Golfo Maggini University of Ioannina Department of Philosophy Dourouti University Campus GR - 451 10 Ιoannina Greece tel.: 00302651-0-05673, 05656, 05657 fax: 2651-0-05801 e-mail: gmaggini@uoi.gr personal webpage: www.golfomaggini.blogspot.com International Society for MacIntyrean Enquiry 8th Annual Conference “Tradition, Modernity, and Beyond” National and Capodistrian University of Athens & University of Ioannina Athens, 9-12 July 2014 MacIntyre’s Nietzschean Anti-Modernism “From Nietzsche’s beginnings until now the genealogical project has been to outwit and thereby to subvert the institutionalization of the gap between theory and practice and the corresponding deformation of both by a kind of intellectual and social guerilla warfare. Thomists by contrast have often enough created […] alternative institutions […] in an attempt to integrate intellectual, moral, and social formation in a way that would escape the deformations of their age.” (Alasdair MacIntyre, “Moral Philosophy and Contemporary Social Practice: What Holds Them Apart?”, 1992, p. 122) Quotation #1: “The notion of choosing one’s own morality makes no sense; what makes sense is the much more radical notion of choosing to displace and overcome morality. So A Short History of Ethics should perhaps have ended by giving Nietzsche the final word, instead of leaving him behind two chapter earlier.” (“Nietzsche or Aristotle? Alasdair MacIntyre” in: The American Philosopher. Interviews with Giovanna Borradori, The University of Chicago Press, 1994, p. 146). Quotation #2: “…from a methodological viewpoint, it is today clear to me that while I was writing A Short History, I should have taken as a central standpoint what I learned from R. E. Collingwood: that morality is an essentially historical subject matter and that philosophical inquiry, in ethics as elsewhere, is defective insofar as it is not historical.” (ibid). Quotation #3: “What worries us in Nietzsche is perhaps like what worries us in Kant […] the conscientious moral agent dominated by the form of the categorical imperative is in fact licensed to do anything at all – provided he does it conscientiously. What looked like a restrictive guide to conduct is in fact empty of restriction. So likewise, and more crudely, with the notion of the Superman. In the name of the Will to Power what might one not do?…” (Alasdair MacIntyre, A Short History of Ethics. A History of Moral Philosophy from the Homeric Age to the twentieth century, Routledge, London-New York 1998 (1967), p. 218). Quotation #4: “To a remarkable extent Nietzsche offers us an inverted mirror-image of the friendship required by the virtues of acknowledged dependence […] Nietzsche thus confronts us with a radical alternative way of thinking about dependence and independence in human relationships […] Yet, although we can learn from Nietzsche we cannot learn from him as one who is able to participate with us in rational conversation, criticism, and enquiry.” (Alasdair MacIntyre, Dependent Rational Animals. Why Human Beings Need the Virtues, Open Court, Chicago, 1999, p. 164165). Quotation #5: “One might even claim that what MacIntyre has shown us thus far really supports Nietzsche’s case; that MacIntyre decoded is the champion of Nietzsche. Why? Because he not only shows that there are incompatible and incommensurable lists and theories of virtue, but has failed thus far to show how we can “rationally” adjudicate among rival claimants.” (Richard J. Bernstein, “Nietzsche or Aristotle? Reflections on Alasdair MacIntyre’s After Virtue”, Soundings 67/1 (1984), p. 9). Quotation #6: “Post-Enlightenment relativism and perspectivism are thus the negative counterpart of the Enlightenment, its inverted mirror image. Where the Enlightenment invoked the arguments of Kant or Bentham, such post-Enlightenment theorists invoke Nietzsche’s attacks upon Kant and Bentham.” (Alasdair MacIntyre, Whose Justice? Which Rationality?, Duckworth, London, 1988, p. 353). Quotation #7: “Perspectivism, in this once more like relativism, is a doctrine only possible for those who regard themselves as outsiders, as uncommitted or rather committed only to acting a succession of temporary parts. [..] from the standpoint afforded by the rationality of tradition-constituted enquiry it is clear that such persons are by their stance excluded from the possession of any concept of truth adequate for systematic rational inquiry.” (MacIntyre, Whose Justice? Which Rationality?, p. 368). Quotation #8: “Psychologically what is taken to be fixed and binding about truth – Nietzsche would of course have said the same about knowledge and duty and right – is an unrecognized motivation serving an unacknowledged purpose. To think and speak of truth, knowledge, duty, and right in the late nineteenth-century mode, the mode in fact of the Ninth Edition, is to give evidence of membership in a culture in which lack of self-knowledge has been systematically institutionalized.” (Alasdair MacIntyre, Three Rival Versions of Moral Inquiry. The Gifford Lectures, University of Notre Dame Press, 1990, p. 35). Quotation #9: “The transformation of the moral inquirer from the participant in an encyclopaedic enterprise shared by all adequately reflective and informed human beings into an engaged partisan of one such warring standpoint against its rivals is an accomplished fact.” (MacIntyre, Three Rival Versions of Moral Inquiry, p. 56). Quotation #10: “…so far as large-scale theoretical and conceptual structures are concerned, each rival theoretical standpoint provides from within itself and in its own terms the standards by which, so its adherents claim, it should be evaluated, rivalry between such contending standpoints includes rivalry over standards. There is no theoretically neutral, pre-theoretical ground from which the adjudication of competing claims can proceed.” (MacIntyre, Three Rival Versions of Moral Inquiry, p. 173). Quotation #11: “…But it now turns out to be the case that in the end the Nietzschean stance is only one more facet of the very moral culture of which Nietzsche took himself to be an implacable critic.” (Alasdair MacIntyre, After Virtue, University of Notre Dame Press, 1981, p. 259). Quotation #12: “Nietzsche’s final standpoint, that towards rather than from which he speaks, cannot be expressed as a set of statements. Statements made only to be discarded – and sometimes taken up again – in that movement from utterance to utterance in which what is communicated is the movement. Nietzsche did not advance a new theory against older theories, he proposed an abandonment of theory.” (MacIntyre, Three Rival Versions of Moral Inquiry, p. 49). Quotation #13: “...Thinkers in this Nietzschean tradition have differed about which Greeks they take to be the good Greeks – since usually it will be granted that reason took over and killed off the good developments at some point […] for Alasdair MacIntyre, it would seem that the good times persist at least through the lifetime of Aristotle and his medieval successors, and do not get really awful until Hume and Kant […] For MacIntyre and for Heidegger (and there are certainly elements of this position in Williams also) the good thing is to suppose that in a well-ordered community we execute our tasks without reflection; the bad thing is to suppose that each political act needs and can have a rational justification.” (Martha C. Nussbaum, “Kant and Stoic Cosmopolitanism”, The Journal of Political Philosophy 5/1 (1997), p. 2). Quotation #13: “Meaning and ostensible use are such that the use of moral concepts and judgments purports to involve an appeal to some impersonal standards of right or good, neutral between the interests, attitudes, preferences and will of persons. Actual use is at the thereby unrecognized serviceof highly specific interests, attitudes, preferences, and will […] To translate these postNietzschean claims into this idiom is at once to recognize both the resemblances and the differences between such claims and a type of theory in modern academic moral philosophy advanced in different versions by C. L. Stevenson and by Simon Blackburn.” (Alasdair MacIntyre, “Moral Philosophy and Contemporary Social Practice: What Holds Them Apart?”(1992), in: The Tasks of Philosophy. Selected Essays, vol. 1, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2006, p. 110). Quotation #14: “…contrary to what MacIntyre suggests, Nietzsche’s perspectivism is not a version of emotivism; it does not involve subjectivity of individual moral judgments […] In order words, Nietzsche’s perspectivism does not arise from his observations of individuals’ moral judgments as expressions of subjective will nor does it claim that moral judgments are individual preferences, which is the basic tenet of emotivism.” (Buket Korkut, “MacIntyre’s Nietzsche or Nietzschean MacIntyre?”, Philosophy and Social Criticism, 38/2, 2012, p. 205). Quotation #15: “the Nietzschean stance turns out not to be a mode of escape from or an alternative to the conceptual scheme of liberal individualist modernity, but rather one more representative moment in itsd internal unfolding. And we may therefore expect liberal individualist societies to breed “great men” from time to time. Alas!” (MacIntyre, After Virtue, p. 259). Quotation #16: “[Nietzsche] takes there to be a multiplicity of perspectives within each of which truth-from-a-point-of-view may be asserted, but no truth-as-such, an empty notion, about the world, an equally empty notion. There are [for Nietzsche] no rules of rationality as such to be appealed to, there are rather strategies of insight and strategies of subversion.” (MacIntyre, Three Rival Versions of Moral Inquiry, p. 42). Quotation #17: “…from the standpoint of the genealogist no tradition can be rational, but in this case for reasons which equally undermine any claim that particular methods or principles are ever as such rational.”? (MacIntyre, Three Rival Versions of Moral Inquiry, p. 117). Quotation #18: “The genealogist […] subordinates philosophy in history. Because he sees, rightly, that total historical detachment, or radical universalism, is impossible, he swings violently in the opposite direction and concludes that every thought and idea is the creature, and hence the instrument, of its time, to be used or abused in the power struggles of social and political history. Whereas the encyclopaedist is unrealistically ahistorical, the genealogist is an historical relativist.” (Gordon Graham, “MacIntyre on History and Philosophy”, in: Alasdair MacIntyre, Mark C. Murphy (ed.), Cambridge University Press, 2003, p. 28). Quotation #19: “…despite MacIntyre’s apparently tolerant claims in acknowledging the “legitimacy” of radically incommensurable traditions of justice and practical rationality, there is an implicit cultural imperialism in his view. For it is a necessary consequence of his claims that a given tradition may contingently turn out to be rationally superior to all its rivals.” (Richard J. Bernstein, The New Constellation. The Ethical-Political Horizons of Modernity/Postmodernity, Polity Press, 1991, p. 64). ***