observers of the symbolic union.256 Justice O’Connor’s opinion asserted that Zobrest undermines the rationale behind finding the presence of public school teachers in parochial school classrooms unconstitutional. However, it fails to address directly whether the scheme in Aguilar conveys a message of “government endorsement or disapproval of religion.”257 This failure in O’Connor’s opinion is particularly curious, since it is her own “endorsement” test258 which so heavily focuses on the effect of symbolism 253. See supra note 79 and accompanying text (referring to Justice O’Connor’s partial dissent in Ball where she rejected the presumption as applied to the public employees but accepted it as to the parochial school employees for the Community Education Program). 254. See supra notes 181-83 and accompanying text (discussing the symbolic union inquiry in Agostini). 255. See Ball, 473 U.S. at 390. 256. See id. (“The symbolism of a union between church and state is most likely to influence children of tender years. . . .”); cf. Widmar v. Vincent, 454 U.S. 263, 274 (1981); Tilton v. Richardson, 403 U.S. 672 (1991). 257. Lynch v. Donnelly, 465 U.S. 668, 688 (1984) (O’Connor, J., concurring). 258. See supra notes 127-33 and accompanying text (on Justice O’Connor’s en- A:\Waite.art.doc 114 Printed On: 5/6/99 4:19:00 PM NEW ENGLAND LAW REVIEW [Vol. 33:1 on the “objective observer” who is familiar with the values recognized in the Free Exercise Clause.259 And here the objective observer is the impressionable child compelled to be at school. Perhaps Justice O’Connor’s endorsement rationale would reject a heightened scrutiny of the symbolism of union when it affects young children and conclude that the enlightened objective observer would find no government endorsement of religion stemming from the generally available benefits of the Title I program. Neverthless, Agostini fails to provide persuasive reasoning for the conclusion that the Title I program does not have an impermissible effect by creating a symbolic union that conveys “a message to nonadherents that they are outsiders, not full members of the political community, and . . . to adherents that they are insiders, favored members of the political community. . . .”260 Surely, there might be some difference between the symbolism involved in a publicly employed sign language interpreter placed in a parochial school classroom to serve the needs of a single deaf student (in Zobrest), and a public school teacher serving the academic needs of a class of parochial school students. If the Court believed those situations to be equal in their degree of symbolism, it should have supported that conclusion. Moreover, it should have recognized that such a conclusion makes new law, at least in so far as it would further refine the symbolic union inquiry. When dealing with concerns over symbolism, off-premises instruction could very well be the solution to constitutional infirmity. Agostini somehow rejects this premise without rejecting the symbolic union inquiry itself. The Court’s analysis of the third potentially fatal effects problem of financing the religious mission of sectarian schools is also flawed. According to the Court, Zobrest and Witters held that this type of supplemental aid to sectarian schools is permissible.261 This conclusion neglects a critical distinction. In Ball, the Court addressed whether aid to religious institutions is provided directly or indirectly, such as through the conduit of individual students. The Court reasonably concluded that where “no meaningful distinction can be made between aid to the student and aid to the school,” the concept of aid “to individuals is a transparent fiction.”262 In short, aid may have the effect of subsidizing religious schools even if it takes the form of aid to students or parents.263 dorsement test). 259. See Wallace, 472 U.S. at 76, 83 (O’Connor, J., concurring). 260. Lynch, 465 U.S. at 688. 261. See Agostini, 117 S. Ct. at 2011. 262. Ball, 473 U.S. at 396, citing Wolman v. Walter, 433 U.S. 229, 264 (1977). 263. See, e.g., Wolman, 433 U.S. at 248-51. A:\Waite.art.doc Fall, 1998] Printed On: 5/6/99 4:19:00 PM ESTABLISHMENT CLAUSE 115 In Agostini, the Court fails to give due attention to the distinction between direct and indirect aid, and ultimately ascribes meanings to Zobrest and Witters that go beyond the holdings in those cases. In Witters, Justice Marshall made clear that central to the Court’s decisions was that the tuition money was paid directly to the student and only flowed to religious institutions by virtue of the independent choices of aid recipients.264 It is somewhat difficult to deem Title I aid indirect aid, without resort to the type of transparent fiction that has been condemned by the Court.265 The Court’s reliance on Zobrest is even more questionable. In that case the Court expressly distinguished the type of Title I aid found unconstitutional in Ball. 266 According to the Court in Zobrest, while Title I aid “in effect subsidized the religious functions of the parochial schools by taking over a substantial portion of their responsibility for teaching secular subjects,”267 the provision of a sign language interpreter to a disabled student in a parochial school was a permissible indirect subsidy that did not relieve the religious school from an expense that it otherwise would have incurred in educating its students.268 The Court in Agostini somehow neglects its prior recognition of differences between the effects of the two programs and finds the situations indistinguishable.269 C. Procedural Cooking Given the uncertainty about the Court’s interpretation of precedent and the ambiguity of when or how the change in Establishment Clause law since Aguilar was effected, Justice Ginsburg’s dissent on the Court’s suspect handling of this 60(b)(5) motion and her general argument that the Court should not have heard the case deserves further analysis. Petitioners relied upon the decision in Rufo v. Inmates of Suffolk County Jail270 to press their 60(b)(5) motion. As recognized by both Justice O’Connor and Justice Ginsburg, in Rufo the Court held that it is appropriate to grant a Rule 60(b)(5) motion when the party seeking modification of a consent decree can show “a significant change either in factual conditions or in law.”271 Indeed, Rufo rejected, as out of context, the strict standard for modification of a consent decree that had been announced by Justice Car264. See Witters v. Wash. Dept. of Serv’s for the Blind, 474 U.S. 481, 488 (1986). 265. See Ball, 473 U.S. at 396 (citing Wolman, 433 U.S. at 264). 266. See Zobrest v. Catalina Foothills School Dist., 509 U.S. 1, 12 (1993). 267. Id. (citing Ball, 473 U.S. at 397). 268. See id. 269. See Agostini, 117 S. Ct. at 2012-13. 270. 502 U.S. 367 (1992). 271. Id. at 384. A:\Waite.art.doc 116 Printed On: 5/6/99 4:19:00 PM NEW ENGLAND LAW REVIEW [Vol. 33:1 dozo in United States v. Swift & Co. 272 That oft-quoted standard required “nothing less than a clear showing of grievous wrong evoked by new and unforeseen conditions . . . .”273 as a predicate to modification of a consent decree. In rejecting that stricter standard, the Court recognized the need for a flexible responsive standard under which district courts may modify decrees based on changed circumstances.274 However, extending that responsiveness to include what is effectively reconsideration of a prior case by the Supreme Court was never the purpose of this procedural mechanism. The consent decree under challenge in Rufo was the product of a finding of unconstitutional jail conditions for pre-trial inmates.275 Accordingly, the decree enjoined the government defendants from housing any pre-trial inmate with another inmate in the same jail cell.276 The petitioners then argued in support of their Rule 60(b)(5) motion that the subsequent decision of Bell v. Wolfish, 277 which held double-celling not to be unconstitutional in all cases, required modification of the decree which was in force.278 However, the Court rejected this argument because “to hold that a clarification in the law automatically opens the door for relitigation of the merits of every affected consent decree would undermine the finality of such agreements and could serve as a disincentive to negotiation of settlements in institutional reform litigation.”279 Of course, Rufo and Agostini might be distinguished on grounds of the difference between a consent decree entered into by the parties, and a permanent injunction entered unilaterally by a court. It is plausible that consent decrees, because based on agreement of the parties, should be more difficult to modify. Indeed, that could explain the Court’s rejection of the petitioners’ change in law argument in Rufo, but acceptance of a similar change in law argument in Agostini. However, the Court in Agostini, while considering the continued validity of a court-entered injunction, did not recognize this possible distinction despite relying on Rufo where a consent decree was under consideration. Therefore, presumably the same standard is applicable to the modification of either type of decree. 272. 286 U.S. 106 (1932) (rejecting defendants’ petition for modification of a consent decree that was the product of a prolonged antitrust battle with the government and had enjoined the defendants from manipulating the meat-packing industry and banned them from engaging in certain foodstuffs activities.). 273. Id. at 119. 274. Rufo, 502 U.S. at 380. 275. Id. at 372-73. 276. Id. at 373. 277. 441 U.S. 520 (1979). 278. Rufo, 502 U.S. at 388. 279. Id. at 389. A:\Waite.art.doc Fall, 1998] Printed On: 5/6/99 4:19:00 PM ESTABLISHMENT CLAUSE 117 Moreover, a differing standard for the two types of decrees would have precisely the same negative effect on constitutional adjudication, a disincentive to settlement in institutional reform litigation that the Court in Rufo expressly avoided.280 In other words, if consent decrees were held to a higher standard for modification than permanent injunctions, settlement by consent decree would present nothing but the opportunity to agree to undesirable conduct that might eventually exceed constitutional requirements, but be more difficult to amend than an injunction entered by a court. The standard would be irrelevant in the event of increased constitutional limitations requiring a change in government conduct, because the consent decree would, of necessity, satisfy the minimum constitutional requirements. Therefore, the Court’s neglect of the distinction between cases involving modifications of consent decrees and those involving permanent injunctions is entirely appropriate because the standard for modification is the same. Accordingly, questions remain about the Court’s use of 60(b)(5) in Agostini. While the question remains why the Court in Rufo rejected the argument that Bell v. Wolfish, directly on point on the issue of the constitutionality of double-celling, constituted a change in law upon which modification of a consent decree under Rule 60(b)(5) could be predicated,281 the Court in Agostini accepted the argument that two analogously applicable Establishment Clause cases constituted a sufficient change in law entitling petitioners to relief from the District Court’s permanent injunction entered in response to Aguilar. 282 While the common law tradition of constitutional interpretation allows general principles to be extrapolated from one specific case and applied to another factually distinct case, it is only after the application of the general principle to a new situation that a change in law has traditionally been recognized to occur. Accordingly, if the Court is intent on overruling Aguilar, it should not, in the context of a Rule 60(b)(5) motion, have overlooked the question of whether a change in law had actually occurred prior to the Agostini decision. This oversight or avoidance injects Agostini with a broader and more dangerous precedent, that implicit repudiations of the reasoning of prior cases can effect a change in law prior to any expression of the change for purposes of Rule 60(b)(5). Justice Ginsburg’s analysis is powerful because the Court’s hearing of the case does expand the scope of Rule 60(b)(5) beyond the previously recognized power of appellate courts to modify decrees.283 The Court 280. 281. 282. 283. Id. at 388-89. See id. See Agostini, 117 S. Ct. at 2003. See id. at 2026-27 (Ginsburg, J., dissenting). A:\Waite.art.doc 118 Printed On: 5/6/99 4:19:00 PM NEW ENGLAND LAW REVIEW [Vol. 33:1 seems to overstep the bounds of what it purports to be doing in Agostini, reviewing the denial of a Rule 60(b)(5) motion. Moreover, the Court’s willingness to construe Rule 60(b)(5) broadly and, in effect, to reconsider Aguilar in this context, is likely one reason for the less than clear weight of the pronouncements in Agostini on the meaning of the Establishment Clause. Indeed, as this Article shifts to considering the import of Agostini and assessing several questions which the Court has left open, opponents of this liberal use of Rule 60(b)(5) may gain another point of attack. That is, Supreme Court reconsideration of cases in this context may not be conducive to announcing well-reasoned law. V. SEARCHING FOR MEANING A. Legislating the Religion Clauses In addition to compounding the confusion over the direction and state of Establishment Clause doctrine, Agostini may also confirm the increased tendency of recent religion clause cases being affected by legislative decisions. As in Bowen, where the Court was openly deferential to Congressional findings that supported legislative judgments about the role religious organizations could play in solving certain secular problems,284 the Court in Agostini may have quietly found a way to prevent congressionally created benefits from being trapped in a constitutional bottleneck. While the analysis in Bowen openly incorporated a measure of deference to Congress, the effect of the decision in Agostini is similar in that the Court engages in a creative analysis, both as to establishment precedents and as to the use of Rule 60(b)(5), so that its decision does not thwart what Congress sought to accomplish through Title I. This deference factor is discernible in other establishment cases as well as in cases invoking the Free Exercise Clause. For example, in Westside Community Board of Education v. Mergens, 285 the Court appeared deferential to the broad congressional purpose at work in the Equal Access Act.286 When rejecting petitioners’ claim that the Act had the primary effect of advancing religion by conveying a message of government approval of the religious activities allowed to be conducted on public school premises by student groups, the Court drew a distinction between “government speech endorsing religion, which the Establishment 284. See Bowen, 487 U.S. at 606-07. See also supra notes 102-11 and accompanying text (regarding Bowen). 285. 496 U.S. 226 (1989). 286. 20 U.S.C. §§ 4071-74 (1994). A:\Waite.art.doc Fall, 1998] Printed On: 5/6/99 4:19:00 PM ESTABLISHMENT CLAUSE 119 Clause forbids, and private speech endorsing religion, which the Free Speech and Free Exercise Clauses protect.”287 The Court supported its reasoning by noting that “Congress specifically rejected the argument that high school students are likely to confuse an equal access policy with state sponsorship of religion . . . we do not lightly second-guess such legislative judgments . . . .”288 Thus, the Court deferentially allowed legislative findings to effectively answer the constitutional question of whether an objective observer in the position of a secondary school student would perceive a government endorsement of religion.289 Again, the Court refused to let the Establishment Clause bar what Congress saw fit to allow. If a statute attempts to accommodate free exercise rights, a lax and deferential approach may be taken by the Court when receipt by religious persons or institutions of neutrally available government benefits is challenged under the Establishment Clause. The general concern over preventing religious persons or institutions from enjoying a neutrally available government benefit can manifest itself by demanding an analysis that is strictly protective of believers. Indeed, the Court has acted zealously to ensure that no religious claimant is excluded from a free exercise accommodation granted by Congress. For example, in United States v. Seeger, 290 the Court heard constitutional challenges to a federal statute allowing for exemption from military service for persons who by reason of their “religious training and belief” are conscientiously opposed to participation in any war.291 The Court construed the statute as setting forth the test of religiosity of belief as, “whether a given belief that is sincere and meaningful occupies a place in the life of its possessor parallel to that filled by the orthodox belief in God of one who clearly qualifies for the exemption.”292 This extremely broad interpretation served at least to ensure that the congressionally conferred benefit and free exercise right of conscientious objection would be enjoyed by the widest possible range of “believers.”293 Thus, when a statutory right is at issue, the Court has, at times, demonMergens, 496 U.S. at 250 (emphasis in original). Id. See id. at 249. See also County of Allegheny v. Am. Civil Liberties Union, Greater Pittsburgh Chapter, 492 U.S. 573, 593 (1989) (regarding the endorsement inquiry as an applicable establishment test). 290. 380 U.S. 163 (1965). 291. Id. at 164-65. 292. Id. at 166. 293. But cf. Lyng v. Northwest Indian Protective Ass’n., 485 U.S. 439 (1988) (refusing to broadly interpret the American Indian Religious Freedom Act in order to preserve sacred sites in national forests); City of Boerne v. Flores, 117 S. Ct. 2157 (1997) (striking down the Religious Freedom Restoration Act, which provided for broad free exercise rights, as beyond the scope of Congressional power). 287. 288. 289. A:\Waite.art.doc 120 Printed On: 5/6/99 4:19:00 PM NEW ENGLAND LAW REVIEW [Vol. 33:1 strated an inclination to engage in creative constitutional and statutory analyses, vigorously protective when the statute confers a free exercise benefit,294 or deferential and lax when the statute is challenged as an establishment violation. The Court in Bowen seized on distinctions in its precedents to shift the burden away from religious grantees when the aid is available neutrally and generally in a public funding scheme.295 In Mergens, however, the Court deferred to Congress’s judgment on the effect of the Equal Access Act, and in Seeger the Court expansively interpreted a statute to ensure receipt by all possible religious claimants of a congressionally conferred free exercise accommodation. In Agostini, the Court first engages in a sleight of hand related to its finding of a significant change in law for Rule 60(b)(5) purposes, and then interprets precedent rather broadly to restore neutral congressional aid to religious institutions. Therefore, Agostini may be another example of the Court’s shaping First Amendment analysis to coincide, rather than conflict with the receipt or enjoyment of government benefits by religious individuals and institutions. The examples of this influence on constitutional analysis are unsettling because of the potential risk that the Court may abdicate its judicial function as a valid check on political processes.296 Moreover, if these considerations have influenced the Court’s analysis, they are one more reason for the continuing lack of a clear and understandable Establishment Clause jurisprudence. 294. Conversely, when confronted with arguments that a statute is unconstitutional because it fails to sufficiently accommodate a free exercise right, the Court has, at times, refused to engage in constitutional decision making which would alter or override legislative or executive judgments. See, e.g., Goldman v. Weinberger, 475 U.S. 503 (1986) (By refusing to interpret the Free Exercise Clause to interfere with the right of the Air Force to enforce a dress code that admittedly infringed upon an important religious exercise by uniformed servicemen, the Court effectively left amendment of the dress code to Congress.); Employment Div., Dep’t. of Human Resources of Oregon v. Smith, 494 U.S. 872 (1990) (The Free Exercise Clause creates no exemption from generally applicable criminal laws. Rather, the legislature can amend the code if it wishes to accommodate religious exercise). 295. See supra notes 106-26 and accompanying text (discussing Bowen). 296. See generally Kevin R. Johnson, Public Benefits and Immigration: The Intersection of Immigration Status, Ethnicity, Gender and Class, 42 UCLA L. REV. 1509, 1528 (1995) (“Deference by the judiciary to the political branches of government . . . may encourage extremes in policy-making.”); see also Comment, The United States Supreme Court's Anomalous Approach to Discriminatory Alienage Classifications: International, Canadian, & Domestic Law Compared, 11 EMORY INT’L. L. REV. 697, 757 (1997). A:\Waite.art.doc Fall, 1998] Printed On: 5/6/99 4:19:00 PM ESTABLISHMENT CLAUSE 121 B. Burden Shifting According to the Court, Zobrest made fresh law that removed the presumption of inculcation of religion by public employees.297 Undoubtedly, the Court’s acceptance in Ball of this presumption was substantially supported by precedent.298 This acceptance was never the result of conclusive evidence of religious inculcation by teachers. Such evidence was considered unnecessary since both inadvertent and subtle inculcation were a part of the constitutional concern.299 Rather, the Court’s repeated acceptance of this principle was prophylactic, because while uncertain whether such inculcation would actually occur, the Court found it unconstitutional to take the chance.300 Judicial circumspection has also informed the symbolic union inquiry.301 As Justice Blackmun once described, the Establishment Clause “calls for fundamentally conservative decisionmaking: our cases do not require a plaintiff to demonstrate that a government action necessarily promotes religion, but simply that it creates such a substantial risk.”302 Neverthless, the Court in Agostini rejects this history of cautious constitutional logic. 303 By linking the need for monitoring that might give rise to excessive entanglement directly to the concern over inculcation, the Court effectively shifts the burden of proving an unconstitutional entanglement.304 Moreover, the Court’s summary account of why the Title I program posed no symbolic union problem without addressing the actual symbolic impact of the program reduces the careful approach that has traditionally been employed and shifts the burden, so to speak, of proving an unconstitutional symbolic effect.305 Thus, Agostini might be read to hold 297. Agostini, 117 S. Ct. at 2011. See also supra note 170 and accompanying text. 298. See Meek v. Pittenger, 421 U.S. 349, 370 (1975); see also Wolman v. Walter, 433 U.S. 229, 247 (1977). 299. See supra notes 66-68 and accompanying text. 300. See Lemon, 403 U.S. at 619 (“The State must be certain, given the Religion Clauses, that subsidized teachers do not inculcate religion.”) (emphasis added); see also Levitt v. Comm. for Pub. Educ. & Religious Liberty, 413 U.S. 472, 480 (1973) (“[T]he State is constitutionally compelled to assure that the statesupported activity is not being used for religious indoctrination.”) (emphasis added). 301. See supra note 81 and accompanying text. 302. See Bowen v. Kendrick, 487 U.S. 589, 648 (Blackmun, J., dissenting) (emphasis in original). 303. See supra note 188 and accompanying text (discussing the Court’s dismissal of the entanglement issue in Agostini). 304. See supra note 188 and accompanying text. 305. See supra notes 253-58 and accompanying text (regarding the Court’s handling of the symbolic union inquiry in Agostini). A:\Waite.art.doc 122 Printed On: 5/6/99 4:19:00 PM NEW ENGLAND LAW REVIEW [Vol. 33:1 that the prophylactic approach to finding unconstitutional establishments is no longer appropriate. Rather, the burden of proving an Establishment Clause violation has shifted to the litigant seeking to vindicate his or her constitutional rights. C. Doctrinal Confusion Establishment Clause law is riddled with uncertainties stemming from sometimes irreconcilable cases that do not rest upon any unifying principles. Indeed, Lemon’s predicted doom has been supported by the introduction of several differing principles vying to control Establishment Clause cases in the future.306 At least three of the justices have announced their conception of the proper reasoning to be applied to establishment issues.307 For better or worse, this situation means that at times lower courts will decide cases based on an interpretation of the Establishment Clause or a form of reasoning that the Supreme Court finds inappropriate. While difficulties abound for a legal system with rules that are contradictory or not understandable,308 it is nonetheless proper for the Court to fulfill its role as the final arbiter of constitutional rights.309 However, in Agostini, while the Court declares why previous Establishment Clause cases (Aguilar and Ball) are no longer good law, it fails to adequately pronounce what general standards or principles have replaced them. Agostini demonstrates that the uncertainty of law in this field has reached record proportions. Rule 60(b)(5) motions normally present lower courts with a routine question about whether facts or law have changed so as to warrant modification of a decree.310 Agostini proves that lower courts cannot truly answer the question of whether the law as announced, in a case upon which a standing decree is predicated, has changed. Regardless of whether a case has ever been expressly overruled, distinguished, or cited with approval, there is no possible way that a lower court can be certain of the case’s continuing validity in the minds of a current majority of Supreme Court Justices. To be sure, it is the province 306. See supra notes 131-44 (on proposed and competing alternative analytical frameworks); see also Paulsen, supra note 141, at 800-01. 307. Id. 308. See FULLER , supra note 241, at 39. 309. See Marbury v. Madison, 5 U.S. (1 Cranch) 137, 177-78 (1803) (“It is emphatically the province and duty of the judicial department to say what the law is.”). 310. See generally 11 W RIGHT, M ILLER & K ANE , FEDERAL PRACTICE AND PROCEDURE § 2863 (2d ed. 1995) (“It is clear that a strong showing is required before an injunction or other prospective judgment will be modified . . . Because the standard is an exacting one, many applications for relief on this ground are denied.”). See also Agostini, 117 S. Ct. at 2026-27 (Ginsburg, J., dissenting). A:\Waite.art.doc Fall, 1998] Printed On: 5/6/99 4:19:00 PM ESTABLISHMENT CLAUSE 123 and duty of the Court to say what the law is, but to admit this state of uncertainty is to admit both that Establishment Clause jurisprudence is nothing more than what the Court says it is in a given case,311 and that in Agostini the litigants used a Rule 60(b)(5) motion to have their case reconsidered. While Agostini could certainly serve as another example of the dangerous pliability of the analytically flawed Lemon test,312 the case ironically renders the continued significance of Lemon an open question. Although the Court goes through each of Lemon’s three prongs, it does so in a methodical attempt to demonstrate that Aguilar and Ball, which both applied the Lemon framework, have been undermined. Therefore, it is unclear whether the Court adheres to Lemon because of the context of Agostini, or because despite the many previously expressed misgivings of members of the current Court,313 it finds the test appropriate and useful again as an Establishment Clause measure. After all, Justice O’Connor makes no more than a passing statement that Agostini would come out the same way under her previously announced endorsement standard, announcing, “[t]he same considerations that justify this holding require us to conclude that this carefully constrained program also can not reasonably be viewed as an endorsement of religion.”314 Adding to the doctrinal confusion, Justice Kennedy joins O’Connor’s opinion despite their vigorous disagreement in the past over the proper Establishment Clause analysis.315 Have Kennedy and O’Connor joined hands to resurrect the previously moribund Lemon test? If not, why does Agostini command a majority who apply Lemon, rather than a plurality 311. See, e.g., Paulsen, supra note 141, at 800-01 (arguing that “Each of Lemon’s three “prongs” for evaluating the constitutionality of government action challenged under the Establishment Clause . . . had some major analytical flaw or ambiguity . . . the ambiguity of the test left the Court leeway to interpret each prong in varying ways, producing a bewildering patchwork of decisions as the justices engaged in a tug-of-war over the interpretation of the test.”); Lynch v. Donnelly, 465 U.S. 668 (1984) (weakly enforcing the Lemon test to uphold a government sponsored creche). See also Philip Kurland, The Religion Clauses and the Burger Court, 34 C ATH. U. L. REV. 1, 12-13 (1984) (criticizing Lynch as “disingenuous” and “sleazy”). 312. See Paulsen, supra note 141, at 800. 313. See supra notes 128-45 and accompanying text (regarding misgivings of Justices about Lemon test). 314. Agostini, 117 S. Ct. at 2016. For a discussion by Justice O’Connor on the “no endorsement” standard, see Allegheny County v. Greater Pittsburgh ACLU, 492 U.S. 573, 625 (1989) (O’Connor, J., concurring); Lynch v. Donnelly, 465 U.S. at 689 (O’Connor, J., concurring). 315. See supra notes 129-38 and accompanying text (discussing the competing views of O’Connor and Kennedy). A:\Waite.art.doc 124 Printed On: 5/6/99 4:19:00 PM NEW ENGLAND LAW REVIEW [Vol. 33:1 that lifts the injunction through differing analyses? Agostini fails to enunciate any “abstract principles regarding the contours and contents of protected realms of liberty” that are desirable because they push us “constantly to check practice against principle.”316 Rather, Agostini determines principle based on practice.317 Despite competing conceptions of the Establishment Clause which have confused precedent and allowed the Court room for creative interpretation to supply and apply the meaning of the establishment guarantee, “those who face the responsibility of the interpretation itself, must wish that it should proceed on the most secure footing that can be obtained . . . .”318 In Agostini, the Court forsakes that wish in favor of a defensible practical outcome and a continued jurisprudence of doubt. 316. Laurence H. Tribe & Michael C. Dorf, Levels of Generality in the Definition of Rights, 57 U. CHI. L. REV. 1057, 1099 (1990). 317. Indeed, Justice O’Connor’s approach to Establishment Clause questions may admit a sort of principled pragmatism. See, e.g., Board of Ed. of Kiryas Joel Village School Dist. v. Grumet, 512 U.S. 687, 718-19 (1994) (O’Connor, J., concurring) (“[T]he same constitutional principle may operate very differently in different contexts . . . setting forth a unitary test for a broad set of cases may sometimes do more harm than good . . . I think it is more useful to recognize the relevant concerns in each case on their own terms . . .”). 318. FULLER , supra note 241, at 102.