Hume’s account of the will The will is not a power, capacity, or ability. It is just a feeling we sometimes have (a type of impression) — specifically a feeling that we are conscious of when we “knowingly give rise” to a body motion or an idea of imagination Since our body motions are direct responses to pleasure and pain, and it accompanies them, it is like a direct passion. But it is not “properly speaking” an impression of reflection (Why not? — Particularly if all occurrences of the feeling of will are consequences of the perception of pleasure or pain or of some motivating passion or reason) Is the will free? Hume considered the notion of a free will to be either absurd or unintelligible. Absurd: Because we think the motions of material things are all causally necessitated. But all our reasons for taking the actions of material things to be necessitated and what we mean by “necessity” in conjunction with the motions of matter (constant conjunction + mental compulsion) are reasons for taking the will to be necessitated in this same sense. Unintelligible: Because we have no notion of necessity apart from constant conjunction a mental compulsion to infer an idea from an impression So we can’t mean anything by denying “necessity” in any other sense. (Side note) Hume thought better of the “unintelligibility” of any other sense of freedom when he wrote the Enquiry. There he recognized that an action might be said to be free when it is accompanied by the feeling of will and constrained when it is not accompanied by that feeling. This position is compatible with still thinking that the will is determined … … though it allows that the notion of liberty is not either false or unintelligible So the change of mind is a change from “hard” determinism to “compatiblism” Hume’s reasons for insisting on parity between material motions and acts of will When we say that material motions are necessitated, we never mean that we perceive some power or force in their causes that makes them come about We only ever mean: • that the causes regularly precede the material motions • that when we perceive the causes we feel a compulsion to form a lively idea of the material motions But: • human actions are just as regularly preceded by causes • when we perceive those causes we feel a compulsion to form a lively idea of the actions More on the first point Given a certain type of person and given certain circumstances in which that person is placed the person’s actions follow as a matter of course. The extent to which human actions are unpredictable is no greater than the extent to which material motions are unpredictable in both cases careful reasoners attribute the inconstancy to the operation of hidden causes The greatest unpredictability is found in the actions of the insane, yet they are considered to have no freedom. More on the second point Given a certain type of person that we have to deal with and give a knowledge of the circumstances in which that person is placed we cannot resist forming a lively idea of what the person is going to do next. In ordinary deliberations we make no distinction between material necessity and human action, but instead rely on both as equally determined. Reasons why it is so widely supposed that the will is free 1. A failure to distinguish between the liberty of spontaneity and the liberty of indifference. Liberty of spontaneity: when the impression of will accompanies an action, as opposed to the action being determined by a cause contrary to the desires of the agent Liberty of indifference: when an effect has no cause (esp. when a determination of the will has no cause) In the case of liberty of spontaneity, the impression of will can be determined, yet we consider ourselves to be free because we are doing what we want and (correctly) think we could have done otherwise had we willed differently. We confuse this liberty of spontaneity with a liberty of indifference, and (incorrectly) think that nothing made us will to do what we did. All that is in fact the case is that we were in a situation where, had it been the case that something else would have determined the will to do the opposite, nothing external would have prevented us from doing the opposite. Reasons why it is so widely supposed that the will is free, cont.’d 2. We have a false sensation or experience of liberty of indifference that arises from our “1st person” point of view of our own actions. When someone else views our actions, they see them as the regular consequence of our character and circumstances. But when we view the causes of our own actions, we don’t get the same lively idea of their effects. This is because we sense that, had we been provoked, we could have done otherwise. (though provocation is itself a cause, and one that would lead another person aware of it to infer that we would behave contrary to our usual practice, … … for us the sense of the ability to do otherwise if provoked creates a sense of looseness over the connection between our actual motive and the actual action that resulted from it We mistake this looseness for an ability of the will to occur independently of any cause … … though in fact it is strictly determined whatever it does. Reasons why it is so widely supposed that the will is free, cont.’d 3. It is supposed to be required by religion and morality. Hume’s initial response: It is unphilosophical to reject a position that is founded on good argument simply because it has unpalatable consequences. Hume’s second response: Far from it actually being the case that religion and morality are invested in the freedom of the will, the opposite is true. Here is why: • when we say that human actions are determined, we do not mean that there is something that forces them happen we just mean that they regularly follow from certain antecedent events and that is something that everyone tacitly accepts • indeed they count on it e.g., in relying on the deterrent effect of punishment Even if we suppose that God does not punish to deter, but only to avenge, … we ought to accept that a just and wise judge would only avenge actions that are deliberate effects of an evil will, not those that are capricious and accidental But the only way an action can be considered to be a deliberate effect of an evil will is if there is regularity in the succession of cause and effect. That means that the person has to be the sort of person who would regularly do that sort of evil thing in those tempting circumstances. i.e., it means the will is caused. Precisely to the extent that the person isn’t the sort of person who would regularly behave that way (because the action follows from ignorance, inattention, haste, strong passion, etc.) we think they aren’t responsible and don’t deserve such severe punishment.