As Others See Us: A Case Study in Path Analysis Author(s): D. A. Freedman Source: Journal of Educational Statistics, Vol. 12, No. 2, (Summer, 1987), pp. 101-128 Published by: American Educational Research Association and American Statistical Association Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/1164888 Accessed: 04/06/2008 10:30 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use. Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=aera. Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. JSTOR is a not-for-profit organization founded in 1995 to build trusted digital archives for scholarship. We enable the scholarly community to preserve their work and the materials they rely upon, and to build a common research platform that promotes the discovery and use of these resources. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org. http://www.jstor.org Journal of Educational Statistics Summer 1987, Vol. 12, No. 2, pp. 101-128 As Others See Us: A Case Study in Path Analysis D. A. Freedman University of California at Berkeley Key words: path analysis, path models, structural equation models, regression, correlation, causation In 1967, Blau and Duncan proposed a path model for education and stratification. This is one of the most influential applications of statistical modeling technique to social data. There is recent use of the same technique in Hope's (1984) comparative study of Scotland and the United States, As OthersSee Us: Schoolingand SocialMobilityin Scotlandand the United States. A review of path analysis is offered here, with Hope's model used as an example, the object being to suggest the limits of the method in analyzingcomplexphenomena. Argumentationcannot suffice for discoveryof any new work, since the subtlety of natureis greatermany times than the subtletyof argument. FrancisBacon Introduction The path model for education and social stratification proposed by Blau and Duncan (1967) was one of the first applications of that method in the social sciences, and certainly the most influential. It is often cited as a great success story: see, for example, Adams, Smelser, and Treiman (1982, p. 46). And it set the pattern for much subsequent research. Indeed, path models are now widely used in the social sciences, to disen- tangle complex cause-and-effectrelationships.Despite their popularity,I do not believe they have in fact created much new understanding of the I would like to thank PersiDiaconis, Otis Dudley Duncan, ArthurGoldberger, ErichLehmann,ThomasRothenberg,JulietShaffer,and Amos Tverskyfor many useful discussions-without implying their agreement (or disagreement)on the issues. Neil Henry was a wonderfulreferee. The quotationsfromKeithHope (1984), andFigure6, are reprintedwithpermission from As Others See Us: Schooling and Social Mobility in Scotland and the UnitedStates,copyright? 1984, CambridgeUniversityPress.The researchin this paper was partiallysupportedby NSF GrantDMS 86-01634. 101 D. A. Freedman phenomenathey are intendedto illuminate.On the whole, they maydivert attentionfrom the real issues, by purportingto do what cannotbe donegiven the limits on our knowledgeof the underlyingprocesses. One problemnoticeable to a statisticianis that investigatorsdo not pay attentionto the stochasticassumptionsbehindthe models. It does not seem possible to derive these assumptionsfrom current theory, nor are they easily validatedempiricallyon a case-by-casebasis. Also, the sheer technical complexityof the method tends to overwhelmcriticaljudgement. I have no magicalsolutionto offer as a replacement.On the other hand, repeatingwell-wornerrorsfor lack of anythingbetter to do can hardlybe the right course of action. If I am right, it is better to abandona faulty researchparadigmand go back to the drawingboards. Blau and Duncan(1967)mayseem like ancienthistory,so I will illustrate the argumentby referenceto Hope (1984). This is a comparativestudy of education and stratificationin Scotlandand the United States. Different chapters of the book take up different substantiveissues (which are all interesting);it seems fair to look only at the first chapter. I ask Hope's pardonfor usinghis workthis way, but it providesa convenientexampleof the path-analyticparadigmin action. At bottom, my critique is pretty simple-minded:Nobody pays much attentionto the assumptions,and the technologytends to overwhelmcommon sense. Since the point is such an elementaryone, the argumentshould start close to the beginning.After sayingin statisticallanguagewhat path models assumeand whatthey do, I will outline Hope's model, and point to the absenceof anythingconnectingit to reality-other thanthe conventions of the paradigmand his desire. Finally, some of the metamodelingliterature will be reviewed. A ResearchFable Latersectionswill reviewthe foundationsof regressionmodels in formal detail. This section presents an informalexample, to identify the issues. Statisticalmodels are often used to make causal inferences, for example, estimates of the impactof interventions:If we put a tariff of $10 a barrel on imported oil, how much will that affect the price level? the Gross National Product?If we spend another million dollars on schools, how much will that affect test scores? Other kinds of causal inferences, more relevantto the stratificationliterature, do not featuresuch explicitinterventions,but raisesimilarissues: How much of a salary difference between men and women is due to sex bias, and how much to differences in productivity?Where does ability count for more in getting high status jobs: Scotlandor the United States? In this section, I would like to present one highly stylized example, to focus the issues:How muchdoes educationaffectincome?Supposewe take a large random sample (so the distinctionbetween parametersand esti102 Case Studyin PathAnalysis mates can be slurredover), and observe in the data that log income has a linear regressionon education: log (income) = a + b x (education) + error. The errorsseem to have nearlyconstantvariance,and follow the normal curve quite nicely. We estimate a and b by ordinaryleast squares;b turns out to be .05, and the conclusion is that sending people to school for anotheryear will increase their incomes on averageby 5%. This conclusion,however,cannotrest on the way the data look, or even on replicationacrosstime or geography.It mustdependon a theoryof how the data came to be generated. (This is very well knownto workingsocial scientists,and I will sketchtheirargumentin a moment;the novelty, if any, is only in the formulation.) In effect, the theoryhas to be (or at least have as a consequence)that we are observingthe resultsof a controlledexperimentconductedby Nature. Subjectsare given some numberof yearsof schooling,and then the logs of their incomes are generatedas if by the followingtwo-stepprocedure: (i) compute a + b x (education); (ii) add noise. Forwantof a better term, I will referto this procedureas a linearstatistical law, connecting log income and education; and the whole thing can be calledthe as-if-by-experiment assumption.A slightlymoredramatictheory: We mightassumethatNaturehas randomlyassignedpeople to the different educationallevels-an as-if-randomizedassumption.(Then the log-linear functionalform can be estimatedfrom the data.) These sorts of theories seem to be implicitin the idea of "structural"or "causal"equations.Of course, it is impossibleto tell just from dataon the variablesin it whetheran equationis structuralor merelyan association.In the latter case, all we learn is that the conditionalexpectationof the response variableshowssome connectionto the explanatoryvariables,in the populationbeing sampled.The decisionas to whetheran equationis structural must ride either on prior theory or on close examinationof data outside the equation. Consideringthe impact of interventionsis a useful armchairexercise to perform in trying to reach the decision, or at least figuringout what it means. Comingbackto income andeducation,it maybe obviousby now thatthe equationis not structural,even if the datalook just like textbookregression pictures. There is a third variable, family background,which drives both educationand income. Ourcoefficientb in the equationpicksup the effect of the omitted variable,and is thereforea biased estimateof the impactof the proposedintervention-sending people backto school. Well, responds a strawmaninvestigator,here's a path model to take care of the problem: education = c + d x (family background) + error log (income) = e +f x (education) + g x (family background) + error. 103 D. A. Freedman This model consistsof two equations,assumedto be structural-as if the resultsof an experimentof nature. (These equationsare hardto interpret on the as-if-randomizedbasis, but they do makesense-right or wrong-as linear statisticallaws.) Anyway, says the strawman,now we've got it: f represents the impact of education on income, with family background controlledfor. Unfortunately,it is not so easy. How do we knowthatit is rightthis time? What about age, sex, or ability, just for starters?How do we know when the equations will reliably predict the result of interventions-without doingthe experiment?In a cartoonexample,the objectionis clear. In other cases, the point is easily lost in the shuffle. Sad experienceshows that all too often, the real modelers pay as little attention to justifying their assumptionsas the strawman,and their results are no more convincing. Of course, the methodologicalissues are extremelyperplexing,and any attemptto bringevidenceto bearon the substantiveissuesdeservesconsiderable sympathy.Duncan (1975) and Wright(1934) stressed the assumptions andthe limitationsof the technique.Simon(1954)presenteda sophisticated defense of our strawman;and see Zellner (1984, chapter1.4) for a critiqueof Simon. Many investigatorsseem to focus only on the statistical calculations.This essay can be viewed as an attemptto put the spotlight back on the assumptions. RegressionModels This sectionwill discussregressionmodelswhen the explanatoryvariable X is underexperimentalcontrol, and modificationsfor observationaldata. Some threats to validitywill be identified, and the first successfuluse of regressionmodels will be noted. To begin with, suppose that a variableX is underexperimentalcontrol, and it "causes"Y in the sense that Y = a + bX + U. (1) In this equation, U is a randomvariable-like a drawmade at randomfrom a box of tickets. Y is observable,but U is not. The stochasticassumptions are as follows: The distributionof U is the same, no matterwhat value of X is selected by the experimenter. (2.1) The expected value of U is 0. (2.2) The varianceof U is finite. (2.3) Each time the system is observed, an independent value of U is generated. (2.4) (The firstandlast of these are seriousrestrictions;the two middleones have a more technicalcharacter.) In this model, ordinary least squares (OLS) is a sensible way to estimate 104 Case Studyin PathAnalysis the parametersa and b. (Optimalityand robustnessare amongthe least of our worries here.) Furthermore,the coefficient b has a straightforward causal interpretation:It is the expected change in Y, if the experimenter intervenes and increasesX by one unit. Of course, many interestingvariablesare not under experimentalcontrol. On the other hand, given the experimentalmodel (1-2), it does not matter how the data on X are collected, providedthe distributionof U is not disturbed.(An exampleto motivatethe caveat:Selectingobservational units on the basis of their Y-valuescan lead to systematicerrors.) Considernext a model like (1-2), but for observationaldata. This is a major transition;from now on, I will be discussingonly studieswhere the investigatordoes not intervene to set the values of the explanatoryvariables. The firstpartof the model is a theoryaboutthe relationshipbetween X and Y, the two variablesof interest. This can be stated, a bit quaintly, as follows: Nature selects X accordingto some distribution,generates Y accordingto the experimentalmodel (1-2), and then presents the pair (X, Y) to the investigator,but hides U. This is a linear statisticallaw connecting Y and X. Much(but not all) of this can be formalizedstartingfroman equationlike (1), with a slightlydifferentinterpretation: Y = a + bX + U. (3) The equation says that the random variable Y depends linearly on the random variable X, with an unobservablerandom error or disturbance term U. The parametersof this linear statisticallaw are a, b, and the varianceof U. In this equation, X is random. The stochasticassumptionson U and X are parallelto the ones in the experimentalmodel, except that (2.4) is droppedfor now: The disturbanceterm U is independentof the explanatoryvariableX. (4.1) The disturbanceterm U has mean 0. (4.2) The disturbanceterm and the explanatoryvariable have finite variance. (4.3) The disturbanceterm U is often interpreted as "the effect of omitted variables."If so, interveningto changeX should not change U, and this is perhapsthe strongestformof the independencehypothesis(4.1). Also, the omitted variablesmust be assumedindependentof the includedvariables. (See Pratt & Shlaifer, 1984 for discussion.) Withpathmodels, one conventionis to standardizethe randomvariables X and Y in Equation (3) to have mean 0 and variance1. The parametera will then be 0. (This conventionwill be followed here for expositoryrea105 D. A. Freedman sons, and its logic will be reviewedlater.) To make the varianceof Y come out to 1, another conditionis needed: var U = 1 - b2. (4.4) So far, X and Y are somewhat platonic. The next part of the model introducesdata, an X-value and Y-valuefor each observationalunit;these unitswill be indexedby i. This partof the model is intendedto connectthe data with the assumedrelationship(3-4), and is the analog of (2.4). The data are modeled as observedvalues of pairsof randomvariables(Xi, 17), which are independentfrom unit to unit, and obey the assumptions(3-4). Technically,the conditionson the data are as follows: The triplets (Xi, Ui, Y) are independentacross units i. (5.1) For each i, the triplet (Xi, U1,Yi)is distributed like (X, U, Y) in (3-4). (5.2) The explanatoryvariable is Xi, the response variable is 1Y,and the disturbanceterm Ui is not observable. This samplingmodel is the basis for estimatingb fromthe databy OLS. (Of course, in the presentsetup it is the random variablesthat are standardized,not the data: Standardizingthe data is one step in estimatingthe parameters.Also, some investigators prefer to condition on the X-values; this hardlyaffects the present argument, but would complicate the exposition, which attempts to define a samplingmodel and give theoremsin terms of populationparameters.Be the conditioningas it may, in the presentsetup the X-values are not under the investigator'sexperimentalcontrol, and that is what matters.) To make the assumptionsmore vivid, imaginetwo boxes of tickets, an X-box and a U-box. In each box, the tickets have numberson them. The tickets in the X-box averageout to 0 with a varianceof 1 (the standardization). The tickets in the U-box averageout to zero with a varianceof 1 - b2. The data are generated as follows. For each observationalunit i, drawone ticketat random(withreplacement)fromthe X-box and another, independently,from the U-box. The firstticket shows the value of Xi, and the second, Ui. Now use Equation (3) to compute Y (Figure 1). This set of assumptionslies behindthe simplepath diagramin Figure2. The straightarrowleadingfromX to Y representsthe X-term in Equation (3); the coefficientis shownnear the arrow.The free arrowleadinginto Y representsthe disturbanceterm U. The assumptions(3-4-5) are not explicitin the diagram.These assumptions are relativelystrong, but somethingratherlike them seems necessary to justify the full range of operations made by path analysts. For some applications,especiallywith relativelysmallsamples,normalitywouldhave to be assumedtoo. (Of course, weaker assumptionscan be used to justify partialconclusionsin specific cases.) 106 Case Studyin PathAnalysis I X-box the I I the U-box Y = bX + Ui FIGURE 1. The observationalmodel The division of the model into two parts (i) the theoreticalrelationshipbetween X and Y, (ii) the connectionwith the data on the observationalunits is not standardbut can be helpful analytically.For example, (3-4) may hold, but if the data are collected on a stratifiedsample then (5) fails. Or the data could be for a simple randomsample so (5) holds, but the theoretical relationship(3-4) could be wrong. Also, the two parts of the model play differentroles. Part (i) underlies the causal interpretationof the parameterb, as the expected change in Y if we intervene and change X by one unit. The idea behind (i) is that changingX by interventionmakes no systematicimpacton U, becausethe two are independent. So the expected change in Y is just b times the proposed change in X. On the other hand, part (ii) enables us to learn b from the data by OLS. In particular,a causalinferencecan be made from observationaldatabut its validity depends on the validity of the assumptionson the relationshipbetweenX and Y for the interpretationof b, and the connection with the data for its estimationby OLS. Together,the conditionssay that FIGURE 2. A first path diagram Xb-- Y 107 D. A. Freedman the observationaldata on X and Y are generatedas if by experiment,with Nature setting the values of X by drawingthem at randomfrom a distribution, and then generatingthe Ys from the Xs througha linear statistical law. This set of conditionsis somewhatmore restrictivethan assuming,for example, that X and Y are jointly normal and (Xi, Y) are independent replicates of (X, Y); and is not fully capturedby (3-4-5). However, the as-if-by-experimentcondition seems to be the hallmarkof a structural equation or causalmodel, as opposed to a mere regressionequation. One useful way to think about this distinctionis to considerwhat the equation says about interventions. The technicalassumptionsin a path model involve the chancebehavior of the disturbanceterms Ui.These termsare in principlenot observable,so the assumptionsare difficultto verify directly.Nor is the chance behavior of an unobservablequantitya topic that fires the imagination.Perhapsas a result, it is hardto get path analyststo focus on the chance assumptions. On the other hand, these assumptionsdo have empiricalcontent-and should be tested before the model is taken seriously. What are the main threatsto the validityof the assumptions?Three will be mentioned now (cf. Tukey, 1954, p. 46): (i) measurementerror in X, (ii) nonlinearity, (iii) omitted variables. Problem(i) is often recognizedby workersin the field, and handledby "latentvariable"models of the type popularizedby Joreskogand Sorbom (1981) or Wold (1985); see Noonan and Wold (1983) for an example. However, the purportedsolution involves the introductionof yet another layerof assumptions,thatthere are repeatedmeasurementslinearlyrelated to the latent variables.In my view, this only begs the question, by moving the kind of difficultiesunderdiscussionhere to other (even less accessible) realms. See Freedman(1985) for a discussion. Problems(ii) and (iii) will be discusseda bit abstractlyin this section and the next, and illustratedon Hope's model. Takenonlinearityfirst. Instead of (1), suppose the generatingequationis Y = a + bX + cX2 + U. (6) An investigatorwho fits a linear model like (1) will get an error term uncorrelatedwith X, but dependenton it. Then, changingX must change the error in a systematicway, and the causal inferenceis invalid. For an extreme case, supposeX is uniformlydistributedon the interval [-1, 1], and Y = X2. Fitting (1) gives a = 1/3 and b = 0, suggestingthat a change in X will cause no changein Y. That is clearlywrong:The effect of X and Y is all in the nonlinearerror U = X2 - 1/3. In particular,the pathanalytic notion of "cause" is intimately bound up with linear statistical laws. 108 Case Studyin Path Analysis In this example, b can be interpretedas the averagechangein Y per unit change in X, that is, the average over X of dldxE{YIX =x}. On this interpretation,however,b dependson the distributionof X. And the whole "average change" idea breaks down if, for example, U = X3 - 3X/5 and Y = U so a = b = 0. The reason is that U takes different values when X = 1 and X = -1 (cf. Tukey, 1954, p. 42). Moving on to (iii), suppose the generatingequation is (1), but the expected value of U increases linearly with X. Then OLS will produce a biasedestimateof b. Put anotherway, causalinferencefailsbecausechanging X makes a systematicchange in U. One source of such dependenceis omitted variables-problem (iii). This problemtoo is well knownto workersin the field, andtheir solution is to expandthe systemby addingmorevariables.Thatis whatpathmodels are all about. In sum, if the mainvariablesin the systemcan be identified, and their causal ordering, and the form of the regressionfunctions, the models can be more or less easily adapted.But there is a major difficulty: Currentsocial science theory cannot deliverthat sort of specificationwith any degree of reliability,and currentstatisticaltheory needs this information to get started. Indeed, the methodof least squareswas developedby Gauss(1809/1963) for use in situationswhere measurementsare well defined, where functional forms are dictatedby strongtheory, and where predictionsare routinely tested against observations.The story is worth retelling:Astronomersdiscoveredthe asteroidCereswhile makingtelescopicsweeps, but lost it when it got too close to the Sun. FindingCeresbecameone of the major scientificproblemsof the day. To solve this problem,Gaussderivedthe equationsconnectingthe observations on Ceres to the parametersof the orbit, usingNewtonianmechanics. He then linearizedthe equationsof motion and estimatedthe parameters by least squares, making careful estimates of the errors due to the linearizationand due to randomvariationin the data. Finally, he used the equationsto predictthe currentposition of Ceres-a predictionborne out by astronomicalobservation. In this example, Gaussstartedfromwell-establishedtheorythatspecified the relevantvariablesand the functionalform of their relationship.Much carefulwork had alreadybeen done on the errorstructureof the astronomical measurements.Finally, the model was tested againstreality. These characteristicsdifferentiatethe originalapplicationof least squaresfrom the applicationin path models. In situationswhere theory and measurement are less well developed, simpler and more informalstatisticaltechniques might be preferable. Path Models This section will develop path models, as linked sets of structural equations, with the response variable from one equation being an explanatory 109 D. A. Freedman variablein a second. The assumptionswill be highlighted,and the possibilityof testingdiscussed;threatsto validitywill be discussed.The development is parallelto the one in the previoussection, and it is convenientto use the example of X and Y in Equation (1). Suppose that there are two additionalvariablesin the system, Z and W. Supposethat together, Z and W cause X; then, Z and X cause Y; and the causationis throughlinear statisticallaws. This theory about the relationshipsof the variablescan be expressedin a path diagram(Figure3). The straightarrowleading from, for example, Z to X indicatesthat Z appearsin the equationexplainingX; the free arrowleadinginto X stands for the disturbanceterm in that equation. The path diagram,then, represents two linear statisticallaws: X = aZ + bW + U (7.1) Y = cX + dZ + V. (7.2) The randomvariablesZ and W are "exogenous":They are viewed as causingthe other variablesin the model, but are not themselvesexplained. This is signaledby the curved, double-headedarrowin the diagram;next to the arrowis the correlationbetween these two variables.The variables X and Y are "endogenous"-explained within the model. The randomvariables U and V in (7) are disturbanceterms. Equation (7.1) relatesX to the exogenousvariables;then (7.2) relates Y to X andthe exogenous variables. As is usually said, the system is "recursive"rather than "simultaneous."(For more carefuldefinitions,see the next section.) Informally,Natureselects (Z, W) fromsome distribution,and generates some noise (U, V). The she or he computesX and Y from (7) and shows (Z, W,X, & Y) to the investigator. The disturbancesU and V remain hidden. The parametersa, b, c, d in (7) are called "path coefficients"and are usuallyunknown.The following are the stochasticassumptions: FIGURE 3. A path diagram -7 d zw ra c 110 1- Case Studyin PathAnalysis the W-box thc Z-box Xi = aZ "Yi = cX + bWi the U-box the, V-box + -t- dZi - V FIGURE 4. Box modelfor path diagram The disturbanceterms U and V are independentof each other and the exogenous variables(Z, W). (8.1) The disturbanceterms U and V have mean 0. (8.2) The disturbanceterms and exogenous variableshave finite variance. (8.3) Z, W, X, and Y are all standardizedto have mean 0 and variance1. (8.4) Now for the connection between the theory and the data. There are n observationalunits, indexedby i; for each unit, there are measurementson the four variablesZ, W, X, and Y. These data are modeled as observed values of randomvariablesZi, W, X;, and Yj,which are independentfrom unit to unit and obey the theory expressedin (7) and (8): The six-tuplets(Zi, W, U1, Vi,X1, Y) are independentacrossunits i. (9.1) For each i, the six-tuplet(Z,, W,, U1, V, X;, Y) is distributedlike (Z, W, U, V, X, Y) in (7-8). (9.2) These assumptionsare shown schematicallyin Figure4. For a moment, come back to the omitted-variablesproblem.If (7-8) are right,then a regressionof Y on X alone gives a biasedestimateof the effect of X, because the regressioncoefficient picks up part of the effect of the omitted variableZ. Specifyingthe right path model fixes this problem. By virtue of assumption(9), the full system can be estimated by OLS. And the parametersof the linear statistical laws do have causal interpretations,as in the previoussection. For example, suppose we intervene by keeping W and Z fixed but increasingX by one unit: On average,this will cause Y to increase by c units-because the disturbanceV in Y is unrelatedto Z, W, or X, so the interventionhas no systematicimpacton 111 D. A. Freedman V. (The usual interpretationof the coefficients does present some difficulties, to be discussedbelow in the section on directand indirecteffects.) Again, a causal inferencehas been made from observationaldata. This is, I think, the most attractivefeature of the methodology. However, its validitydepends on the assumptionthat the variablesare related through linear statisticallaws-and the path analyst got the variablesand arrows right. These assumptionsare embodied in the path diagramand equations (7-8-9). They are inputsto the statisticalanalysisratherthan outputs.All the statisticalanalysis can do (and it is no mean feat) is to estimate the correlationsand path coefficients, or test that particularcoefficients are zero-given the assumptions.Standardtheory does not offer any strong tests of those assumptions;and the existingones (plottingresiduals,crossvalidation,examiningsubgroups)are seldom done by path analysts. The point maybe a bit obscuredby the somewhattechnicalwaythe term causal inferenceis being used. To restate matters:A theory of causalityis assumed in the path diagram(the causal ordering,linear statisticallaws, etc.). Within this context, what the path analysis does is to provide a quantitativeestimateof the impactof interventions.The path analysisdoes not derive the causal theory from the data, or test any major part of it againstthe data. Assumingthe wrong causaltheory vitiates the statistical calculations. The FundamentalTheorem One object of path analysisis to decomposecorrelationcoefficientsinto additivecomponents.Considerfor now a generalpath diagram.The variables are still standardized,and the analogs of (7-8) are in force. The "fundamentaltheorem" is an identity among correlationcoefficientsand path coefficients. First, some terminology and the assumptions.Say a variableX is a "proximatecause" of Y if there is a straightarrowleadingfromX to Y in the path diagram(i.e., X appearsin the regressionequationexplainingY). By definition,an "exogenous"variablehas no proximatecausewhereasan "endogenous"variablehas at least one proximatecause. (In this paper, I am takingthe exogenousvariablesto be random,and will state the fundamental theorem and related decompositionsat the level of population parameters,ratherthan sample estimates.) There is a curved arrowjoining every pair of exogenous variables,and one free arrowleading into each endogenousvariable.But no free arrows lead into exogenousvariables,or curvedarrowsinto endogenousvariables. Say X is a "remote cause" of Y if there is a sequence of straightarrows leading from X to Y in the diagram. Assume that the path diagramis recursive,in the followingsense: No variablecan be a cause of itself, proximateor remote. 112 (10) Case Studyin PathAnalysis li~ z W- xaX >?-- Y j7 Z< T Y FIGURE 5. Violatingthe conditions.In the left diagramX causesY and Y causes X. At the right,X is a remotecause of itself. In particular,X may be a remote cause of Y, or Y a remote cause of X, or neither-but not both. Figure5 showstwo diagramsthat violate the conditions. (The left hand diagramin Figure 5 provides an example of "simultaneity":X and Y are obtainedfrom Z and W by solvingthe pairof simultaneous linear equations: X = aZ +bY + U Y = cW + dX + V. Such systemsare commonin econometricwork, but less commonin other social science fields. The new difficultyis that the righthandside variables become correlated with the errors, so OLS must be replaced by more complex estimationprocedures.) The "fundamentaltheorem"(Duncan, 1975,pp. 36ff or Wright,1921)is the following: Suppose Y is endogenous and not a cause of X, proximateor remote. Then (11) rxy = prxz, z zP where pyz is the path coefficient from Z to Y, rxyis the correlationcoefficient between X and Y, and the sum is over all Z that are proximatecauses of Y. Technically,the set of exogenousvariablesis assumedindependentof the disturbanceterms, which are independentamong themselves, as in (8.1). 113 D. A. Freedman It follows that an endogenousvariableis independentof all the disturbance terms-except those among its causes. The identity (11) can be applied recursively,to expressany correlationin termsof the path coefficientsand the correlationsamong the exogenous variables. This leads to the deep "path tracingrule" of Wright(1921). Direct and IndirectEffects One object of path analysisis to measure the "direct"and "indirect" effects of one variableon another.Take, for example, the path diagramin Figure 3. Successiveapplicationsof (11) show rzy= d + ac + rzwbc. Associated with this identity is some terminology: rzy is called the "total effect of Z on Y," d is the "directeffect of Z on Y," ac + rzwbcis the "indirecteffect of Z on Y," and ac is the "effect of Z on Y throughX. " The relationshipbetween the terminology and the diagram is pretty clear, but the connectionto causal inferencemore problematic.Take the last effect first: We interveneby holding W fixed but increasingZ by one unit; this increasesX by a units, which in turn makes Y go up ac units. So far, so good. Now try the directeffect of Z on Y: We interveneby fixing W andX but increasingZ by one unit; this should increase Y by d units. However,this hypotheticalinterventionis self-contradictory,because fixing W and increasingZ causes an increasein X. Or is the disturbanceterm U in (7.1) supposedto come down?How does that squarewith independence?Or the idea that U represents"omittedvariables?" This may seem like a pointless tease about semantics, but given the researcheffort spent in composingand decomposingcorrelations,surely some attention to interpretationis called for. The only possibilityfor d seems to be the rate of changeof E (Y IX, Z) with respectto Z, and calling this a "directeffect" is ratherstrange. My view, stated in detail earlier, is that a path model representsthe analysisof observationaldata as if it were the resultof an experiment.At points such as this, it would be helpful to know more about the structure of such hypotheticalexperiments:What is to be held constant, and what manipulated? Standardizingthe Variables Should path models be given in termsof variablesin their naturalscale, or shouldthey be standardized?The questionis hardlya new one-see, for example, Achen (1982, p. 76), Blalock (1964, p. 51), Tukey(1954, p. 41), or Wright (1960). Apparently, standardizing only matters when comparing 114 Case Studyin PathAnalysis path coefficients estimated from different populations, that is, different distributionsfor the exogenousvariables.And the answerdependson what is consideredto be invariantacrosspopulations-that is, on the formof the social law assumedto governthe data. In other words,there is an empirical issue. To focus ideas, considerthe simpleregressionmodel of Equation(1). Let X and Y denote the variablesin theirnaturalscale (dollars,yearsof schooling completed, etc.); let X and f denote the standardizedvariables.There are two versionsof the equation, raw and standardized: Y = a + bX + U (1) f = 6X+ . (1) Supposefirstthat equation(1) expressesa sociallaw, with parametersa, b, andvar U, whichare invariantacrosspopulations(X-distributions).Now the path coefficient 6 depends on the scale of X: 6 = b VvarX/[b2 varX + var U]. Twoinvestigatorswho workwith differentpopulationsandstandardizewill get differentpath coefficients-and miss the invarianceof a and b. This is not a good researchstrategy. On the other hand, the law governingthe data could be in terms of standardunits-Equation (i). That is, 6 could be invariantacross populations. Then fitting(1) in "natural"unitswill miss the invariance,because a and b vary across populations. Of course, the situation could be more complicatedthan (1) or (i). Even if (1) is the rightchoice, the standarddeviationsof the disturbance terms in more complex models need not be invariantacrosspopulations. Consider, for example, the path model in Figure3. Suppose that the law (7-8) underlyingthe social processis in standardunits, so the variablesZ, W, X, and Y should be standardized.And the path coefficients will be stable across populations(joint distributionsfor Z and W). But the standard deviations of the disturbanceterms U and V depend on the path coefficientsand rzw,so these standarddeviationswill change from population to population, because rzwdepends on the joint distributionof the exogenous variables. The point can be illustratedon var U in (7.1): 1 = varX = a2 var Z + b2 var W + var U + 2ab cov (Z, W) + 2a cov (Z, U) + 2b cov (W, U) = a2 + b2 + var U + 2ab rzw. The first line holds by the standardization.For the same reason, in the second line, var Z = var W = 1 and cov (Z, W) = rzw. The other two covar115 D. A. Freedman iances in line 2 vanishby (8.1). Now the equationcan be solved for var U: var U = 1 - a2 - b2- 2abrzw. Thus, the unexplainedvariationdependson the populationbeing studied. Hope's Model In this section, I will describeHope's model, andthen reviewit underthe headings proposed earlier, stressingthe weakness of the connection between the model andthe underlyingsocialprocess.One of Hope's technical innovations is the "autonomycoefficient," which may be viewed as an attempt to deal with certain kinds of measurementerror. It will be discussed too. Along the way, I will try to give the flavorof the conclusions drawnfrom the model. First,some backgroundfor the model. Sincethe publicationof the Coleman et al. report(1966), there has been an extendeddebateconcerningthe impact of schools on the educational attainmentsof students, and the achievementsafterward.Jencks et al. (1972) is often cited in this connection. Chapter 1 of Hope (1984) is a contributionto this literature.It addressesthe followingsorts of questions:Do schools matter?Does education have more of an impact in Scotland or in the United States? Of course, to answerthese questions,the termshave to be defined, and backgroundvariablescontrolled. Hope measures outcomes in terms of the occupationsof his subjects. Only secondary education is considered. The backgroundvariables are two: IQ andfather'soccupation.The Americandataare drawnfromJencks and will not be discussedhere. For Scotland,Hope measuresoccupations on a 9-pointscale, rangingfrom "professionalsand largeemployers"at the top to "agriculturalworkers"at the bottom (1984, p. 17). For the path model, occupationswere rankedaccordingto "socialstanding"by 12 college students, and the principalcomponentof the 12 rankingswas used as the occupationvariable(p. 18). Secondaryeducationin Scotlandwas on a tracksystem, and Hope measures this variableon a 7-point scale, accordingto the track taken by the subjects (1984, p. 14). The top track "completedfive years of secondary education in a general course with two foreign languages."The bottom track"threeyears of secondaryeducationin a modifiedclass (for less able and backwardchildrenin an ordinaryschool)." The data are from the "ScottishMentalSurvey."The samplewas drawn in 1947, and consists of all 11-year-oldboys born on the first day of every other month. The childrenwere followeduntil 1964,and data are available on nearly600 of them, includinganthropometry,scores on FormL of the Stanford-BinetIQ test, and a "sociologicalschedule"that includedfather's occupation.Sample attritionwas less than 10%. Hope proposes a path model for his four variables;it is shownin Figure 6, with coefficientsestimatedfrom the Americanand Scottishdata. There 116 Case Studyin PathAnalysis are two structuralequations: education= a x IQ + b x (father'soccupation)+ error (12.1) occupation= c x (education)+ d x IQ + e x (father'soccupation) + error. (12.2) (In these equations,of course,IQ, education,andoccupationare attributes of the sons.) This model will now be reviewedunderthe headingsproposed earlier, startingwith measurementissues. The difficultiesin measuringintelligenceand successin life are only too well known. But what about education?For one thing, the school variable in the United States is quite different from the one in Scotland (years completed ratherthan track). And this kind of differencecan have a substantial impact on the path coefficients. (A similarissue is noted in the section on standardization,above.) Moreover, the school variablein Scotlandincludes not only characteristics of the schools, but also characteristicsof the students. For example, the difference between tracks 1 and 3 lies in whether the students completed the course: This is a measureof students'ability and character,as well as of the educationreceived. The path analysisis being used to separate the inputs to the school from outputs, but the two are alreadyentangled in the school variable-before the path analysiscan do anything. This point has been questioned by some readers. To make the issue clearer, suppose the measuredschool variableis just anotherIQ scorelike form M instead of form L. None of the analysiswould then have anythingto do with education.Fora second examplein a similarvein, suppose the path model in Figure 6 is right-for some variable that represents FIGURE 6. Hope'spath model IQ .466 .- \758654 Education IQ o. \55 Education .300 .357 Father's occupation United 147 - Occupation 35 States Father's occupation .172 - Occupation /22 Scotland Source:Hope (1984,pp. 26-27). 117 D. A. Freedman educationalquality.In this second hypotheticalworld, the path fromIQ to educationrepresentsthe fact thatbrighterstudentschoose betterschooling, on average.Supposetoo that the measuredschool variableis a linearcombinationof IQ and the underlyingeducationalqualityvariable.In this second hypothetical,the estimatedpath coefficientsare substantiallybiased; and the bias dependson the unknownerrorstructurein the measurements. One of Hope's technicalinnovationsmightbe viewedas an attemptto get around the second sort of measurementproblem. He decomposes the directeffect of educationon occupationinto an "autonomous"and a "heteronomous"component(1984, pp. 9, 24ff). To define these terms, assume the relationshipspart of the model in Figure6, that is, the analogof (7-8). Let E and O be the endogenousvariables,educationand occupation;let the exogenous variablesbe I and F, IQ and father'soccupation. Hope's decompositioncan be expressed as an equation: rEF. POE= POEV + POEPEJ rEI+ POEPEF (13) The first term on the right is the "autonomouseffect" of education on occupation;v is the varianceof the disturbancetermin the equationfor E. To understandthis termgeometrically,let L and 6 be the projectionsof E and O on the spacespannedby I and F; let E = E - Land 0- = O - 0, so E' and O are the projectionson the orthocomplement.In otherwords, E' and 0' represent education and occupation, net of IQ and father's occupation:"net" means, after subtractingout the projections.The "autonomous effect" of educationon occupation,that is, the firsttermon the rightof (13), turnsout to be the covarianceof 0' and E'. Since E' is not standardized,the covarianceis not a regression coefficient; apparently, division by v = varE' just gives you backPOE,as is also clear from (13). (The remainingtwo termsin the equationseem to be part of the "heteronomous effect"; however, I see no direct geometric interpretationfor them, nor do Hope's verbaldescriptionsin his table 1.6 make much sense to me, let alone the identificationof these termswith the "universalistic" and "particularistic"in education.) In principle,it is harmlessto compute a covariance.But what is Hope's interpretation? Theaimof theresearchis ... to quantifytheeffectsof educationoverand aboveanyeffectswhichit transmitsfrominputvariables[I andF]. To accomplishthat aim, we must ask ourselvesa very simplequestion: Towhatextentis educationactingas a transmitter and (heteronomously) to whatextentis it contributing itsownautonomous effect,overandabove the transmitted effects,to the processof stratification? (1984,p. 9) There is at least one peculiarityin this interpretation:Supposethe path model in Figure 6 is right. If we intervene by holding IQ and father's occupationfixed but increase education, then it is POE that measuresthe changein the subject'soccupation,not the "autonomouseffect." Similarly, if the measured school variable is a linear combination of IQ and the 118 Case Studyin PathAnalysis underlyingeducationalqualityvariable,the autonomycoefficientis quite a biased estimate of the path coefficient for educationalquality. On the other hand, if the measuredschool variableis just anotherIQ score, the autonomycoefficientmay say somethingabout the relationshipof IQ tests to occupationalachievement-but nothingaboutschools,becausethese are absent from the model. Statisticalcomputationsare no substitute for a proper specification. Hope cites Finney (1972) in defense of the autonomy coefficient, but Finney'smessage is more that the "indirecteffect" of an exogenous variable on an endogenousone includesthe correlationsamongthe exogenous variables,and is thereforenoncausal;also, this indirecteffect depends on the population, that is, the joint distributionof the exogenous variables, and so is not comparableacrosspopulations(cf. previoussectionson direct effects and standardization).Finney's second criticismapplies directlyto Hope's autonomycoefficient. Now let me quote Hope (1984) again: The basicidea [of the autonomycoefficient]can be quiteadequately represented by the followingsimpleanalogy.If we thinkof thepathsin a pathmodelas pipesalongwhichwaterflows,andif we imagineone pipe A andB, andanotherconnecting B andC, thenwe naturally connecting wonderwhethertheflowbetweenB andC is entirelyaccounted forbythe flowbetweenA andB, or whethermorewatercomesintothe systemat B. Suchincomingwatermodelsourideaof the autonomous effectof B of the analogy,standsfor education.(p. 8) which,in ourapplication This analogy does not really serve to differentiateamong disturbance terms, direct effects, or autonomy coefficients. Indeed, since correlation and regressioncoefficientsdescribechangesratherthanlevels, the passage seems to be a confusion:The statisticalconstructsin the path model relate less to the flow of water than to variationsin the flow-ripples. This completes the discussionof measurementissues and the autonomy coefficient. Now we come to the stochasticassumptions.Why do the variables satisfya linearstatisticallaw? Nowheredoes Hope ask this question. With a 7-point scale for education, linearityis hardto take seriously;and Hope himself points to noticeable skewness in the IQ data. Also, the impact of the fast track may be larger on the brighterstudents. Heteroscedasticityis another problem: American data suggest that varianceof intelligenceand schoolingdepend on occupationallevel (see, e.g., Crouse & Olneck, 1979). Omitted variables must be considered too. Is the process of social stratificationthe same in the Highlandsas in the cities?Geographydoes not appearin the model. Are schoolsin Edinburghsimilarto those in Glasgow? Schools per se do not appear in the model, except through the tracks variable. To have schools omitted is peculiarlyironic in a study of their effects, especially when the author thinks (as Hope does, see pp. 19-20) 119 D. A. Freedman that it is the individualcharacteristicsof differentschools that make for strong educationaleffects. Given such problems,what connectsthe model to reality?What makes Hope think the assumptionshold? I could only find a few sentences responsive to these questions, and quote them in full (1984, pp. 14-15): The theoreticalmodel thatinformsour analysisof the effectsof education wasimplicitin the designof the ScottishMentalSurvey on stratification that,forboys,thesignificant (Hope,1980).It postulates inputstheybring to the social system are cleverness,character,and class. Since we lack comparativedata on character,we omit that variablefrom the current model (it was includedin the model in Hope, 1980). At best, this passage justifies includingIQ and father's occupationin (12). It does not justifythe linearityor the stochasticassumptions.Nor does it justify treating the equations in (12) as structural,rather than mere associations;on the contrary,it flags anotherimportantmissingvariable. And so in the end Hope does not connect Figure6 with real boys who go to school, graduate, and get jobs. Neither does the cited article (Hope, 1980), which presents a path model rather like Figure 6, but including variableslabeled "personality"and "qualifications."In that article, there is much ingenuitydevoted to the geometryof factoranalysis-and none to elucidatingthe relationshipbetween the geometryand the boys. Hope is not alone in these respects. Indeed, I do not think there is any reliablemethodologyin place for identifyingthe crucialvariablesin social systems or discoveringthe functionalform of their relationships.In such circumstances,fittingpath models is a peculiarresearchactivity:The computercan pass some planesthroughthe data, but cannotbindthe arithmetic to the world outside. At suchpoints as this, modelerswill often explainthat nothingis perfect, all models are approximations,so maybe Hope's model is good enough: How much difference can the blemishes make? In this particularcase, blemishescould really matter, because the differencesin path coefficients between Scotlandand the U.S. are small (the largestis for the directeffect of IQ on education). And substantialconclusionsare drawnfrom these differences: Whatwe haveshownis thatScotland...is moremerit[ocratic] thanthe UnitedStates.Takingtransmission of IQasuniversalistic andtransmission of father'soccupationas particularistic, we may say that the ratioof universalismto particularismin education... is 2 to 1 in the United States andmorethan4 to 1 in Scotland.Theoveralldirecteffectof education on occupationis about .47 in both. Withinthis total, the ratioof autonomous effect: universalism:particularismis 57 : 27: 15 in the United States, as against43:47:10 in Scotland. We conclude, therefore, that data which have previouslybeen held to manifestnegligibleautonomouseffects of schools (in the United States) in fact ascribea strongereffect to schools 120 Case Study in Path Analysis than they do to the characteristicsof students entering those schools. (Hope, 1984, p. 30) This sort of finding has to be really sensitive to the rather arbitrary specification. To illustrate the sensitivity: Adding "personality" and "qualifications" to the model, as in Hope (1980), makes the direct effect of education on occupation drop from .47 to .23. (This is rather close to the autonomy coefficient, but I do not see much logical connection between adding those two variables and projecting out the two exogenous variables.) The differences in path coefficients between Scotland and the United States may be largely due to the scaling, or the differential impact of omitted variables and measurement error. In any case, the central issue is what connects the path model and the process by which boys get jobs; this connection is simply not established. Assumptions matter, and with path models it is too easy to lose track of this. Modelers may then explain that they are only doing data reduction. Let us agree for the moment that Hope's data look more or less like a sample from the multivariate gaussian distribution, and that standardization is appropriate. (Otherwise, his analysis goes off the rails almost immediately.) Now the data for each country can be summarized by a table of six correlation coefficients. However, the path model has six parameters too, and Hope's table 1.6 analyzes these into a dozen components. Data reduction is not the game here. Other readers may feel that nobody could be taking the models so seriously; after all, a model is just some way of looking at the data. Well, here is Hope's view: We begin our study by askingwhetherScotlandwas indeed the meritocracy it is often alleged to have been. In the course of answeringthis questionwe will refine the definitionof meritocracyto the point whereits presence or absence, or ratherthe degree to which it is present, can be assessedin precise, quantitativeterms. Of course, no such quantification can be final or irrevocable;nevertheless,it has distinctadvantagesover imprecise and impressionisticstatements. In the first place, it gives us some idea of an orderof magnitudewe did not possess before. Second it enablesus to comparedegreesof magnitudein differentsocieties. And in the thirdplace it is disputableon empiricalgroundsand corrigibleaccording to rationalcriteriaof evidence and rebuttal.But the reallysignificant effect of quantificationis, or oughtto be, none of these. Ratherdoes it lie in the effort at refiningand exploringthe meaningof analyticalconcepts whichemploymentof a model callsfor. ... But in so constrainingthemwe will make every effort to see to it that meaningis not warpedbeyondthe bounds of normalusage, but ratheris tightenedup in a way which will commandgeneral approval.(1984, p. 6) Hope is doing something much more ambitious than data analysis. But his statistical technique has led him astray, and he almost knows it: 121 D. A. Freedman to thereaderthatthefollowingworkis notmodest It willbecomeapparent arebuilt in its aims.Andto thosewhoobservethatextensiveconclusions onfairlyexiguousfoundations, theauthorcanonlyreplythatthisis indeed the case. (1984,p. 3) Hope's startingpoint may have been that a son's intelligence and his father'soccupationjointlyinfluencethe boy'seducation,and then all three factors influence the boy's choice of occupation-influence but do not determine.Look back at Figure6. FixingIQ, fathers'occupationalstatus, and educationstill leaves about 70% of the variationin sons' occupational status, both in the U.S. and in Scotland-in good agreementwith Blau and Duncan (1967, p. 170). These seem to me to be quite interestingfacts, not muchaffectedby the difficulties in path modeling under discussion. Scotland may be more meritocraticthan the U.S., but on the evidenceof Figure6 neithercountry is exactlycaste-ridden;roughinsightswhose value is considerable.(Something like this is at the core of Blau & Duncan, 1967.) There are now some interestingquestions, and to answerthem, Hope takes for granted that his measurementson the variablesare connected through linear statistical laws. He can hardly be blamed for doing so, because nearly everyonedoes the same; but it is preciselythe move from rough insightto full-blownpath model that seems so counterproductiveto me. The path model mightbe usefulto predictthe resultsof interventions,or of changing circumstances,or to provide a better understandingof the stratificationprocess. But this sort of interpretationmustride on a theory, because somethingis needed to connect the statisticalcalculationsto the process. As far as I can see, this theory is exactlywhat is missing. Meta-Arguments For a historical discussion of path models in sociology, see Bernert (1983). These models were developedby Wright(e.g., 1921, 1934)for use in genetics. But later applicationseven in that field remaincontroversial: see Karlin(1979), or Karlin,Cameron,and Chakraborty(1983), with discussionby Wrightet al. Tukey(1954, pp. 60-66) found the method attractive, but had doubts about the one specific example he presented. Manyinvestigatorshave writtenabout the problemof drawingcausalinferencesfromobservationaldata. Some have stressedthe as-if-randomized assumption:for example, see Holland (1986) or Prattand Shlaifer(1984). Others have focused on the weaknesses of causal models: see Baumrind (1983), Cliff (1983), de Leeuw (1985), and Ling's(1983) scathingreviewof Kenny (1979). Lieberson (1985) is quite skepticalabout the possibilityof makingstatisticaladjustmentsthat bringobservationaldata into the as-ifrandomizedcondition. Econometricsis an interestingtest case for the modelingapproach,because the technique is extremely sophisticated,and commercialservices 122 Case Studyin PathAnalysis usingmacro-modelsmakerealforecastswhose accuracycanbe tracked:see Christ (1975), Litterman (1986), McNees (1979, 1986), and Zarnowitz (1979). Basically,the majorforecastingmodels do not do at all well unless their equationsare revisedfrequently,and the interceptsreestimatedsubjectively by the modelers. Even then, such modelinggroupsdo no better than the forecasterswho proceed without models. Finally, the different modeling groups tend to make quite similar forecasts; but their models often disagreesharplyabout the projectedimpactof policy actions. There are prominentcritiquesof standardeconometricsand the underlying data by insiders, startingwith the classic exchangebetween Keynes (1939, 1940)andTinbergen(1940). More recentcitationsare Hausmanand Wise (1985), Hendry (1980), Leamer (1983), Leontief (1971), Lucas and Sargent (1979), Morgenstern(1963), and Sims (1980). In some cases, of course, the proposed cure may be worse than the disease. My own views have been arguedin Daggett and Freedman(1985), and Freedman(1985), with discussionby JoreskogandFienberg;in the context of energy models, see Freedman(1981), or Freedman,Rothenberg,and Sutch(1983), with discussionby Hogan and Smith;in the context of census adjustment,see Freedmanand Navidi (1986), with discussionby Kadane et al. One line of defense againstfoundationalattackis Bayesian, as in Sims (1982). The disturbanceterms are held to representnot omitted variables but a componentof subjectiveuncertainty;anothercomponentof subjective uncertaintyis expressedby a prioron the parametersof the model. The functionalformof the modelis commonground,on whichall suchBayesian econometriciansmeet. Given the great diversityof functionalformsin the econometricliterature,andtheirtransience,his argumentdoes not seem to reach an important question: What is the relevance of textbook linear models to the economy? Another interestingline of defense is sketched by Achen (1982), who saysthatwe can use datato learnaboutsocialprocess.He provesthe point, drawingon Veblen (1975) to make a charmingand primafacie persuasive argumentthat the ManchesterUnion-Leaderinfluencedelections in New Hampshire.A major tool is regressionequations. He and Veblen think througha variety of qualitativepositions about the political process, and their implicationsfor the regressions.Then they look at the data, and only one position survives the test. But as Achen notes (p. 29), there is no pretenseof developinga structuralmodel;the equationsare purelydescriptive. In some circumstances,regressionequations are useful ways to look at data; the coefficients and the standarddeviation around the regression plane can be good summarystatistics.Thisis so, at least when the datalook somethinglike a sample from a multivariategaussiandistribution.Achen and Veblen have one success story along these lines. So did Blau and Duncan (1967). And so does Hope, as noted above. But there is a real 123 D. A. Freedman differencebetween summarizingdata and buildingpath models. To take a simplerexample, you can reporta battingaveragewithoutadoptingcountably additiveprobabilitytheory and the stronglaw of large numbers. The critiqueof path models in this paperis hardlyoriginal.A few words more about some of the conventionalresponsesmay be in order. Models are often held to be of valuein offeringguidelinesto decisionmakersrather than descriptionsor forecastsof behavior.The test often proposedfor such models is whether decisionmakersfind them useful. (The argument is strongestfor normativemodels, but is often madefor descriptivemodelsas well.) In the present context, this argumentseems circular. Decisionmakersmay like path analysis because the models appear to provide answersto importantquestions,but it is the use of the models by academicinvestigatorsthat makes the process respectable.(For example, there are plenty of chartistson Wall Street, but their technique is not prominentin our literature.)The real issue is old-fashioned:Why are the answersfrom the path model at all dependable?In the end, we still need to verify the model's assumptions,by some combinationof theory and practice, before recommendingits conclusionsto the decisionmaker. We arrive, then, at the descriptiveaspect. Here, two points are often made: (i) Valid inferencescan be drawnfrom axioms known to be false. (ii) No model is perfect;what counts is that the model shouldbe better than the next-best alternative. Both points are quite weak. In the present context, the first is almost irrelevant,because the conclusionsof path models are so close to their assumptions.More generally,argument(i) can only shift the burdenfrom the assumptionsto the conclusions.After all, if the modelerdoesn'tbelieve those assumptions,they can hardlybe partof his or her reasonfor believing the conclusions. Even in the best of theories,individualaxiomsmaynot be testable,so the modelerhas to considerseveralaxiomsin combinationand derivetestable implicationsfrom the set: compareBlalock (1969, chapter2). So there is a grainof truthto argument(i). However,the street versionalmostrelies on a parody:If A then B, and A is false, thereforeB. The anti-syllogismcan be tracedback to Friedman(1953), but that time he had to be kiddingus. Argument (ii) has some merit in some situations, but its relevance to statisticalmodelingin the social sciences is slight. The reason is that there is a wide range of imperfectionin human knowledge, and it is not so obviouswhere to locate path modelsin that spectrum.The resultsof a path analysisdepend for their validityon some underlyingcausaltheory. If the theory is rejected, the interpretationshave no foundation. Why, then, should they be held to dominatealternatives?And other modes of enquiry do exist: De Tocquevillewas makingcomparativestudiesof the new world and the old long before path models arrivedon the scene. 124 Case Study in Path Analysis Conclusion Thiskindof negativearticlemayseem incomplete.Pathanalystswill ask, not unreasonably,"Well,whatwould you do?" To this question, I have no general answer, any more than I can say in generalhow to do good mathematicalresearch.Still, socialscienceis possible, andneeds a strongempirical component.Even statisticaltechniquemayproveuseful-from time to time. There are some such techniqueson the horizon,whichdo not dependon prior specificationthe way path models do: see Asimov (1985), Breiman, Friedman,Olshen, and Stone (1984), Fisherkeller,Friedman,and Tukey (1975), Huber (1985), or McDonald(1984). It remainsto be seen whether these innovationscan be used to make improvementsover path analysis. They do offer better data-analyticcapabilities.Log linear models should also be mentioned (and their problemsnoted). My opinionis that investigatorsneed to thinkmore aboutthe underlying social processes, and look more closely at the data, withoutthe distorting prismof conventional(and largelyirrelevant)stochasticmodels. Estimating nonexistentparameterscannotbe very fruitful.And it must be equally a waste of time to test theorieson the basisof statisticalhypothesesthat are rooted neitherin priortheorynor in fact, even if the algorithmsare recited in every statisticstext without caveat. References Achen, C. (1982). Interpreting and using regression. Beverly Hills, CA: Sage. Adams, R., Smelser, N., & Treiman, D. (1982). Behavior and social science re- search:A nationalresource.Washington,DC: National Academy of Sciences Press. Asimov, D. (1985). The grand tour. SIAM Journal of Scientific and Statistical Computing, 6, 128-143. Baumrind,D. (1983). Speciouscausalattributionin the social sciences:The reformulatedstepping-stonetheoryof heroinuse as exemplar.Journalof Personality and Social Psychology, 45, 1289-1298. Bernert,C. (1983). The careerof causalanalysisin Americansociology. TheBritish Journal of Sociology, 34, 230-254. Blalock, H. M. (1964). Causal inferences in non-experimental research. Chapel Hill: Universityof North CarolinaPress. Blalock, H. M. (1969). Theoryconstruction.EnglewoodCliffs, NJ: PrenticeHall. Blau, P. M., & Duncan, O. D. (1967). The American occupational structure. New York: Wiley. Breiman, L., Friedman,J., Olshen, R., & Stone, C. (1984). Classificationand regression trees. Belmont, CA: Wadsworth. Christ, C. (1975). Judgingthe performanceof econometricmodels of the United States economy. International Economic Review, 16, 54-74. Cliff, N. (1983). Some cautions concerningthe applicationof causal modeling methods. Multivariate Behavioral Research, 18, 115-126. Coleman, J. S., Campbell,E. Q., Hobson, C. J., McPartland,J., Wood, A. M., 125 D. A. Freedman Weinfield, F. D., & York, R. L. (1966). Equality of educational opportunity. Washington, DC: U.S. Department of Health, Education, and Welfare. Crouse, J., & Olneck, M. (1979). The IQ meritocracy reconsidered. American Journal of Education, 88, 1-31. Daggett, R., & Freedman, D. (1985). Econometrics and the law: A case study in the proof of antitrust damages. In L. LeCam & R. Olshen (Eds.), Proceedings of the Berkeley conference in honor of Jerzy Neyman and Jack Kiefer (Vol. I, pp. 126-175). Belmont, CA: Wadsworth. de Leeuw, J. (1985). Review of books by Long, Everitt, Saris and Stronkhorst. Psychometrika, 50, 371-375. Duncan, O. D. (1975). Introduction to structural equation models. New York: Academic Press. Finney, J. M. (1972). Indirect effects in path analysis. Sociological Methods and Research, 1, 176-186. Fisherkeller, M. A., Friedman, J. H., & Tukey, J. W. (1975). PRIM-9: An interactive multidimensional data display and analysis system (Report SLAC-PUB1408). Stanford, CA: Stanford Linear Accelerator Center. Freedman, D. (1981). Some pitfalls in large econometric models: A case study. Journal of Business, 54, 479-500. Freedman, D. (1985). Statistics and the scientific method. In W. Mason & S. Fienberg (Eds.), Cohort analysis in social research: Beyond the identification problem (pp. 345-390). New York: Springer. Freedman, D., & Navidi, W. (1986). Regression models for adjusting the 1980 census. Statistical Science, 1, 3-39. Freedman, D., Rothenberg, T., & Sutch, R. (1983). On energy policy models. Journal of Business and Economic Statistics, 1, 24-36. Friedman, M. (1953). Essays in positive economics. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Gauss, C. (1963). Theoria motus corporum coelestium. New York: Dover. (Original work published 1809.) Hausman, J., & Wise, D. (1985). Technical problems in social experimentation: Cost versus ease of analysis. In J. Hausman & D. Wise (Eds.), Social experimentation. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. or science? Econometrica, 7, Hendry, D. (1980). Econometrics-Alchemy 387-406. Holland, P. (1986). Statistics and causal inference. Journal of the American Statistical Association, 81, 945-970. Hope, K. (1980). A geometrical approach to sociological analysis. Quality and Quantity, 14, 309-325. Hope, K. (1984). As others see us: Schooling and social mobility in Scotland and the United States. New York: Cambridge University Press. Huber, P. (1985). Projection pursuit. Annals of Statistics, 13, 435-475. Jencks, C., Smith, M., Acland, H., Bane, M. J., Cohen, D., Gintis, H., Heyns, B., & Michelson, S. (1972). Inequality: A reassessment of the effect of family and schooling in America. New York: Basic Books. Joreskog, K. G., & Sorbom, D. (1981). LISREL-Analysis of linear structural relationships by the method of maximum likelihood. Chicago: International Educational Services. Karlin, S. (1979). Comments on statistical methodology in medical genetics. In C. 126 Case Study in Path Analysis F. Sing & M. Skolnick (Eds.), Genetic analysis of common diseases: Application to predictive factors in coronary disease (pp. 497-520). New York: Liss. Karlin, S., Cameron, E. C., & Chakraborty, R. (1983). Path analysis in genetic epidemiology: A critique. American Journal of Human Genetics, 35, 695-732. Kenny, D. (1979). Correlation and causation. New York: Wiley. Keynes, J. (1939). Professor Tinbergen's method. The Economic Journal, 49, 558-570. Keynes, J. (1940). [Comment on Tinbergen's response.] The Economic Journal, 50, 154-156. Leamer, E. (1983). Taking the con out of econometrics. American Economic Review, 73, 31-43. Leontieff, W. (1971). Theoretical assumptions and nonobserved facts. American Economic Review, 61, 1-7. Lieberson, S. (1985). Making it count. Berkeley: University of California Press. Ling, R. (1983). Review of correlation and causation by Kenny. Journal of the American Statistical Association, 77, 489-491. Litterman, R. B. (1986). Forecasting with Bayesian vector autoregressions-Five years of experience. Journal of Business and Economic Statistics, 4, 25-38. Lucas, R. E., & Sargent, T. J. (1979). After Keynesian macroeconomics. Federal Reserve Bank of Minneapolis Quarterly Review, 3. McDonald, J. A. (1984). Interactivegraphics for data analysis (Report ORION 11). Stanford, CA: Stanford University, Dept. of Statistics. McNees, S. (1979). The forecasting record for the 1970's. New England Economic Review. McNees, S. (1986). Forecasting accuracy of alternative techniques: A comparison of U.S. macroeconomic forecasts. Journal of Business and Economic Statistics, 4, 5-24. Morgenstern, 0. (1963). On the accuracy of economic observations (2nd ed.). Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Noonan, R., & Wold, H. (1983). Evaluating school systems using partial least squares. Evaluation in Education, 7, 219-364. Pratt, J. W., & Shlaifer, R. (1984). On the nature and discovery of structure. Journal of the American Statistical Association, 79, 9-21. Simon, H. (1954). Spurious correlation: A causal interpretation. Journal of the American Statistical Association, 49, 467-479. Sims, C. (1980). Macroeconomics and reality. Econometrica, 48, 1-49. Sims, C. (1982). Scientific standards in econometric modeling. Paper presented at the symposium on the Developments in Econometrics and Related Fields, Netherlands Econometrics Institute. Tinbergen, J. (1940). [Reply to Keynes.] The Economic Journal, 50, 141-154. Tukey, J. W. (1954). Causation, regression and path analysis. In O. Kempthorne, T. A. Bancroft, J. W. Gowen, & J. L. Lush (Eds.), Statistics and mathematics in biology (pp. 35-66). Ames: Iowa State College Press. Veblen, E. (1975). The Manchester Union-Leader in New Hampshire elections. Hanover, NH: University Press of New England. Wold, H. (1985). Partial least squares. In J. Kotz & N. L. Johnson (Eds.), Encyclopedia of social sciences Vol. 6, pp. 581-591. New York: Wiley. Wright, S. (1921). Correlation and causation. Journal of Agricultural Research, 20, 557-585. 127 D. A. Freedman Wright, S. (1934). The method of path coefficients. Annals of Mathematical Statistics, 5, 161-215. Wright, S. (1960). Path coefficients and path regressions. Biometrics, 16, 189-202. Zarnowitz, V. (1979). An analysis of annual and multiperiod quarterly forecasts of aggregate income, output, and the price level. Journal of Business, 52, 1-34. Zellner, A. (1984). Basic issues in econometrics. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Author D. A. FREEDMAN, Professor of Statistics, University of California, Berkeley, CA 94720. Specializations: statistics: modeling, foundations. 128