Abortion: Parental Consent Attempts to obtain an abortion are much more difficult for minors than for their adult counterparts due in part to laws and restrictions that regulate the consent and notification of a minor's parents. Thirty-four states require some form of parental involvement in a minor's decision to have an abortion. The laws are intended to foster parent-child relationships, protect the rights of parents, and deter young women from obtaining abortions or becoming pregnant in the first place, but research casts doubt on whether the laws have their intended effect, and Supreme Court rulings allow minors some privacy rights regarding obtaining an abortion. Historical Background The history of parental consent and notification laws extends back almost as far as 1973 and the passage of Roe v. Wade, which legalized abortion in the United States. The first case to reach the U.S. Supreme Court in the aftermath of Roe v. Wade that tested parental consent laws was decided in 1976. The case, Planned Parenthood of Central Missouri v. Danforth, involved a Missouri law that required, among other things, parental consent to obtain an abortion in all cases involving a minor. The law was found to be unconstitutional, because it did not make any exceptions regarding minors to provide circumstances under which they could receive an abortion without parental consent. Several other cases came before the Supreme Court following this ruling, and in the 1983 case of Planned Parenthood of Kansas City v. Ashcroft, the court ruled that all parental involvement laws must include a judicial bypass for minors who are unable to obtain parental consent. Thus the Supreme Court set rules that individual states had to follow when setting up their parental consent laws. State Level Data In light of the Supreme Court rulings, states approached parental involvement legislation in a variety of ways. Thirty-four states currently mandate parental involvement. Although all include a form of judicial bypass, they differ in the levels of stringency. Some states focus on parental notification which is simply notifying parents of their daughter's impending abortion decision, while others require parental consent in some fashion before an abortion can legally occur. Understanding the differences from state to state can be challenging for both abortion providers and the minors seeking an abortion. Without uniformity in the law, minors with the ability to do so have been able to avoid their own state's restrictions and travel to a state with more flexible regulations. Federal Involvement There have been attempts to pass federal legislation that would ensure state parental involvement laws are not circumvented. The Child Interstate Abortion Notification Act (CIANA) in the House and the Child Custody Protection Act (CCPA) in the Senate were introduced in the 2005– 2006 congressional session but were unable to garner enough congressional support to pass. The bills sought to make it a federal crime to transport a minor out of state with the intention of obtaining an abortion to evade the resident state's parental consent laws. No additional federal legislation has been enacted concerning parental involvement in a minor's abortion decision. Although the CIANA was reintroduced by lawmakers in the House of Representatives in 2007, it has not been acted upon. Effect on Abortion Rates Proponents of parental involvement laws claim that more pregnant teenagers would choose childbirth and possibly adoption over abortion if they had the benefit of their parents' guidance. They also maintain that parental consent laws may influence teenagers to not become sexually active in the first place. Research shows, however, that state parental involvement laws have little effect on a minor's decision to pursue an abortion. Proponents also argue that state and federal laws should honor parents' authority to control their children's upbringing and that abortion is a surgical procedure, which makes it different than other health care services, such as contraceptive information, substance abuse treatment, or care and testing for sexually transmitted diseases, covered by other state and federal confidentiality laws. True Impact of Parental Involvement Laws In an article published in March 2009 by the Guttmacher Institute, "The Impact of Laws Requiring Parental Involvement for Abortion: A Literature Review," the authors conducted a review of twenty-nine studies of the impact of parental involvement laws. Their report states, "The clearest documented impact of parental involvement laws is an increase in the number of minors traveling outside their home states to obtain abortion services in states that do not mandate parental involvement or that have less restrictive laws." They point out that while several studies did report a decline in minors' abortion rates after parental involvement laws were enacted, most of the studies ignored the fact that minors had left their home state to obtain an abortion and did not account for the teens who avoided coming to the state to seek an abortion after the change in law. Two studies did include these occurrences, one in Mississippi and one in Massachusetts, and showed no change in the abortion rate among teens compared to prior to the law. One exception was noted in Texas, however, which revealed a decrease in the number of abortions but with an apparent correlation to an increasing number of teen pregnancies in the state. The Guttmacher review found that many of the studies had serious limitations due to incomplete data that did not focus only on minors, and the authors called for additional research that would provide more definitive results. Medical Professionals' Opinions Although current research may not present conclusive results, healthcare organizations consistently speak out against parental involvement laws. Medical groups such as the American Academy of Family Physicians and American Medical Association take the position that even though health care providers are obligated to encourage their minor patients to discuss matters such as pregnancy and abortion with their parents, the groups strongly feel that minors should not be forced by law to involve their parents in decisions involving abortion or contraception. This strong opinion that minors must have the right to confidential healthcare is born out of the increased risks minors face when access to abortion is restricted. Research indicates that parental consent laws have a negative impact on the timing of minors' abortion decisions. In a November 2005 analysis conducted by the Guttmacher Institute, "Teenagers' Access to Confidential Reproductive Health Services," the authors assert that "parental consent requirements can have potentially serious adverse consequences associated with delayed access to timely medical care among those teenagers who do not wish to involve their parents in their abortion decisions." Unintended Consequences Many teens who do not want their parents to know they are seeking an abortion find it intimidating to pursue the alternative method, judicial bypass. They often do not know how to navigate the court system and have difficulty sharing personal details about their pregnancy with strangers. Many states employ waiting periods and counseling which also can be burdensome to teens. They may be forced to delay their abortion until later in the pregnancy when it is much more dangerous to complete or seek illegal means to terminate the pregnancy. Proponents dispute these arguments. They contend there is a need for more stringent federal regulations not less, which would then influence teen behavior by eliminating the option of traveling to another state. When the CIANA bill was being debated in 2005, President George W. Bush, a long time conservative backer of the pro-life movement, issued a written statement encouraging passage of the law as it would "protect the health and safety of minors by ensuring that state parental involvement laws are not circumvented." According to NARAL Pro-Choice America, a non-profit organization advocating for women's reproductive rights, most young women do share the news of their pregnancy with at least one parent. However a number of teens who are the victim of abuse, rape, or incest often feel they cannot tell their parents they are pregnant. In the presence of one of these factors, knowledge of the pregnancy can lead to violence within the family that can delay or prevent an abortion. A tragic incident in Michigan in 2005 highlighted the unintended consequences of a parental consent law. A young pregnant girl and her boyfriend wanted to get an abortion but did not want to tell her parents of the pregnancy. She felt she could not consult her family doctor and was seemingly unaware of alternatives available in seeking a legal abortion. The couple decided to end the pregnancy themselves, and the girl's boyfriend repeatedly beat her abdomen with a baseball bat to induce a miscarriage, which they did. This horrific case drew national attention and highlighted the fact that laws cannot prevent unintended pregnancies or a woman's choice to end that pregnancy legally or otherwise. Attempts to regulate or restrict a woman's right to an abortion have not been shown to make a difference in the number of abortions. Solutions through Pregnancy Prevention Evidence does suggest, however, that better access to and use of contraceptives can make a difference in lowering abortion rates in teens. An example of this approach can be found in Western Europe, which has the lowest abortion rate in the world. Contraceptive availability and use is widespread and access to safe abortions is available and legal with minimal restrictions. At the other end of the spectrum are Africa, Asia, and Latin America, who have the world's highest abortion rates even though abortion is very restricted. Parental involvement laws do not appear to live up to their desired intentions of fostering better family communications and preventing teen pregnancies and abortions. Amanda Dennis of Ibis Reproductive Health and lead author of the Guttmacher Institute's 2009 Literature Review, asserts "… the reality is you can't legislate good parent-child communication. If we want to protect young women's health and safety, access to confidential reproductive health services— both contraception and abortion—is critical." Source Citation: "Abortion: Parental Consent." Current Issues: Macmillan Social Science Library. Detroit: Gale, 2010. Gale Opposing Viewpoints In Context. Web. 9 Apr. 2012. Parental Consent Laws Are Necessary "Well-designed parental-involvement laws have been surprisingly effective at reducing abortion rates among minors." Michael New is a political science professor at the University of Alabama. He is also the author of a 2008 study for the Family Research Council, which concludes that abortion rates drop when states adopt parental involvement laws. In the viewpoint that follows, New summarizes his findings and the findings of other researchers and reiterates that states requiring parents to be notified if their daughter is seeking an abortion have witnessed a drop in abortion rates among minors. New asserts that parental notification laws are helpful in reducing abortion rates, but that consent laws are more powerful because they ensure parents the right to prevent an abortion to be carried out on their minor daughter, despite the wishes of the minor. As you read, consider the following questions: 1. By what percentage have parental involvement laws reduced abortion in states that have enacted such legislation, as Michael New maintains? 2. According to a 2000 New England Journal of Medicine study, how had seventeen-year-olds been evading the parental involvement laws in Texas? 3. As New reports, how many states have enacted two-parent parental involvement laws? Political candidates who support legal abortion have been changing their rhetoric in recent years. Indeed, during the current election cycle, a number of pro-choice candidates, including Barack Obama, have expressed an interest in lowering the incidence of abortion. Such statements present a unique opportunity for the pro-life movement. Indeed, pro-lifers should insist that these candidates support pro-life parental-involvement laws. Such laws enjoy broad support and unlike other laws limiting abortion, they can be easily justified as a parental-rights issue. Furthermore, my [2008] study for the Family Research Council provides evidence that well-designed parental-involvement laws have been surprisingly effective at reducing abortion rates among minors. Indeed, there are a number of academic and policy studies which demonstrate the effectiveness of pro-life parental-involvement laws. Four studies in peer-reviewed academic journals use timeseries, cross-sectional data to simultaneously analyze all the enacted pro-life parentalinvolvement laws over an extended period of time. These studies find that these pieces of legislation reduce the in-state minor abortion rate by anywhere from 13 to 19 percent. Case studies of parental-involvement laws that have been enacted in Massachusetts, Indiana, Missouri, and Minnesota arrive at similar conclusions about the effects of parental-involvement laws. Proven Test Cases However, the best case study of a pro-life parental-involvement law appeared in the New England Journal of Medicine in 2006. This study analyzed the Texas parental-notification law that took effect in 2000. The authors found that the law resulted in statistically significant declines in the abortion rate in Texas among 15-year-olds, 16-year-olds, and 17-year-olds. Now the authors did find some evidence that some 17-year-olds were able to circumvent the law by waiting until their 18th birthday to have an abortion. However, they found little evidence that Texas minors were circumventing the law by obtaining abortions in neighboring states. My ... Family Research Council study contributes to this body of research. It is actually the first study that compares the effect of different types of pro-life parentalinvolvement legislation. The results indicate that parental-involvement laws reduce the minor abortion rate by 13 percent—a finding that is consistent with other research on the subject. However, state laws that require parental consent instead of parental notification are even more effective, reducing the abortion rate by an average of 19 percent. This finding held true for all age groups that were analyzed—17-year-olds, 16-year-olds, and 15-year-olds. Consent Laws Are More Powerful at Curbing Abortion There are a number of reasons why parental-consent laws might be more effective than parentalnotice laws. Consent laws, unlike notification laws, would effectively give parents the ability to prevent an abortion from being performed on their daughter. Additionally, a parental-notice law might not deter a minor who feels she can intercept the notification. Finally, it should also be noted that abortion providers might have a greater incentive to follow parental-consent laws. A missed notification can possibly be blamed on timing or other incidental factors. However, failure to obtain consent would likely be seen as the responsibility of the abortion provider and could result in legal action—especially if the parents did not approve of the abortion being performed. Interestingly, those parental-involvement laws that require the involvement of two parents instead of one are even more effective. The regression model indicates that these laws reduce the minor abortion rate by 31 percent. Now only three states—Minnesota, Mississippi, and North Dakota—have enacted parentalinvolvement laws that require the involvement of two parents. However, the substantial abortion declines that have occurred in each of these states suggest that they are models that other states should follow. These abortion declines all sound impressive. However, it is entirely possible that some of these in-state abortion reductions could be offset by minors who obtain abortions in neighboring states where the laws are more permissive. Federal legislation has been introduced that would considerably strengthen these state-level parental-involvement laws. The Child Custody Protection Act that has been introduced in the U.S. Senate and the Child Interstate Abortion Notification Act (CIANA) that has been introduced in the U.S. House would make it a felony for anyone other than a parent to take a child across state lines for the purpose of obtaining an abortion. CIANA and the Child Custody Protection Act passed the House and Senate respectively in 2006. However, this legislation ultimately was defeated when Senate Democrats refused to appoint members to a conference committee to work out the differences in the two pieces of legislation. Regardless, by making it more difficult for a minor to obtain an abortion in neighboring states, these federal laws could considerably strengthen the state-level parental-involvement laws that are already in place. Indeed, both CIANA and the Child Custody Protection Act should both remain a high priority for pro-life organizations working on federal legislation. Work to Be Done Meanwhile at the state level, the pro-life movement still has plenty of work to do. Right now about 36 states have pro-life parental-involvement laws in effect. However, about 15 of these laws only require parental notification. Furthermore, only three of these laws mandate the involvement of two parents. Strengthening these state laws could be a worthwhile project for pro-life activists. The Supreme Court has consistently upheld strong state-level parentalinvolvement laws, and it is certainly possible that other legislative proposals to limit abortion at the state level may not withstand judicial scrutiny. During the 2008 election campaign, abortion will undoubtedly continue to be a major issue. The Supreme Court appointments by the next president will likely determine the extent to which federal government and the states are able to protect unborn children. It is laudable that a number of candidates have expressed an interest in lowering the incidence of abortion. However, serious pro-life voters should support only those candidates who have a consistent track record of supporting pro-life legislation. While campaign rhetoric often does not amount to much, this study—and other studies—provide solid evidence that well-designed laws are effective at protecting mothers and their unborn children. Source Citation: New, Michael. "Parental Consent Laws Are Necessary." Abortion. Ed. Tamara L. Roleff. San Diego: Greenhaven Press, 1997. Opposing Viewpoints. Rpt. from "Study Shows Parental Involvement Laws Reduce Abortions 19-31 Percent." LifeNews.com. 2008. Gale Opposing Viewpoints In Context. Web. 9 Apr. 2012. Parental Consent Laws Are Unnecessary "Because of parental involvement laws, reproductive options are not a reality for teens whose parents seek to punish their behavior rather than support or protect them." In the following viewpoint, Diana Philip argues that laws requiring parental involvement in a minor's decision to have an abortion are detrimental to the welfare of those young women. In Philip's opinion, such laws force minors who are not ready for the financial or emotional responsibility of parenthood to forfeit the right to decide whether to carry through with an unplanned pregnancy. Philip believes this is a challenge to women's reproductive rights and a form of punishment inflicted on minors who may not agree with their parents' views on abortion. Philip is the cofounder of Jane's Due Process, an organization providing legal services to pregnant minors in Texas. As you read, consider the following questions: 1. As Diana Philip reports, what percentage of Texas minors involved their parents in the abortion process before the passing of the 2000 parental involvement law? 2. Why does Philip consider the waiver needed to bypass parental consent another obstacle for teens seeking abortions? 3. What are "Baby Moses" laws, according to the author? No one wants to see a teenager be trapped by poverty, abuse, or neglect. Yet, laws concerning the rights of pregnant minors to access certain medical care do just that. Since the late 1970s, state legislatures have been passing state "parental involvement" laws, which mandate that a parent or legal guardian be notified of or give consent for a pregnant minor's decision to seek an abortion. Texas has one of the most recent laws, now five years old [in 2005], and as of June 5, 2005, its law changed from requiring notification to mandating consent. Congress is now in the process of creating a nationwide parental notification law through the Child Interstate Abortion Notification Act (CIANA). CIANA also would make it illegal for anyone to help a teen obtain an abortion in another state without satisfying her home state's law. Supporters of this bill generally think such a law will protect children. However, before the Senate votes on CIANA or similar legislation, lawmakers should carefully consider the damage parental involvement laws have done to pregnant youth in Texas. Overcoming Obstacles in Texas Mandated notification by Texas clinics did not result in an increase of actual parental involvement in teenagers' decisions regarding abortion, as the law intended. Instead, the state's parental notification law targeted youth whom some lawmakers claim they did not intend to harm. Before the law's enactment in January 2000, Texas abortion providers reported that 80-95 percent of minors involved a parent in the decision to terminate a pregnancy. The ones who did not had compelling reasons. For instance, some parents physically abused, abandoned, or disowned their daughters when they found out they were pregnant. These youth understood that a family that is unable to communicate due to a significant degree of dysfunction, separation, and/or abuse is unlikely to respond appropriately during such an important life decision. If at least one parent cannot or will not give written consent to the clinic, a minor may seek a judicial bypass waiver by demonstrating that she is mature enough to make the decision, that the abortion would be in her best interest, or that notification will lead to physical, sexual, or emotional abuse. However, although Texas has had over five years to implement a fair system, minors seeking judicial bypass still experience challenges in locating effective counsel and struggle with confidentiality and due process issues in local courthouses. Judges have been known to deny waivers even when the petitioner has met more than one of the three alternative grounds that qualify for a waiver. If the waiver is denied, the minor has a right to appeal. However, when a minor seeks legal relief through the courts, her abortion procedure is delayed, increasing the costs, and at times, the risk of complications in terminating a pregnancy at a more progressed stage. For these and other reasons, some youth consider seeking abortion services out of state, in Mexico, or under unsafe and illegal circumstances. Desperate Teens and Trying Circumstances No population of minors is exempt from this law. Not teens removed by the state from their homes for family violence. Not victims of sexual assault whose parents would not believe they were raped and would force them to continue the pregnancy as a punishment for "youthful indiscretion" or due to certain religious beliefs. Not teens who have already given birth and are either active parents or have given babies up for adoption in the past, some forced to do so by their parents. Not orphans or other youth whose parents are missing or incarcerated. All minors must find ways to comply with this very harmful law. In the last few years, problems have grown regarding pregnant youth along the Mexican border, which some activists have attributed to Texas's parental involvement statutes. Despite the passage of a "Baby Moses" law, which allows a mother to leave her newborn infant at designated safe havens like hospitals or churches without legal repercussions, the number of abandoned infants has risen, resulting in their deaths and the prosecution of their teen mothers. More minors have sought second trimester procedures after illegal ones obtained over the border earlier in their pregnancies failed. And there have been increased reports of abnormalities in infants born to immigrant teens along the border. When tests were run to see if the babies had been affected by environmental causes such as water pollution, medical professionals found that 25 percent of the babies were the result of incest. A Form of Neglect and Abuse Mothering with dignity? Becoming a parent when emotionally, physically, and financially ready? Not for these youth. Deciding when to become a parent or whether to have another child has been taken out of their hands entirely. Because of parental involvement laws, reproductive options are not a reality for teens whose parents seek to punish their behavior rather than support or protect them. Just like in any other domestic violence dynamic, the decision to make a teen bear a child against her better judgment is more about power and control than anything else. Where is the dignity in becoming a parent amid domestic violence, sexual assault, and economic abuse? In essence, states have passed laws that allow parents to abuse their daughters and neglect their emotional health. And now Congress wants to do the same. Source Citation: Philip, Diana, and Center For American Progress. "Parental Consent Laws Are Unnecessary." Abortion. Ed. Tamara L. Roleff. San Diego: Greenhaven Press, 1997. Opposing Viewpoints. Rpt. from "Legal Child Abuse: The Harm of Parental Involvement Laws." 2005. Gale Opposing Viewpoints In Context. Web. 9 Apr. 2012. Bioethics Ethics are rules and principles prescribing right and wrong actions; ethics can also refer to the study of how moral standards of right and wrong can affect the conduct of individuals and groups. Bioethics refers to the moral standards, questions, and regulations pertaining to the practice of medicine, the scientific and medical research of living beings, and the applications of such research. These applications include assisted reproduction, organ donation, animal experimentation, cloning, embryo research, and genetic engineering. The rapid advances in such areas as genetics and biotechnology have continually raised new ethical issues in the biomedical community. The fundamental questions of bioethics can perhaps be summarized as follows: What are the ethical obligations of doctors and scientists in the course of their work? If scientists or doctors can do something, does that mean they should? Or should some science and medical experiments be avoided because they do not protect the rights and dignity of individuals or in some other way cross the ethical line? The Field of Bioethics Beginning in the 1970s bioethics emerged as a separate interdisciplinary field of study in universities, combining elements of philosophy, medicine, biology, theology, and history. By 1990 more than one hundred institutions devoted to bioethics existed in the world, most of them in the United States. In addition, many major scientific and medical institutions employ professional bioethicists to help them make decisions if their work poses ethical questions. In addition to local and professional groups, many countries have established official and semiofficial committees and consultative bodies to recommend laws on bioethical questions. These bodies generally bring together scientists, philosophers, religious scholars, lawyers, and other experts to discuss implications of biomedical research and what laws and rules should be developed. In the United States, the President’s Council on Bioethics consists of experts appointed by the president; the council studies and issues periodic reports on human cloning, stem cell research, and other issues. France has the National Consultative Ethics Committee for Health and the Life Sciences. The European Group on Ethics on Science and New Technologies (EGE) advises the European Commission, while the International Bioethics Committee (IBE) performs a similar function for the United Nations. One issue under debate is how much the doctrines of various religions should be taken into account in making bioethical decisions. Religious scholars and theologians helped pioneer the academic field of bioethics in the 1960s and 1970s and are often included in bioethics committees and consultative groups such as the president’s council. Arguments for or against certain scientific and medical practices are often couched in religious terms, such as the argument that humanity should not play God by, for example, creating new forms of life by combining genes of different species. But some argue that religious views should play a limited role in these debates and should not set binding limits for individuals who are not adherents of a particular faith. The practice of medical and scientific research itself often raises ethical questions, especially when humans are the experimental subjects. In addition to research methodologies, other areas in which ethical questions are often raised include how humans are conceived and born and how the genes of humans and other living creatures are studied and manipulated. Medical Research A significant historical event in the field of bioethics was the discovery of the horrific experiments the Nazis performed on human prisoners during World War II. At concentration camps, Nazi doctors infected people with diseases to test vaccines, submerged people in freezing water to see how long they would survive, and committed other atrocities. After these doctors and other Nazis were tried and convicted for war crimes at Nuremberg following the war, the Nuremberg Code was developed to distinguish ethical research on humans from unethical research. In the 1960s critics of America’s medical establishment noted that unethical research was not confined to the Nazis. Two famous examples are the Tuskegee syphilis study, in which hundreds of black men were denied medicine to treat syphilis so the effects of the disease could be studied, and the Willowbrook study, in which disabled children at the Willowbrook State School were infected with hepatitis so that disease could be studied. Reforms and safeguards have been established within the medical community since then to ensure that humans give informed consent to being part of experiments and to ensure that children, prisoners, and others who are unable to give consent are protected. One area that remains controversial is research on human embryos. Embryonic stem cells—the cells created at the earliest stages of human development—may be the key to treating or curing many diseases. However, stem cell research and cultivation generally involves creating and then destroying very young embryos. This has raised many of the same issues as in the debate on abortion. Many who oppose abortion also oppose human embryonic research because they believe that such embryos are potential human beings who have rights. Supporters of stem cell research counter that the embryos are not human beings. Assisted Reproduction The status of embryos is also a factor in another significant area of bioethics controversy— assisted reproduction. For much of human history little could be done to help couples or individuals who wanted to be parents but were unable to have children. That has changed. In 1978 scientists removed an ovum from a woman, fertilized it with sperm in a laboratory (in vitro fertilization), and implanted the fertilized egg in the woman. Nearly nine months later the world’s first "test-tube baby" was born. The development was criticized by some at the time as a monstrous interference with a natural process, but since then thousands of children have been born with various forms of assisted reproduction. In addition to in vitro fertilization, couples can use artificial insemination by donor (AID), donated eggs, and surrogate wombs. Fertilized eggs can be selected for sex and screened for genetic disorders before being implanted (an experimental process called preimplantation genetic diagnosis). Assisted reproduction has also enabled gay and lesbian couples, single women, and postmenopausal women to have children. Assisted reproduction has been celebrated by some who say it helps people who desperately want children. But it has also been criticized by some as unethical. Some critics object to what they view as deviations from the "natural" family of a mother and father. Another objection some have is to the fate of unused embryos. Many assisted reproduction techniques involve the creation of multiple embryos, not all of which are implanted. Those that are not used are either frozen or destroyed—something that is morally objectionable to those who believe all embryos deserve a right to life. Finally, some people object to children being made-to-order, like a product. Bioethicists Arthur L. Caplan and Glenn McGee say, "preimplantation genetic diagnosis … could one day be applied to such traits as personality or intelligence, raising additional ethical questions about the rights of parents to design their descendants." One human reproductive technique that has not yet been tried—but which has generated much discussion over its ethics—is human cloning. To clone something is to grow an organism from a single cell, resulting in a new organism that is virtually genetically identical to its parent. In 1996 scientists successfully cloned a sheep, leading some to speculate that human cloning, then the subject of science fiction, was close at hand. The prospect was highly controversial, and many countries and states have passed laws banning reproductive cloning. Genetic Engineering and the Creation of New Life Forms Genetic engineering refers to techniques that artificially alter the genes (the chemicals that control heredity) in an organism, thus changing both the organism and its descendants. In the 1970s, scientists developed ways to make new combinations of genes and to introduce individual genes into the genetic makeup of plants, animals, and other organisms. Scientists have developed bacteria, for example, with genes that produce or break down certain chemicals. They have inserted a growth gene into mice, causing them to grow twice their natural size. They have transferred genes from one species into another; in one experiment, a bacteria gene was inserted into a tomato plant, creating a line of plants resistant to caterpillars. Researchers for the J. Craig Venter Institute replaced the entire genetic identity of a microbe and applied for a patent for the new bacteria in 2006. Such developments, like those of assisted reproduction, have been met with concern about their ethical implications. Some opponents of genetic engineering stress the possible environmental damage caused by the accidental or purposeful release of genetically engineered bacteria or other organisms. Others object to the creation of chimeras (genetic combinations of multiple species) or the idea that any life form can be patented. As in the field of assisted reproduction, many object to the idea that life is a commodity that can be manipulated or tinkered with for selfish reasons. Longtime genetics critic Jeremy Rifkin asks, "Do we want our children to grow up in a world where the genetics codes of plants, animals, and humans are interchangeable and living things are programmed as engineered products with no greater intrinsic value than autos or microwave ovens?" But many researchers on the cutting edge of biotechnology reject the notion that their work is unethical. Mark Bedau, a philosopher and chief executive of a company trying to make single-cell organisms from chemical components, acknowledges that what he is doing could be seen as "playing God," but argues that "playing God is a good thing to do as long as you’re doing it responsibly." Source Citation: "Bioethics." Current Issues: Macmillan Social Science Library. Detroit: Gale, 2010. Gale Opposing Viewpoints In Context. Web. 9 Apr. 2012. Gender Selection Is Ethical Norbert Gleicher, professor of obstetrics, gynecology, and reproductive sciences at Yale University School of Medicine, is a consultant at the Center for Human Reproduction. David H. Barad is professor of epidemiology and social medicine at Albert Einstein College of Medicine in the Bronx, New York. In developed nations such as the United States, gender selection is not inherently unethical. Research suggests that while there is a greater demand for male than female babies among those parents who choose to select gender in the United States, the bias disappears when certain ethic groups are removed from the analysis. This finding contradicts the assumption that gender selection always discriminates against females. Thus, adopting ethical opinions concerning gender selection that apply to all cultures worldwide is unfair. Women who meet objective criteria and have not been coerced should be allowed to choose the gender of their children. Elective gender selection has remained controversial worldwide. In the United States (US), the issue had remained largely dormant until the Ethics Committee of the American Society for Reproductive Medicine (ASRM) published an opinion, potentially validating elective gender selection under selected circumstances. This publication gave rise to controversy in the US, matching differences of opinion elsewhere in the world. A Variety of Ethical Opinions Some ethics opinions (from major professional societies) have differentiated between 'prefertilization' gender selection by sperm sorting, and 'post-fertilization' sex selection through in vitro fertilization (IVF) and preimplantation genetic diagnosis (PGD), with the former considered more ethically acceptable than the latter. The reasons are complex, with many ethicists considering the creation of a human embryo as a differentiating step. A recently issued opinion by the Ethics Committee of the American College of Obstetricians and Gynecologists (ACOG), however, placed a surprising degree of emphasis on a different argument: in following the reasoning of the International Federation of Gynecology and Obstetrics, it considers all forms of elective gender selection as discriminatory and sexist. In its opinion, the ACOG committee states, 'The committee shares the concerns expressed by the United Nations and the International Federation of Gynecology and Obstetrics that sex selection can be motivated by and reinforce the devaluation of women'. Continuing, the committee concluded that, '...the use of sex selection techniques for family balancing violates the norm of equality between the sexes; moreover, this ethical objection arises regardless of the timing of the selection (i.e. preconception or postconception) or the stage of development of the embryo or fetus.' Such an implied utilization of elective gender selection for sexist and discriminatory purposes, devaluatory to women, of course implies that, given the opportunity, a large majority of couples would choose gender selection for male offspring. This contention has been disputed on theoretical grounds, and based on population surveys, but still has led to international regulatory and legal prohibitions, although, in an exception, the House of Commons Science and Technology Committee of the United Kingdom recently adopted less dogmatic recommendations. The introduction of elective gender selection would, at least in the developed world, not affect gender ratios to a significant degree. Studying Gender Selection The issue has, however, never before objectively been investigated. This study attempts such an investigation in a multiethnic US patient population, which chose to undergo gender selection procedures for family balancing purposes.... The results of this study demonstrate overall a statistically larger demand for male than female gender selection. When these data are, however, further analyzed, it becomes apparent that the demand for males is driven by strong biases toward male selection in only some ethnic minorities. Except for Chinese, Arab/Muslim and Asian-Indian patients, no other ethnic group demonstrates a bias toward male selection. Indeed, the opposite is true, especially among Caucasian/Hispanic patients, where 59.6% of selections were for female. This finding confirms previously expressed opinions, and population surveys in a number of countries, which have argued that the introduction of elective gender selection would, at least in the developed world, not affect gender ratios to a significant degree. In the US, two prior surveys have addressed this issue: [T.] Jain et al. noted a significant preference for female gender, especially in older women, who were not religious, had more living children, had only sons and carried a diagnosis of male factor infertility. Interestingly, nulliparous [never having given birth] women, who, of course, were not the subject of our study, did not demonstrate preference for the selection of one gender over the other. Among parous [having given birth] women, the distribution of gender among their children significantly affected their preferred choices: those with only daughters preferred to select for male; those with only sons preferred selection for female, thus validating the concept of family balancing. [E.] Dahl et al. noted that 50% of men and women wished to have a balanced family, 7% wanted more boys, 6% more girls, 5% with only boys, 4% with only girls and 27% had no preference. Our study did not demonstrate that age represented a contributing factor toward the differences observed between ethnic groups. Asian patients were, however, minimally younger than nonAsian and younger age predisposed to male selection. Especially remarkable was the fact that the two most committed ethnic groups, Caucasian/Hispanic (to female selection) and Chinese (to male selection), were almost identical in mean ages. The Contradicting Arguments This study also contradicts the argument that offering elective gender selection for family balancing purposes 'always' is discriminatory against females and should, therefore, 'always' be considered sexist, as expressed by the United Nations, a recent ACOG Ethics Opinion and in a number of ethical opinions in the literature. The data presented here instead suggest that in the US, the situation is more complex: although certain minorities may still have maintained cultural biases of their homelands, a majority of remaining couples do not demonstrate discriminatory, or sexist, behavior toward females. Indeed, this majority may actually act discriminatorily against males by predominantly selecting for female. Discrimination against male gender has, however, to our best knowledge, never been recognized by any of the international ethical panels commenting on this issue. This study does not address the potential choice [of] gender [that] couples would prefer in first pregnancies. Although the studies by Jain et al. and Dahl et al. suggest that expected findings should not differ significantly from those reported in this study, such a conclusion remains to be confirmed by future studies in the field. Studying Ethnic Minorities As a New York based fertility center, our program appears well suited to investigate this issue because many of our patients represent ethnic minorities, where, for cultural reasons, gender discrimination in favor of male selection can, indeed, be expected. The 22 Chinese, 6 Arab/Muslim and 6 Asian-Indian couples, who to a significant degree favored male selection, represent the approximate overall representations of these ethnic groups within our center's patient population. It is, therefore, reassuring that the availability of gender section for family balancing purposes does not appear to have selectively drawn couples from these two minorities. In the US, ethnic minorities are usually concentrated in large urban centers. For example, Chinese minorities can be found in largest numbers in New York City and San Francisco areas, whereas Arab/Muslim populations concentrate in the New York City and Michigan areas. The ethnic biases presented here toward male gender selection will, therefore, only be visible in relatively small parts of the country. The offer of elective gender selection for family balancing purposes does not necessarily violate the norm of equality between the sexes to the disfavor of females. Other minorities were represented in only small sample sizes, and lack of obvious biases can, therefore, not necessarily be understood as absence of such biases. Further studies, involving larger patient populations, are needed to fully absolve other minority populations from antifemale biases. At the same time, this study also suggests that in a less ethnically diverse population, representing a more homogenous Caucasian/Hispanic population, and thus a large majority of the US population, one, indeed, can expect no bias toward male selections and, potentially, even bias toward the selection of females. Drawing Conclusions This observation suggests that in an ethnically diverse, and economically developed country, like the US, the offer of elective gender selection for family balancing purposes does not necessarily violate the norm of equality between the sexes to the disfavor of females, as suggested in the recent Ethics Opinion of ACOG, and, therefore, does not universally appear to represent a discriminatory and sexist medical practice. In developed countries ethnic biases [in favor of male selection] will fade over time as new generations are influenced by their new homeland's cultural habits. Yet, at the same time these findings raise the question [of] how obviously existing biases toward male gender selection in certain minority populations should be addressed. We have given considerable thought to this issue but have been unable to reach an unequivocal answer: on the one hand, we strongly believe in the right of patients to choose the makeup of their families; however, our belief in such rights is, of course, predicated on free choice for each individual, which in an enlightened society will, as most published data and this study have demonstrated, lead to an approximately equal gender distribution, not discriminatory toward females. When such free choice, based on ethnic habits and/or pressures, is lacking, it would seem only fair to withhold the right to choose the gender makeup of one's family. The decision to withhold the right of elective gender selection would, therefore, appear appropriate in countries where widespread discrimination against females, indeed, exists. Moral and ethical values, however, vary in different societies and, as this study demonstrated, in different ethnicities within US society. It would, therefore, appear mistaken to assume that universal ethics opinion can be developed for worldwide consumption, as suggested by the United Nations' opinion on elective gender selection, and by some individuals. Instead, developed nations would be well advised to develop educational outreach programs for their ethnic minorities, which teach non-discriminatory value systems, while allowing the conduct of practices which are not abused by a large majority of the population. It seems reasonable to assume that in developed countries ethnic biases will fade over time as new generations are influenced by their new homeland's cultural habits. Our experience with elective gender selection also indicates that, independent of ethnicity, the choice to pursue this process is in over 80% of couples initiated by the woman. In developed countries, with mixed ethnic populations, like the US, this observation suggests that a psychological investigation, prior to initiation of treatment, may allow for an objective differentiation between women who chose gender selection out of free will, and those who feel coerced. Such a psychological examination could then, in a non-discriminatory way, be used to determine who should, and who should not, be given access to selective gender determination of their offspring. We in that sense agree with Dahl who commented that outlawing a harmless practice in one country, simply because it has been demonstrated to have potentially harmful effects elsewhere in the world, represents bad public policy. Similarly, there is no reason to impose ethics opinions on a whole nation, simply because a small minority acts in an unethical fashion. Ethical advisories should, in their respective opinions, be more considerate of national value systems, and should not attempt to find consensus based on lowest common denominators. Source Citation: Gleicher, Norbert, and David H. Barad. "Gender Selection Is Ethical." Reproductive Technology. Ed. Cindy Mur. San Diego: Greenhaven Press, 2005. At Issue. Rpt. from "The Choice of Gender: Is Elective Gender Selection, Indeed, Sexist?" Human Reproduction 22 (1 Nov. 2007): 3038-3041. Gale Opposing Viewpoints In Context. Web. 9 Apr. 2012. Gender Selection Can in Some Cases Be Unethical Preeti Shekar is a feminist activist and journalist from India. According to Preeti Shekar, the decision to select a child's gender may be harmful if made for social rather than medical reasons. In societies that favor male children, gender selection technologies help parents to select male rather than female offspring. This helps the parents avoid resorting to female infanticide and feticide and removes pressure on the mother from husband and relatives to bear sons. However, use of these technologies for gender selection for societal reasons perpetuates sexist attitudes about the feminine gender. Moreover, the practice creates an imbalance in the ratio of males to females in countries, such as India and China, that favor the use of these gender selection methods. Nobel Prize-winning economist Amartya Sen speaks of "missing women." Other experts call the phenomenon "gendercide." They refer to gender selection, a practice that is thriving in South Asian societies in the United States and abroad, thanks to new, sophisticated reproductive technologies. "We get several calls a week from folks, especially from India and China either living here or who plan to visit, asking if we can definitely help them make a baby boy," notes a hotline operator for The Fertility Institutes in Los Angeles, one of numerous clinics that have mushroomed in the United States to cater to the growing demand for state-of-the-art reproductive technologies. Doctors Use Three Techniques There are currently three techniques of gender selection available: pre-natal testing, preimplantation genetic diagnoses and sperm sorting. Pre-natal testing consists of ultrasound that detects the gender of the fetus, allowing parents to abort if the fetus is of an undesired sex. The latter two techniques are more complex. With genetic diagnosing, a woman first goes through in vitro fertilization, during which her eggs are surgically extracted and fertilized outside the body. Doctors then test the embryos and implant only those of the desired gender. Originally developed for the detection of sex-linked genetic disorders, the technique is now employed in gender selection. MicroSort technology, or sperm sorting, involves literally sorting through sperm to find the sex-determining chromosome (Y for a boy and X for a girl) and then inseminating the woman with sperm that will create a baby of the desired gender. Gender selection technologies are of increasing interest to an elite class that filters issues through a paradigm of choice and access. While many mainstream news reports and articles do gently hint at the ethical issues of using the technologies for non-medical purposes, the final verdict rests on each family's shoulders. Since genetic diagnosing and sperm sorting help families avoid the trauma of female infanticide and feticide that earlier, less sophisticated technologies allowed, it is a popular notion, even among some progressive members of the South Asian community. What's lacking, however, is a deeper analysis of the sexist and racist consequences of the technologies. "It is important to have a critical discussion of the implications of reproductive technologies, especially for women of color," affirms Sujatha Jesudason of the Center for Genetics and Society, who is a veteran reproductive rights activist and community organizer. "Because if we don't, then we as a society let the market determine what is acceptable instead of challenging the current and future misuse of technology that is growing increasingly sophisticated. This is a deeply ethical and feminist issue." South Asians Are Targeted Despite the formidable costs—between $18,000 and $23,000 on average—it is not uncommon for middle-class and affluent couples from India and China to visit the United States to access these technologies, which are either banned or unavailable back home. Dubbed as the new face of reproductive tourism, many clinics encourage the practice with slick marketing strategies targeting South Asian communities. Advertisements for gender selection appear in Asia-bound in-flight magazines and increasingly in South Asian community papers. Often, the new technologies are framed in "neutral" ways (many U.S.-based institutes refer to gender selection as "family balancing"), reducing the practice to the level of the family's choice to have a baby boy or girl. Perhaps the most disturbing aspect underlying the availability of these technologies is the racism that helps perpetuate it. In their newsletters and online testimonials, the Washington, D.C-based Genetics and IVF Institute and The Fertility Institutes with centers in L.A., Las Vegas and Mexico, feature largely white American couples who herald the technology for enabling them to complete their families. The fact that Asian families use these technologies to sire boys is completely suppressed. While clinic websites project availability and access as a race-neutral phenomenon, the news reports featuring these centers and calls to their information hotlines paint a different picture—one in which representatives grudgingly acknowledge that Asian couples are a huge consumer base that typically prefers boys. A 2006 UNICEF report finds India battling a highly skewed national gender ratio of 927 females for every 1,000 males—a drop from the 1991 figure of 945 females for every 1,000 males. Most of the calls to centers like The Fertility Institutes are from women. There is enormous pressure on women from their families and husbands to produce that baby boy who will continue the family name and be their future economic savior. "A lot of women who come to us for help tell us that the sex of their baby determines the security of their married life," says Atashi Chakravarty, who heads Narika, a Bay Area-based group that works to end domestic violence in the South Asian community. "Giving birth to a girl can many times accelerate the abuse and violence they experience from their husband or his family." A Worldwide Issue As profits of these U.S.-based clinics soar, several South Asian governments have become alarmed at the imbalanced gender ratios in India and China, where "son preference" is an established reality. A 2006 UNICEF report finds India battling a highly skewed national gender ratio of 927 females for every 1,000 males—a drop from the 1991 figure of 945 females for every 1,000 males. China is experiencing a similarly alarming imbalance that is compounded by its one-child-per-family policy. But this hasn't stopped the Genetics and IVF Institute from operating branches in Shanghai and Guangzhou since 1996. Numbers a[s]ide, the concerns of reproductive rights groups and activists worldwide focus on the ethics of gender selection. These concerns caused Canada, Australia and the United Kingdom to ban the use of reproductive technology for gender selection purposes. But in the United States, the clinics propagate it as free choice. As new technologies emerge that enable a booming middle class in South Asian countries to access them freely and guiltlessly, activists, community organizers and policymakers are recognizing the need to work across borders and boundaries. Source Citation: Shekar, Preeti. "Gender Selection Can in Some Cases Be Unethical." Reproductive Technology. Ed. Cindy Mur. San Diego: Greenhaven Press, 2005. At Issue. Rpt. from "Reproductive Racism: Gender Selection Technologies Target Asian Communities." Colorlines Magazine 10.5 (Sept.-Oct. 2007): 23-24. Gale Opposing Viewpoints In Context. Web. 9 Apr. 2012. Civil Rights Civil rights are the rights of all citizens to political and social freedom and equality. These include the right to vote and the right to be treated fairly by the legal system. In the United States intense battles have been waged over civil rights throughout the nation’s history, particularly since the end of the Civil War in 1865, when 4 million newly freed slaves suddenly found themselves in a nation that no longer considered them property but did not yet regard them as citizens. The End of Jim Crow The late nineteenth and early twentieth centuries were the worst periods of civil rights abuses in America, especially for minorities. In many Southern states, so-called Jim Crow laws were enacted by state legislatures that relegated African Americans to a second-class status. Based on the assumption that there should be two separate spheres of public life divided by race, the Jim Crow statutes mandated separate schools for black students, prevented the descendants of slaves from voting in elections by placing onerous restrictions on voter registration or required the payment of poll taxes, and banned interracial marriage. Railroad cars, public restrooms, and even drinking fountains were labeled "Colored" or "White." There were also unwritten rules. Owning too much property, being overly friendly with a white woman, or even attempting to exercise the right to vote were all violations of an unwritten Southern code that compelled blacks to "mind their place," as white Southerners put it. To challenge any of these laws or rules was to invite swift and harsh retribution. For decades African American males were targeted by local lynch mobs or more organized white-separatist groups like the Ku Klux Klan, which kidnapped them—sometimes at night, from their homes, in front of their families—and subjected them to mock trials and summary execution, usually by hanging. In other cases African Americans were tortured or their homes were burned to the ground. Lynchings persisted in some parts of the South well into the 1950s, but the integration of the U.S. armed forces at the end of World War II helped push the civil rights movement forward. The landmark 1954 U.S. Supreme Court case Brown v. Board of Education was another major milestone. In this case the Court ruled that separate-but-equal schools were unconstitutional. The official beginning of the civil rights movement in the United States, however, is often cited as the four-month period between August and December 1955. The late-summer lynching of a fourteen-year-old Chicago youth named Emmett Till, who was visiting relatives in Mississippi when he became the victim of mob justice, shocked the nation, especially when Jet magazine published a picture of the late teen in his coffin that showed his disfigured face. On December 1 Rosa Parks, a forty-two-year-old seamstress in Montgomery, Alabama, refused to comply with the city’s decades-old rules that governed public transportation. Blacks were supposed to sit in the rear seats on buses, and if the bus was full, they were required to give up their seats to whites and stand in the aisle. They also had to enter at the front, pay the fare, and if whites were present, exit and reenter through the rear door. Sometimes the driver left before a black passenger reentered. Parks was arrested for refusing to surrender her seat to a white passenger, and her case spurred a year-long boycott of the Montgomery city bus system that galvanized blacks across the South. The Montgomery boycott was followed by scores of sit-ins, strikes, and court challenges to repeal all discriminatory laws in the former slave states. The passage of the Civil Rights Act of 1964 was a pivotal event in U.S. history. It states in part, "all persons shall be entitled to the full and equal enjoyment of the goods, services, facilities, privileges, advantages, and accommodations of any place of public accommodation, as defined in this section, without discrimination or segregation on the ground of race, color, religion, or national origin or sex." A year later, Congress passed the National Voting Rights Act of 1965, which prohibited poll taxes, literacy tests, and other means by which local election commissions in many Southern states had prevented African Americans from exercising their right to vote. Rights Versus Liberties The term civil rights is sometimes used interchangeably with civil liberties. Both refer to the protections guaranteed to all Americans in the U.S. Constitution. Some of the most important civil liberties include the right to privacy, the right to trial by jury, and the right to due process and equal protection under the law. After the terrorist attacks on the United States on September 11, 2001, several new laws were enacted that have raised fears about the civil liberties of all Americans to be free of unwarranted intrusions into their private lives by the government. Several core tenets that have historically served to guarantee certain basic civil liberties that most Americans believed were inviolable were also repealed. The attacks on September 11th (9/11) and fears about national security were the basis for these new laws and strategies. The Patriot Act Just six weeks after 9/11, Congress approved the USA PATRIOT Act; its name is an acronym for "Uniting and Strengthening America by Providing Appropriate Tools Required to Intercept and Obstruct Terrorism." Several of its more controversial provisions give law-enforcement and intelligence-agency personnel unprecedented new powers. Conservative politicians who, twenty years earlier, had decried the "police state" mentality in Communist nations in comparison to the guarantees of "freedom" that defined America were now supporters of measures that breached the traditional system of checks and balances enshrined in the U.S. Constitution. For example, the Patriot Act allows for warrantless wiretaps; previously, law enforcement was required to submit an application to a judge and show probable cause if they wanted to tap a suspect’s telephone lines. The judge then reviewed the reasons and either approved or declined the request. National security letters (NSLs) are another investigative tool whose expanded use, like wiretapping, is sanctioned by the provisions of the Patriot Act. NSLs can be issued by Federal Bureau of Investigation (FBI) agents above a certain rank and do not require judicial approval. In 2005, concerns were raised about several thousand NSLs issued to casinos and other touristrelated businesses in Las Vegas, Nevada. It was not necessary for the FBI to demonstrate probable cause to compile information on credit-card transactions and even hospital visits, and there were fears about the compilation of a secret database that might be used in the future to embarrass potential political opponents. The city’s mayor, Oscar B. Goodman, told Business Week that NSLs were worrisome and certainly in direct contrast to the slogan used for the city’s national advertising campaign—"What Happens in Vegas Stays in Vegas." Referencing the fictional works of early-twentieth-century German writer Franz Kafka, who imagined a chilling totalitarian world, Goodman called the FBI’s tactics "Kafkaesque. The central component to our economy is privacy protection. People are here to have a good time and don’t want to worry about the government knowing their business." In the argument for national security, however, it is known that six of the 9/11 hijackers traveled to Las Vegas at least six times in the months before the attack. Intriguingly, they gambled, visited bars where exotic dancers simulated sexual acts on patrons, and drank alcohol, all of which are prohibited by their religion, Islam. The Real ID Act A national identity card was another aftereffect of 9/11. While U.S. drivers hold vehicleoperating licenses issued by their state, and overseas travelers are required to carry a federally issued passport, the idea of a national identity card had long been resisted as one of the hallmarks of a repressive society. Even in some European countries, a police officer can stop a citizen on the street and, for no reason, ask to see an internal passport or national ID document. Such tactics, however, are more commonly used in totalitarian regimes. Concerns about preventing future terrorist attacks led to the passage of the Real ID Act by Congress in 2005. It mandates that all states must issue redesigned driver’s licenses that meet new federal antiterrorist standards by May 2008. The act has been met with widespread resistance from the states, largely over cost and privacy concerns, and the deadline has been extended to May 2011. Civil-liberty watchdog groups have also raised concerns about biometric data collection. This refers to fingerprinting and iris scanning, used in conjunction with photographs, to prevent ID theft. Even though several of the 9/11 hijackers had been identified as potential terrorists, they were allowed to board planes because they used false identities or state-issued drivers’ licenses that were not part of the antiterrorism database. Advocates for increased security measures note that had those measures been in place on the morning of 9/11, the nineteen men would not have been allowed to board their planes. Nature Bestows, Not Governments Some critics argue that the recent erosion of civil rights in the United States supports the idea that al Qaeda—the Islamic militant group behind the 9/11 attacks—actually did gain a significant advantage by their act: a democratic society willingly handing over its prized personal freedoms to the government. In 1774, future president Thomas Jefferson wrote A Summary View of the Rights of British America, a blistering attack on abuses perpetrated by England’s King George III on the thirteen colonies in the New World. He warned the monarch that "a free people [claim] their rights as derived from the laws of nature, and not as the gift of their chief magistrate." Source Citation: "Civil Rights." Current Issues: Macmillan Social Science Library. Detroit: Gale, 2010. Gale Opposing Viewpoints In Context. Web. 9 Apr. 2012. Ethnic and Religious Profiling Is Necessary "There is nothing intrinsically wrong with profiling. Some people, quite simply, pose greater security risks than others." Carl F. Horowitz is the director of the Organized Labor Accountability Project of the National Legal and Policy Center in Fall Church, Virginia. In the following viewpoint, Horowitz asserts that racial and religious profiling is a necessary defense against terrorism in a post-September 11, 2001, world. Horowitz argues that Muslim extremists commit the vast majority of terrorist acts against the United States in subterfuge, so their movements and activities in the country must be scrutinized. Increased surveillance of suspicious Muslims—which was enabled through the Patriot Act—have stifled terrorist activity and prevented potential attacks without violating civil liberties, he claims. As you read, consider the following questions: 1. As stated by Horowitz, what has eroded national identity and security? 2. How does Horowitz use the example of Muhammad al-Qahtani to support his argument for profiling Muslims in the United States? 3. How does the author describe "fourth-generation warfare"? Good evening. I'd like to thank the Robert A. Taft Club for giving me the opportunity to speak on an incendiary subject: ethnic and religious profiling as an anti-terrorism strategy. Some people, on the Right as well as the Left, believe that examining movement into and within the U.S. by Muslims, especially Arab Muslims, is irreconcilable with preserving basic civil liberties. With all due respect, I happen to reject that view. There is no reason to believe that a policy of vetting individuals who belong to the ethno-religious entity responsible for most of the terrorism against this country harms law-abiding citizens. Toward that end, I offer a defense of ethnic and religious profiling, and one of its primary tools, the USA Patriot Act. Profiling: Workable and Necessary National identity and security now more than ever go together. The terror attacks against the World Trade Center and the Pentagon [in 2001] were the result of decades of erosion of our national identity and national security. They were the result of a comfortable self-delusion that all ethnic, national and religious groups want to be, and are equally capable of being, Americanized. It's as if entry into this country is an act of de facto patriotism. The reality, of course, is that many people come to this country with every intention of conquering us, or at any rate, flouting our laws. More invaders than immigrants, such people live in a state of infantile wish-fulfillment that equates mass murder and religious obligation. And they have a rather nasty tendency to be Muslims, especially from the Middle East. Now unlike certain misguided "patriots," I regard as poisonous the psychology of Battered American Syndrome. This is the famous we-got-what-was-coming-to-us argument. The 9/11 [September 11, 2001] terror attacks, we are told incessantly, constituted "blowback," just desserts for our gratuitous meddling in the Middle East. This is anti-Americanism, whether it comes from the Right or the Left. It certainly is inadequate to the task of understanding the nature of our terrorist enemies. It is true that most Muslims living in this country, not to mention those who plan to come, are not terrorists by any stretch. But a good many are the kind who would give terrorists aid, comfort and applause. And as we all know now, it only takes a few dozen terrorists to inflict nationwide mayhem. Back when our immigration policy really functioned—that is to say, prior to the 1965 amendments to the Immigration and Nationality Act—virtually none of these people, even the sympathizers, would have gotten into the U.S. That leads to a governing principle. To stand an old expression on its head, the best offense is a good defense. About 175 years ago [military strategist] Carl von Clausewitz put it this way: Defense is simply the stronger form of war, the one that makes the enemy's defeat more certain ... We maintain unequivocally that the form of warfare we call defense not only offers greater probability of victory than attack, but that its victories can attain the same proportions and results. Profiling Based on a Statistical Fact In today's context, on a practical level, that means that the movement, conversations and other behavior of Muslims, whether native-born or foreign-born, need to be scrutinized, monitored and analyzed—in a word, profiled. In all likelihood, they are not radical anti-Americans. Yet on the other hand, they just might be. And unlike mere dissenters, these people are at war with us. That is the underlying reality of the cliche, "the post-9/11 environment." It is a statistical fact: A young Muslim man is tens of thousands of times more likely than anyone else in the world to commit an act of terrorism. He should be profiled. Consider the following scenario: I am an airport security inspector. A young Middle Eastern man or women walks up to my checkpoint. Would I be inclined to ask (or have another person ask) this passenger some extra questions about his background and beliefs before I let him through? You bet I would. Equally to the point, I'm not going to give extra attention to persons who don't look Middle Eastern or display outward signs of Islamic belief. To ask extra questions of each and every passenger, on a practical basis, would be a logistical disaster. Taking such inconvenience to its extreme, almost nobody would choose to fly. There is nothing intrinsically wrong with profiling. Some people, quite simply, pose greater security risks than others. Membership in a particular ethnic or religious group is a valid marker for assuming and judging unobserved behavioral traits in another person, especially when we have no other information to go on at that moment in time. To insist otherwise is to not live in the real world. Can profiling produce results? Purer-than-thou libertarians insist the U.S. government is incapable of defending us from terrorists. I say baloney. When federal law enforcement is allowed to do what local cops long have been able to do—monitor, question and detain criminal suspects based on observable physical traits—they can catch terrorists planning their misdeeds. And they have caught them, despite pressure from supervisors to look the other way.... In August 2001, a month before the 9/11 attacks, a certain Muhammad al-Qahtani, a Saudi, was turned away from this country while attempting to enter the U.S. at Orlando International Airport. Customs officer Jose Melendez-Perez understood the real requirements of his job rather than the bureaucratically mandated requirements. Though he'd been warned by his superiors against racial profiling of Arabs, he responded, "I don't care. This guy's a bad guy. I can see it in his eyes." Officer Melendez-Perez was right. There was something in this guy's eyes. As al-Qahtani was being led off, he turned around and announced, "I'll be back." He kept his word, though under unplanned circumstances. Qahtani was identified as the would-be 20th hijacker. In the recent trial of Zacarias Moussaoui, it had come out that 9/11 mastermind Khalid Shaikh Muhammad had pointed to al-Qahtani as the hijacker who would "complete the group." His assignment: United Flight 93, the one that crashed in rural Pennsylvania, now the subject of a splendid new movie, a suicide hijacking mission whose intended target, based on all available evidence, was either the White House or the U.S. Capitol. The three other planes each had five hijackers; Flight 93 had only four. That fact might have been why the latter's passengers were able to overpower the terrorists. Our armed forces in Afghanistan, by the way, managed to track Qahtani down. He's now reportedly a resident of Guantanamo Bay prison.... Yet the [George W.] Bush administration has learned little. Federal officials, if anything, appear more frightened of offending the sensibilities of Islamic and Arab "civil-rights" groups than going the extra mile to track down and arrest the most dangerous criminals in the world. On June 17, 2003, acting on the stern advice of President Bush, the Department of Justice [DOJ] ordered a total ban on racial and ethnic profiling at dozens of federal agencies. The DOJ guidelines directly affected around 120,000 law enforcement officers at the FBI, the DEA [Drug Enforcement Agency], the Department of Homeland Security, ATF [Bureau of Alcohol, Tobacco, Firearms, and Explosives], the Coast Guard and elsewhere.... The Patriot Act Reconsidered The case for profiling, put simply, is far stronger than the case against it. Whether the USA Patriot Act is an appropriate vehicle for profiling is a separate issue. Let us go into a bit of detail. This legislation, officially known as the Uniting and Strengthening America by Providing Appropriate Tools Required to Intercept and Obstruct Terrorism Act, does not formally authorize profiling persons on ethnic, racial or religious grounds. Yet given its overwhelming passage in the House and the Senate in October 2001, only weeks after the 9/11 atrocities, the context was the danger posed by this country's current and future Islamic population. By giving law enforcement extra tools of surveillance, infiltration and arrest, and by breaking down the traditional information-sharing firewall between enforcement and intelligence agencies, the Patriot Act was meant to root out Muslim terrorists before they attack. Congress, after a lengthy and contentious debate, reauthorized the act in March 2006. The law is needed, quite simply, because the enemy gives us no choice. Their mode of operation, to use military strategist William Lind's term, is "fourth-generation warfare." In this form of combat, subterfuge is everything. The Islamic terrorist radicals are masters of deception as well as destruction. Consider that: ï‚· ï‚· ï‚· ï‚· ï‚· ï‚· They don't have a national capital and, with the exception of the Chechen thugs, are in no sense nationalists. They don't have tanks, uniforms, infantry or battle formations. They don't seek summit meetings or peace talks, since they don't want to be found. They frequently change their laptop computers and cell phones to minimize detection of messages they send to each other. They use fake IDs, not exactly impossible to come by these days. They heavily recruit inside mosques, which our government apparently deems off-limits for infiltration. These people live, breathe and think war 24 hours a day. And as long as they are outnumbered and outgunned, at least here in the United States, they will plan terrorist acts with the utmost of guile. That is why we must use every available tool of infiltration, including the roving wiretaps authorized by the Patriot Act. Without those wiretaps, it would be far more difficult, absent random luck, to gather evidence of a pending attack. But hasn't the Act severely diminished our civil liberties? Critics who make this point, from [journalist] Alexander Cockburn (Left) to [libertarian] James Bovard (Right), typically denounce the law in terms of what it would do or might do. You'll notice, interestingly, that their broadsides aren't in the past tense—as in "has done." That's because there's no hard evidence— even anecdotal, much less systematic—that our liberties have been violated. A couple years ago Sen. Dianne Feinstein (D-CA) responded to a request by the ACLU [American Civil Liberties Union] to monitor the use of the Patriot Act. Her response: "We've scrubbed the area, and I have no reported abuses." This finding should not come as a surprise. The law was written to set a very high bar of proof for a judge to issue a search warrant, wiretap authorization, or some other surveillance tool. It also authorized the creation of a civil liberties board, overseen by Congress, to ensure compliance with existing laws that protect innocent citizens. Here's what the law has done. It has brought terrorism-related charges against at least 400 people, many of whom are in this country illegally; more than half those charges have led to convictions. It has broken up confirmed terror cells in New York, Oregon, Virginia, and Florida. Through its information-sharing features, for example, it has led to the arrest of a Kashmir-born Islamic fundamentalist (and naturalized U.S. citizen) from Columbus, Ohio, Iyman Faris, who had been supplying al-Qaeda with information on how to blow up New York City's Brooklyn Bridge. Terrorists continue to strike—very recently in Israel and Egypt, and [summer 2005] in London, murdering dozens of innocent people. But they haven't done anything in America since the 9/11 attacks and the anthrax letter attacks (also likely the work of Islamic extremists) in their immediate wake. It strains the imagination to suggest the Patriot Act has had nothing to do with the lack of attacks on our soil since 2001. If the Committee on American Islamic Relations, the ACLU and convicted lawyer Lynne Stewart are enraged over the law's "insensitivity" toward Muslims, that should be of no concern to anyone with patriotic instincts. Conclusion: The Necessity of Scrutiny To sum up, there are two separate issues at hand: First, should profiling be used to prevent terrorism? Second, should the USA Patriot Act serve as a means of prevention? The answer in both cases is "yes." As for the first consideration, there are inherent legal and political risks in profiling. No matter how good the information, every cop runs the risk of questioning, frisking, or arresting the wrong person. As for the second, while the Patriot Act may require amending, that's a far cry from repeal. The Patriot Act has shown it is capable of protecting us from Islamic terrorists, without violating basic liberties. It is mild stuff, really. Unlike during World War II, for example, we don't have rationing, rent control, endless war bond appeals, film and newspaper censorship, draft registration, and other intrusive demands by the State for collective sacrifice. This is all to the good. But until Muslims, the world over, cease in any way to take part in, or endorse, the mass murder of Americans, I shall willingly put up with the Patriot Act's rather negligible excesses. The long-range goal of America—and the rest of the West—should be defusing Islamic aggression. Since this isn't about to happen anytime soon, we should focus on self-defense. The necessity of deploying troops in the Middle East, and risking more of our men coming home in body bags, is open to debate. The necessity of scrutinizing people who share ethnic and religious traits of our avowed enemies should not be. In the end, America is our country to defend. And this Northern paleoconservative is willing to defend it. Thank you very much. Source Citation: Horowitz, Carl F. "Ethnic and Religious Profiling Is Necessary." Civil Liberties. Ed. Auriana Ojeda. San Diego: Greenhaven Press, 2004. Opposing Viewpoints. Rpt. from "Profiling in an Age of Terrorism." Social Contract 17 (Fall 2006): 47-51. Gale Opposing Viewpoints In Context. Web. 9 Apr. 2012. Ethnic and Religious Profiling Violates Civil Liberties "The war on terrorism has lent profiling the veneer of legitimacy...." In the following viewpoint, Chisun Lee contends that ethnic and religious profiling in the wake of the September 11, 2001, terrorist attacks has rolled back civil rights. Lee insists that terrorist profiling of Muslims is the same as discriminatory profiling of African Americans and Latinos. Lee contends that thousands of innocent Arab, Muslim, and South Asian immigrants have been disproportionately rounded up and jailed for minor infractions without resulting in any terrorist charges. Ultimately, the author warns that such government bias and intrusion opens the door to sweeping discrimination against individuals belonging to these groups. Lee is a contributing writer to the Village Voice. As you read, consider the following questions: 1. Why does the author insist that a major civil rights victory nearly occurred in 2000? 2. What "technical infractions" were immigrants profiled for terrorism jailed for, in Lee's view? 3. According to Lee, what is the state of profiling for African Americans and Latinos? Four years ago [2000] the nation stood at the cusp of a major civil rights victory. Activists from across the country rallied in Washington, D.C., to end racial profiling. Polls showed a majority of Americans opposed the practice. Al Gore vowed that as president he would make a law banning it, "the first civil rights act of the 21st century." George W. Bush agreed with his opponent. "I can't imagine what it would be like to be singled out because of race and stopped and harassed," he said during one 2000 debate. "That's just flat wrong." Then he did Gore one better: "There is other forms of racial profiling that goes on in America. Arab Americans are racially profiled.... People are stopped, and we got to do something about that." But today his administration's reaction to the 2001 terrorist attacks has not only betrayed Bush's own rhetoric, but worse, it has undermined the political force of the anti-profiling movement in general—the force that made it a profound civil rights cause, not just a policy debate. By couching group-based profiling as necessary to homeland security, the government has traded the principles of universal equality and individual dignity for the presumption of safety. Nearly no one this election year [2004] has been bold enough to hint at the outrage that once powered a bipartisan movement. It has become impossible to be righteous about racial profiling without encountering the inevitable "But what about 9-11?" What about it? Three years out, the question demands more than a knee-jerk nod. A thoughtful look will show that the terrorist attacks did not make such profiling any less wrong than it was on September 10, 2001. In fact, it is all the more insidious today, because the war on terrorism has lent profiling the veneer of legitimacy—even urgency, after alerts such as the one regarding financial centers last weekend [July 2004]. As this modern civil rights movement begins to put itself back together, with a renewed push for federal legislation, it is important to realize that racial profiling has not gotten any less wrong—the government is just more willing to do the wrong thing. And to be willing to do the wrong thing is a devastating rejection of the values of American life. One and the Same "Racial profiling is being stopped driving while black or driving while Hispanic. This is not racial profiling," said Mark Corallo, spokesperson for the Department of Justice, when asked about the administration's 9-11-related operations. He voiced precisely the kind of thinking that has obscured the crisis of profiling for the past three years. Trawling for terrorists and pulling over motorists in search of drugs are in fact the same thing. While it may be acceptable to target people based on a racial or ethnic description if—and only if—there is some specific indication that those particular people are actually criminals, broad sweeps based on general traits are never OK. Not only are they unlikely to yield "hits" and certain to humiliate innocent parties, but such dragnets also violate this nation's fundamental principle that people will be treated as individuals and not according to stereotypes. "You either have racial profiling, or you don't have racial profiling. You can't have it both ways," says LaShawn Warren, a leader in pushing for passage of the End Racial Profiling Act of 2004, currently a bill with support from 124 members of the House and 16 of the Senate. As a national legislative counsel for the American Civil Liberties Union, she has been struggling to show Congress members that FBI questioning and immigration roundups of people who appear to be Arab or Muslim—whatever that looks like—are "no different than the old kind of racial profiling that we said was wrong." There is little wonder that some people refuse to believe her. The Bush administration has led the way. In his long-promised racial profiling ban, announced with great fanfare in June 2003, Bush told federal law-enforcement agencies that "racial profiling is wrong and will not be tolerated" and that "stereotyping certain races as having a greater propensity to commit crimes is absolutely prohibited." (The directive, which is not a law, lacks any enforcement mechanism, so the prohibition is absolute only in theory.) But he created a crippling exception: "The above standards do not affect current federal policy with respect to law enforcement activities and other efforts to defend and safeguard against threats to national security." In effect, that "national security" loophole has become the exception that would erase the rule. Like a political ray gun, it neutralizes any critic who would cry racism or xenophobia [fear of foreigners] when it comes to 9-11-related profiling. Corallo pointed out, "There were 19 hijackers who were from an Islamic background." Certainly it makes sense to hunt for people like them—but like them how? There was once a time when people defended the "driving while black" variety of profiling, because searching certain minorities for drugs was said to make sense. But as public indignation mounted over the years, the U.S. Customs Service, for example, scaled back its profiling and turned to behavior- and intelligence-based investigations instead. Drug-runner apprehensions more than doubled. This administration has not scored big points for its investigative depth. Nevertheless, it "outright rejects" allegations that it engages in broad, stereotype-based profiling, Corallo said. "I understand what they're saying when they feel there's a focus on them," he said of Arab, Muslim, and South Asian immigrants and citizens who complain of biased treatment, "but there's not." Maybe it depends on how one defines "focus." Pervasive Pattern Tens of thousands of people from Muslim, Arab, and South Asian backgrounds have been targeted by the government in a slew of sweeps since 9-11. Teenage boys and men from 25 predominantly Muslim countries, none accused of any crime, at one point were ordered to report to immigration offices for questioning and fingerprinting, or risk arrest and deportation. By the end of the "special registration," over 82,000 individuals had complied and over 13,000 were slated for deportation as a result. The FBI initiated two official rounds of interviews it called "voluntary" with some 8,000 immigrants and citizens of Arab, Muslim, and South Asian backgrounds. Community advocates claim that agents show up unannounced all the time—although Corallo said, "People are not getting knocks on the door and questioned." In everyday encounters with local police, coworkers, and neighbors, thousands more have been reported to authorities and detained, according to these advocacy groups. The Justice Department's own internal watchdog revealed in 2003 that scores of immigrants experienced physical abuse or due process violations while in government custody. No matter that exactly zero terrorism-related charges have emerged from these initiatives, and that all the high-profile cases have resulted from real investigative work or pure accident. (From Timothy McVeigh to John Walker Lindh, the most infamous national security threats do not fit the Arab terrorist profile at all.) The roundups continue, according to weekly e-mail updates among immigration lawyers and advocates. Well, these are immigrants, one argument goes. They're not supposed to be here in the first place, and they don't enjoy the same rights as citizens. Corallo claims that border control has "stopped 12 known terrorists from getting into the country. We also caught hundreds of convicted felons." (The Voice could find no mention of these figures, outside of Corallo's comment.) The vast majority jailed as a result of the immigration crackdowns are, in fact, guilty of something—although almost universally of technical infractions like staying past a visa deadline or not taking enough class credits to fulfill the student-visitor requirements. Putting aside the important debate about whether prolonged detention is the right response to a paperwork problem, these folks technically are subject to monitoring by the U.S. government. Yet this monitoring has hardly been equally applied. "They weren't calling in immigrants from Great Britain," the ACLU's Warren points out. "There's a really unjustifiable distinction being made." That distinction is where 9-11-related profiling and the more traditional notion of racial profiling meet. That distinction is stereotype. Whether based on race, religion, or national origin, the special burden of a profiled person is being plagued by negative assumptions tagged to his or her "type." The result of such profiling is not just indignation but rank inequality. Says Leti Volpp, author of a widely cited 2002 law article entitled "The Citizen and the Terrorist," "Being a citizen means enjoying all the rights of a citizen. But 'driving while black' was a sign that African Americans could only enjoy second-class citizen-ship." She explains that people who are perceived to be Arab or Muslim face the same injustice. Instead of the right to be considered innocent until proven guilty, for instance, they "have to prove themselves innocent." Just last week [July 2004] it emerged that the Census Bureau had given detailed location and national-origin data on Arab Americans—U.S. citizens—to the Department of Homeland Security [DHS]. DHS claimed it wanted the information in order to post Arabic language signs in the right airports. But as the news shot around civil rights listservs, people recalled how census data was used during World War II to identify Japanese Americans who would be sent to U.S. internment camps. Though the administration may deny it, former federal appellate judge Timothy Lewis, who was appointed to the Third Circuit by the first President George Bush, insists that there has been a widespread pattern of unjustified profiling by the government since 9-11. He agreed to chair a series of national public hearings on "war on drugs" and "war on terror" profiling last year for Amnesty International USA, only after the organization agreed to invite law enforcement representatives for fairness's sake. "What struck me more than anything was the pervasiveness of the practice," said Lewis, who was also once a federal prosecutor and is now of counsel at Schnader Harrison Segal & Lewis in Washington, D.C. "I'm talking about going after people without any criminal predicate. Racial profiling is a national phenomenon. And the hearings barely scratched the surface." The profiling of blacks and Latinos continues to thrive, even as the once robust opposition to it has deflated "in the frenzied atmosphere after 9-11," as Lewis put it. From Massachusetts to Missouri to Texas, studies as recent as this May [2004] showed that minorities were still disproportionately—in one state as much as 40 percent more often—subjected to traffic stops, at rates unjustified by their actual record of possessing drugs. In one egregious situation, police in Charlottesville, Virginia, indiscriminately demanded DNA samples from area black men in their hunt for a serial rapist. The dragnet continued for over two years before public scrutiny this spring finally convinced authorities to stop. Private Hate, Public Problem For 9-11-related-profiling victims, the element of "foreignness" gives discrimination a special twist, says Volpp. "People who look a certain way are assumed not to be citizens to begin with," but rather unwelcome outsiders, she says. That perception makes them especially vulnerable, not just to government intrusions but to private acts of violence. Over a thousand 9-11-related bias incidents, including harassment and physical attacks, have been recorded since 2001 by groups such as the Council on American-Islamic Relations and the Sikh Coalition, and by the Justice Department's Civil Rights Division. They have included assaults, arson, and even killings. And those are just the incidents that have been reported by people confident or informed enough to seek out these resources. Official profiling and private bias are connected, says Muneer Ahmad, an associate professor at American University Law School. Although no one can legislate away personal prejudices, he says, "The government sends signals and cues all the time as to what is permissible. The end of racially discriminatory laws against African Americans didn't translate instantly into substantive equality. But when the government said segregation was okay, it was communicating a lot about what was appropriate. It's one thing for racial prejudice to be a part of society, but you provide people license to engage in that kind of behavior if you don't have a policy that condemns it." The federal government has vigorously prosecuted some hate crimes, for example one in which a Sikh postal carrier in California was shot in the neck with a pellet rifle. And President Bush has repeatedly admonished the nation not to engage in bias against Muslims and Arabs. But Ahmad says those statements must be juxtaposed with the official profiling of people from certain backgrounds. "Condemning the private violence gives the administration political cover. If you morally condemn something, you elevate yourself." Racial profiling can only be eradicated by a renewed social movement that exposes and opposes it. Politicians can't be trusted to buck 9-11 politics and challenge the practice on their own, without strong popular support, since they fear being labeled soft on terror. And profiling victims have almost never found justice in the courts, since judges are notoriously reluctant to apply the Constitution's equal treatment mandate in a way that might interfere with police discretion. Indeed, President Bush was oddly prescient when he said in 2000, "Racial profiling isn't just an issue with local police forces. It's an issue throughout our society. And as we become a diverse society, we're going to have to deal with it more and more." He couldn't have known how much more urgent that message would become after four years of his leadership. But at this moment when reasonable fears of terrorism too often find expression in unreasonable fears of certain people, and the government flatly denies that it is part of the prejudice problem, only a broad social movement can achieve the civil rights victory that seemed so possible four years ago. The effort to end racial profiling is part of the ongoing struggle to make the American dream of equality and dignity come true for everyone. Source Citation: Lee, Chisun. "Ethnic and Religious Profiling Violates Civil Liberties." Civil Liberties. Ed. Auriana Ojeda. San Diego: Greenhaven Press, 2004. Opposing Viewpoints. Rpt. from "Civil Rights Rollback." Village Voice 27 July 2004. Gale Opposing Viewpoints In Context. Web. 9 Apr. 2012. Alcoholism Long-term heavy drinking can lead to alcohol addiction and a condition known as alcoholism, a disease in which the effects of drinking alcohol become worse over time. Alcohol addiction involves a physical and psychological dependence or need for alcohol. When a person addicted to alcohol stops drinking, he or she often experiences withdrawal, a series of symptoms that may include tremors, vomiting, and convulsions. Hazards of Alcohol The abuse of alcohol is very costly to society. In the United States, alcohol-related diseases, accidents, lost time from work, and rehabilitation cost billions of dollars each year. The Centers for Disease Control and Prevention (CDC) estimated there were 75,766 alcohol-related deaths in 2001. In addition to its role in about 39 percent of all motor vehicle fatalties in 2005, alcohol abuse also contributes to injuries and deaths from falls, drowning, fires, and violence, and more recent studies show that alcohol-related deaths are on the rise. According to a report published June 26, 2009, in The Lancet, one in twenty-five deaths worldwide is the result of alcohol. Effects on Physical Abilities and Health Alcohol is a depressant, which means that it slows the functioning of all the organs in the central nervous system, including the brain. The intensity of the effects caused by alcohol depends on the concentration of alcohol in the blood, a measurement known as the blood alcohol content (BAC) or blood alcohol level (BAL). BAC is determined using a person's body weight. For example, a 150-pound man who consumes four drinks in an hour will have a BAC of 0.10 percent. The higher the BAC, the greater the level of intoxication, or drunkenness. At 0.25 percent BAC (about ten drinks in one hour) the man would be extremely drunk, and at 0.40 percent BAC he would lose consciousness. Both acute (short-term) and chronic (long-term) use of alcohol pose great risks to individuals. Acute intoxication stops the brain from functioning normally, leading to slurred speech, loss of coordination, and impaired judgment. Acute intoxication can also cause vomiting and a hangover, a condition that includes headache and nausea. By impairing judgment and coordination, both acute and chronic heavy drinking increase the risk of injury or death from motor vehicle collisions, falls, or other accidents. In the United States and many other countries, efforts to reduce alcohol-related motor vehicle accidents have resulted in various laws against drunk driving. In most U.S. states, operating a motor vehicle with a BAC between 0.08 percent and 0.10 percent is a crime, and the driver may be arrested for driving under the influence (DUI) or for driving while intoxicated (DWI). While in most states there is no difference between a DUI and DWI, in some states a DWI means the driver had a higher level of intoxication and may receive a stiffer penalty. In addition to these problems, chronic alcohol use can lead to serious health problems, including certain types of ulcers, high blood pressure, heart disease, and stroke. Because alcohol is metabolized, or processed, by the liver, heavy drinkers are also at risk for cirrhosis, hepatitis, cancer, and other diseases of the liver. Between 10 and 20 percent of heavy drinkers develop cirrhosis, which ranks among the leading causes of death in the United States. In addition, chronic alcohol use can damage the central nervous system, leading to problems in brain function, such as memory loss, impaired learning ability, and general disorientation. Symptoms of Alcoholism Screening for Mental Health, an organization that conducts large-scale mental health screenings, differentiates between alcohol abuse and alcohol dependence, or alcoholism. They explain that "alcohol abuse is characterized by clinically significant impairment or distress but does not include physical dependence," whereas alcoholism "is characterized by 10 diagnostic criteria according to the DSM-IV." The Diagnostic and Statistical Manual (DSM) criteria for alcoholism include: withdrawal symptoms when one stops drinking, tolerance to alcohol, and continued drinking even after one experiences alcohol-related problems. Approximately 8.5 percent of Americans meet the criteria of either alcohol abuse or alcoholism. Cause of Alcoholism There are two basic views about the cause of alcoholism and the nature of drinking problems. Some people believe that those who drink heavily do so because they lack good character or selfcontrol. Others, however, argue that alcoholism is a disease or physical disorder, possibly linked to certain genetic factors that make some people particularly susceptible. Critics of the alcoholism-as-a-disease theory argue that the research is not really scientific. They doubt that the alcoholic has an irresistible craving for alcohol and that the condition gets worse with time. They also challenge the notion that alcoholism is incurable and that some alcoholics can never return to moderate drinking. The modern notion of alcoholism as a disease gained acceptance mostly on humanitarian grounds rather than on the basis of scientific evidence. Viewing alcoholics as sick people helped overcome the idea that such people were immoral. This led, in turn, to greater compassion for alcoholics and support for treatment rather than blame for the drinker. Alcoholics Anonymous One leading approach to overcoming alcoholism is a program called Alcoholics Anonymous (AA), based on connecting alcoholics with recovered alcoholics. Founded in the United States in 1935, Alcoholics Anonymous views alcoholism as an incurable physical and mental illness. The program provides a system of twelve steps that encourage alcoholics to admit their faults, make amends to people they have hurt, and help other alcoholics become sober. A central idea of the AA approach is the alcoholic's decision to stay away from alcohol "one day at a time." The AA program considers recovery a lifelong process requiring constant vigilance and regular attendance at the organization's meetings. Although it is difficult to know the exact number of groups because not all are registered, there were an estimated 53,665 AA groups in 2009, and worldwide membership was estimated at nearly 2 million. At AA meetings, members share their experiences as a way of providing hope and strength to others struggling with alcoholism. Alcoholics Anonymous has been quite successful at reaching people with drinking problems, but the great majority of alcoholics remain untreated. Many people are critical of AA because the organization rejects other types of treatment, such as changing behavior or attempting to control drinking rather than stopping it completely. Meanwhile, those in favor of controlled drinking have been sharply criticized by AA for even suggesting an alternative to complete abstinence. Others are critical of AA's assumption that alcoholics are powerless against alcohol and must submit to a "higher power." These critics consider this idea self-defeating and a sign of helplessness. Instead, they prefer to emphasize alcoholics' ability to use reason in choosing abstinence and adopting values that support a sober lifestyle Source Citation: "Alcoholism." Current Issues: Macmillan Social Science Library. Detroit: Gale, 2010. Gale Opposing Viewpoints In Context. Web. 9 Apr. 2012. Early Alcohol Consumption Puts Youth at Risk The National Institute on Alcohol Abuse and Alcoholism of the National Institutes of Health provides leadership in the national effort to reduce alcohol-related problems. Despite a minimum legal drinking age of 21, many young people in the United States consume alcohol. Some abuse alcohol by drinking frequently or by binge drinking—often defined as having five or more drinks in a row. The progression of drinking from use to abuse to dependence is associated with biological and psychosocial factors. This Alcohol Alert bulletin examines some of these factors that put youth at risk for drinking and for alcohol-related problems and considers some of the consequences of their drinking. Prevalence of Youth Drinking Thirteen- to fifteen-year-olds are at high risk to begin drinking. According to results of an annual survey of students in 8th, 10th, and 12th grades, 26 percent of 8th graders, 40 percent of 10th graders, and 51 percent of 12th graders reported drinking alcohol within the past month. Binge drinking at least once during the 2 weeks before the survey was reported by 16 percent of 8th graders, 25 percent of 10th graders, and 30 percent of 12th graders. Males report higher rates of daily drinking and binge drinking than females, but these differences are diminishing. White students report the highest levels of drinking, blacks report the lowest, and Hispanics fall between the two. A survey focusing on the alcohol-related problems experienced by 4,390 high school seniors and dropouts found that within the preceding year, approximately 80 percent reported either getting "drunk," binge drinking, or drinking and driving. More than half said that drinking had caused them to feel sick, miss school or work, get arrested, or have a car crash. Some adolescents who drink later abuse alcohol and may develop alcoholism. Although these conditions are defined for adults in the DSM [Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders], research suggests that separate diagnostic criteria may be needed for youth. While drinking may be a singular problem behavior for some, research suggests that for others it may be an expression of general adolescent turmoil that includes other problem behaviors. Drinking and Adolescent Development While drinking may be a singular problem behavior for some, research suggests that for others it may be an expression of general adolescent turmoil that includes other problem behaviors and that these behaviors are linked to unconventionality, impulsiveness, and sensation seeking. Binge drinking, often beginning around age 13, tends to increase during adolescence, peak in young adulthood (ages 18-22), then gradually decrease. In a 1994 national survey, binge drinking was reported by 28 percent of high school seniors, 41 percent of 21- to 22-year-olds, but only 25 percent of 31- to 32-year-olds. Individuals who increase their binge drinking from age 18 to 24 and those who consistently binge drink at least once a week during this period may have problems attaining the goals typical of the transition from adolescence to young adulthood (e.g., marriage, educational attainment, employment, and financial independence). Risk Factors for Adolescent Alcohol Use, Abuse, and Dependence Genetic Risk Factors. Animal studies and studies of twins and adoptees demonstrate that genetic factors influence an individual's vulnerability to alcoholism. Children of alcoholics are significantly more likely than children of nonalcoholics to initiate drinking during adolescence and to develop alcoholism, but the relative influences of environment and genetics have not been determined and vary among people. Biological Markers. Brain waves elicited in response to specific stimuli (e.g., a light or sound) provide measures of brain activity that predict risk for alcoholism. P300, a wave that occurs about 300 milliseconds after a stimulus, is most frequently used in this research. A low P300 amplitude has been demonstrated in individuals with increased risk for alcoholism, especially sons of alcoholic fathers. P300 measures among 36 preadolescent boys were able to predict alcohol and other drug (AOD) use 4 years later, at an average age of 16. Childhood Behavior. Children classified as "undercontrolled" (i.e., impulsive, restless, and distractible) at age 3 were twice as likely as those who were "inhibited" or "well-adjusted" to be diagnosed with alcohol dependence at age 21. Aggressiveness in children as young as ages 5-10 has been found to predict AOD use in adolescence. Childhood antisocial behavior is associated with alcohol-related problems in adolescence (24-27) and alcohol abuse or dependence in adulthood. Psychiatric Disorders. Among 12- to 16-year-olds, regular alcohol use has been significantly associated with conduct disorder; in one study, adolescents who reported higher levels of drinking were more likely to have conduct disorder. Six-year-old to seventeen-year-old boys with attention deficit hyperactivity disorder (ADHD) who were also found to have weak social relationships had significantly higher rates of alcohol abuse and dependence 4 years later, compared with ADHD boys without social deficiencies and boys without ADHD. Whether anxiety and depression lead to or are consequences of alcohol abuse is unresolved. In a study of college freshmen, a DSM-III diagnosis of alcohol abuse or dependence was twice as likely among those with anxiety disorder as those without this disorder. In another study, college students diagnosed with alcohol abuse were almost four times as likely as students without alcohol abuse to have a major depressive disorder. In most of these cases, depression preceded alcohol abuse. In a study of adolescents in residential treatment for AOD dependence, 25 percent met the DSM-III-R criteria for depression, three times the rate reported for controls. In 43 percent of these cases, the onset of AOD dependence preceded the depression; in 35 percent, the depression occurred first; and in 22 percent, the disorders occurred simultaneously. Suicidal Behavior. Alcohol use among adolescents has been associated with considering, planning, attempting, and completing suicide. In one study, 37 percent of eighth-grade females who drank heavily reported attempting suicide, compared with 11 percent who did not drink. Research does not indicate whether drinking causes suicidal behavior, only that the two behaviors are correlated. Parents' drinking behavior and favorable attitudes about drinking have been positively associated with adolescents' initiating and continuing drinking. Psychosocial Risk Factors Parenting, Family Environment, and Peers. Parents' drinking behavior and favorable attitudes about drinking have been positively associated with adolescents' initiating and continuing drinking. Early initiation of drinking has been identified as an important risk factor for later alcohol-related problems. Children who were warned about alcohol by their parents and children who reported being closer to their parents were less likely to start drinking. Lack of parental support, monitoring, and communication have been significantly related to frequency of drinking, heavy drinking, and drunkenness among adolescents. Harsh, inconsistent discipline and hostility or rejection toward children have also been found to significantly predict adolescent drinking and alcohol-related problems. Peer drinking and peer acceptance of drinking have been associated with adolescent drinking. While both peer influences and parental influences are important, their relative impact on adolescent drinking is unclear. Expectancies. Positive alcohol-related expectancies have been identified as risk factors for adolescent drinking. Positive expectancies about alcohol have been found to increase with age (50) and to predict the onset of drinking and problem drinking among adolescents. Trauma. Child abuse and other traumas have been proposed as risk factors for subsequent alcohol problems. Adolescents in treatment for alcohol abuse or dependence reported higher rates of physical abuse, sexual abuse, violent victimization, witnessing violence, and other traumas compared with controls. The adolescents in treatment were at least 6 times more likely than controls to have ever been abused physically and at least 18 times more likely to have ever been abused sexually. In most cases, the physical or sexual abuse preceded the alcohol use. Thirteen percent of the alcohol dependent adolescents had experienced posttraumatic stress disorder, compared with 10 percent of those who abused alcohol and 1 percent of controls. Advertising. Research on the effects of alcohol advertising on adolescent alcohol-related beliefs and behaviors has been limited. While earlier studies measured the effects of exposure to advertising, more recent research has assessed the effects of alcohol advertising awareness on intentions to drink. In a study of fifth- and sixth-grade students' awareness, measured by the ability to identify products in commercials with the product name blocked out, awareness had a small but statistically significant relationship to positive expectancies about alcohol and to intention to drink as adults. This suggests that alcohol advertising may influence adolescents to be more favorably predisposed to drinking. Consequences of Adolescent Alcohol Use Drinking and Driving. Of the nearly 8,000 drivers ages 15-20 involved in fatal crashes in 1995, 20 percent had blood alcohol concentrations above zero. Sexual Behavior. Surveys of adolescents suggest that alcohol use is associated with risky sexual behavior and increased vulnerability to coercive sexual activity. Among adolescents surveyed in New Zealand, alcohol misuse was significantly associated with unprotected intercourse and sexual activity before age 16. Forty-four percent of sexually active Massachusetts teenagers said they were more likely to have sexual intercourse if they had been drinking, and 17 percent said they were less likely to use condoms after drinking. Risky Behavior and Victimization. Survey results from a nationally representative sample of 8th and 10th graders indicated that alcohol use was significantly associated with both risky behavior and victimization and that this relationship was strongest among the 8th-grade males, compared with other students. Puberty and Bone Growth. High doses of alcohol have been found to delay puberty in female and male rats, and large quantities of alcohol consumed by young rats can slow bone growth and result in weaker bones. However, the implications of these findings for young people are not clear. Source Citation: "Early Alcohol Consumption Puts Youth at Risk." Should the Legal Drinking Age Be Lowered? Ed. Stefan Kiesbye. Detroit: Greenhaven Press, 2008. At Issue. Rpt. from "Youth Drinking: Risk Factors and Consequences." Alcohol Alert. Gale Opposing Viewpoints In Context. Web. 9 Apr. 2012. In Most Cultures, Youth Drinking Does Not Lead to Alcoholism "In a 'wet culture' where young people are early socialized to drinking, they ... learn how to drink moderately." In the following viewpoint, Dwight Heath maintains that the correlation between youth drinking and alcoholism exists only in the United States, where adults try to prevent youth under age twenty-one from consuming alcohol. The problem with such a policy is that American youth are not taught how to drink responsibly, says Heath, and thus they often do end up abusing alcohol. In his opinion, the best way to reduce alcohol-related problems is to socialize youth to alcohol at an early age. Heath is a professor of anthropology at Brown University in Rhode Island. As you read, consider the following questions: 1. How do Orthodox Jews approach the issue of youth drinking, according to Heath? 2. Rather than viewing drinking as a risky act, what do children who drink with their families learn about alcohol, in the author's opinion? 3. In Heath's opinion, what kind of problems result from the "just-say-no" approach? Newspapers and magazines in the United States have just been crowded with another gloomy piece of news about alcohol. The press-release that triggered this most recent wave of ominous predictions grew out of a research project (sponsored by National Institute on Alcohol Abuse and Alcoholism) concerning the correlation between "age-of-onset" and alcoholism. In simplest terms, investigators discovered that those individuals who started drinking at an early age were more likely to become alcoholics later in life to a statistically significant degree. Correlation Does Not Mean Causation One need not be a scientist to realize that correlation often has little to do with causation, but most journalists wrote as if this were dramatic proof of the highly addictive quality of alcohol, and of the dangers of drinking on the part of anyone under 21 years of age. However, to anyone who has paid attention to life in contemporary Europe where children are frequently introduced to drinking at an early age and where rates of dependency tend to be quite low the finding seems counter-intuitive. Similarly, when one thinks of Orthodox Jews anywhere in the world it is difficult to reconcile their famously low rates of drinking problems with the fact that male infants are given wine on the occasion of their circumcision (on the 8th day of life), and men, women, and children all drink at least twice a week to celebrate the beginning and end of the Sabbath. In view of the vast panorama of human experience, the fateful findings about early drinking are in fact not only counter-intuitive but would be factually wrong in most of the world. However, in the contemporary US, there is little question that the findings are correct, and, when one thinks about it for a while, quite logical. The Problem with Protecting Children from Alcohol The difference is that part of the way in which members of the new temperance movement have tried to "protect American children from alcohol" has obviously been counter-productive. Given a setting where it is deviant (or even illegal) to drink at an early age, it is no surprise that those who do so are precisely those who choose to act in deviant, illegal, or other risky ways. By the same token, moderate individuals who are willing to conform to norms, obey the laws, and minimize risks are those most likely to defer drinking until later. The anti-drink constituency have succeeded in structuring the situation in such a way that the fateful outcome ("early drinking results in drinking problems") is all but inevitable! By contrast, in most parts of the world, beverage alcohol has not been endowed with a mystical aura of "forbidden fruit" in such a way that drinking it is expected by young people to demonstrate their maturity, to make them more powerful or sexy or dynamic or sociable. Where children are not "protected from alcohol," they show no need of such protection. They learn to drink, usually at home and among their families. Drinking is a wholesome and enjoyable part of everyday life, rather than a risky act which they should hide from their elders, and learn from their ill-informed and inexperienced peers. As an anthropologist, I often deal with patterns of small, isolated, or even tribal populations whose exotic patterns of belief and behaviour would be impractical in a modern urban setting in the industrial or post-industrial world. But this is not such a case. Some of the best illustrations of my point are the middle-class cultures of contemporary France, Italy, and Spain (among many others). It is in those well-studied and heavily documented contexts that I have repeatedly demonstrated, using their own official statistics, that the occurrence of so-called "alcohol-related problems" (whether physiological, psychological, social relational, economic, or other) is inversely related to both "age-of-onset" and to average per-capita consumption. As you know, this is just the opposite of what is claimed by the World Health Organization, US [United States] National Institute on Alcohol Abuse and Alcoholism, and other organizations and individuals that are primarily concerned with restricting or curtailing availability as a public health policy. Importance of Socialization to Drinking Incidentally, the same context that guarantees that early-onset drinkers be deviant and willing to flout the law, also guarantees that they will often do so surreptitiously, drinking too much and/or too fast, among peers who lack knowledge about the specific risks of drunkenness or chemical harm, and who may be reluctant to summon adults in the event that an acute problem should occur. Here again, it is the "just-say-no" approach that makes for problems rather than reducing the potential for harm. In a "wet culture" where young people are early socialized to drinking, they simultaneously learn how to drink moderately, how and why to avoid drunkenness, not to expect magical transformations from drink, and to view excesses as inappropriate and illustrative of weakness (generally the opposite of what supposedly "protected" youths in the US learn). In short, the "early onset" theory is accurate but only in those few parts of the world in which the legal and normative system makes it so. In the rest of the world, the opposite is the case!... How ironic it is that an illogical scientific finding should hold, if only because an illogical legal context structures the situation in a way that assures that perverse outcome. Source Citation: Heath, Dwight. "In Most Cultures, Youth Drinking Does Not Lead to Alcoholism." Alcohol. Ed. Andrea C. Nakaya. Detroit: Greenhaven Press, 2008. Opposing Viewpoints. Rpt. from "'Age-of-Onset' as Risk: A Self-Fulfilling Prophecy." Aim Digest. 2005. Gale Opposing Viewpoints In Context. Web. 9 Apr. 2012. Assisted Suicide Since the 1960s medical science has made great progress in prolonging people’s lives, even those suffering from terminal illnesses. Some people think that individuals should be allowed access to medical assistance to end their lives voluntarily, when and how they choose. Known as assisted suicide (or physician-assisted suicide), this practice involves helping a person who is hopelessly ill to end his or her own life. Assisted suicide has strong supporters and opponents. The issue is likely to gain importance as scientists find new ways to prolong life, and the number of elderly people in the population grows. People in many countries debate whether assisted suicide should be legal. What Is Assisted Suicide? In the past, patients did not have much say in the medical treatment they received. Then, during the 1900s, doctors in the United States began to adopt the standard of informed consent. This requires doctors to explain the available treatment options and to obtain the patient’s consent prior to treatment. Although patients can draw on their doctors’ medical knowledge and experience, they must ultimately make their own decisions. Those who cannot understand and grant consent themselves, such as children and people who are unconscious or of unsound mind, can be represented by family members or others close to them. Some of these decisions involve treatments that will keep a patient alive. Increasingly, an individual’s wishes are taken into consideration when doctors or hospitals face the question of whether to start or stop using life-support treatment, such as respirators that help patients breathe. The controversy over assisted suicide rests on the difference between letting someone die and helping him or her die. Stopping life-support treatment, or not starting it in the first place, is both legal and commonplace. Neither measure is considered killing, although the result is often the death of the patient. But in the eyes of many people, and under the law in most places, assisted suicide is killing and killing is illegal. Assisted suicide occurs when a physician provides a patient with the means of ending his or her life—usually a prescription for a fatal dose of drugs. The patient takes the drugs independently of the doctor. This procedure differs from euthanasia, in which the doctor administers the fatal dose or performs some other act, such as a lethal injection, that ends the patient’s life. Like assisted suicide, euthanasia is illegal in most places. Allowing someone to die by not acting, such as not restarting a heart that has stopped beating, is sometimes called passive euthanasia. The Debate Should society permit those who want to die to arrange an easy and comfortable death? Writer Derek Humphry believes that it should. Humphry has helped start several organizations to promote assisted suicide and euthanasia. His book Final Exit serves as a guide for people who want to end their lives. Like most supporters of assisted suicide, Humphry desires to help individuals with incurable, hopeless illnesses. However, critics fear that his efforts might make it too easy for others—such as people suffering from treatable depression—to commit suicide. Supporters of assisted suicide argue that people are already allowed to refuse medical treatment even when they know that they will die without it. If people can choose death in this passive way, why should they not be allowed to choose it more actively? Another argument is that an individual determined to end his or her life may use painful, violent, or uncertain methods. Why not allow a more certain, pain-free alternative? Supporters of this viewpoint claim that assisted suicide respects the individual’s right to determine his or her destiny. Likewise, some physicians feel that it is appropriate for them to end the suffering of a patient who is capable of making a rational decision and asks to die. Those opposed to assisted suicide believe that the taking of life is wrong in any circumstance. They argue that there is no such thing as a "mercy killing." Various religious faiths maintain that it is the business of God, not of doctors or patients, to determine the time of death. The Hippocratic oath, a statement of medical ethics, tells physicians, "First, do no harm." Many physicians regard assisted suicide and euthanasia as murder. Opponents point out that legalizing assisted suicide and euthanasia could result in serious consequences. One fear is that dying people might not receive proper care if euthanasia appeared to be a cheaper, easier alternative. Another fear is that choice and the right to determine one’s fate might not always be the deciding factors. Voluntary euthanasia might lead to the involuntary euthanasia of individuals incapable of making the choice or thought to be unworthy of life. This occurred during the 1930s and 1940s when the Nazi rulers of Germany euthanized mentally retarded people and others they classified as "defective." Legislation Assisted suicide has been in the news frequently since the 1990s. Dr. Jack Kevorkian, a supporter of the practice, played a supporting role in more than one hundred suicides before he was charged with murder. Ironically, his highly publicized efforts may have done more harm than good for his cause. Concern about his activities led to laws against assisted suicide in his own state, Michigan, as well as in other states. In 1999 Dr. Kevorkian was convicted of seconddegree murder in Michigan for engaging in euthanasia, which is illegal in all states. He was released from prison in 2007. Physician-assisted suicide has been openly practiced in the Netherlands for some time. The government adopted euthanasia guidelines in 1993, with the understanding that it would not prosecute doctors despite the illegality of the practice. In 2001 the Netherlands became the first country to legalize euthanasia. To qualify for euthanasia under Dutch law, a person must be mentally capable of making the decision, act voluntarily, be ill without hope of recovery, and have a lasting wish to die. Physicians performing euthanasia must consult with at least one other doctor and must write reports on each case. In 1995, the Northern Territory of Australia also legalized euthanasia, but the federal parliament overturned the law two years later. In the United States, Oregon was the first state to legalize physician-assisted suicide. Oregon voters passed the Death with Dignity Act in 1994, but a lawsuit blocked its enforcement until 1997, when it went into effect. During the first year the law was in force, twenty-four people obtained a prescription for lethal drugs, and sixteen took the drugs and died. Some Oregon lawmakers have opposed physician-assisted suicide, claiming that the desire to reduce medical costs may put pressure on patients and caregivers to choose death. In November 2008 voters in Washington approved Initiative 1000, making the state the second in the nation to legalize physician-assisted suicide. The law, which went into effect in March 2009, was approved by 58 percent of the voters. Assisted suicide became legal in Montana in December 2008, not by a referendum approved by voters, but by a court case. In Baxter v. Montana, terminally ill Robert Baxter sued for the right to die, claiming that doctors who refused to assist him were violating his rights. A lower court ruled that a patient has the right to end his or her life and that doctors who assist cannot be prosecuted for homicide. The case was appealed to the state supreme court which upheld the lower court’s decision in December 2009. In its ruling the state supreme court said, "We find nothing in Montana Supreme Court precedent or Montana statutes indicating that physician aid in dying is against public policy." Source Citation: "Assisted Suicide." Current Issues: Macmillan Social Science Library. Detroit: Gale, 2010. Gale Opposing Viewpoints In Context. Web. 9 Apr. 2012. Individuals Should Have a Legal Right to Choose Death Thomas A. Bowden is a legal analyst at the Ayn Rand Institute. This month [October 2007] marks the tenth anniversary of Oregon's pathbreaking assisted suicide law. But despite legislative proposals in California and elsewhere, Oregon remains the only state to have provided clear procedures by which doctors can help end their dying patients' pain and suffering while protecting themselves from criminal prosecution. For a decade now, Oregon doctors have been permitted to prescribe a lethal dose of drugs to a mentally competent, terminally ill patient who makes written and oral requests, consults two physicians, and endures a mandatory waiting period. The patient's free choice is paramount throughout this process. Neither relatives nor doctors can apply on the patient's behalf, and the patient himself administers the lethal dose. Elsewhere in America, however, the political influence of religious conservatism has thwarted passage of similar legislation, leaving terminal patients with nothing but a macabre menu of frightening, painful, and often violent end-of-life techniques universally regarded as too inhumane for use on sick dogs or mass murderers. Society Should Permit Assisted Suicide Consider Percy Bridgman, the Nobel Prize-winning physicist who, at 79, was entering the final stages of terminal cancer. Wracked with pain and bereft of hope, he got a gun and somehow found courage to pull the trigger, knowing he was condemning others to the agony of discovering his bloody remains. His final note said simply: "It is not decent for society to make a man do this to himself. Probably this is the last day I will be able to do it myself." What lawmakers must grasp is that there is no rational basis upon which the government can properly prevent any individual from choosing to end his own life. When religious conservatives enact laws to enforce the idea that their God abhors suicide, they threaten the central principle on which America was founded. The Declaration of Independence proclaimed, for the first time in the history of nations, that each person exists as an end in himself. This basic truth—which finds political expression in the right to life, liberty, and the pursuit of happiness—means, in practical terms, that you need no one's permission to live, and that no one may forcibly obstruct your efforts to achieve your own personal happiness. But what if happiness becomes impossible to attain? What if a dread disease, or some other calamity, drains all joy from life, leaving only misery and suffering? The right to life includes and implies the right to commit suicide. To hold otherwise—to declare that society must give you permission to kill yourself—is to contradict the right to life at its root. If you have a duty to go on living, despite your better judgment, then your life does not belong to you, and you exist by permission, not by right. The Right to Life Implies the Right to Death For these reasons, each individual has the right to decide the hour of his death and to implement that solemn decision as best he can. The choice is his because the life is his. And if a doctor is willing (not forced) to assist in the suicide, based on an objective assessment of his patient's mental and physical state, the law should not stand in his way. Religious conservatives' opposition to the Oregon approach stems from the belief that human life is a gift from the Lord, who puts us here on earth to carry out His will. Thus, the very idea of suicide is anathema, because one who "plays God" by causing his own death, or assisting in the death of another, insults his Maker and invites eternal damnation, not to mention divine retribution against the decadent society that permits such sinful behavior. If a religious conservative contracts a terminal disease, he has a legal right to regard his own God's will as paramount, and to instruct his doctor to stand by and let him suffer, just as long as his body and mind can endure the agony, until the last bitter paroxysm carries him to the grave. But conservatives have no right to force such mindless, medieval misery upon doctors and patients who refuse to regard their precious lives as playthings of a cruel God. Rational state legislators should regard the Oregon law's anniversary as a stinging reminder that 49 of the 50 states have failed to take meaningful steps toward recognizing and protecting an individual's unconditional right to commit suicide. Source Citation: Bowden, Thomas A., and Ayn Rand Institute. "Individuals Should Have a Legal Right to Choose Death." Assisted Suicide. Ed. Karen F. Balkin. San Diego: Greenhaven Press, 2005. Current Controversies. Rpt. from "After Ten Years, States Still Resist Assisted Suicide." 2007. Gale Opposing Viewpoints In Context. Web. 9 Apr. 2012. Legalized Assisted Suicide May Lead to Legalized Euthanasia Susan W. Enouen is a professional engineer who volunteers for the Life Issues Institute, a nonprofit pro-life educational organization. In 1994, Oregon voters approved the Death with Dignity Act (DWDA) by a vote of 51% to 49%. It became effective in 1998, surviving court challenges and a repeal effort, to make Oregon the first state in the country to legalize physician-assisted suicide (PAS). The law allows physicians to prescribe life-ending drugs that are requested by terminally ill patients with six months or less to live. In the nine years since then, DWDA records show that 455 people have requested lethal drugs from their physician and 292 people have died from using them. The yearly numbers continue to rise, beginning with 16 deaths in 1997, increasing to 38 in 2005, and reaching 46 deaths in 2006. Although these records show that relatively few Oregonians choose to use this option, the lack of accountability and safeguards in the process have many people concerned that the numbers are not telling the whole story. In addition to that, disturbing trends appear to be developing. For example, only 17 complications have been reported in the 292 deaths, and 16 of these were regurgitation. However, in the Netherlands, where they have had many years to work on overcoming complications in assisted suicide, serious complications are still reported. In fact, a study found that Dutch doctors feel the need to intervene (by giving lethal injections) in 18% of cases because of complications or problems. The lack of reported complications in Oregon has caused even pro-assisted suicide physicians to question the credibility of Oregon's reported data. One of the reasons to suspect the accuracy of the data is that the prescribing physician is not required by law to be present when the drugs are taken. Since 2001, when this data was first collected, prescribing physicians had only been present at 29% of the deaths. The recording of complications is therefore dependent upon the self-report of a physician who, in most cases, was not even present, and who must rely on second-hand information or guesswork to file a report. The Oregon Department of Human Services (DHS), which collects the information, must depend on the word of the doctors for the reliability of their data and "it has no authority to investigate individual Death with Dignity cases." What Happens to Unused Lethal Drugs? Even more chilling is the fact that the Death with Dignity Act applies no penalties to doctors who do not report that they have prescribed lethal drugs for the purpose of suicide. This means that there is no way to know for sure how many assisted-suicide deaths may actually be occurring in Oregon. Nor is there any way to know whether the prescribed drugs are being made available to people other than the patient who requested them. Only 64% of patients who have received the prescriptions are known to have died from taking them. What becomes of all the other deadly drugs? It is possible the prescriptions have never been filled, or maybe the lethal drugs are sitting in medicine cabinets unused, but clearly there is the potential for accidents, and the law provides very little safeguard from abuse. So far, no one has been disciplined for disregarding the safeguards that the law does provide. Complications are not investigated and likely not reported in many cases, and the reality is DHS "has no regulatory authority or resources to ensure compliance with the law." According to the Oregon data, the majority of patients who choose assisted suicide have some type of cancer, have a median age of about 70 years, are overwhelmingly white (98-), somewhat more likely to be male (57-), have had at least a partial college education (63-), are enrolled in hospice care (86-), and die at home (93-). The most common concerns given for choosing assisted suicide are "losing autonomy" (87-), being "less able to engage in activities making life enjoyable" (87-), and "loss of dignity" (80-). (The last category was added in 2003.) No category is provided to indicate whether or not the patient might be depressed, yet all of these concerns have much to do with a patient's gloomy appraisal of life, a possible indicator of treatable depression. Still only 4-5% of patients were referred for psychiatric evaluation from 2003 to 2006, having dropped from 37% in 1999, to 13% in 2002 and reaching its lowest point of 4% in 2006. This indicates a weakening response on the part of prescribing doctors to ensure that the patient is truly capable of making such a decision. Prescriptions from Unfamiliar Doctors There may be a reason for this trend. One of the safeguards touted by the promoters of assisted suicide was that this decision would be made between the patient and his long-time trusted doctor. This familiar doctor would discuss all other options with the patient and would be able to evaluate the patient's true physical and psychological state. To prevent hasty decisions, the law requires a patient to make two oral requests for the lethal drugs, at least two weeks apart, before the physician can prescribe them. Yet for the past 6 years, the minimum recorded duration for a patient-physician relationship has been 1 week or less. Not only does this indicate that at least some doctors are not following the law's requirements, but with a median duration of about 12 weeks, it means that most patients are not receiving these prescriptions from a trusted doctor who knows them well. It is much more cost effective and easier to let people kill themselves, and it can be rationalized as a compassionate approach. In fact, many physicians are unwilling to write lethal prescriptions, causing at least one HMO [health maintenance organization] to make an email plea to enlist doctors who would be willing to act as the "attending physician" for patients requesting assisted suicide. And nurses' organizations admit to sending patients to an assisted-suicide advocacy group when their own doctor does not want to participate. These patients then find a doctor through the advocacy group Compassion and Choices (formerly called Compassion in Dying, until it merged with the Hemlock Society in 2005), which sees "almost 90% of requesting Oregonians." Not only are assisted-suicide patients becoming disengaged from their trusted doctors and relying heavily upon the aid of an assisted-suicide advocacy group, but HMO's are becoming involved in administering assisted suicide, a much cheaper option for them than paying for longer-term palliative care that would focus on alleviating a patient's pain. It is much more cost effective and easier to let people kill themselves, and it can be rationalized as a compassionate approach. One of the primary arguments for assisted suicide is the ending of unbearable physical pain. Experience in The Netherlands, where euthanasia is legal, is revealing. Concern that pain will become unbearable is common, this being a worry in one-third or more of such patients. However, the Dutch experience is that of those actually requesting euthanasia, only 5% list physical pain as their major reason, and typically when pain is controlled they change their mind. As noted above, loss of autonomy and other psychologically "painful" concerns are the overwhelming majority of reasons given. Acceptance of assisted suicide can lead to involuntary euthanasia of the disabled and dying, which can lead to legal euthanasia. All in all, there are many troubling aspects of Oregon's assisted suicide law, and yet several states have tried to follow suit with nearly identical bills. California, Hawaii, Arizona, Vermont and Wisconsin have all faced assisted-suicide bills in their legislatures this year [2007], and for some of these states it has been an ongoing attempt for several years. As assisted-suicide proponents continue to lobby for this legislation, their language has evolved into less threatening-sounding terms. Rather than "physician assisted suicide," the phrase is "physician aid in dying" or PAD, so physicians now "induce PAD." In fact, the DHS has been threatened with litigation if the state continues to use the word "suicide." Other euphemisms include "patient choice," "control at end of life," "assisted death" and "death with dignity." This is all part of a program to help people think of it as a compassionate approach to death. From Assisted Suicide to Euthanasia Where will the Oregon experiment go from here? The Netherlands' experience has shown that acceptance of assisted suicide can lead to involuntary euthanasia of the disabled and dying, which can lead to legal euthanasia. This melds easily into illegal but accepted euthanasia of disabled and dying babies. It is then just a small baby step to legalize the infanticide of such "suffering" little ones. This is where the thinking in The Netherlands has gone in the past 30 years. As Wesley J. Smith, an anti-euthanasia advocate, author, and an attorney for the International Task Force on Euthanasia and Assisted Suicide, says about the euthanasia movement: "euthanasia and assisted suicide have gone ... from the unthinkable, to the debatable, to the justifiable, on its way to unexceptional." We would be wise to keep a very close eye on Oregon. Source Citation: Enouen, Susan W. "Legalized Assisted Suicide May Lead to Legalized Euthanasia." Assisted Suicide. Ed. Karen F. Balkin. San Diego: Greenhaven Press, 2005. Current Controversies. Rpt. from "Oregon's Euthanasia Law: It's About Far More than the Number of People Dying." Life Issues Connector (July 2007). Gale Opposing Viewpoints In Context. Web. 9 Apr. 2012. Book Banning Book banning has been an active part of literary history perhaps since the first words were written down on paper. It is a form of censorship that attempts to control the dissemination of thoughts and ideas that some groups in society believe to be harmful. When books were handwritten, the censorship of ideas was much easier, and book burning was an effective method. Government, Religion, and Book Bans The printing press was invented in 1450, and shortly thereafter led to mass production and distribution of popular books. Thus the practice of burning books to censor literature became largely symbolic as it became virtually impossible to find and destroy every copy of a particular book. That, however, did not stop attempts to control access to information. A mere forty years after the printing press was invented in Germany, the country's first official censorship office opened to suppress what religious authorities labeled "dangerous publications." Centuries later, the battle continues. In the United States, the first book ban occurred in 1650 in Springfield, Massachusetts. Ironically the Puritans, who had fled England less than fifty years before to escape religious persecution, condemned and confiscated a religious text written by one of their own members and had it burned in a public demonstration in the center of town. Censorship and book bans were often supported at the national level in the United States. Federal laws, such as the Comstock Law of 1873, made it a crime to distribute "obscene, lewd, and/or lascivious" materials through the mail. Interpretation of what exactly constituted these materials was left up to law enforcement officials. The banning, and often burning, of books continued unchecked until the early 1920s when existing standards were challenged. The tide turned against national laws and judgments during the 1930s as Americans witnessed the disturbing activities in Nazi Germany surrounding censorship and mass book burnings. First Amendment Rights vs. Censorship For democratic societies such as the United States, book banning contradicts core beliefs. The First Amendment of the U.S. Constitution prohibits Congress from making laws that impinge on the freedom of speech and freedom of the press. Americans have struggled with defining these parameters since their adoption. Although book banning continues, the arena of controversy has moved from the national to the local level. The most common challenges today occur in school libraries and classrooms. Most of the battles are fought at the school board level, but some cases have been legally challenged, and several have made it to the Supreme Court. The Supreme Court ruled on one such case in 1982 in the Board of Education, Island Trees Union Free School District v. Pico in what has been considered one of the most important decisions regarding First Amendment rights and school libraries. The U.S. Supreme Court set parameters under which a board of education could consider removing a book from its collection. The board, said the court, was constrained by the students' First Amendment rights. Justice William J. Brennan Jr. wrote in his majority opinion that local school boards may not remove books from school libraries simply because they dislike the ideas contained in those books and seek by their removal to "prescribe what shall be orthodox in politics, nationalism, religion, or other matters of opinion." A significant point about the Pico decision was that the vote was 5–4 in favor of the students who challenged the school board's removal of library materials. There was no one majority opinion; seven out of the nine justices wrote opinions on the case. This reflects the mixed feelings of the justices as well as the nation as it grapples with difficult questions regarding First Amendment rights. Banned Books Week Publicizes Challenges Sex, profanity, and racism are the primary categories of objections according to Robert P. Doyle, author of the list "Books Challenged and Banned in 2008–09," created as part of Banned Books Week 2009. Banned Books Week, which launched in 1982, is an annual event sponsored by the American Library Association, American Booksellers Foundation for Free Expression, the Association of American Publishers, the American Society of Journalists and Authors, and the National Association of College stores that celebrates the freedom to read and to select from a full array of possibilities. "The challenges documented on this list are not brought by people merely expressing a point of view," says Doyle. "Rather; they represent requests to remove materials from schools or libraries, thus restricting access to them by others." Book challenges are often launched by parents to protect their children. But every parent has different opinions of what is appropriate for his or her child. Many times attempts to ban material have more to do with its perceived suitability for a particular age group. For example, it might be widely agreed that certain adult subjects should not be allowed in the young children's section of a library, leading to restricted access rather than an outright removal. But as children get older, the answers become a bit less clear—"unsuitable for this age group" becomes a weaker argument when applied to teenagers about to enter adulthood. Libraries and schools often encounter resistance to books and curriculum. They must strike a balance between respecting individual opinions and the rights of others. "Individuals may restrict what they themselves or their children read, but they must not call on governmental or public agencies to prevent others from reading or seeing that material," asserts Doyle. Sometimes book challenges can have unintended side effects. The challenge itself often draws attention to the methods used in determining what books are included in school and public collections. In this way, attempts at restricting material have led to examination of policies. Actual practices are in the spotlight, and healthy discussion can result. In 2008 a case of book censorship in New Rochelle, New York, led to a national debate and much publicity for the book at the center of the controversy. The book was Girl, Interrupted, by Susanna Kaysen. School officials tore pages out of student copies of the book that they deemed inappropriate due to sexual content and strong language. Their actions became the subject of intense scrutiny across the Internet as popular websites such as Boing Boing and Hot Air took up the discussion online, along with many smaller blog sites dedicated to literary and free speech issues. The New Yorkerand The Atlantic Monthly magazines also featured the incident. The intent to shield New Rochelle students from inappropriate material clearly had the opposite effect. Book bans in the digital age may seem almost archaic given the many ways that information can be accessed in the modern world. But the removal of books from school libraries or curriculum can have an overall chilling effect on future decisions and discussions regarding book purchases. The promoters of Banned Book Week estimate that 85 percent of book challenges go unreported and unnoticed. Moreover, the number of books that are quietly passed over for inclusion in collections because of fear of controversy cannot even be estimated. Corporate Decisions Influence Availability Public and school libraries are not the only ones who ban books. In the larger context, corporate censorship in deciding what books it will sell may be far more dangerous. Online retailer, Amazon, and big box competitors, such as Walmart and Target, have become a dominant force in book sales as many independent bookstores have been forced to close their doors in the face of competition. Some argue these are private industries and can do as they wish, but as available book purchasing options shrink, their choice to sell or not sell a book can determine its success. Walmart's 2004 decision not to carry Jon Stewart's book America, due to potentially offensive images of the faces of Supreme Court justices pasted onto naked bodies, garnered much media attention. It did not stop people who wanted to read the book from doing so, and ultimately may have led to increased sales. But it also may have led Walmart to be more careful in revealing what they do not sell in their stores. Fewer sales and less revenue can lead to a homogenization of book offerings and can suppress freedom of speech and expression, a type of book censorship using purchasing power as a determining factor. Online book sales bring another host of challenges. Amazon and other Internet retailers have tremendous control over what products are shown and in what order when a customer performs a subject search. Books usually are shown according to their sales ranking, with best sellers at the top of the list. Amazon also categorizes books by format and age group. An incident in April 2009 provided a glimpse into the power they can wield in censoring book availability. Hundreds of gay- and lesbian-themed books disappeared from Amazon's sales rankings, leading to protests from authors and activists who accused the company of stealth censorship. Amazon officials later blamed it on an internal categorizing error, but the episode was not an isolated one for the leading online retailer of books. Although Amazon and other online book retailers remain a dominant force on the Internet, increasingly independent bookstores are establishing online stores to replace or compliment their brick and mortar ones. Using the same sales techniques and tools as Amazon, they can potentially provide the more diverse offerings they are known for, but in an online setting. Book challenges and bans may always be with us, but the greater transparency and easier access afforded by the Internet make it difficult to ultimately regulate the publications people want to read. As Supreme Court Justice William O. Douglas said in 1953, "Restriction of free thought and free speech is the most dangerous of all subversions. It is the one un-American act that could easily defeat us." Full Text: COPYRIGHT 2012 Gale, Cengage Learning. Source Citation: "Book Banning." Current Issues: Macmillan Social Science Library. Detroit: Gale, 2010. Gale Opposing Viewpoints In Context. Web. 9 Apr. 2012. Book Banning Protects Family Values Rebecca Hagelin is the author of Home Invasion: Protecting Your Family in a Culture That's Gone Stark Raving Mad and a vice president of communications and marketing at the Heritage Foundation. While we as a society have been taught to believe that any reading is good for adolescents, it is important to consider the kinds of books that children are reading. The American Library Association (ALA), for instance, recommends books for young readers, but these recommendations reflect the organization's liberal values. Books recommended by the ALA contain curse words and graphic sexual information. In order to guarantee that a child is reading quality books—books that a parent approves of—a parent should review a child's reading material beforehand. It is a parent's responsibility—not the ALA's and not an educational institution's—to decide what a child should read. Reading isn't always good for our kids. How's that for an opening sentence to stir a little controversy among the educational elites? We've been bombarded by so many messages about how reading expands the mind, excites the imagination and enhances the vocabulary (all of which are true) that many parents have forgotten that the benefit of reading for our children very much depends on what they're reading. And, I'm afraid that many children spend hours reading what often turns out to be pure rot. With school starting all over the country between last week and just after Labor Day, it's time for a reading warning: Parents, beware. In many cases the very liberal American Library Association exerts great influence over what reading materials teachers assign their students. But that material may be highly inappropriate for your child. Don't let the following scenario unfold in your home: Mrs. Jones hands out a book report assignment that includes several books for her class to choose from. Mom dutifully drives Suzi to the local library and browses while Suzi selects her book. Within half an hour, book in hand, everyone is feeling rather satisfied that they have been so responsible in starting on the project early. Mom and Suzi arrive home, and while mom begins making dinner, the conscientious and responsible Suzi heads to her room and begins to consume what turns out to be highly sexualized, vulgar garbage, filled with four-letter words and enough verbal porn to embarrass even an ol' salt. Mom doesn't have a clue that her daughter's innocence has just been molested in the privacy of her own bedroom. She won't ever know because Suzi, a bit stymied by the fact that Mom took her to get a book that her teacher assigned, will be too embarrassed and confused to ever tell. Yet, she's just had sexuality, relationships and acceptable behavior defined for her by some perverted author most folks have never heard of. And the kid was simply trying to get her homework done. Inappropriate Books for Young Readers While researching my book, Home Invasion: Protecting Your Family in a Culture That's Gone Stark Raving Mad, I took an ALA-recommended reading list for 13- and 14-year-olds to my local library and headed to the "Young Adult" section (code for "pre-teen" and "teen"). I found some books from the list; others were already checked out. One book, the librarian told me, had just been returned, but hadn't been re-shelved, so I patiently waited while she went into the back room to retrieve it. With several items in hand, I headed back to the Young Adult section, where I couldn't help but notice pre-teen and teen girls and guys in various stages of development and maturity, dutifully searching the shelves for assigned books. I sat down on a reading bench and began flipping through the pages of the book that had just been returned. There's something very moving about holding a book in your hand that a child has just finished reading. But the warmth in my heart soon turned into a sickening feeling in my gut when I began to read passages so cheap and trashy that I could scarcely believe my eyes. I only had to get to page four before the first of many uses of the term "motherf—" showed up. Several scenes described, in graphic detail, sexual acts between teenagers. In the interest of decency, there's no way I can give you word-for-word examples. And I refuse to give the trashy book and its loser author free publicity in a column that often gets forwarded around the World Wide Web. I'd rather parents and other adults who care about our children and their education—and whether ... educational elites indoctrinate them in immorality—actually go to their local library and research the reading lists themselves. Lest you think the first book was put on the list in error, the next recommended teen item I thumbed through was equally as nauseating. A sexual act between fourth-graders was a "highlight," as well as graphic details of sex between teens, including a homosexual encounter. And this is the garbage that today's educators pass off as great literature for our children? The great classics, meanwhile, are all but missing. One list I reviewed for eight-graders contained about 20 authors—none recognizable save the lone great Mark Twain. And they call this education? The lesson here is simple. Moms and dads: Don't just naively drive your kids to the library—you must be careful to help them choose books that reflect your values. Even if your kids are in private school, you're hardly safe—many of the best schools blindly use ALA lists. Of course, if you home school your kids, you're probably already aware of the moral problems of many ALA decisions, but even if you're using a good curriculum guide, it's always best to preview the books first. The ALA is quick to call anyone who questions its decisions a "censor." But remember, part of our responsibility and privilege as parents is to be the ones who determine what is and is not appropriate for our own children. Source Citation: Hagelin, Rebecca. "Book Banning Protects Family Values." Book Banning. Ed. Ronnie D. Lankford. Detroit: Greenhaven Press, 2007. At Issue. Rpt. from "Are Your Kids Reading Rot?" Townhall (16 Aug. 2005). Gale Opposing Viewpoints In Context. Web. 9 Apr. 2012. Book Destruction Controls Ideology Rebecca Knuth is an associate professor in the Library and Information Science Program at the University of Hawaii. In the 20th century, fascist and communist ideologues attempted to destroy democratic and humanistic thought by destroying books. Books disseminate ideas, and many of these ideas form cultural myths and identities; censoring books, then, is one way to eliminate ideas and myths that oppose a particular ideologue's philosophy. A number of modern conflicts, like World War II, pitted ideologues against humanists. Ideologues believed that destroying offending books and libraries—both their own and those of an enemy—encouraged the correct thinking of the reigning regime. "Utopias have their value—nothing so wonderfully expands the imaginative horizons of human potentialities—but as guides to conduct they can prove literally fatal. Heraclitus was right, things cannot stand still." In the most general sense, one could say that the ultra-nationalists and Communists of the twentieth century effectively replaced traditional systems of ethics and morality by a single means: the leveraging of ideology. Nationalism and socialism, in themselves compelling belief systems, were transformed by merciless leaders into totalistic dogmas that reduced what is sacred to a single notion of predestined collective potential. Familial loyalties were subordinated to loyalty to the state. A sociopolitical environment was engineered to snuff out alternative ideas. Violence was instituted as necessary, and even desirable, in the quest to maintain the totalitarian structures that would deliver a purified and transformed society. Fueling the impulse toward violence was the ideologues' conviction that enemies—animate or inanimate, a person, even a book—surrounded them. When a book's content contradicted an ideologue's dominance over ideas and seemed to support cosmopolitanism, democracy, or humanism, that book was labeled a tool of the enemy and in itself, a dangerous thing. Such a book, therefore, became a candidate for censorship, which ran the gamut from blacklisting to burning or pulping. Similarly, when libraries were identified as hindering ideological transformation and impeding progress toward the desired utopia, they were attacked and sometimes eliminated, along with their human possessors. Perhaps the most astonishing part of this phenomenon was the inclusion of a nation's own possessions as enemies to the cause. The Nazis first censored and destroyed those German books that they considered problematic, then destroyed the books of those they considered pathological (the Jews), inferior (the Poles), and resistant (the British). When ideological fervor intensified in China, the Communist radicals destroyed classic Chinese texts and intellectuals and in Tibet, both texts and resistant Tibetans. With progress narrowly defined as achieving ideological goals, print materials often came to be associated with cultural or political intransigence and their destruction a war effort on the same two fronts. The violence and public nature of destruction often obscured the fact that the ruin was a practical means of destroying information that contradicted the myths of the regime or substantiated the claims of other ethnic or political groups to resources and territory. Books were destroyed as part of the process of homogenizing discourse, suppressing individualism in the interest of the collective, and co-opting or purging the intellectuals. Books as Ideas Books were destroyed as part of the process of homogenizing discourse, suppressing individualism in the interest of the collective, and co-opting or purging the intellectuals. The goal of extremist regimes was complete control, and books and libraries were compromised by their association with humanism, the creed of enemy democracies. Indeed, the twentieth-century ideologues despised humanists, who valued books and libraries for precisely those qualities that pitted them against ideologues. Regardless of their individual agendas, books ultimately, by their very existence and coexistence with the entirety of the world's print literature, support individualism, pluralism, creativity, rationalism, freedom of information, critical thinking, and intellectual freedom. The ideologue must reject traditional knowledge in order to look to the future, while the humanist actively seeks inspiration from the past. Humanists believe that written materials are fundamental to the maintenance and progress of culture; ideologues seek to politicize and overturn existing culture. Ideologues view libraries as problematic, their potential as instruments of indoctrination compromised by their humanistic or reactionary nature and ability to pose alternate realities or ideas. World War II was fought between ideologues and humanists, and books and libraries played no small role. The jubilant Nazi book burnings and the ensuing wartime devastation of cultural institutions throughout the world resulted in the United Nations' orientation toward the preservation of humanism. The cultivation of a world in which cultural resources are safe became a declared goal of both and technology by preserving and disseminating the information necessary for scientific inquiry, technological development, and the systematic advancement of knowledge. These functions, which made libraries the quintessential representation of humanism, were problematic for extremists. For example, Chinese Communist radicals of the 1960s and 1970s wanted industrialization based not on scientific and technological expertise but on revolutionary will and zeal. Libraries suffered as a consequence. The Nazis sought to rationalize racism, and German libraries flourished only when they aligned with this goal. Extremists need to control humanist institutions and transform them from cultural resources into political tools, part of the overall machine of the revolution. Ideologues censor and then reconstruct their own libraries and those of conquered enemies, or they destroy books or entire libraries outright because they fear the connection between libraries and alternate belief systems, especially humanism, which allow for pluralism. Books and libraries are destroyed not only because of their functions within a society, but because, by the twentieth century, books, libraries, and all intellectual pursuits had become clearly linked to humanism. Their destruction was part of an overall system of eliminating the influence of humanism in the sociopolitical arena, particularly as concerned intellectuals, scholarship, science, history, and foreign relations. Ideologues censor and then reconstruct their own libraries and those of conquered enemies. ... Source Citation: Knuth, Rebecca. "Book Destruction Controls Ideology." Libricide: The Regime-Sponsored Destruction of Books and Libraries in the Twentieth Century. Westport, CT: Praeger Publishers, 2003. 236-238. Rpt. in Book Banning. Ed. Ronnie D. Lankford. Detroit: Greenhaven Press, 2007. At Issue. Gale Opposing Viewpoints In Context. Web. 9 Apr. 2012. Capital Punishment Capital punishment is literally a life-and-death issue. Sometimes called the death penalty, it is the execution of people who have been found guilty of offenses considered to be capital crimes. Supporters of capital punishment believe that some crimes, especially murder, are so serious and so destructive to society that the perpetrators deserve the most severe punishment. Many of these people believe that the death penalty is a deterrent to crime. Opponents of capital punishment argue that there are no circumstances under which taking a human life is justified. They think that society’s interests are better served by placing criminals in jail, where they can do no further harm. Other important issues regarding capital punishment include the wrongful execution of innocent people and lack of uniformity in applying the death penalty. Capital Punishment and the Law Today Americans on both sides of the death penalty issue look to the U.S. Constitution to support their positions. However, because of varying interpretations of the law by state governments and the U.S. Supreme Court, the use of the death penalty has been inconsistent. The Constitution and the States The Fifth Amendment to the Constitution recognizes the existence of capital punishment and outlines conditions for trying individuals accused of capital crimes. The amendment states that no person "shall be deprived of life … without due process of law." This means that before an execution, certain legal procedures—such as formal arrest, charges, and a trial—must be followed. The first known execution in what is now the United States occurred in the colony of Virginia in 1622. By the 1800s, the law in the United States not only accepted capital punishment but also required it. Execution was the automatic penalty for anyone convicted of murder or several other serious crimes. A jury that believed a defendant guilty of murder had no legal power to avoid the death penalty. As a result, a jury that considered a defendant guilty of a serious crime but did not think he or she deserved execution might find the defendant not guilty—an outcome known as jury nullification. Over time, state legislatures rejected the automatic death penalty, partly because of a growing feeling that some defendants deserved legal mercy, even if guilty, and partly to end jury nullifications. By the early 1900s, most states had adopted a new type of death penalty law that gave juries a choice between the death penalty and a life sentence in prison. This policy remained in effect until 1972, although a few states banned capital punishment completely. Executions in the United States peaked at about two hundred a year in the 1930s and remained fairly frequent until the 1960s. By that time, however, the death sentence began to face growing moral and political opposition. Critics of capital punishment cast serious doubt on its value as a deterrent to crime. They also argued that the death penalty was applied unequally. Similar cases were not treated alike, and race appeared to play a part in sentencing. Blacks who had committed crimes against whites received a proportionally greater share of death sentences than other convicted criminals. The Supreme Court faced increasing pressure to regulate or set limits on capital punishment. Supreme Court Decisions In 1972, in the case of Furman v. Georgia, the Supreme Court delivered a crucial decision on capital punishment. By a vote of five to four, the justices overturned the death sentence of William Furman, declaring it to be cruel and unusual punishment according to the Eighth Amendment. Furman was a mentally retarded African American whose trial lasted less than one day. The ruling put a stop to future executions until better standards could be set. While the decision pointed out the problems associated with the death penalty, it offered no immediate solution. The Furman case opened the way for each state to try to develop sound capital punishment laws that might address some of the problems. Executions were suspended for a few years while about three-fourths of the state legislatures revised their laws. In 1976, in five cases handed down on the same day, the Supreme Court ruled on the states’ efforts. The Court decided that automatic death penalty laws were too rigid, that capital punishment did not violate the Constitution, and that retribution was a justifiable basis for execution. The Court also indicated that random and racially biased sentences could be prevented through penalty hearings held after the trial to determine punishment. At penalty hearings, the prosecution and the defense present information about the defendant’s character and background and call for stern or merciful treatment. In most states, a jury decides the penalty, although in some states the judge either makes the decision alone or can overrule the jury. Capital punishment returned to the United States with the execution of Gary Gilmore in Utah in 1977. The rate of executions remained low for some time, and death penalty laws were required to follow due-process rules strictly. During the late 1970s, the Supreme Court handed down decisions that expanded defendants’ rights in capital offense trials and also limited the death penalty to murder cases. Although the Court had taken steps toward regulating the practice of capital punishment, the justices changed course again in the 1980s. The Court narrowed the grounds on which capital defendants could claim legal error, and the rate of executions began slowly but steadily increasing. During the 1980s a majority of the Supreme Court justices attempted without much success to detach the Court from its role in the day-to-day administration of capital punishment. During this same period, the nation revealed its mixed feelings about execution. More than half of all federal appeals court decisions in death penalty cases resulted in death sentences being overturned, and many states delayed resuming executions. Executions began to increase during the 1990s, while the Supreme Court continued to withdraw from active monitoring of the death penalty. In 1994 Justice Harry Blackmun came to the conclusion that it was impossible to balance the two goals associated with the death penalty: eliminating arbitrary or random sentencing and ensuring sentencing appropriate for the individual case. "From this day forward," he wrote, "I no longer shall tinker with the machinery of death." Supreme Court decisions throughout the 1990s tended to limit defendants’ opportunities to have their cases reviewed and, in general, favored the continuance of capital punishment. In early 2010 capital punishment was legal in 36 states. The 2001 execution of Timothy McVeigh, convicted for his role in the 1995 bombing of the Alfred P. Murrah Federal Building in Oklahoma City, marked the first federal execution to be carried out in twenty years. Issues While most Western nations have eliminated capital punishment, many people in the United States continue to believe that this type of justice—summed up by the biblical phrase "an eye for an eye"—is appropriate. Others, however, want to abolish capital punishment because they believe it is immoral, unfair, or both. The moral argument is simply that killing is wrong. Furthermore, killing as retribution is wrong because societies should hold themselves to a higher standard than that of individual murderers. The issues of fairness have to do with the way the death penalty is applied and its possible consequences. Race and Capacity In 1987, in the case of McCleskey v. Kemp, the Supreme Court dealt with the difficult issue of race and capital punishment. Statistical studies showed that African Americans in Georgia were 4.3 times more likely to receive death sentences when they killed whites than when they killed other African Americans. A black man named McCleskey was convicted of killing a white police officer during an armed robbery. McCleskey claimed that the fact that his race made it more likely that he would receive the death penalty was a violation of equal protection guarantees and of the Eighth Amendment’s ban on cruel and unusual punishment. The Court determined that statistics alone could not determine whether a particular individual had faced discrimination. Its ruling stated, "McCleskey must prove that the decision makers in his case acted with discriminatory purpose." But, for many people, the well-established pattern of racial bias in sentencing remains a strong argument against capital punishment. Another death penalty issue concerns the mental capacity of convicted felons. Should mentally retarded criminals face the death penalty? By 2001, eighteen states had banned execution of the mentally retarded. In the 2002 case Atkins v. Virginia the Supreme Court ruled that execution of the mentally retarded violated the cruel and unusual punishment clause of the Eight Amendment to the U.S. Constitution. Preventing Wrongful Executions "If statistics are any indication," said Supreme Court Justice Sandra Day O’Connor in 2001, "the system may well be allowing some innocent defendants to be executed." She was referring to the fact that, since 1973, ninety death row inmates had been freed after a review of evidence proved their innocence. In many cases this evidence consisted of DNA tests that showed there was no way that the convicted criminal could have committed the crime. Advances in technology, such as new and improved methods of DNA testing and other laboratory procedures, have shown that the justice system can make mistakes. Another source of errors is identification or testimony by eyewitnesses to crimes. Countless experiments in psychology have shown that witnesses frequently misinterpret or misremember what they see. If the wrongful conviction of an innocent person is a tragedy, that tragedy increases immeasurably when an innocent person is put to death. The mere possibility of taking the life of an innocent person is, to some, sufficient reason to abolish capital punishment. Source Citation: "Capital Punishment." Current Issues: Macmillan Social Science Library. Detroit: Gale, 2010. Gale Opposing Viewpoints In Context. Web. 9 Apr. 2012. The Death Penalty Should Be Abolished "An execution cannot be used to condemn killing; it is killing." In the following viewpoint, Amnesty International argues that government use of the death penalty as a form of punishment violates human rights as defined by the United Nations' Universal Declaration of Human Rights, and that because of this, the death penalty should be abolished. Additional factors Amnesty examines to support its call for the abolition of the death penalty include the possibility of an innocent person being sentenced to death and the lack of evidence supporting the claim that the threat of death as punishment deters crime. Amnesty International is a global organization dedicated to ensuring the preservation of human rights worldwide. As you read, consider the following questions: 1. What fraction of countries worldwide has abolished the death penalty, according to Amnesty International? 2. Why does Amnesty International believe the death penalty might encourage people to commit politically motivated crimes or acts of terror? 3. What does the "argument for retribution" boil down to, in Amnesty International's view? The time has come to abolish the death penalty worldwide. The case for abolition becomes more compelling with each passing year. Everywhere experience shows that executions brutalize those involved in the process. Nowhere has it been shown that the death penalty has any special power to reduce crime or political violence. In country after country, it is used disproportionately against the poor or against racial or ethnic minorities. It is also used as a tool of political repression. It is imposed and inflicted arbitrarily. It is an irrevocable punishment, resulting inevitably in the execution of people innocent of any crime. It is a violation of fundamental human rights. [Since the late 1990s] an average of at least three countries a year have abolished the death penalty, affirming respect for human life and dignity. Yet too many governments still believe that they can solve urgent social or political problems by executing a few or even hundreds of their prisoners. Too many citizens in too many countries are still unaware that the death penalty offers society not further protection but further brutalization. Abolition is gaining ground, but not fast enough. The death penalty, carried out in the name of the nation's entire population, involves everyone. Everyone should be aware of what the death penalty is, how it is used, how it affects them, how it violates fundamental rights. The death penalty is the premeditated and cold-blooded killing of a human being by the state. The state can exercise no greater power over a person than that of deliberately depriving him or her of life. At the heart of the case for abolition, therefore, is the question of whether the state has the right to do so. A Human Rights Issue When the world's nations came together [in 1945] to found the United Nations (UN), few reminders were needed of what could happen when a state believed that there was no limit to what it might do to a human being. The staggering extent of state brutality and terror during World War II and the consequences for people throughout the world were still unfolding in December 1948, when the UN General Assembly adopted without dissent the Universal Declaration of Human Rights. The Universal Declaration is a pledge among nations to promote fundamental rights as the foundation of freedom, justice and peace. The rights it proclaims are inherent in every human being. They are not privileges that may be granted by governments for good behaviour and they may not be withdrawn for bad behaviour. Fundamental human rights limit what a state may do to a man, woman or child. No matter what reason a government gives for executing prisoners and what method of execution is used, the death penalty cannot be separated from the issue of human rights. The movement for abolition cannot be separated from the movement for human rights. The Universal Declaration recognizes each person's right to life and categorically states further that "No one shall be subjected to torture or to cruel, inhuman or degrading treatment or punishment". In Amnesty International's view the death penalty violates these rights. Self-defence may be held to justify, in some cases, the taking of life by state officials: for example, when a country is locked in warfare (international or civil) or when law-enforcement officials must act immediately to save their own lives or those of others. Even in such situations the use of lethal force is surrounded by internationally accepted legal safeguards to inhibit abuse. This use of force is aimed at countering the immediate damage resulting from force used by others. The death penalty, however, is not an act of self-defence against an immediate threat to life. It is the premeditated killing of a prisoner who could be dealt with equally well by less harsh means. State Subsidized Torture There can never be a justification for torture or for cruel, inhumane or degrading treatment or punishment. The cruelty of the death penalty is evident. Like torture, an execution constitutes an extreme physical and mental assault on a person already rendered helpless by government authorities. If hanging a woman by her arms until she experiences excruciating pain is rightly condemned as torture, how does one describe hanging her by the neck until she is dead? If administering 100 volts of electricity to the most sensitive parts of a man's body evokes disgust, what is the appropriate reaction to the administration of 2,000 volts to his body in order to kill him? If a pistol held to the head or a chemical substance injected to cause protracted suffering are clearly instruments of torture, how should they be identified when used to kill by shooting or lethal injection? Does the use of legal process in these cruelties make their inhumanity justifiable? The physical pain caused by the action of killing a human being cannot be quantified. Nor can the psychological suffering caused by fore-knowledge of death at the hands of the state. Whether a death sentence is carried out six minutes after a summary trial, six weeks after a mass trial or 16 years after lengthy legal proceedings, the person executed is subjected to uniquely cruel, inhuman and degrading treatment and punishment. Internationally agreed laws and standards stipulate that the death penalty can only be used after a fair judicial process. When a state convicts prisoners without affording them a fair trial, it denies the right to due process and equality before the law. The irrevocable punishment of death removes not only the victim's right to seek redress for wrongful conviction, but also the judicial system's capacity to correct its errors. Like killings which take place outside the law, the death penalty denies the value of human life. By violating the right to life, it removes the foundation for realization of all rights enshrined in the Universal Declaration of Human Rights. As the Human Rights Committee set up under the [UN's] International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights has recognized, "The right to life ... is the supreme right from which no derogation is permitted even in time of public emergency which threatens the life of the nation ..." In a general comment on Article 6 of the Covenant issued in 1982, the Committee concluded that "all measures of abolition [of the death penalty] should be considered as progress in the enjoyment of the right to life within the meaning of Article 40". Many governments have recognized that the death penalty cannot be reconciled with respect for human rights. The UN has declared itself in favour of abolition. Two-thirds of the countries in the world have now abolished the death penalty in law or practice.... Amnesty International's statistics also show a significant overall decline in the number of reported executions in 2006. In 2006, 91% of all known executions took place in a small number of countries: China, Iran, Iraq, Pakistan, Sudan and the USA. Europe is almost a death penaltyfree-zone—the main exception being Belarus; in Africa only six states carried out executions in 2006; in the Americas only the USA has carried out executions since 2003. Justifying the Death Penalty Unlike torture, "disappearances" and extrajudicial executions, most judicial executions are not carried out in secret or denied by government authorities. Executions are often announced in advance. In some countries they are carried out in public or before a group of invited observers. No government publicly admits to torture or other grave violations of human rights, although privately some officials may seek to justify such abuses in the name of the "greater good". But retentionist governments, those that keep the death penalty, for the most part openly admit to using it: they do not so much deny its cruelty as attempt to justify its use; and the arguments they use publicly to justify the death penalty resemble those that are used in private to justify other, secret abuses. The most common justification offered is that, terrible as it is, the death penalty is necessary: it may be necessary only temporarily, but, it is argued, only the death penalty can meet a particular need of society. And whatever that need may be it is claimed to be so great that it justifies the cruel punishment of death. The particular needs claimed to be served by the death penalty differ from time to time and from society to society. In some countries the penalty is considered legitimate as a means of preventing or punishing the crime of murder. Elsewhere it may be deemed indispensable to stop drug-trafficking, acts of political terror, economic corruption or adultery. In yet other countries, it is used to eliminate those seen as posing a political threat to the authorities. Once one state uses the death penalty for any reason, it becomes easier for other states to use it with an appearance of legitimacy for whatever reasons they may choose. If the death penalty can be justified for one offence, justifications that accord with the prevailing view of a society or its rulers will be found for it to be used for other offences. Whatever purpose is cited, the idea that a government can justify a punishment as cruel as death conflicts with the very concept of human rights. The significance of human rights is precisely that some means may never be used to protect society because their use violates the very values which make society worth protecting. When this essential distinction between appropriate and inappropriate means is set aside in the name of some "greater good", all rights are vulnerable and all individuals are threatened. No Evidence for Deterrence The death penalty, as a violation of fundamental human rights, would be wrong even if it could be shown that it uniquely met a vital social need. What makes the use of the death penalty even more indefensible and the case for its abolition even more compelling is that it has never been shown to have any special power to meet any genuine social need. Countless men and women have been executed for the stated purpose of preventing crime, especially the crime of murder. Yet Amnesty International has failed to find convincing evidence that the death penalty has any unique capacity to deter others from commiting particular crimes. A survey of research findings on the relation between the death penalty and homicide rates, conducted for the UN in 1988 and updated in 2002, concluded: "... it is not prudent to accept the hypothesis that capital punishment deters murder to a marginally greater extent than does the threat and application of the supposedly lesser punishment of life imprisonment". Undeniably the death penalty, by permanently "incapacitating" a prisoner, prevents that person from repeating the crime. But there is no way to be sure that the prisoner would indeed have repeated the crime if allowed to live, nor is there any need to violate the prisoner's right to life for the purpose of incapacitation: dangerous offenders can be kept safely away from the public without resorting to execution, as shown by the experience of many abolitionist countries. Nor is there evidence that the threat of the death penalty will prevent politically motivated crimes or acts of terror. If anything, the possibility of political martyrdom through execution may encourage people to commit such crimes. Every society seeks protection from crimes. Far from being a solution, the death penalty gives the erroneous impression that "firm measures" are being taken against crime. It diverts attention from the more complex measures which are really needed. In the words of the South African Constitution Court in 1995, "We would be deluding ourselves if we were to believe that the execution of ... a comparatively few people each year ... will provide the solution to the unacceptably high rate of crime ... The greatest deterrent to crime is the likelihood that offenders will be apprehended, convicted and punished". The Dangerous Logic of Retribution When the arguments of deterrence and incapacitation fall away, one is left with a more deepseated justification for the death penalty: that of just retribution for the particular crime committed. According to this argument, certain people deserve to be killed as repayment for the evil done: there are crimes so offensive that killing the offender is the only just response. It is an emotionally powerful argument. It is also one which, if valid, would invalidate the basis for human rights. If a person who commits a terrible act can "deserve" the cruelty of death, why cannot others, for similar reasons, "deserve" to be tortured or imprisoned without trial or simply shot on sight? Central to fundamental human rights is that they are inalienable. They may not be taken away even if a person has committed the most atrocious of crimes. Human rights apply to the worst of us as well as to the best of us, which is why they protect all of us. What the argument for retribution boils down to, is often no more than a desire for vengeance masked as a principle of justice. The desire for vengeance can be understood and acknowledged but the exercise of vengeance must be resisted. The history of the endeavour to establish the rule of law is a history of the progressive restriction of personal vengeance in public policy and legal codes. If today's penal systems do not sanction the burning of an arsonist's home, the rape of the rapist or the torture of the torturer, it is not because they tolerate the crimes. Instead, it is because societies understand that they must be built on a different set of values from those they condemn. An execution cannot be used to condemn killing; it is killing. Such an act by the state is the mirror image of the criminal's willingness to use physical violence against a victim. Innocent People Will Be Executed Related to the argument that some people "deserve" to die is the proposition that the state is capable of determining exactly who they are. Whatever one's view of the retribution argument may be, the practice of the death penalty reveals that no criminal justice system is, or conceivably could be, capable of deciding fairly, consistently and infallibly who should live and who should die. All criminal justice systems are vulnerable to discrimination and error. Expediency, discretionary decisions and prevailing public opinion may influence the proceedings at every stage from the initial arrest to the last-minute decision clemency. The reality of the death penalty is that what determines who shall be executed and who shall be spared is often not only the nature of the crimes but also the ethnic and social background, the financial means or the political opinions of the defendant. The death penalty is used disproportionately against the poor, the powerless, the marginalised or those whom repressive governments deem it expedient to eliminate. Human uncertainty and arbitrary judgements are factors which affect all judicial decisions. But only one decision—the decision to execute—results in something that cannot be remedied or undone. Whether executions take place within hours of a summary trial or after years of protracted legal proceedings, states will continue to execute people who are later found to be innocent. Those executed cannot be compensated for loss of life and the whole society must share responsibility for what has been done. Abolition Is the Only Answer It is the irrevocable nature of the death penalty, the fact that the prisoner is eliminated forever, that makes the penalty so tempting to some states as a tool of repression. Thousands have been put to death under one government only to be recognized as innocent victims when another set of authorities comes to power. Only abolition can ensure that such political abuse of the death penalty will never occur. When used to crush political dissent, the death penalty is abhorrent. When invoked as a way to protect society from crime, it is illusory. Wherever used, it brutalizes those involved in the process and conveys to the public a sense that killing a defenceless prisoner is somehow acceptable. It may be used to try to bolster the authority of the state—or of those who govern in its name. But any such authority it confers is spurious. The penalty is a symbol of terror and, to that extent, a confession of weakness. It is always a violation of the most fundamental human rights. Each society and its citizens have the choice to decide about the sort of world people want and will work to achieve: a world in which the state is permitted to kill as a legal punishment or a world based on respect for human life and human rights—a world without executions. Source Citation: International, Amnesty. "The Death Penalty Should Be Abolished." Criminal Justice. Ed. David Haugen and Susan Musser. Detroit: Greenhaven Press, 2009. Opposing Viewpoints. Rpt. from "The Death Penalty v. Human Rights: Why Abolish the Death Penalty?" 2007. Gale Opposing Viewpoints In Context. Web. 9 Apr. 2012. The Death Penalty Should Not Be Abolished "Capital punishment produces a strong deterrent effect that saves lives." In the following viewpoint, David B. Muhlhausen argues that capital punishment should not be abandoned because it deters crimes, saves lives, and the majority of American citizens support its use. Additionally, he maintains that evidence does not support claims that racial discrimination results in a disproportionate number of African Americans incarcerated on death row. David B. Muhlhausen is a senior policy analyst in the area of criminal justice for the Heritage Foundation, a conservative public policy research organization. As you read, consider the following questions: 1. According to the 2006 study conducted by the RAND Corporation, what affects whether the death penalty is sought as punishment for a crime? 2. What are the three findings of Joanna M. Shepherd's analysis of data from 1977 to 1999 on the death penalty? 3. Based on research conducted by H. Naci Mocan and R. Kaj Gittings, how many murders result from each commutation of a death row sentence? While opponents of capital punishment have been very vocal in their opposition, Gallup opinion polls consistently demonstrate that the American public overwhelmingly supports capital punishment. In Gallup's most recent poll, 67 percent of Americans favor the death penalty for those convicted of murder, while only 28 percent are opposed. From 2000 to the most recent poll in 2006, support for capital punishment consistently runs a 2:1 ratio in favor. Despite strong public support for capital punishment, federal, state, and local officials must continually ensure that its implementation rigorously upholds constitutional protections, such as due process and equal protection of the law. However, the criminal process should not be abused to prevent the lawful imposition of the death penalty in appropriate capital cases. Crime Characteristics More Important Than Race As of December 2005, there were 37 prisoners under a sentence of death in the federal system. Of these prisoners, 43.2 percent were white, while 54.1 percent were African-American. The fact that African-Americans are a majority of federal prisoners on death row and a minority in the overall United States population may lead some to conclude that the federal system discriminates against African-Americans. However, there is little rigorous evidence that such disparities exist in the federal system. Under a competitive grant process, the National Institute of Justice awarded the RAND Corporation a grant to determine whether racial disparities exist in the federal death penalty system. The resulting 2006 RAND study set out to determine what factors, including the defendant's race, victim's race, and crime characteristics, affect the decision to seek a death penalty case. Three independent teams of researchers were tasked with developing their own methodologies to analyze the data. Only after each team independently drew their own conclusions did they share their findings with each other. When first looking at the raw data without controlling for case characteristics, RAND found that large race effects with the decision to seek the death penalty are more likely to occur when the defendants are white and when the victims are white. However, these disparities disappeared in each of the three studies when the heinousness of the crimes was taken into account. The RAND study concludes that the findings support the view that decisions to seek the death penalty are driven by characteristics of crimes rather than by race. RAND's findings are very compelling because three independent research teams, using the same data but different methodologies, reached the same conclusions. While there is little evidence that the federal capital punishment system treats minorities unfairly, some may argue that the death penalty systems in certain states may be discriminatory. One such state is Maryland. In May 2001, then-Governor Parris Glendening instituted a moratorium on the use of capital punishment in Maryland in light of concerns that it may be unevenly applied to minorities, especially African-Americans. In 2000, Governor Glendening commissioned University of Maryland Professor of Criminology Ray Paternoster to study the possibility of racial discrimination in the application of the death penalty in Maryland. The results of Professor Paternoster's study found that black defendants who murder white victims are substantially more likely to be charged with a capital crime and sentenced to death. In 2003, Governor Robert L. Ehrlich wisely lifted the moratorium. His decision was justified. In 2005, a careful review of the study by Professor of Statistics and Sociology Richard Berk of the University of California, Los Angeles, and his coauthors found that the results of Professor Paternoster's study do not stand up to statistical scrutiny. According to Professor Berk's reanalysis, "For both capital charges and death sentences, race either played no role or a small role that is very difficult to specify. In short, it is very difficult to find convincing evidence for racial effects in the Maryland data and if there are any, they may not be additive." Further, race may have a small influence because "cases with a black defendant and white victim or 'other' racial combination are less likely to have a death sentence." The Death Penalty Deters Crime Federal, state, and local officials need to recognize that the death penalty saves lives. How capital punishment affects murder rates can be explained through general deterrence theory, which supposes that increasing the risk of apprehension and punishment for crime deters individuals from committing crime. Nobel laureate Gary S. Becker's seminal 1968 study of the economics of crime assumed that individuals respond to the costs and benefits of committing crime. According to deterrence theory, criminals are no different from law-abiding people. Criminals [economist Paul H. Rubin writes] "rationally maximize their own self-interest (utility) subject to constraints (prices, incomes) that they face in the marketplace and elsewhere." Individuals make their decisions based on the net costs and benefits of each alternative. Thus, deterrence theory provides a basis for analyzing how capital punishment should influence murder rates. Over the years, several studies have demonstrated a link between executions and decreases in murder rates. In fact, studies done in recent years, using sophisticated panel data methods, consistently demonstrate a strong link between executions and reduced murder incidents. The rigorous examination of the deterrent effect of capital punishment began with research in the 1970s by Isaac Ehrlich, currently a University of Buffalo Distinguished Professor of Economics. Professor Ehrlich's research found that the death penalty had a strong deterrent effect. While his research was debated by other scholars, additional research by Professor Ehrlich reconfirmed his original findings. In addition, research by Professor Stephen K. Layson of the University of North Carolina at Greensboro strongly reconfirmed Ehrlich's previous findings. The Death Penalty Saves Lives Numerous studies published over the past few years, using panel data sets [statisticians make distinctions between panel sets vs. what they call "one-dimensional," or "cross-sectional" data sets] and sophisticated social science techniques, are demonstrating that the death penalty saves lives. Panel studies observe multiple units over several periods. The addition of multiple data collection points gives the results of capital punishment panel studies substantially more credibility than the results of studies that have only single before-and-after intervention measures. Further, the longitudinal nature of the panel data allows researchers to analyze the impact of the death penalty over time that cross-sectional data sets cannot address. Using a panel data set of over 3,000 counties from 1977 to 1996, Professors Hashem Dezhbakhsh, Paul R. Rubin, and Joanna M. Shepherd of Emory University found that each execution, on average, results in 18 fewer murders. Using state-level panel data from 1960 to 2000, Professors Dezhbakhsh and Shepherd were able to compare the relationship between executions and murder incidents before, during, and after the U.S. Supreme Court's death penalty moratorium. They found that executions had a highly significant negative relationship with murder incidents. Additionally, the implementation of state moratoria is associated with the increased incidence of murders. Separately, Professor Shepherd's analysis of monthly data from 1977 to 1999 found three important findings. First, each execution, on average, is associated with three fewer murders. The deterred murders included both crimes of passion and murders by intimates. Second, executions deter the murder of whites and African-Americans. Each execution prevents the murder of one white person, 1.5 African-Americans, and 0.5 persons of other races. Third, shorter waits on death row are associated with increased deterrence. For each additional 2.75-year reduction in the death row wait until execution, one murder is deterred. Commuting Death Penalty Sentences Is Deadly Professors H. Naci Mocan and R. Kaj Gittings of the University of Colorado at Denver have published two studies confirming the deterrent effect of capital punishment. The first study used state-level data from 1977 to 1997 to analyze the influence of executions, commutations, and removals from death row on the incidence of murder. For each additional execution, on average, about five murders were deterred. Alternatively, for each additional commutation, on average, five additional murders resulted. A removal from death row by either state courts or the U.S. Supreme Court is associated with an increase of one additional murder. Addressing criticism of their work, Professors Mocan and Gittings conducted additional analyses and found that their original findings provided robust support for the deterrent effect of capital punishment. Two studies by Paul R. Zimmerman, a Federal Communications Commission economist, also support the deterrent effect of capital punishment. Using state-level data from 1978 to 1997, Zimmerman found that each additional execution, on average, results in 14 fewer murders. Zimmerman's second study, using similar data, found that executions conducted by electrocution are the most effective at providing deterrence. Using a small state-level data set from 1995 to 1999, Professor Robert B. Ekelund of Auburn University and his colleagues analyzed the effect that executions have on single incidents of murder and multiple incidents of murder. They found that executions reduced single murder rates, while there was no effect on multiple murder rates. In summary, the recent studies using panel data techniques have confirmed what we learned decades ago: Capital punishment does, in fact, save lives. Each additional execution appears to deter between three and 18 murders. While opponents of capital punishment allege that it is unfairly used against African-Americans, each additional execution deters the murder of 1.5 African-Americans. Further moratoria, commuted sentences, and death row removals appear to increase the incidence of murder. The strength of these findings has caused some legal scholars, originally opposed to the death penalty on moral grounds, to rethink their case. In particular, Professor Cass R. Sunstein of the University of Chicago has commented: If the recent evidence of deterrence is shown to be correct, then opponents of capital punishment will face an uphill struggle on moral grounds. If each execution is saving lives, the harms of capital punishment would have to be very great to justify its abolition, far greater than most critics have heretofore alleged. Americans support capital punishment for two good reasons. First, there is little evidence to suggest that minorities are treated unfairly. Second, capital punishment produces a strong deterrent effect that saves lives. Source Citation: Muhlhausen, David B. "The Death Penalty Should Not Be Abolished." Criminal Justice. Ed. David Haugen and Susan Musser. Detroit: Greenhaven Press, 2009. Opposing Viewpoints. Rpt. from "The Death Penalty Deters Crime and Saves Lives." Heritage Foundation. 2007. Gale Opposing Viewpoints In Context. Web. 9 Apr. 2012. Censorship Censorship is the regulation or suppression of writing or speech that is considered harmful to the common good or a threat to national security. Although censorship can be carried out by private individuals or corporations, the term is typically used to refer to government efforts to control speech or media content. The First Amendment to the U.S. Constitution states that "Congress shall make no law … abridging the freedom of speech, or of the press." There are exceptions to this guarantee of freedom of expression, however, with some classes of speech enjoying greater protection than others. History of Censorship The modern idea of censorship first emerged in Western Europe shortly after the invention of the printing press in the late 1400s. Before that time, most books and manuscripts in Europe were created in monasteries, which controlled what could be written. The printing press ended the monasteries’ control over the written word and resulted in the publication and distribution of a greater variety of written materials. Governments soon took over the task of censorship. Many countries established offices to monitor the media and to prohibit the publication of materials considered offensive, undesirable, or a threat to the state. As democratic ideas became more widespread, so did resistance to censorship. Many English and French philosophers of the 1700s argued that freedom of expression was essential to the practice of democracy. They claimed that suppressing ideas denied citizens access to information they needed to participate effectively in a democratic system. British common law reflected this view, banning government control of speech and published materials. The framers of the U.S. Constitution followed the British example in trying to protect citizens’ freedom of expression from interference by the government. However, the limits of this protection were soon tested, and they have been the subject of debate ever since. Protected and Unprotected Speech Not all forms of speech are entitled to equal protection under U.S. law. Cultural, social, or religious expressions have the highest value in the eyes of the law, and authorities must provide a compelling reason to limit or censor such speech. Political speech in particular cannot be regulated unless it is likely to spur people to lawlessness. However, government agencies can limit the publication of or access to material that could compromise national security. Some other forms of expression come under stricter rules of censorship. Pornographic or obscene material, for example, enjoys very little protection under the law. Congress and state governments have the right to censor such works. State law and local community standards are used to determine whether a work is obscene, allowing for different interpretations from place to place. Child pornography, on the other hand, is prohibited throughout the United States and in most other nations. Commercial speech, such as advertising, was once viewed as not protected by the First Amendment and was often strictly regulated. Although commercial speech now enjoys greater protection, the government can still censor false or misleading advertising if it can prove that the harm caused by censorship is less than that caused by the advertisement. In recent years there has been much debate over the censorship of hate speech, which demeans someone’s race, religion, gender, or sexual orientation. Some people feel it should be treated as "fighting words"—words meant to provoke a fight—a form of speech that the Constitution does not protect. Others fear that allowing censorship of hate speech would lead the government to suppress other ideas it finds undesirable. Media Censorship Although the Supreme Court has been reluctant to regulate print media, such as newspapers, magazines, and books, it has been more willing to place restrictions on broadcast media. There are three main reasons for this. First, the paper and presses used by print media are privately owned, but radio and television airwaves are publicly owned. Second, anybody who can set up a press can produce a newspaper, but the limited availability of broadcast frequencies restricts the number of possible radio or television stations. Finally, people can easily control the content they read, but it is much more difficult for people to control the content they or their children might hear or see in a radio or television program. Government control of the airwaves occurs in many ways, the most basic of which is licensing. Radio and television broadcasters must be licensed by the Federal Communications Commission (FCC) and must renew their licenses periodically. The government also requires that broadcasters serve the public interest. This includes airing local news programs and public service announcements, as well as running all political advertisements, not just those that support the broadcaster’s point of view. The FCC can also restrict, in the public interest, programs that it finds "indecent." International Perspectives While citizens in democratic countries enjoy considerable freedom of speech, people in many nations experience censorship on a daily basis. Authoritarian governments often use censorship as a way to restrict the information their citizens receive and to maintain power over people. Perhaps the most widespread method is through government control of the press. Many governments also suppress opposing viewpoints by requiring journalists to be licensed by the state, managing the distribution of newsprint, or withholding government advertising. Some governments try to prevent citizens from receiving news from outside sources. For example, they may prohibit the ownership of satellite dishes. However, the expansion of the Internet presents a serious challenge to the control of information. It is very difficult to restrict access to the Internet. In addition, because computer-based communications play a central role in today’s economy, denying people access to these communications may endanger the strength and health of the state. As the U.S. media becomes increasingly dominant around the world, some governments are seeking to limit the amount of American movies and television programming that can enter their countries. Those who support such efforts feel that U.S. culture threatens to overwhelm local cultures or to undermine their values with scenes of violence and sex and of a lifestyle well furnished with material goods. Such concerns are likely to intensify as nations become more involved in the global marketplace. Full Text: COPYRIGHT 2012 Gale, Cengage Learning. Source Citation: "Censorship." Current Issues: Macmillan Social Science Library. Detroit: Gale, 2010. Gale Opposing Viewpoints In Context. Web. 9 Apr. 2012. The Arts Should Be Censored "The public has an interest in preventing the pollution of its artistic culture—and the law should reflect that interest." In the following viewpoint, columnist Ben Shapiro argues that laws must be enacted to set limits on free artistic expression. He cites several examples of artists whose unbound "free expression" has crossed the boundaries of acceptable public expression. Unless regulations are enacted, he insists, artists will continue to create art that is obscene, vulgar, and demeaning to human beings. Moreover, he fears that this "art" will become the norm, to the detriment of the culture at large. As you read, consider the following questions: 1. How does Ben Shapiro describe Aliza Shvarts's so-called art project? 2. What rights besides artistic freedom have limits, according to Shapiro? 3. Who were some of the past artists that flourished despite the imposition of restrictions on free expression, as noted by the author? Art, they say, is in the eye of the beholder. No one has come up with a workable definition of art that can universally separate garbage like Karen Finley's body goo1 from Michelangelo's David. And because art is so difficult, so amorphous and difficult to define, civilized people have shied away from attempting to place limits on it. The best policy, we have decided, is to allow everything into the artistic marketplace, and let history and time sort it all out. There's only one problem with this strategy: If you pollute the artistic marketplace with unmitigated crap, no one will want to visit the marketplace. Art itself will die, or at least be relegated to the few, proud elitists who busily wade through mountains of manure, proclaiming it intellectual gold. The Need for Limits Art thrives most when it has reasonable limits. When there are no hard limits, artists who push the envelope are given the most attention. Those "artists" attract the most imitators. And so the "artist" who drops a crucifix in a jar of urine [a reference to a work by photographer Andres Serrano] breeds the "artist" who douses herself in chocolate syrup [Finley]. The "artist" who douses herself in chocolate syrup breeds the "artist" who engages in acts of sodomy before a live audience [a reference to the play The Romans in Britain, which contains a scene in which a man rapes another man]. And all of these artists breed the "artist" who supposedly artificially inseminates herself, induces her own miscarriages, films those miscarriages, saves the blood, mixes it with Vaseline, spreads the mixture on saran wrap and then projects the video of her miscarriages onto the saran wrap screen. Last week [April 2008], a national furor arose over Yale student Aliza Shvarts's "art" project, which contemplated doing just that: projecting abortion videos onto abortion leftovers. The political right was understandably outraged—the immorality of the abortions is sick-making on its own. The political left was, somewhat puzzlingly, also perturbed—they condemned Shvarts's "approach and presentation," though one struggles to see their problem, considering Shvarts's repeated abortions are legal only due to their adamant support for abortion-on-demand. The Art World's Response The art world was largely silent on Shvarts's project. They were not silent, however, on the prospect of censorship. "Public media has been practicing vigilant self-censorship ever since (Sept. 11, 2001)—in my opinion, a very irresponsible choice," said performance artist, Yale lecturer and probable Shvarts-advisor Pia Lindman. "I am still waiting for this self-aggrandizing mass psychosis; the uncritical belief in the omnipotence and goodness of the American people, troops and government, to dissolve and have it replaced with sober self-reflection." Cary Nelson of the American Association of University Professors was more circumspect: "Academic freedom for faculty and intellectual freedom for students give them the right to speech that shocks and challenges." Helaine S. Klasky, spokeswoman for Yale, stated, "The entire project is an art piece, a creative fiction designed to draw attention to the ambiguity surrounding form and function of a woman's body. (Shvarts) is an artist and has the right to express herself through performance art." All rights have reasonable limits. The right to bear arms does not include a right to own a nuclear weapon. The right to free exercise of religion does not include a right to ritualistic child sacrifice. The right to free expression in art should not include a right to film yourself having an abortion; neither should it include a right to use feces, urine or any other bodily fluid in public, nor should it include a right to engage in sex acts before live audiences. The public has an interest in preventing the pollution of its artistic culture—and the law should reflect that interest. As for the "boundary-pushing" performance "artists," those "artists" who cannot work within the bounds of common decency should find another line of work. [William] Shakespeare somehow worked within the strict guidelines of his time; so did da Vinci, and so did Beethoven, Brahms, Bach and Mozart. If Aliza Shvarts, Robert Mapplethorpe [a controversial photographer whose work is sometimes sexually explicit], Andres Serrano and other "artists" cannot do the same, they ought to consider going into the demolition business. After all, they're so good at destroying worthwhile ideas and limits already. Footnotes 1. 1. Karen Finley is a controversial performance artist whose shows have included smearing her body with chocolate and other substances. Source Citation: Shapiro, Ben. "The Arts Should Be Censored." Censorship. Ed. Byron L. Stay. San Diego: Greenhaven Press, 1997. Opposing Viewpoints. Rpt. from "No Bodily Fluids in the Public Square." Human Events.com. 2008. Gale Opposing Viewpoints In Context. Web. 9 Apr. 2012. The Arts Should Not Be Censored "Artists have a right—and sometimes a duty—to offend their audiences." Dominic Cooke is an English theatre director, playwright, and the artistic director of the Royal Court Theatre in London. In the following viewpoint, he argues that while official censorship of the arts has decreased, a dangerous self-censorship has taken its place. He notes several attempts by fundamentalist religious groups to censor art they consider offensive. These efforts, he believes, have led artists to stifle their own views out of fear of offending overly sensitive religious groups, thus diminishing the power of their art to provoke thought and dialogue on important issues. As you read, consider the following questions: 1. How did William Gaskill evade the censors, according to the author? 2. Why is Terence Koh's exhibition controversial, as reported by Dominic Cooke? 3. How do liberals complicate the issue of self-censorship of the arts, as explained by the author? Forty years ago, the Theatres Bill removed from the Lord Chamberlain [the senior officer of the Royal Household] his centuries-old power to censor the British stage. Under a law unchanged since 1843, every work intended for production in British theatres had first to be submitted to, and approved by, his office. Each work came back with a report from one of the censors, who became renowned for their hypersensitive ability to read sex and subversion into the most innocent of dialogue. Kenneth Tynan quotes some choice reports in his famous 1965 polemic The Royal Smut-Hound: the phrase 'balls of the Medici' is banned, for example (although the report does give the helpful suggestion that 'testicles of the Medici' would be acceptable). Another personal favourite, also quoted by Tynan, is the following masterpiece of straight-faced absurdity: 'Page 14: Omit "the perversions of rubber". Substitute "the kreurpels and blinges of the rubber". Omit the chamber pot under the bed.' As well as Tynan, the Royal Court Theatre, under its artistic director William Gaskill, fought bitterly against the Lord Chamberlain's office, even, on occasion, openly flouting the censor's demands. At performances of Edward Bond's Early Morning, Royal Court patrons were charged a 'membership fee' on the door, rather than being sold a ticket, thereby exploiting a loophole which exempted private theatre clubs from censorship. Aside from the more comical aberrations of the censor's pencil, there is, of course, a sinister side to the limiting of freedom of speech by a government-appointed official. Peter Hall has written wisely about the function of censorship as 'a means of exerting power, preventing debate and discouraging challenge'. It is a despicable form of bullying, made all the more hurtful and infuriating when legitimised by the state, or other institutions. At last, in September 1968, common sense prevailed and the law was changed. The single biggest limit on the freedom of expression in British theatre was abolished, and new worlds of possibilities opened up to writers and directors. The Danger of Self-Censorship But censorship remains. A whole generation of playwrights has grown old without the amendments of the blue pencil, but the limits placed on our speech now come not from the government, but from our own fear of repercussion in the face of religious extremism. Artists have a right—and sometimes a duty—to offend their audiences. And audiences have a right— and sometimes a duty—to be offended by what they see or hear. But when it is generally assumed that an audience has a right not to be offended, then the restrictions imposed upon an artist are just as stifling as the Lord Chamberlain's. I say this because Terence Koh's recent exhibition, which includes a statue of Christ with an erection, has re-inflamed the debate about the rights and wrongs of art which offends. I have not seen the exhibition, but I support the Baltic Centre in presenting it. The ongoing battle against the suppression of free expression will not be won by fearing to cause offence. Nevertheless, it is true that sometimes the reaction to a piece will deny it the chance of a fair appraisal, necessitating a painful act of self-censorship on the part of arts programmers. One does not need an encyclopaedic knowledge of British culture to be able to name an example of modern attempts at censorship. The fatwa against Salman Rushdie, the pickets outside Jerry Springer—The Opera, the violent protests against Behzti at the Birmingham Repertory Theatre.1In all these cases, religious fundamentalists have attempted and, in the example of Birmingham, won their attempt to deny freedom of expression to artists, and to audiences the opportunity to make up their own minds. Of course, the claims are specious. To fear that a centuries-old faith might be endangered by one play, or that a person's strongly held beliefs may be devalued by somebody else disagreeing, or even satirising them, reveals a hatred of plurality that is common to all fascist ideologies. However, it is made more complex by the fact that many liberals, out of a fear of appearing racist, and with shared sympathy for many of the political causes that also motivate those with a fundamentalist agenda turn a blind eye to such intolerance. Examples such as the ones above are rare. And the groups that cause them are small, and led by literalists rather than the majority of religious believers. Nevertheless, such actions, especially when successful, foster fear in artistic organisations of the possible ramifications of producing work that criticises religion. This is a profoundly insidious form of censorship, unspoken and therefore hard to criticise. A Self-Perpetuating Climate of Fear Sometimes this is a result of a genuine safety threat posed to arts organisations. The management of Birmingham Rep, faced with credible threats of violence against their staff, and without adequate protection from the police, had no choice but to pull Behzti. I do not blame them for that. But I believe we are in danger of reaching a situation where a fear of offending has become so internalised and automatic that it isn't even noticed. It may appear well intentioned, but it is no less harmful to free speech than the Lord Chamberlain. The only way we can establish our boundaries is by testing them, and the overly sensitive suppression of anything that even brushes against those boundaries creates a self-perpetuating climate of fear and timidity. For once arts organisations cease to present work that might offend, artists will cease to create it. Then the small-minded, the bigoted, and the self-righteous can celebrate their victory, and the arts world can only count its losses. But every morning when I arrive at work, I long to find in that day's post good plays that are not hampered by fear of what they can and can't say, or by fear of causing offence. Plays like Christopher Shinn's Now or Later, which is accurate in its analysis of the complex question of the limits of pluralism and its conflict with fundamentalism. The theatre I run exists to produce exactly those plays. They're out there. They've probably already been written, and I am convinced that there are hundreds of people who could yet write them, even if they have never considered doing so. I want that play, and I want the Royal Court to produce it. And when we do, we may fear the consequences, but if we feel the play can bear it, that certainly wouldn't stop us. Footnotes 1. 1. In 1989, the Ayatollah Khomeini, the leader of Iran, issued a fatwa, or religious decree, calling for the death of author Salman Rushdie for his book The Satanic Verses, which he deemed blasphemous toward Islam. In 2005, Jerry Springer—The Opera, a musical comedy based on the Jerry Springer TV show, was deemed blasphemous by Christian groups. In 2004, riots broke out on opening night of Behzti, a play that was viewed as offensive to Sikhs, leading to cancellation of the play. Source Citation: Cooke, Dominic. "The Arts Should Not Be Censored." Censorship. Ed. Byron L. Stay. San Diego: Greenhaven Press, 1997. Opposing Viewpoints. Rpt. from "An Insidious Form of Censorship." Spectator (11 Oct. 2008): 49. Gale Opposing Viewpoints In Context. Web. 9 Apr. 2012. The Arts Should Be Censored "The public has an interest in preventing the pollution of its artistic culture—and the law should reflect that interest." In the following viewpoint, columnist Ben Shapiro argues that laws must be enacted to set limits on free artistic expression. He cites several examples of artists whose unbound "free expression" has crossed the boundaries of acceptable public expression. Unless regulations are enacted, he insists, artists will continue to create art that is obscene, vulgar, and demeaning to human beings. Moreover, he fears that this "art" will become the norm, to the detriment of the culture at large. As you read, consider the following questions: 1. How does Ben Shapiro describe Aliza Shvarts's so-called art project? 2. What rights besides artistic freedom have limits, according to Shapiro? 3. Who were some of the past artists that flourished despite the imposition of restrictions on free expression, as noted by the author? Art, they say, is in the eye of the beholder. No one has come up with a workable definition of art that can universally separate garbage like Karen Finley's body goo1 from Michelangelo's David. And because art is so difficult, so amorphous and difficult to define, civilized people have shied away from attempting to place limits on it. The best policy, we have decided, is to allow everything into the artistic marketplace, and let history and time sort it all out. There's only one problem with this strategy: If you pollute the artistic marketplace with unmitigated crap, no one will want to visit the marketplace. Art itself will die, or at least be relegated to the few, proud elitists who busily wade through mountains of manure, proclaiming it intellectual gold. The Need for Limits Art thrives most when it has reasonable limits. When there are no hard limits, artists who push the envelope are given the most attention. Those "artists" attract the most imitators. And so the "artist" who drops a crucifix in a jar of urine [a reference to a work by photographer Andres Serrano] breeds the "artist" who douses herself in chocolate syrup [Finley]. The "artist" who douses herself in chocolate syrup breeds the "artist" who engages in acts of sodomy before a live audience [a reference to the play The Romans in Britain, which contains a scene in which a man rapes another man]. And all of these artists breed the "artist" who supposedly artificially inseminates herself, induces her own miscarriages, films those miscarriages, saves the blood, mixes it with Vaseline, spreads the mixture on saran wrap and then projects the video of her miscarriages onto the saran wrap screen. Last week [April 2008], a national furor arose over Yale student Aliza Shvarts's "art" project, which contemplated doing just that: projecting abortion videos onto abortion leftovers. The political right was understandably outraged—the immorality of the abortions is sick-making on its own. The political left was, somewhat puzzlingly, also perturbed—they condemned Shvarts's "approach and presentation," though one struggles to see their problem, considering Shvarts's repeated abortions are legal only due to their adamant support for abortion-on-demand. The Art World's Response The art world was largely silent on Shvarts's project. They were not silent, however, on the prospect of censorship. "Public media has been practicing vigilant self-censorship ever since (Sept. 11, 2001)—in my opinion, a very irresponsible choice," said performance artist, Yale lecturer and probable Shvarts-advisor Pia Lindman. "I am still waiting for this self-aggrandizing mass psychosis; the uncritical belief in the omnipotence and goodness of the American people, troops and government, to dissolve and have it replaced with sober self-reflection." Cary Nelson of the American Association of University Professors was more circumspect: "Academic freedom for faculty and intellectual freedom for students give them the right to speech that shocks and challenges." Helaine S. Klasky, spokeswoman for Yale, stated, "The entire project is an art piece, a creative fiction designed to draw attention to the ambiguity surrounding form and function of a woman's body. (Shvarts) is an artist and has the right to express herself through performance art." All rights have reasonable limits. The right to bear arms does not include a right to own a nuclear weapon. The right to free exercise of religion does not include a right to ritualistic child sacrifice. The right to free expression in art should not include a right to film yourself having an abortion; neither should it include a right to use feces, urine or any other bodily fluid in public, nor should it include a right to engage in sex acts before live audiences. The public has an interest in preventing the pollution of its artistic culture—and the law should reflect that interest. As for the "boundary-pushing" performance "artists," those "artists" who cannot work within the bounds of common decency should find another line of work. [William] Shakespeare somehow worked within the strict guidelines of his time; so did da Vinci, and so did Beethoven, Brahms, Bach and Mozart. If Aliza Shvarts, Robert Mapplethorpe [a controversial photographer whose work is sometimes sexually explicit], Andres Serrano and other "artists" cannot do the same, they ought to consider going into the demolition business. After all, they're so good at destroying worthwhile ideas and limits already. Footnotes 1. 1. Karen Finley is a controversial performance artist whose shows have included smearing her body with chocolate and other substances. Source Citation: Shapiro, Ben. "The Arts Should Be Censored." Censorship. Ed. Byron L. Stay. San Diego: Greenhaven Press, 1997. Opposing Viewpoints. Rpt. from "No Bodily Fluids in the Public Square." Human Events.com. 2008. Gale Opposing Viewpoints In Context. Web. 9 Apr. 2012.