FOUR FOUNDATIONAL PRINCIPLES FOR ETHICAL DECISION-MAKING 1. Ends-based thinking. Known to philosophers as utilitarianism, this principle is best known by the maxim Do whatever produces the greatest good for the greatest number of people. It demands of us a kind of cost benefit analysis, determining who will be hurt and who will be helped, and measuring the intensity of both. It is the staple of public policy debate: most legislation, these days, is crafted with this utilitarian test in mind. At the heart of this principle is an assessment of consequences, a forecasting of outcomes. Philosophers typically refer to utilitarianism, in fact, as a teleological principle, from the Greek word teleos, meaning “end” or “issue” because you cannot determine the greatest good without speculating on probable futures. Utilitarianism examines possible results and picks the one that produces the most blessing over the greatest range. 2. Rule-based thinking. Often associated with the name of German philosopher, Immanuel Kant, this principle is best known by what Kant obtusely called the categorical imperative. Kant put it this way: “Act only on that maxim you want everyone else to follow.” In other words, act in such a way that your actions could become a standard others should obey. Rule-based thinkers ask, “If everyone in the world followed the rule of action I am following, would it produce the greatest good or [in Kant’s words] the greatest ‘worth of character’?” This mode of thinking stands directly opposite utilitarianism. Arguing that we cannot know all the consequences of our actions (as ends-based principle asks us to), the rule-based thinker believes we should act according to fixed rules. The rule-based thinker says, never mind the outcomes: stick to your principles and let the chips fall where they may. Based firmly on duty—on what we ought to do rather than what we think might work—it is known among philosophers as a deontological principle, from the Geek word deon, meaning “obligation” or duty”. 3. Care-based thinking: Putting love for others first, this principle’s most famous maxim is the Golden Rule: Do unto others what you would like them to do to you. It partakes of a feature philosophers call reversibility. Reversibility tests your actions by putting yourself in the other person’s position and imagining how you would feel if you were the recipient, rather then the perpetrator, of those actions. Often associated with Christianity, it is in fact universal; it appears in every one of the world’s great religious teachings. While some philosophers have disputed its standing as a practical principle, it is for many people the first rule of ethics they learn and has provided moral glue for communities over the centuries. [ For a comparison of the expressions of the golden rule in world cultures, see this website: http://www.jcu.edu/philosophy/gensler/goldrule.htm] 4. Justice as Fairness: First articulated by John Rawls, an American philosopher, this principle envisions a society of free citizens holding equal basic rights and shows how unity can endure within a group with diverse views. Cooperation should be fair to all citizens. Citizens do not “deserve” to be born into a rich or a poor family, to be born naturally more gifted than others, to be born male or female, to be born a member of a particular racial group, and so on. Since these features of persons are in this sense morally arbitrary, citizens are not at the deepest level entitled to more or less of the benefits of social cooperation because of them. For example the fact that a citizen was born rich, white, and male in itself generates no reasons for this citizen to be either favored or disfavored by social institutions. This thesis does not in itself say how social goods should be distributed; it merely clears the decks. Rawls's positive distributive thesis is equality-based reciprocity. All social goods are to be distributed equally, unless an unequal distribution would be to everyone's advantage. Justice then requires that any inequalities must benefit all citizens, and particularly must benefit those who will have the least. Equality sets the baseline; from there any inequalities must improve everyone's situation, and especially the situation of the worst-off. [Adapted from: Rushworth Kidder, How Good People Make Tough Choices. William Morrow, 1995] and “John Rawls” in the Stanford Dictionary of Philosophy. Page 2