Journal of Philosophy, Inc. Utilitarian Morality and the Personal Point of View Author(s): David O. Brink Source: The Journal of Philosophy, Vol. 83, No. 8 (Aug., 1986), pp. 417-438 Published by: Journal of Philosophy, Inc. Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/2026328 . Accessed: 04/06/2013 16:24 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at . http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp . JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org. . Journal of Philosophy, Inc. is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The Journal of Philosophy. http://www.jstor.org This content downloaded from 128.54.33.205 on Tue, 4 Jun 2013 16:24:18 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions THE JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY VOLUME LXXXIII, NO. 8, AUGUST 1986 4.-- 0 -4- U UTILITARIAN MORALITY AND THE POINT OF VIEW* TTILITARIANISM PERSONAL has been the object of much criticism, most of which is thought to undermine nonutilitarian forms of consequentialism or teleology as well. The most common objections to utilitarianism are moral objections.' It is alleged that utilitarianism fails to accommodate the extent of our obligations to * I would like to thank David Lyons, T. H. Irwin, Alan Sidelle, and Nicholas Sturgeon for helpful commentson previous versions of this paper. 1 Of course, it is often argued that utilitarianism is either theoreticallyor practicallyincoherent,because itpresupposes abilitiesto compare the consequences of an infinitenumber of possible actions and to make interpersonal comparisons of welfare. See, e.g., Lionel Robbins, An Essay on the Nature and Significance of Economic Science (New York: Macmillan, 1935) and Alan Donagan, The Theoryof Morality (Chicago: UniversityPress, 1977), pp. 201f. Cf. Jerome Schneewind, Sidgwick and Victorian Moral Philosophy (New York: Oxford, 1977), pp. 141/2, 146. There is a theoreticalor metaphysicalproblem here just in case interpersonal comparisonsof welfareare impossibleor incoherent.There is a practical or epistemological problemforutilitarianism just in case, thoughinterpersonalcomparisons of welfare are possible, we are unreliable measurers of value. Though I cannot argue for these claims here, I thinkthat both metaphysicaland epistemological objections can be dismissed.If therewere a metaphysicalobjection to interpersonal comparisonsof welfare,it would have sweepingimplications.A metaphysicalobjection to interpersonalcomparisonsof welfarewould underwritemetaphysicalobjectionsboth to any moral theorythatincluded duties of beneficenceand to any theory of rationalityrequiringdiachronic intrapersonal comparisons of welfare.We need a better motivationfor denying the possibilityof interpersonal comparisons of welfare than has been given before we scrap all plausible moral theories and theories of rationality.The epistemological objection, on the other hand, is, in a way,well motivated.For obvious reasons, we are not alwaysreliable calculators of welfare.But this fact undermines utilitarianismonly if utilitarianismis a decision procedure. However, as we shall see, utilitarianismis a standard or criterionof rightnessand not a decision procedure and thus avoids the practical or epistemological problem about interpersonalcomparisons of welfare. This defense of utilitarianismsummarizesargumentswhich can be found in my Moral Realism and the Foundations of Ethics (manuscript),chapter 9. 0022-362X/86/8308/0417$02.20 ?) 1986 The Journal of Philosophy,Inc. 417 This content downloaded from 128.54.33.205 on Tue, 4 Jun 2013 16:24:18 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 418 THE JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY and thedemands others,2theexistenceof moraland politicalrights,3 justice.4 In a series of recent papers, Bernard Wilof distributive liams5has added a new, ifrelated,moral objection to utilitarianism; he argues that utilitarianismcannot account for the moral signifiStill more recently,in The Rejection of cance of personal integrity. has argued thatutilitarianism Consequentialism,Samuel Scheffler6 cannot account forthe naturalindependence of the agent's point of view and so should be replaced by a "hybridmoral theory" that incorporateswhat he calls "agent-centeredprerogatives."On this hybridmoral theory,agentsare permittedbut not required to maximize the good. The claim common to Williams, Scheffler, and in parcharacteristicof utilitarianism, others7is thatthe impartiality ticular,and teleologicaltheories,in general,cannot account forthe moral significanceof what I shall call thepersonal point of view. It is thisclaim that I wish to examine. There are two reasons for thisfocus. First,Williams,Scheffler,and othershave made thiscritiquite influential.Second, thiscriticismof utilicismof utilitarianism tarianismis relatedto manyothermoralobjections to utilitarianism. Though I cannot argue the claim here, it is reasonable to regard manyof the moral objections to utilitarianismas stemmingfroma common source: these objections assign great moral importanceto the fact that people lead separate lives, possess differentcommit2 See, e.g., W. D. Ross, The Right and the Good (New York: Oxford, 1930), pp. 22, 34/5, 38; Kurt Baier, The Moral Point of View (Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell, 1958), pp. 203/4;John Rawls,A TheoryofJustice(Cambridge,Mass.: Harvard, 1971), pp. 572/3; Charles Fried, Right and Wrong (Cambridge,Mass.: Harvard, 1978), pp. 2, 169. 3See, e.g., Rawls, pp. 209-211; Ronald Dworkin, "Taking Rights Seriously," reprintedin his Taking Rights Seriously (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard, 1978) and "Rights as Trumps" in J. Waldron, ed., Theories of Rights (New York: Oxford, 1984); Robert Nozick, Anarchy,State, and Utopia (New York: Basic Books, 1974), pp. 28/9; Alan Gewirth,Reason and Morality (Chicago: UniversityPress, 1978), pp. 200, 296; Fried, pp. 81-105; David Lyons, "Utilityand Rights" reprintedin Waldron. 4See, e.g., Rawls; Nozick, pp. 150-164; Gewirth,pp. 200, 296; Bernard Williams, "A Critique of Utilitarianism"in J. J. C. Smart and Williams, Utilitarianism: For and Against (New York: Cambridge, 1973), p. 137. 5 "Persons, Character, and Morality" and "Utilitarianismand Moral Self-indulgence," both reprintedin his Moral Luck (New York: Cambridge, 1981), and "A Critique of Utilitarianism,"pp. 77-135, hereafter"A Critique." 6 New York: Oxford, 1982. 7Cf. Rawls, "Social Unityand PrimaryGoods," in A. Sen and B. Williams,eds., Utilitarianism and Beyond (New York: Cambridge, 1982), pp. 180/1; Fried, pp. 2, 34, 114; Loren Lomasky, "A Refutationof Utilitarianism,"Journal of Value Inquiry, XVII, 4 (1983): 259-279; Thomas Nagel, "Subjective and Objective," reprintedin his Mortal Questions (New York: Cambridge, 1979), p. 205, and "The Limits of Objectivity" in S. McMurrin, ed., The Tanner Lectures on Human Values I (Salt Lake City: Utah UP, 1980), pp. 108, 119/20, 127, 131, 135. This content downloaded from 128.54.33.205 on Tue, 4 Jun 2013 16:24:18 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions UTILITARIANISM AND THE PERSONAL POINT OF VIEW 419 ments,and pursue differentprojects and plans.8If thisdiagnosisis correct,examinationof the objection from the personal point of view should cast some lightupon these other moral objections to utilitarianism. I shallargue thatthereis no successfulmoralobjection to utilitarianism fromthe personal point of view. There are various ways in can accommodate the moral significanceof the whichutilitarianism personal point of view. It must be conceded, however,that these imparstrategiesdo not eliminateall conflictbetweenutilitarianism's tialityand the personal point of view.But thisresidual conflictdoes for,in thisconflict, not constitutea moralobjection to utilitarianism, or therationality of worries about view represents thepersonalpoint supremacyof utilitariandemands. These worriesare properlyunderstoodas worriesabout ratherthanwithinmoralityand so do not threatenand, indeed, support a utilitariananalysisof morality. I. UTILITARIAN AND TELEOLOGICAL ETHICS Utilitarianismis a kind of teleological moral theory.Teleological moraltheories,unlikedeontologicaland othernonteleologicalmoral theories,hold that rightnessor justifiedness consists in maximal goodness; somethingis rightor justifiedjust in case it realizes the most value possible in the circumstances.9It is sometimesclaimed thatteleologicaltheoriesmustalso specifygoodness independently of rightness,with the result that a moral theoryis nonteleological just in case eitherit denies thatrightnessis maximalgoodness or its Though I could, specificationof goodness is in termsof rightness.10 for mypurposes, accept this account of teleological and nonteleological theories,we should, I think,question it. Teleological and nonteleologicaltheoriescan be distinguishedalong traditionallines ifa theoryis teleologicaljust in case itholds thatrightnessconsistsin 8 Cf. Rawls, A Theory of Justice, pp. 23/4, 27, 29, 187/8, 191; Nozick, pp. 31-34; Fried, pp. 33/4, 105, 114; Williams,"Persons, Character and Morality,"p. 3; and Scheffler,pp. 11/2. 9 Michael Slote, Common-sense Morality and Utilitarianism (Boston: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1985), chs. 3 and 5, suggeststhatwe construe consequentialist or teleological moral theoriesas claimingonlythatcorrectmoral assessmentis some functionof value realized. The claim that rightness is maximal goodness is, according to Slote, only a special case of teleologyor consequentialism. I thinkthat Slote's broad construalof teleologymaymake it difficultto distinguishteleological and deontological moral theories.Whetheror not thisis so, traditionalteleological theories such as utilitarianismconform to my more narrow characterization of teleology. I intend to adhere to this narrower,more traditionalconstrual. Those sympatheticwithSlote's broader construal can treat mydefense of utilitarianand teleological ethics as a defense of a special class of teleological theories. '? Cf. WilliamFrankena,Ethics (Englewood Cliffs,NJ.: Prentice-Hall,1973), pp. 14-17 and Rawls, A Theory ofJustice, pp. 24/5, 30/1. This content downloaded from 128.54.33.205 on Tue, 4 Jun 2013 16:24:18 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 420 THE JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY to maximalgoodness. This weakerconstrualof teleologyis sufficient distinguish between teleological and nonteleological theories, thoughit allowsthe goodness of statesof affairsto be determinedby or acceptability.As long as considerationsof moral permissibility or obligation, is permissibility rightness,i.e., all-things-considered maximal goodness, rightnessand goodness will be distinctproperties,no matterhow goodness is conceived. We can fairlydemand of teleologicaltheories,that theytreatrightnessand goodness as distinct properties,without requiring that they make rightnessand goodness independent of each other. So I shall assume that what distinguishesteleologicaland nonteleologicalmoral theoriesis that the former,unlike the latter,hold rightnessto consist in maximal goodness. We can now make several importantpoints about teleological moral theories,so construed. First,we can distinguishbetween teleological and consequentialistmoral theories; the latterare, on a certainconstrual,just a special case of theformer.Consequentialism is usuallyunderstood as the claim thatactions and other objects of moral assessmentare rightor justifiedjust in case theircausal consequenceshave more intrinsicvalue thanalternativeactions,etc. This is a special case of the teleologist'sclaim that actions and other objects of moral assessmentare rightor justifiedjust in case they realize more intrinsicvalue than alternativeactions, etc. Consequentialism,so construed,is only a special case of the teleological claim,because, unlikethe teleologicalview,consequentialismtreats the objects of moral assessmentas bearers only of extrinsicvalue. The teleologist,on the other hand, allows that objects of moral assessment,such as actions,mighthave intrinsicvalue and thattheir intrinsicvalue counts towardthe rightnessor justifiednessof those objects of assessment." Second, this characterizationof teleologydoes not require that teleologicaltheoriesprovidereductivetheoriesof goodness or value. Teleological theoriesmaydefinerightnessin termsof goodness and goodness in termsof moralpropertiessuch as fairnessor respectfor persons. The resultingtheoryneed be neithercircularnor deontological. It would be circular,as we have seen, to identifyrightness withgoodness and then to identifygoodness withrightness.But we or oblipermissibility can definerightness,i.e., all-things-considered gation, in termsof goodness and goodness in termsof still other " If, however,the consequences whose intrinsicvalue consequentialismseeks to maximizeinclude conceptual as well as causal consequences, thenconsequentialism can treatactions, motives,etc. as intrinsicallyvaluable. So construed, consequentialismand teleologywould be equivalent. Cf. Scheffler,pp. ln-2n. This content downloaded from 128.54.33.205 on Tue, 4 Jun 2013 16:24:18 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions UTILITARIANISM AND THE PERSONAL POINT OF VIEW 421 moralpropertieswithoutcircularity (contrastFrankena,14). Indeed, as we have seen, since the teleologistdefinesrightnessas maximal goodness, he can give an account of the good which relies on the acceptabilityof certainstatesof affairswithoutidentifying rightness and goodness. Third, this characterizationof teleologyallows for a pluralityof objects of moral assessment.Utilitarianismand other teleological theorieshave traditionallybeen concerned with the assessmentof therightnessof actions.But actionsneed not be theteleologist'sonly objects of moral assessment.'2The teleologistcan assess motives, rules,and institutions as wellas actions.These too the teleologistwill assess by the value thattheyrealize. Fourth, as we shall see at greater length below, teleological theoriescan be construedas standards or criteriaof rightnessor as decision procedures.A standard or criterionof rightnessexplains what makes an action or motiverightor justified;a decision procedure provides a method of deliberation.Teleological theories do provide criteriaof rightness,but need not provide decision procedures.'3 Justas an agent maybest secure his own happiness not by alwaysseekinghis own happiness,but by pursuingcertainactivities fortheirown sake,so too an agentmaymaximizetotalwelfarenot as the result of deliberatingabout how to do so or by acting out of benevolence,but byreasoningin nonutilitarian waysor byactingon nonutilitarian(nonbeneficent)motives. Finally,different teleologicaltheoriesresultfromdifferent specificationsof thegood. Utilitariantheoriesare teleologicaltheorieswith a welfaristtheoryof value. Utilitarianism claimsthathuman welfare or happinessis whatis of value.'4 As a teleologicaltheory,utilitarian12 Cf.JeremyBentham,An Introduction to thePrinciples ofMorals and Legislation (London: Athlone Press, 1970) ch. VII, sec. 13; J. S. Mill, Utilitarianism (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1979) ch. II, ? 17; Henry Sidgwick,The Methods of Ethics, 7thed. (Chicago: UniversityPress, 1907), p. 428; Robert MerrihewAdams, "Motive Utilitarianism"thisJOURNAL, LXXIII, 14 (Aug. 12, 1976): 467-481; AmartyaSen, "Utilitarianismand Welfarism,"ibid., LXXVI, 9 (September 1979): 463-489. '3 Cf. Joseph Butler, Fifteen Sermons (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1983), sermon XII, sec. iv, ? 31;J. S. Mill, Utilitarianism, ch. II, ?? 16 and 19, Autobiography(New York: Columbia, 1924), p. 100, A Systemof Logic (London: Longmans, 1970), book VI, ch. xii, sec. 7; Sidgwick,pp. 405/6, 413, 431-433, 489/90; G. E. Moore, Principia Ethica (New York: Cambridge, 1903), pp., 162-164; R. E. Bales, "Actutilitarianism:Account of Right-makingCharacteristicsor Decision-makingProcedure?" American Philosophical Quarterly, VIII, 3 (July1971): 257-265; Peter Railton,"Alienation,Consequentialism,and the Demands of Morality,"Philosophy and Public Affairs, XIII, 2 (Spring 1984): 140-146, 152/3; and Derek Parfit, Reasons and Persons (New York: Oxford, 1984), pp. 24-29. 14 Of course, a utilitariancan construe the good as sentientwelfareor happiness. I will not discuss this form of utilitarianism;the sentient-welfareteleologist can interpretmyargumentsand claims mutatis mutandis. This content downloaded from 128.54.33.205 on Tue, 4 Jun 2013 16:24:18 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 422 THE JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY ism claims thatactions, motives,institutions,etc. are rightor justifiedjust in case theyrealize as muchhumanwelfareas anyalternative action,motive,institution, etc. available (i.e.,just in case theymaximize welfare).Of course, different conceptionsof welfareare possible, and differentconceptions of utilitarianismresult from these different conceptionsof thegood. Traditionalversionsof utilitarianism offersubjectiveconceptionsof welfare.'5They construewelfare as eitherpleasure or preferencesatisfaction.These theoriesof welfare are subjective,because theymake welfareconsistin or depend importantly upon psychologicalfactsabout what people happen to want.Bycontrast,objectivetheoriesof welfaremaketheconstituents of welfarelargelynonsubjective;on thisview,a valuable lifeconsists in such thingsas having a certain kind of character,engaging in certainkindsof activities,and exercisingcertaincapacities.'6 What makes such thingsvaluable is largelyindependent of what people happen to prefer.Of course, different formsof objectiveutilitarianism resultfromdifferentobjective conceptions of welfare. Althoughthe claim that utilitarianismcannot accommodate the personal point of view is oftenurged against traditionalsubjective versionsof utilitarianism, it is supposed to be true in virtueof utilitarianism'steleologicalaspects.'7 For thisreason, the personal point of viewis supposed to tellagainstnonsubjectiveversionsof utilitarianism and nonutilitarianteleological theories as well. Part of my responseto thisobjection relieson the resourcesavailable to utilitarianism.Utilitarianism can partiallyaccommodatethe demandsof the personal point of viewif utilitarianism is construedas a criterionof rightness,ratherthan as a decision procedure, and if its theoryof value is objective.There is no good reason to denytheseresourcesto utilitarianism. Since the objection fromthe personal point of viewis supposed to undermineall teleological theories,however,it is im- '5 If Fred Berger,Happiness, Justice, and Freedom (Los Angeles: CaliforniaUP, 1984) is correct,J. S. Mill is an importantexception to this general tendency. Accordingto Berger,Mill defends a versionof objective utilitarianism, whichI find quite plausible. 16 Cf. T. M. Scanlon, "Preferenceand Urgency,"thisJOURNAL, LXXII, 19 (Nov. 6, 1975): 655-669 and "Rights, Goals, and Fairness" reprintedin Waldron; Richard Kraut,"Two Conceptions of Happiness," Philosophical Review, LXXXVIII, 2 (April 1979): 167-197. Kraut distinguishesbetween subjectiveand objective conceptions of happiness. Though I thinkKraut is rightto find objective components in our conception of happiness, it may be easier to see this distinctionas a distinction between differentconceptions of welfare. For we mightthinkthat our criteriafor application of the word 'happiness' are predominantlysubjective, even if we can thinkof welfarein completelynonsubjective terms. 17 See Williams,"A Critique," pp. 79, 81; Nozick, pp. 28/9; Fried, pp. 2, 8, 104. This content downloaded from 128.54.33.205 on Tue, 4 Jun 2013 16:24:18 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions UTILITARIANISM AND THE PERSONAL POINT OF VIEW 423 portantonly that these resources be available to some teleological theories. II. THE PERSONAL POINT OF VIEW Williamsformulateshis versionof the claim thatutilitarianism cannot accommodate the importanceof the personal point of viewas a claim about personal integrity.He claims that it is a deep commitmentto certainpersonalprojectswhichgivesone's lifemeaningand, hence, integrity. Because utilitarianism assesses the rightnessof, say, actionsby the consequences of those actions foreveryone'swelfare, Williamsclaims,utilitarianismrequires agents to assume an impersonal point of view.This impersonalpoint of viewrequiresagentsto take an impartialattitudetowardtheirown welfare;an agent must viewhis own projects as no more valuable than those of others.But thisis inconsistentwiththe concern thatan agent,as an agent,must have for his own projects and commitments.Utilitarianism,therefore,cannot accommodate the personal point of view. The pointis thathe [an agent]is identified withhisactionsas flowing fromhisprojectsandattitudes whichin somecaseshe takesseriously at thedeepestlevel,as whathislifeis about.. . . It is absurdtodemandof sucha man,whenthesumscomein fromtheutility network whichthe projectsofothershaveinpartdetermined, thathe shouldjuststepaside fromhisownprojectand decisionand acknowledge thedecisionwhich utilitarian calculation requires.It is to alienatehimin a realsensefrom hisactionand thesourceof hisactionin hisownconvictions. It is to makehimintoa channelbetweenthe inputof everyone'sprojects, including his own,and an outputof optimific decision;but thisis to neglecttheextenttowhichhisactionsandhisdecisionshavetobe seen as theactionsand decisionswhichflowfromtheprojectsand attitudes withwhichhe is mostcloselyidentified. It is thus,in themostliteral sense,an attackon hisintegrity ("A Critique,"116/7). Utilitarianismas a Criterionof Rightness.As Williamsand others construethisobjection,it is an objection to utilitarianism's requirementthatagents regard theirprojectsfroman impersonalpoint of view.'8So construed,the integrity objection is an objection to utilitarianismas a decision procedure: utilitarianreasoning requires agents to discounttheirown projects in a waywhichdisregardsthe personalpointof view.If utilitarianism were a decisionprocedure,it would require everyoneto value his projects and commitmentsimpersonallyand, hence, impartially.People would be required to act on motivesof impartialbenevolenceand to sacrificefrequentlytheir 18 See Williams, "A Critique," pp. 113, 115/6, 123, 128, 135, and Scheffler, p. 43. This content downloaded from 128.54.33.205 on Tue, 4 Jun 2013 16:24:18 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 424 THE JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY own projects and commitments in order to maximize total welfare. Utilitarian reasoning cannot recognize the special concern that an agent has for his own projects and commitments and so cannot recognize the moral importance of the personal point of view. But utilitarianism does not require the assumption of the impersonal point of view in normal circumstances. It would require this only if it were a decision procedure. Utilitarianism need provide only a standard or criterion of rightness and not also a decision procedure. Although some utilitarians may have taken their theory to offer a decision procedure,l9 utilitarianism need not be and typically has not been construed in this way. Utilitarianism need only provide the criterion or standard of rightness. Joseph Butler, J. S. Mill, Henry Sidgwick, G. E. Moore, and others have distinguished, in various terms, between moral theories as criteria or standards of rightness and as decision procedures (see fn 14). Criteria of rightness supply the property or properties in virtue of which objects of moral assessment, e.g., actions, are right or justified. A decision procedure states how agents should deliberate, reason, and make moral decisions. As such, a decision procedure also has implications for the content of a moral agent's motives. Because utilitarianism claims that everyone's happiness matters and that total happiness be maximized, a utilitarian decision procedure would require, among other things, that agents be disinterestedly benevolent at all times. But utilitarianism can be a criterion of rightness without being a decision procedure. Sidgwick makes this point in the following way: Finally,the doctrinethatUniversalHappiness is the ultimatestandard mustnot be understoodto implythatUniversalBenevolence is the only rightor alwaysthe best motiveof action. For, as we have observed,it is not necessarythatthe end whichgivesthe criterionof rightnessshould alwaysbe the end at whichwe consciouslyaim: and ifexperienceshows that the general happiness will be more satisfactorily obtained if men it is frequently act fromothermotivesthanpure universalphilanthropy, obvious that these other motivesare reasonably to be preferredon Utilitarianprinciples(413). Sidgwick's point is that because of facts such as our limited abilities to benefit effectivelypeople whom we do not know and the special importance of personal projects and relationships, utilitywill not be maximized by universal benevolence. Rather, the standard of utili19Bentham, ch. ii, sec. 10, seems to be construingutilitarianismas a decision procedure (Berger, pp. 73-77, disputes this). Interestingly,it is almost entirely opponents of utilitarianismwho make this assumption. This content downloaded from 128.54.33.205 on Tue, 4 Jun 2013 16:24:18 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions UTILITARIANISM AND THE PERSONAL POINT OF VIEW 425 tarianismwillbe bettersatisfiedif we have special concern for ourselves and those near at hand (432-434). Call an agent who uses utilitarianism as a decision procedure and acts withthe intentionof maximizingwelfarea U-agent. There are familiar utilitarian reasons for thinkingthat we should not be U-agents. Interpersonal comparisons of welfare and estimatesof total,long-runconsequences of alternativeactions and policies are often difficultto make with accuracy. The causal mechanismsin manyof these counterfactualsituationsare numerousand complex, our timeis frequentlylimited,and our calculationsare oftensubject to distortiondue to prejudice, self-interest, and failureof imagination. For these and otherreasons, therewillbe manycases in which our estimatesof what would maximize human welfare would be highlyunreliable.U-agents,therefore,would frequentlyfailto maximize welfare.Of course, U-agentscan make use of rules of thumb. But these are just summariesof formerprospectiveand retrospective estimates.Any U-agent must continuallyscrutinizethese rules and departfromthemwheneverhe thinksa new situationsufficiently differentfrom previous ones. And, of course, both the estimates embodied in the rules of thumband those used in departingfrom rules of thumb are subject to the same sort of errors as are the estimatesthat the rules of thumbwere introducedto avoid. These limitationson our abilityto make reliableestimatesof consequences and theirvalue present utilitarianreasons for believing that agents should deliberate,not by attemptingto maximizewelfare,but byappealing to rulesthatare infactjustifiableas contributing to human welfare.These rules willnot be mere rules of thumb, because they will not functionas aids in utilitariandeliberation. Rather,moralrules,on thisview,should be appealed to and applied more or less strictly and uncritically in mostcases. The complexityof the moral rules that are justifiableon utilitariangrounds and the strictnesswithwhichtheyshould be followeddepends upon just how serious and general our inabilityto estimateconsequences and their value is, and thismayvaryamong societiesand individuals.It maybe thatour inabilitiesas U-agentsare so greatthatwe are neverjustified in departingfroma relativelycoarse-grainedset of moralrules.20But it is much more likelythatwe should set aside the moral rules and deliberateas U-agentsin certainunusual circumstancesand in cases of conflictsof moral rules.2'When the applicationof generallyoptiMoore, pp. 162-164, thoughtso. Cf. Mill, Utilitarianism, ch. ii, ? 25 (Berger,pp. 66-73, 82-84); Sidgwick,pp. 401, 426, 429, 453, 461; R. M. Hare, Moral Thinking (New York: Oxford, 1981), chs. 2 and 3. 20 21 This content downloaded from 128.54.33.205 on Tue, 4 Jun 2013 16:24:18 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 426 THE JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY mificrules would clearlyfail to maximizethe general welfare(e.g. and when and clearlyavoidable suffering) would produce significant moral rules, each of which has a utilitarianjustification,conflict, agents should deliberate as U-agents.22 The utilitarian,then, can construe his theoryas a criterionof rightnessratherthana decisionprocedure. Our cognitivelimitations provide us withgood utilitarianreason for acting on valuable motivesand by appeal to valuable rules. By regularlyactingfromthese motivesand withregard to these rules, we will maximizethe total value realized by our actions.23 Indeed, as Sidgwickobserves,there is good reason to thinkthat such a set of moral rules would specify,among other things,that concernfortheirown projectsand agentsshould adopt a differential to knowwhat them. It is oftendifficult close to of others thewelfare would benefitothers,and, even when one does know,one is oftenin a poor positionto produce some of thosebenefitswithoutgreatcost to oneself.Moreover,thepossessionand pursuitof personalprojects and the developmentof close personal relationshipsinvolvingmutual concern and commitmentare a source of great utility.Of course, the utilitarianjustificationof the personal point of view willrecognize obligations should not be exaggerated.Utilitarianism to assistotherswhen significantharm can be avoided or significant benefitprovided withoutgreat cost to the agent. But even these 22 Of course, in some cases of conflictwe maybe poor U-agents,and theremaybe generallyoptimificpriorityrules that should, therefore,be followed. 23 It maybe useful to emphasize that,insofaras it is a theoryof rightaction, this utilitarianaccount of moral rules is an act-utilitariantheory.The rightnessof actions is determinedby theiractual contributionto human welfare.But agents need not and should not deliberate as U-agents. Because of our unreliabilityas calculators of welfare,we would oftenbe betteroffacting from"nonutilitarian"motives and rules. Part of our unreliabilityas U-agentsis our frequentinabilityto discriminate those cases in which the best action would involvedepartingfromestablished rules. Our motivationaland cognitiveabilitiesare such that we could depart from established rules and maximize welfare in this case only by being such as also to depart fromestablishedrules in other cases in whichdoing so would not maximize welfare.There are good utilitarianreasons, therefore,for acting fromsturdymotivesand established rules thatone knowswill sometimesfail to maximizewelfare. By acting fromoptimificmotivesand in accord withoptimificrules, we will almost certainlyperformsome actions that are wrong. But thisjust shows that the assessmentof particularactions is not the most importantdimension of assessmentfora utilitarian.For by acting fromoptimificmotivesand in accord withoptimificrules, we will mazimize the total value realized by our actions. Even if agents should typicallyact fromsturdymotivesand in accord withestablished rules,theremaynonethelessbe good utilitarianreason forthemto deliberate as U-agents in order to avert disaster,adjudicate conflictsamong moral rules, and criticallyassess the value of theirmoral rules in a "cool hour" when theircalculations are less subject to distortion. This content downloaded from 128.54.33.205 on Tue, 4 Jun 2013 16:24:18 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions UTILITARIANISM AND THE PERSONAL POINT OF VIEW 427 other-regarding obligationscan be carriedout in waysthatare minimallydisruptiveof agents' personal projectsand commitments, e.g., bymeans of public taxationschemesor mutual-aidorganizations.In normalcircumstances,therefore,utilitarianism can justifya limited but nonethelessdifferential concernforpersonalprojectsand so will not require agentsto be foreversettingaside theirown projectsand in the impersonalpursuitof welfaremaximization.24 A commitments utilitarianmaythusdefendhis theoryas a standardof rightnessand claim to accommodate the moral importanceof the personal point of view. There are two worriesabout this defense of utilitarianism, however, which need to be addressed. This defense depends upon the distinctionbetween criteriaof rightnessand decision procedures. The firstworryconcernsthelegitimacyof thisdistinction;the second concerns the adequacy of the defense thisdistinctionaffords. The Publicity Objection. Some would claim thatutilitarianismcannot be maintainedas a criterionor standardof rightnessratherthan a decision procedure. In order for a moral theoryto provide a standardof rightconduct, theywould claim,it must be a standard whichcan be taughtand whichcan serve as a publicjustificationof actions,policies,institutions, etc.25 Utilitarianism, therefore,cannot distinguishbetweencriteriaof rightnessand decision procedures so as to justifynonutilitarianmotivesand uncriticalacceptance of a pluralityof moral rules. Williamsmakes thisobjection as follows. There is no distinctiveplace for . . . utilitarianism unless it is, within fairlynarrowlimits,a doctrineabout how one should decide whatto do. This is because its distinctivedoctrineis about whatacts are right,and, especially,for utilitarians,the only distinctiveinterestor point of the question what acts are right,relates to the situationof deciding to do them("A Critique," 128). Williamsalso referswith approval to John Rawls's insistencethat utilitarianism not violate a publicitycondition. Rawls writes We should note, then,thatutilitarianism, as I have definedit,is theview that the principleof utilityis the correctprinciplefor society'spublic Cf. Sidgwick,pp. 432-434; Scheffler,p. 15; and Railton. See Rawls, A Theory of Justice, pp. 133, 177-182, 582; Williams, "A Critique," pp. 123, 125, 128, 135; Michael Stocker, "The Schizophrenia of Modern Moral Theories," thisJOURNAL, LXXIII, 14 (Aug. 12, 1976): 453-466; Donagan, pp. 198-200; and Lomasky, pp. 275, 279. Cf. Brian Medlin, "Ethical Egoism and UltimateMoral Principles," reprintedin D. Gauthier,ed., Morality and Rational Self-interest(Englewood Cliffs,N.J.: Prentice-Hall, 1970). 24 25 This content downloaded from 128.54.33.205 on Tue, 4 Jun 2013 16:24:18 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 428 THE JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY of Whatwewanttoknowiswhichconception conception ofjustice.. equilibrium in reflective judgments ourconsidered justicecharacterizes Unlessone maintains andbestservesas thepublicmoralbasisofsociety. one is not a thatthisconceptionis givenby the principleof utility, utilitarian(A TheoryofJustice, 32). Rawls's objection to the distinction between criteria of rightness and decision procedures rests upon his acceptance of the publicity constraint. This constraint can be construed as a conceptual constraint upon what can count as a moral theory or, alternatively, as a substantive and revisable moral belief. Construed as a formal or conceptual claim which would undermine the distinction between criteria of rightness and decision procedures, the publicity constraint simply begs the question against teleological moral theories. Whether the true moral theory should be recognized, taught, or recommended as a decision procedure are themselves practical questions the answers to which, the teleologist claims, depend upon the intrinsic and extrinsic value that this sort of publicity produces. Nor is this separation of truth and acceptance value peculiar to ethics (cf. Railton, 154/5). Not only do we distinguish the truth and acceptance value of nonmoral claims, but we recognize, as reasonable, claims that certain facts should be suppressed. We may not always thinksuppression is justified, but we find such claims intelligible and take them seriously. It is conceivable that truth and acceptance value are not separate in the case of moral truth, but this needs to be argued.26 The publicity constraint, therefore, must be construed as a substantive moral claim. Here, I think, a utilitarian should claim that there is no reason to think that utilitarianism will violate the publicityconstraint and that, in those counterfactual situations in which it would, this constitutes no objection to utilitarianism. In the actual world utilitarianism satisfies the publicity constraint. Publicity would be violated only if utilitarianism could not be recognized as the standard of rightness and utilitarian reasoning was always inappropriate. But a utilitarian commitment to moral rules 26 Of course, it would be difficult to separate moral truthand acceptance value if moral realismwere rejected. If moral claims could be not true but onlyacceptable, as some noncognitivistsclaim, or if the truthof moral claims consisted in their claim, then moral truthand acceptance value acceptability,as some constructivists could not be distinguishedso as to justifythe claim that utilitarianismcan be a standard of rightnesswithoutbeing a decision procedure. But, of course, it takes a separate argumentto show thatmoral realismis false. For defense of moral realism, see my "Moral Realism and the Sceptical Arguments from Disagreement and Queerness," Australasian Journal of Philosophy, LXII, 2 (June 1984): 111-125, and Moral Realism and the Foundations of Ethics. This content downloaded from 128.54.33.205 on Tue, 4 Jun 2013 16:24:18 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions UTILITARIANISM AND THE PERSONAL POINT OF VIEW 429 thatare more thanrules of thumband to the moralvalue of motives other than benevolence is compatiblewiththe recognitionthat the moraljustificationfor these rules and motivesconsistsin theircontributionto human welfare.Moreover,utilitarianassessmentis appropriatein some circumstances.Circumstancesin which the relevantcalculationscan be made accuratelycan limitthe applicationof moral rules and call for utilitariandeliberation; conflictsamong moral rules,each of whichhas a utilitarianjustification,can call for utilitariandeliberation; and some agents in some circumstances should take the time and effortto assess the consequences of past and continued adherence to a particularset of moral rules. This is psychologically possibleand does not attitudetowardutilitarianism offendagainst the publicitycondition. Of course,theremustbe possiblecircumstances,even ifwe cannot representthem,in whichit would be best thatmostpeople not even recognize utilitarianismas providingthe standard or criterionof rightconduct. Under these circumstances,utilitarianismwould indeed be an "esoteric morality"(Sidgwick,489/90). But this is a possibilityfor any moral theory.For any moral theory,there are possible circumstances in which its recognition and application would satisfythe theoryworse than recognitionand application of The proper response of anyone,who, as some alternativetheory.27 theorist,believesthe theoryin question to be true,is to thinkthatin thosecircumstancesthe true theoryshould be suppressedand some false theoryrecognized. Publicityis a plausible but revisable subA moraltheorythatviolatedpublicityin stantivemoralcommitment. the actual worldwould be less plausible forthatreason. But the fact thatthereare merelypossible circumstancesin whicha moral theory would require violationof publicityis not a factpeculiar to utilitarior to any anismand is not itself,I think,an objection to utilitarianism moral other theory. So, a defense of utilitarianismthat relies on the distinctionbetweencriteriaof rightnessand decision proceduresis legitimateand is not undermined by considerationsof publicity.The utilitarian 27 Aren't there circumstancesin whicha Kantian would thinkpublicityshould be violated? Imagine people who have hopelessly false beliefs about what a rational being as such would will. In such circumstances,agents mightbetter satisfythe Categorical Imperativeif theydo not alwaysdeliberate about how to satisfyit. They mightbetterapproximate how rational beings as such would act by acting directly on a particularset of moral rules. In such circumstances,mightnot a Kantian want to suppress the Categorical Imperativeand advocate some particularset of moral rules which a rational being as such would will? Indeed, we mightwonder whether these circumstancesare merelypossible. This content downloaded from 128.54.33.205 on Tue, 4 Jun 2013 16:24:18 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 430 THE JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY claimsthatthevalue of publicitydepends upon the effectsof publicityon human welfare.There are possible circumstancesin whicha utilitarianwould and should violate the publicitycondition.In normal circumstances,however,there is no reason for a utilitarianto violate publicity.28 The Value of Autonomy.Even if the distinctionbetweencriteriaof rightnessand decision procedures is legitimate,one may wonder whetherthe defense that it affordsutilitarianismis adequate. The objection fromthe personal point of view can be construed as an criterionof rightness.Even ifutilitarianobjection to utilitarianism's ismdoes not require agentsto adopt a purelyimpersonalattitude,it stillassigns moral value impersonally.Is thisfeatureof utilitarianism consistentwiththe recognitionof the moral importanceof the personal point of view? I am not convinced that this sort of impersonalityis morallyobjectionable. Is it objectionable for a standard of rightnessto be impersonal?Do I care whethervalue is assigned to projects impersonally,ifI am not requiredto viewmyown projectsimpersonally?If fromthe personal point of not, then the objection to utilitarianism is a standardof viewhas now been answered:because utilitarianism rightnessand not a decision procedure, it need not and in factwill not require agents to adopt an impersonalattitude.But let us see of a what can be said to someone who thinksthat the impartiality utilitarianstandardof rightnessundervaluesthe moral significance of agents' projects and commitments. If the possession and pursuit of personal projects and commitare mentsthatare supposed to be constitutiveof personal integrity so important,then a utilitarian'saccount of human welfareshould is can claimthatself-determination recognizethisfact.Utilitarianism a dominantcomponentin an agent's welfareand that,therefore,a certain amount of personal autonomyis a necessarycondition for realizingthiskindof value. Because possession,pursuit,and realization of personal projects and commitmentsare dominant componentsin an agent's good, freedomto formulateand pursue personal projects will trump other less important intrinsicand extrinsic goods. On such a theory,one person's reasonable and important projects will not be held hostage to others' whimsor preferences. 28 Cf. Sidgwick,pp. 489/90; Scheffler, pp. 45-52; Railton,pp. 154/5; and Parfit, pp. 24-51, especially40-43. Railton and Schefflerappear to assume thatutilitarianism does violate the publicityconstraintand argue that thisis not so bad. I agree thatviolationof publicityis not so bad when it is necessary,but I do not agree thatit is actuallynecessary. This content downloaded from 128.54.33.205 on Tue, 4 Jun 2013 16:24:18 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions UTILITARIANISM AND THE PERSONAL POINT OF VIEW 431 This response presupposes an objective theoryof welfare;it would depart from traditionalsubjective versions of utilitarianism.But there is no reason to rule out objective theoriesof welfareor the utilitariantheoriesthatincorporatethem.In thisway,objectiveutilitarianismmightclaimthatit accommodatesthe moralimportanceof the personal point of view.29 Is the Impartial Value of AutonomyEnough? This response may well not satisfythose who thinkthat the impersonalassignmentof value undervalues the moral significanceof agents' projects. For their objection presumablyis not that utilitarianismundervalues projectsbut thatit undervaluestheagent's projects. Their worryis about theimpersonalpointof view,and thisworryis not assuaged by takingaccount of the personal point of view, as it were, fromthe can treatautonomy impersonalpoint of view. Even if utilitarianism as a dominantgood, it mustbe impartialbetween the autonomyof differentpeople. Williamspresentsan example whichillustratesthisissue. His example is this.Jimis a foreignexplorerwho comes upon a smallSouth Americanvillagein whichan armycaptainis about to execute twenty innocentvillagersfor"purelypolitical" reasons. As an honored visitor,Jim is offeredthe privilegeof shootingone of the twentyvillagers. If he does, the other nineteenvillagerswill be released unharmed (of thisthereis no doubt!). If he does not, the captain will shoot all twentyas planned. No otheroptionsare reasonablyopen to Jim(Williams'sstipulation).Not implausibly,Williamsclaimsthatin these circumstancesit is clear that Jim would maximize welfare, including,we mightadd, personal projects, by killingthe one villager, and so utilitarianismrequires him to do so ("A Critique," 98/9; Williamsis not explicitabout this,but, presumably,the commitmentthatutilitarianism requiresJimto abandon here is a moral commitmentnot to killinnocentpeople). Jim'scase illustrateswhat, utilitarianism allows on thisview,is the problemwithutilitarianism: the impersonalvalue of an agent's projects to exhaust theirmoral significance(Scheffler,9, 61). Should We Incorporatethe Personal Point of View into Morality? One mightaccept this criticismof utilitarianismand demand that moralityaccommodate the personal point of view. One mightthen in favorof a moraltheorythatincorporateswhat rejectutilitarianism Schefflercalls "agent-centeredprerogatives"(chs. 2 and 3). On such 29 This objective utilitariandefense mightbe compared withNozick's "utilitarianism of rights"; see Nozick, pp. 28-30. This content downloaded from 128.54.33.205 on Tue, 4 Jun 2013 16:24:18 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 432 THE JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY a theory,the moral significanceof agents' projects is not exhausted by their impersonalvalue; an agent's projects have moral significance out of proportionto theirimpersonalvalue. Agent-centered prerogativespermitbut do not require agentsto maximizethe good and so would produce whatSchefflercalls a "hybrid"moral theory. Rightness,on thishybridview,is defineddisjunctively: an action,say, is rightjust in case it either maximizesthe good or preservesthe agent's projects and commitmentsin the appropriate way.30This hybridtheoryis superior to utilitarianism, according to Scheffler, because itreflects"the naturalindependence" of an agent's concern for his own projects and commitments.3' A hybridmoral theory containingagent-centeredprerogatives,therefore,mightseem the best wayto recognize the importanceof the personal point of view. But the utilitarianneed not accept thiscriticismand so need not move to a hybridmoraltheory.Impersonalmoraltheoriescan assign moralvalue to the commitments of agentslikeJim,but theyrefuseto assign Jim's commitmentsany special value because theyare his. Jim'scommitmentsare important,but theyare no more important thanthose of the nineteenvillagerswhomhe could save. In thisway, theimpersonalpointof viewis impartial.It is impartiality of thiskind whichwe expect a moral theoryto reflect.Nor is thiskindof impartiality peculiar to utilitarianism or even to teleological moral theories. Many nonteleological theories recognize duties to forgo one's own good in order to preventgreat harm to or provide great benefitforothers.It is, of course, a substantivemoralclaimthatit is thiskindof impartiality whichis characteristicof the moral point of view,but it is a plausible claim whichcannot be rejected lightly.If thisclaimis correct,thenit is no indictmentof utilitarianism thatit is impersonal. This defense of utilitarianismdoes not force us to deny the importanceof the personal point of view.The personalpoint of viewis important,and we can recognize thiswithoutmakingmoralitycaptureitsimportance.The worriesthatthe importanceof the personal pointof viewraisescan be viewednot as moralworriesbut as worries 30 Scheffler,pp. 17f. discusses more specificformulationsof the second disjunct. In particular,the scope of agent-centeredprerogativesdoes not include just any personal projects or commitments;morallyobnoxious projects and commitments receive littleor no protection fromagent-centeredprerogatives. 31Scheffler, pp. 56, 79, 116. Schefflerseems ambivalentabout whatconclusion to draw. At times,he explicitlyrefusesto conclude thathis hybridtheoryis superior to sophisticatedformsof utilitarianismof the sortdiscussed in pp. 423-427 and 430/1 above (see Scheffler,pp. 65 and 77). But he does claim that the objection to utilitarianismbased upon the personal point of view is well founded (pp. 6, 13, 56, 90, 116). If this objection to utilitarianismis well founded, then a hybridtheory which avoids this objection is presumablysuperior to utilitarianism,other things being equal. This content downloaded from 128.54.33.205 on Tue, 4 Jun 2013 16:24:18 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions UTILITARIANISM AND THE PERSONAL POINT OF VIEW 433 about morality.Our sympathiesforJimneed not be moral sympathies. Cases like Jim's can be dilemmatic,if they are dilemmatic, because theyraise serious questionsabout thejustificationof morality.We can imaginethatifJimis a decent fellow-having the right sortof motives-he maybe haunted by doing as utilitarianmorality requiresand killingan innocentvillager.He mayexperience doubts and serious personal anguish.We maycome to wonderwhetherJim has reason or enough reason to do as moralityrequires in these circumstances.These are worriesabout thejustificationor supremacy of moral demands, not about the correctnessof a utilitarian account of morality. Two preliminarypoints should be made about thisinterpretation of the importanceof the personal point of view.First,thisinterpretationof the conflictbetween utilitarianismand the personal point of view makes the externalistassumption that it is a substantive questionwhethermoralconsiderationsprovidean agentwithreason or sufficient reason foraction, the answerto whichdepends upon a substantivetheoryof reasons for action or rationalityand, in all probability,a substantivetheoryof human welfare.An internalist of moraldemandsmightdenythis,claimingthat about therationality "the concept of morality"makesthisconflictinconceivableor unintelligible.It is simplypart of the concept of a moral consideration that moral considerationsnecessarilyprovide reason or conclusive reason for action.32The dispute between internalismand externalism raises large issues, whichcannot be settledhere. But there are familiarreasons to doubt thisinternalistassumption,whichshould at least force an opponent of utilitarianismto provide a defense of internalism.As many internaliststhemselvesrecognize, common moral experience and philosophical reflectioncan lead one to ask whetherthere are good or sufficientreasons to do as moralityrequires. Call this the amoralist's challenge. Internalismclaims that we can rule out thischallenge as incoherentby appeal to "the concept of morality."But the amoralist'schallenge to the rationalityof moral demands not onlyseems intelligiblebut deserves to be taken seriously.Externalismdoes not claimthattheamoralist'schallengeis unanswerable;itclaimsonlythatthischallengeis intelligibleand that it can be addressed onlyin conjunctionwitha substantivetheoryof reasons foraction. The factthatour abilityto representthe worries 32 Cf. H. A. Prichard, "Does Moral PhilosophyRest on a Mistake?" reprintedin his Moral Obligation (New York: Oxford, 1949); W. D. Falk, " 'Ought' and Motivation" reprintedin W. Sellars and H. Hospers, eds., Readings in Ethical Theory 1952), pp. 494/5, 499-501; and R. M. Hare, (New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts, The Language of Morals (New York: Oxford, 1952), pp. 20, 31, 169, 197 and Moral Thinking, pp. 21, 23/4, 83-86. This content downloaded from 128.54.33.205 on Tue, 4 Jun 2013 16:24:18 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 434 THE JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY whichthe personal point of view raises as worabout utilitarianism ries about the rationalityor supremacyof moral demands depends upon these externalistclaims, therefore,does not seem to be a weaknessin thiswayof representingthe importanceof the personal point of view.33 Second, on this interpretation,the worries about utilitarianism whichthe personalpointof viewraisescan be representedas worries about either the rationalityor the supremacyof moral demands. I assume thatif somethingis in one's interestthen one has reason to bringthatthingabout. Rationalegoismclaimsthatone has reason to do x if and only if x is in one's own interest.The personal point of viewcan be seen as representingtheinterestsof theagent.If rational whichthe peregoism is true,then the worriesabout utilitarianism sonal point of view raises can be representedas worriesabout the rationalityof morality.Do agents have reason to do as utilitarian moralityrequires?This question is answeredby a substantivetheory of human welfarewhich explains to what extent the demands of utilitarianmorality,in particularits demands to benefitothers,promote or are constitutiveof the moral agent's well-being.For example, an objective conception of human welfare which recognizes importantsocial or other-regardingcomponents in an individual's good can provide the basis of a strongjustificationof utilitarian moralityeven on rational-egoistassumptions.(Indeed, if there are componentsto an agent's good, there both self-and other-regarding be a reason to do as utilitarianismrerational-egoist may always quires,even ifthereis not alwaysconclusiverational-egoistreason to do so.) I willsay somethingbelow about a rational-egoistaccount of the rationalityof utilitarianism's implicationsin exceptionalcircumstances,such as Jim's. Alternatively, if rationalegoism is false and agentshave reason to do as utilitarianmoralityrequires independentlyof its contribution to theirown well-being,we can representthe worriesabout utilitarianism which the personal point of view raises as worriesabout the supremacyof moraldemands. Even ifrationalegoismis false,agents presumablystillhave prudentialreasons for action, and these prudential reasons can conflictwith the reasons for action which,on such a theoryof rationality,other-regardingfeatures of morality themselvesprovide.One maythenwonderwhetheragentshave sufficientor conclusivereason to do as utilitarianmoralityrequires. I shallnot attemptto decide here betweenthesealternativerepre33 For a fuller defense of externalism,see William Frankena, "Obligation and Motivationin Recent Moral Philosophy" reprintedin his Perspectiveson Morality, K. Goodpaster, ed. (Notre Dame, Ind.: UniversityPress, 1976) and my Moral Realism and the Foundations of Ethics, chapter 3. This content downloaded from 128.54.33.205 on Tue, 4 Jun 2013 16:24:18 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions UTILITARIANISM AND THE PERSONAL POINT OF VIEW 435 sentations of the conflict between utilitarian morality and the personal point of view. Rather, I want to stress what is common to them; both represent the worries that the personal point of view raises as worries about the justifiability of moral demands rather than as moral worries. This interpretation of the true conflict between utilitarianism and the personal point of view is confirmed by Williams's claims in "Persons, Character and Morality": A man who has such a groundprojectwillbe requiredby Utilitarianism to giveup whatit requiresin a givencasejust ifitconflictswithwhathe is whenall of thecausally requiredto do as an impersonalutility-maximizer relevantconsiderationsare in. That is quite an absurd requirement.But the Kantian,who can do ratherbetter than that,still cannot do well enough. For impartialmorality,ifthe conflictreallydoes arise,mustbe requiredto win;and thatcannot necessarilybe a reasonable demand on theagent.There can come a pointat whichit is quite unreasonablefora man to giveup, in thename of the impartialgood orderingof theworld of moralagents,somethingwhichis a conditionof his havinginterestin being around in the world at all (14). The fact that Williams here takes Kantian views of morality to be equally guilty of making unreasonable demands upon agents supports the claim that the real worry latent in the conflict between utilitarianism and the personal point of view is not the worry within morality about which moral theory is correct but the worry about morality concerning the rationality or supremacy of moral demands.34 We can recognize the importance of the personal point of view without granting it moral importance. Indeed, not only can we recognize the importance of the personal point of view without granting it moral importance; we should not concede it moral importance. Not only is Scheffler's preference for a hybrid moral theory incorporating agent-centered prerogatives unnecessary; hybrid moral theories actually misrepresent the connection between morality and the personal point of view. There are two reasons for this. First, the impartialityamong various people's goods which is characteristic of utilitarianism and other teleological theories represents important considered beliefs about the nature and demands of mo3 Though we arrivedat our viewsseparately,I would like to record myagreement on thispoint withSarah Conly's suggestivereviewof Scheffler'sbook in the Philosophical Review, XCIII, 3 (uly 1984): 489-492. Interestingly,this theme is not emphasized in her discussion of Williams;see Conly, "Utilitarianismand Integrity" The Monist, LXVI, 2 (April 1983): 298-311. Though Railton's title suggests this interpretationof Williams'sargument,Railton does not develop thisinterpretation fully.But see Railton, pp. 163n-164n. This content downloaded from 128.54.33.205 on Tue, 4 Jun 2013 16:24:18 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 436 THE JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY ralitybetterthan a hybridmoral theorythat incorporatesthe personal point of view into morality.An importantmoral belief is that the moral perspectiveis an impartialperspective;moral demands frequentlyrequireus to put aside purelypersonal projectsand commitmentsin order to preventharm to or do good for others. One argumentforthe impartialcharacterof moralityparallelsScheffler's own argumentagainst agent-centeredrestrictions.Schefflerdistinguishes between his own agent-centeredprerogativeswhichpermit but do not require an agent to maximizethe good and agent-centeredrestrictionsthatdo not even permitthe agent to maximizethe good. Agent-centeredrestrictionsare based upon the claim thatit is sometimeswrongto maximizethe good. Schefflerdefendswhat he thesis:althoughthe naturalindependence of the calls theasymmetry personal point of viewprovidesa principledrationaleforagent-centered prerogatives,there is no principledrationale for agent-centeredrestrictions (ch. 4, esp. 82-100). In particular,Schefflerargues that a moral theoryincorporatingagent-centeredrestrictionsdoes not represent a rational response to the demands utilitarianism places upon agents.For example,againstNozick's construalof rights as side constraints(Nozick, 28-30), Schefflerclaims,ifa violationof a rightis a bad thing,then it is rational to want to minimizethe violationof rights-even if we must violate one person's rightsin order to do this. Similarly,ifJim's projects and commitmentsare valuable, then so are those of the nineteenvillagerswhose lives he could save, and it is rational to minimizethe violation of people's projects and commitmentsas utilitarianisminstructsJim to. But, againstScheffler,if these violationsof people's basic projects are of disvalue, their minimizationis arguablyobligatoryand not merely permissible.Moreover,thisjudgment seems to be confirmedbyconsidered moral beliefs. Regrettableas this kind of situationis, one oughtto violateone person's right,say,to libertyin order to prevent a greaternumber of equally serious violationsof liberty(or some equally weightyright).Also, disagreeable as thisis,Jimought to kill the one innocentvillagerin order to save nineteen other innocent lives. Moralityappears impartialamong people's good in the way utilitarianism and other teleological theoriesclaim. Second, ifwe were to accept the demand thatmoralityaccommodate the personal point of view, as Schefflerdoes, we would find ourselvesunable to ask a question that,we have seen, is surelyintelligible and legitimate.We would be unable to ask whetherthe demands of moralityare reallyrationalor justifiable.If moralitywere forced to incorporatethe personal point of view,we could not get whatare at least apparentconflictsbetweenthe demands of morality and the interestsof agents.Common sense and philosophicalreflec- This content downloaded from 128.54.33.205 on Tue, 4 Jun 2013 16:24:18 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions UTILITARIANISM AND THE PERSONAL POINT OF VIEW 437 tion upon the demands thatmoralitycan make lead one to question whetherthere are alwaysgood and sufficientreasons to be moral. Philosophical deliberationabout the demands of morality,the nature of an agent's good, and the nature of rationalitymayvindicate the rationalityor supremacyof moral demands. But, even if we are able to answerthe question, Whybe moral?,we need to be able to formulatethe question. If we are to be able to formulatethe question about the rationalityor supremacyof morality,we mustbe able to representwhat are at least apparent conflictsbetween the demandsof moralityand theinterestsof agents.Hybridmoraltheories could representapparent conflictswithinmorality,but not the conflictsbetween moralityand the agent's interestwithwhich we are Since we are familiarwiththese apparent conflicts,it is a familiar.35 virtueof moraltheoriesthatare impartialin thewayin whichutilitarianismis that theyallow, indeed, lead one to expect such conflicts, and a defectof hybridmoraltheoriesthattheycannotrepresentsuch conflicts. or supremacyof morality If it is reallya worryabout therationality whichthe personal point of view raises, then the personal point of view presentsno objection to utilitarianaccounts of morality.Indeed, as Williams'slater writingstestify,the worryabout morality which the personal point of view raises is not a worrypeculiar to or even to teleologicalmoral theories. utilitarianism of moralityraiseslarge issues whichare indepenThe justifiability dent of the meritsof utilitarianism.Nevertheless,the defense of utilitarianism givenabove does suggestcertainclaims.An objective version of utilitarianismthat recognizes autonomyas a dominant good can explainwhythepursuitand realizationof personalprojects is a standardor is so important.Because thisversionof utilitarianism criterionof rightnessand not a decision procedure,it can and will justify agents in adopting a differentialconcern for their own projects and the welfareof those close to them. Even on rationalegoistassumptions,therefore,agentswillnormallyhave reason to do as utilitarianism requires. Of course, not all circumstancesare normal.Jim'scase illustrates 3 It mightseem thathybridtheoriescould representthe conflictbetween moralbecause agent-centeredprerogativesdo not incorporate the ityand self-interest, personal point of view completely into morality.Scheffler,pp. 17f. claims that agent-centeredprerogativeswould not protectmorallyobnoxious personal projects and commitments(e.g. those of Caligula or Hitler). So hybridtheoriesleave room for conflictbetween moralityand these personal projects and commitments.But I doubt that any plausible theoryof agent good would recognize these conflictsas conflictsbetween moralityand self-interest.In any case, the apparent conflicts between moralityand self-interest withwhichwe are familiarare not limitedto such cases. This content downloaded from 128.54.33.205 on Tue, 4 Jun 2013 16:24:18 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 438 THE JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY can sometimesdemand of agentsa greatdeal. It is how utilitarianism true thatifJimis a decent fellow-having the rightsort of motives he maysufferifhe complieswiththe demand of utilitarianmoralwould suffer just as itythathe killan innocentvillager.But surelyJim much if not more, assumingagain that he is a decent fellow,if he refusesto complywiththedemandsof utilitarianmorality.Here too, he mayexperience doubts and anguish. Indeed, thistimehe would be haunted not by the death of one innocent villagerbut by the nineteen innocent lives he could have saved. It seems to be the situation, notutilitarian morality,thatis hard on Jim.The factthat Jim may be poorly offno matterwhat he does is one reason the situationis dilemmatic. Fortunately,these kinds of dilemma are rare. In normal circumstances,utilitarianism'saccount of moralityis compatible with the concern forone's own projects of a differential moral permissibility and the welfareof those close to one. In some circumstances,an impartialweightingof everyone'sgood will require agents to sacriin orderto prevent ficeimportantpersonalprojectsor commitments greatharmto, or produce greatbenefitfor,others.This is the sortof demand we expect a moral theoryto make. And where the sacrifice demanded of the agent is great,he maytypicallytake consolationin the knowledgethathis sufferingwould be no less were he to resist the demands of morality. III. CONCLUSION Considerationof the objection fromthe personal point of view reThe utilitariancan offera parveals the resources of utilitarianism. betweencriteriaof rightnessand decitial rebuttalbydistinguishing sion proceduresand claimingthat,because his theoryis a criterionof rightnessand not a decision procedure,he can justifyagents' differentialconcernfortheirown welfareand thewelfareof thoseclose to theoryof value allows further in utilitarianism's them.The flexibility rebuttal of this objection; objective versions of utilitarianismcan or autonomy as a dominant good which treat self-determination trumpseven large magnitudesof lessergoods such as pleasure. After are exhausted,though,thereremains the resourcesof utilitarianism a worry,generatedby the personal point of view,about utilitarianBut thisworryis correctlyviewed,not as a moral ism's impartiality. as a moral theory,but as a worryabout the meritsof utilitarianism worryabout moralityconcerning the rationalityor supremacyof impartialmoral demands. Whether or not this worrycan be answered, the fact that it arises supports rather than underminesa utilitarianaccount of morality. DAVID Case WesternReserve University This content downloaded from 128.54.33.205 on Tue, 4 Jun 2013 16:24:18 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 0. BRINK