Firm-Specific Human Capital and the Theory of the Firm Margaret M. Blair The Brookings Institution First Draft: April 1996 Version of February, 1997 An earlier version of this paper was prepared for a conference on Employes and Corporate Governance, Columbia University School of Law, Nov. 22, 1996. I welcome comments and feedback. Please do not cite or quote without permission. I am grateful to Gabriel Loeb for research assistance on this paper, to Bengt Holmstrom, Victor Goldberg, Greg Dow, Louis Putterman, David Ellerman, and participants in the Columbia Law School conference for comments and feedback, and to the Alfred P. Sloan Foundation, Pfizer Inc., and an anonymous donor who provided grants to the Brookings Institution to help support this research. The opinions expressed in this paper, and all errors of fact and of judgment are those of the author and are not to be attributed to Brookings, its officers or trustees, nor to any of those who have helped to fund the research. I. Introduction. The “theory of the firm” in modern economics has advanced dramatically from the simple black-box production function model that is still presented in most undergraduatelevel microeconomics textbooks. Likewise, economic theories of the employment relationship have advanced far beyond simple supply and demand curves for labor. But, while the nature of the relationship between a firm and its employees would seem to be a central, perhaps defining, feature of the firm itself, economists have generally studied questions about the nature of the firm, as well as the ownership rights and governance structure of firms, separately from questions about the structure and terms of employment relationships, and they have not yet produced a unified theory of the firm that adequately explains and accounts for the role of “human capital.” 1 Of course, there may be no single, simple theory that explains the numerous complex organizational forms and relationships that we actually observe. But a growing body of theoretical and empirical work, by scholars working from a number of different angles, suggests that specialized investments -- investments whose value in a particular enterprise greatly exceeds their value in alternative uses -- play a critical role in determining the boundaries of firms, and the allocation of “property” rights (i.e., risks, rewards, and control rights) within firms. For example, a number of different scholars have stressed the incentive benefits that flow from assigning control rights over the assets of a firm, or over the firm itself, to parties who make important firm-specific investments of one sort or another. But much of this literature has focussed on investments in physical or other alienable capital. There are two exceptions to this general rule, both of which will be discussed briefly later in 1 this paper. The first exception is the small body of theory and empirical research on labormanaged firms (See e.g., Ward (1958), Domar (1966), Vanek (1970, 1977), Meade (1972), Furobotn and Pejovich (1974), Putterman (1984), Ellerman (1986) and Dow (1993). The second is the effort by Masahiko Aoki to develop a “cooperative game theory of the firm.” See Aoki (1984). Neither of these strands of the literature have had much impact on mainstream economic thought. 2 To be sure, scholars have recognized and discussed the importance of firm-specific investments by employees for decades. Specialized knowledge and skills of employees are increasingly understood to be important factors that influence the structure and character of the employment relationship, and the allocation of risks and rewards between employees and employers. But work by labor theorists has generally argued that investments in firm-specific human capital are protected through such institutional arrangements as collective bargaining or promotion ladders -- arrangements that do not normally convey control rights over the firm itself. In the models used by these theorists, the contributors of firm-specific human capital are generally viewed as parties to transactions with the firm (where the firm is apparently some well-defined entity on the other side of the relationship) rather than parties to the firm itself. Meanwhile, the modeling approach that has dominated legal and normative discussions of corporate governance questions in recent years has been the principal-agent model, in which managers are viewed as agents of shareholders. Principal-agent analysis can be a misleading tool for analyzing certain kinds of corporate governance problems for at least two reasons, however. First, the canonical principal-agent model is asymmetric and hierarchical. It assumes that we know who the principal is and who the agent is in a given relationship, and it focusses on structuring the relationship in such a way that the agent will be motivated to do what the principal wants. It ignores any problems of enforcement in the other direction. That is, it assumes away all of the potential problems that might arise in getting the principal to deliver on its end of the bargain. Second, the model assumes that the principal is a well-defined entity (usually an individual) with an unambiguous agenda. The principal knows what it wants the agent to do. Thus principalagent analysis doesn't help to sort out the complexities that arise when there are multiple parties involved in a joint enterprise, perhaps with many different goals. 3 These two limitations suggest that, while principal-agent analysis has provided some important insights into certain kinds of contracting problems, it tells us very little about the essential nature of corporations. Moreover, it can be very misleading when used to draw normative implications about corporate governance if used in ways that ignore, or mask, the underlying ambiguity about who the principal is in a given context (Is it the “corporation”? Is it the shareholders? Is it management? Are any of these necessarily a monolithic entity with an unambiguous agenda?), or how the goals of the principal are determined. A small, but important and growing body of work on the economic theory of the firm, however, attempts to explain, or at least explore, the nature of the firm itself. Why are some productive activities organized within firms and others not? What is the difference between a within-firm relationship, and one that is governed by contract, or across markets? What determines who is in the firm and who is out? This work generally considers the institutional arrangements for encouraging and protecting relationship-specific investments, and/or for encouraging and rewarding effort toward a group goal by individual employees, as defining features of the firm itself. Although most of these theoretical efforts are new, and still quite sketchy, they may well lead to normative implications about the allocation of claims and control rights in publiclytraded firms that are different from those drawn from the principal-agent models that have been so prevalent in legal analysis in the last two decades. In this paper, I will assess the status of theoretical work on the role of firm-specific human capital in the theory of the firm, and comment on the implications of some of the newest work for legal analyses of control rights and of the responsibilities of managers in firms. II. A Brief History of Thought 4 Firm-specific (or relationship-specific) investments have been important in two subfields of economics, labor theory, and the theory of the firm. A. Labor Theory. Gary Becker (1964) coined the phrase “human capital” to refer to the fact that much of the skills and knowledge required to do a job could only be acquired if some “investment” was made in time and resources. In his pathbreaking work on human capital, Becker considered the implications of the fact that some of the knowledge and skills acquired by employees have a much higher value in a given employment relationship than they do in other potential relationships. This fact, he speculated, would influence choices about wages, investments in training, and other terms of the employment relationship, Becker argued that such specialized knowledge and skills may often be productivity enhancing, and are therefore likely to be an important part of the employment relationship in practice. But, he noted, they introduce a complication into simple models of wage determination and equilibrium employment levels. In particular, the labor services of employees with specialized skills can no longer be modeled as undifferentiated, generic inputs, for which equilibrium price (wages) and quantity (number of employees or number of hours of work) are determined by the intersection of supply and demand curves. Once employees are understood to have specialized skills, it matters which employee does what job for what firm. “If a firm had paid for the specific training of a worker who quit to take another job, its capital expenditure would be partly wasted, for no further return could be collected. Likewise, a worker fired after he had paid for specific training would be unable to collect any further return and would also suffer a capital loss,” Becker noted. Where investments in specific skills are important, Becker reasoned, it is no longer a matter of indifference 5 “whether a firm's labor force always contained the same persons or a rapidly changing group.” 2 Thus, although Becker's primary purpose was to study and explain the economic incentives for investments in training and education, along the way he introduced a concept that provides an important rationale for long-term relationships between firms and their employees. Doeringer and Piore (1971) built on this insight to develop their theory of internal labor markets. They argued that investments by firms in specialized training encourage firms to put in place other institutional arrangements designed to stabilize employment and reduce turnover. The organizational stability that results from these practices, in turn, facilitates further development of specific skills. Doeringer and Piore further argued that the use of mass-production technology, with its detailed division of labor, required specialized skills and made stable employment relationships more important. 3 Becker also argued that employees and employers would be likely to split both the costs and returns from specialized training, in order to provide an incentive for both parties to stay in the relationship. One of the implications of his arguments was that employees would typically earn less 4 See Becker (1964), p. 21. 2 Jacoby (1990) questions this conclusion. Though he concedes that empirical evidence supports 3 a shift from the late 1800s to at least the mid-1970s toward greater job stability, but he argues that “there is little evidence that the shift resulted from a growing reliance on firm-specific techniques or skills. In fact, the evidence suggests that the opposite was true: that technology and job skills became less, rather than more firm-specific over time.” See p. 323. The notion of firmspecific skills that lies behind Jacoby's assertion is that of skills necessary to carry out unusual or specialized production techniques. It does not encompass the admittedly less welldefined notions of knowledge and relationships necessary to participate effectively in a given organization. Hashimoto (1981) subsequently provided a formal model that suggested that the division of the 4 costs and returns from training would be split according to a formula that was a function of the relative probabilities of layoffs versus quits, and the costs of evaluating and agreeing on both the worker's productivity in the firm and his opportunity cost, or potential productivity in an alternative firm. 6 than their opportunity cost during the early stages of their employment relationship (while they were in training, for example), and more than their opportunity cost later in their relationship. An earnings pattern like this would produce an “upward sloping wage-tenure profile,” an empirical regularity that labor economists before Becker had observed, and that work by subsequent scholars has documented extensively. Consistent with the “firm-specific human capital” hypothesis, labor 5 economists have also observed that long-tenured employees typically earn quite a bit more than their short-run opportunity cost. This fact is confirmed through studies of layoffs, which show that longtenured employees laid off through no fault of their own (as a result of plant closings, for example) typically earn 15 to 25 percent less on their next jobs. These estimates and others by scholars doing 6 related work suggest that the aggregate returns to investments in firm-specific human capital could represent as much as 10 percent of the total wage bill of the corporate sector -- a figure that is of the same order of magnitude as all of corporate profits. 7 Not all labor economists are convinced that the empirical evidence that wages rise with tenure, and that wages of long-tenured employees often exceed short-run opportunity costs, should be taken as evidence that employees have acquired substantial amounts of firm-specific human capital. Some labor economists have argued that other features of the labor market could account for these empirical regularities. The other explanations that have been offered also imply that labor For recent contributions to this literature, see Topel (1990), Topel (1991). 5 See, e.g., Jacobson, LaLonde, and Sullivan (1993). 6 See Blair (1996), p. 10, and footnote 4. 7 markets would exhibit involuntary unemployment. Hence they have been very important in the debate about whether labor markets clear. 8 But these stories (and the empirical studies that support them) do not generally rule out the possibility that firm-specific human capital is an important factor in determining the structure of many employment relationships. Indeed, most labor economists believe such investments are important in many situations. 9 Once acquired, knowledge and skills that are specialized to a given enterprise are assets that are at risk in that enterprise, and as such, they inevitably present a contracting problem for the employee and the firm. If the firm compensates the employee up front and fully for the costs of developing and using such assets, the employee could, in principle, take the compensation and the assets and walk out the door. Suppose, however, that the firm does not fully compensate the employee up front, but instead, compensates him or her in the way that Becker predicted, with a lower wage at first, and a promise of a higher wage later. That employee would then have a stake in the firm that is unrecoverable except as payments are made to the employee out of the economic For a summary of arguments on the efficiency of non-market clearing wages, see Krueger and 8 Summers (1988) and Weiss (1990); for evidence on non-market clearing wages and employment practices, see Katz and Summers (1989) and Dickens and Lang (1993). As the reader may have guessed, my interest in firm-specific human capital is derived from my 9 primary interest the effect of various corporate governance arrangements on the incentives and risks facing employees of corporations. Characterizing the problem as one associated with investments in human capital emphasizes the parallels to the corporate governance problems facing investors in equity capital. The governance issues raised by investments in human capital are similar, however, to those that arise with any compensation scheme that is “backloaded” for whatever reason, as well as with any compensation scheme that results in employees being paid more than their (short-run) opportunity cost. Matching models predict back-loaded compensation schemes, and both matching models and efficiency wage models predict wages in excess of short-run opportunity costs. In such cases, employees have something of substantial value at risk in the firm that can only be recovered over time, and that can be expropriated, or that can be lost altogether if the employees lose their job with their current employer. 8 surplus generated by the relationship. This stake is generally regarded as very difficult to protect by means of explicit contracts: The firm can't enforce a contract that requires the employee to stay and utilize those skills in the firm. And, because the skills in question are likely to be hard to define, let alone measure, the employee can't enforce a contract that requires the firm to pay for the development and use of skills. Yet, without explicit contractual protection, the stakes held by providers of firmspecific human capital take on many of the characteristics of the stakes held by providers of equity capital. B. Theory of the Firm. The earliest efforts by economists to get inside the black-box production function model of the firm focussed on the fact that production in firms is characterized groups of people working together, and organized hierarchically, with some individuals having the authority to make decisions about how people and resources are used. The authority relationship, Coase argued, is substituted 10 for a series of market transactions, because, for a variety of different reasons, the central authority figure in the relationship can coordinate activities more efficiently than individual input providers could if they were all contracting with each other separately. From this initial insight, economists took the theory of the firm in two different directions. One direction stressed the importance of joint production technologies, in which it is difficult to measure and reward the individual productivity of team members. In this approach, the purpose of 11 “If a workman moves from department Y to department X, he does [so] . . . because he is 10 ordered to do so,” writes Coase. “Outside the firm, price movements direct production, which is coordinated through a series of exchange transactions on the market. Within a firm, these market transactions are eliminated and in place of the complicated market structure with exchange transactions is substituted the entrepreneur-co-ordinator, who directs production.” See Coase (1937), p. 19. See Alchian and Demsetz (1972). 11 9 the firm is to provide a mechanism by which a central authority can monitor the activities of the team members to be sure they all carry their weight. The central authority has the incentive to monitor effectively because he gets to keep any surplus, over and above what he has to pay the team members. The principal-agent models can be understood as extensions or supplements to this key idea. The second approach has been to focus on circumstances in which it might be less costly to organize production within a firm. This second approach has stressed, among other things, the importance of investments in specialized assets. I will review the literature on the latter approach first, and then return to the problem of team production. 1. Transactions costs theory. Oliver Williamson has identified several features of transactions that make it costly to trade in impersonal, arms-length markets. Where these features apply, transacting parties might choose to administer such transactions through hierarchical governance arrangements. These features include the longevity and “asset-specificity” of 12 investments made to engage in a given transaction. The former means that the asset will generate its return over time, while the latter imposes limits on the ability of the transacting parties to redeploy assets to other uses if for any reason they are unhappy with the returns they are getting in the given enterprise. Other features that encourage hierarchical administration rather than market transactions, according to Williamson, include the uncertainty and complexity of the transaction (a problem which is exacerbated when assets are long-lived); the “bounded rationality” of the See Williamson (1975, 1985). “Markets” and “hierarchies” were treated as dichotomous 12 organizational forms in Williamson's early work, but more recent work, by Williamson and others, tends to view them as two ends of a continuum of possible structures in which transactions take place, with various kinds of contracts in between. See e.g. Williamson and Bercovitz (1996), Baker, Gibbons, and Murphy (1996), and Kreps (1996). 10 transacting parties (which makes it impossible for them to anticipate all possible outcomes and complications and to write “complete” contracts that specify what is to happen under each scenario); and the tendency of transacting parties to be “opportunistic.” Of these, asset specificity is central in Williamson's theory of the firm. Assets that are not specific to a given enterprise or transaction can be readily redeployed and hence are not at risk in a given relationship. But when assets are specific, they are, almost by definition, at risk, and the other problems (uncertainty and complexity, bounded rationality, and opportunism) become important. Williamson's work spawned a literature on the contracting problems that arise when assets are specific. Klein, Crawford and Alchian (1978), for example, argued that when two contracting parties each make investments that are specific to their relationship, either party can attempt to expropriate the returns from those investments by threatening to “hold up” the enterprise. The potential “hold-up” problem, they speculated, would encourage the contracting parties to integrate their operations vertically (the supplier would acquire the customer, or vice versa) so that all of the assets that were specific to the enterprise would be owned by the same party. For example, if one party owns a coal mine, and the other party owns a power plant built at the mouth of the coal mine and designed to use coal from the mine, the two parties might find themselves in frequent disputes about the price and terms on which the coal is to be sold to the power plant. But if a single party owns both the mine and the power plant, and administers them jointly, this owner would probably try to maximize the joint return, and would no longer be tempted to waste resources in haggling over the terms of trade between the two units. Empirical research that has attempted to test the Williamson and Klein, Crawford, and Alchian hypotheses has generally confirmed that firm-specific investments are important in determining ownership structure and degree of vertical integration. But this research has taken an 11 interesting twist. Monteverde and Teece, for example, studied parts production in the automobile industry to ask under what circumstances firms might choose to undertake production in-house rather than contracting production out to a supplier. They argue that vertical integration might not be necessary if the specialized assets used in production of the parts include only physical capital, such as tools or dies. The hold-up problem, in this case, can be avoided if the automobile assembly company owns the specialized tools and leases them to the contractor who produces the parts. Such arrangements, which Monteverde and Teece refer to as “quasi-integration,” are commonly observed in the auto parts production business. But where the specialized investment involved in producing the parts is in nonpatentable know-how and skills, Monteverde and Teece argue that quasiintegration will no longer solve the hold-up problem. They speculate that full integration will be required to minimize the transactions costs. Consistent with this hypothesis, they found in one 13 study that quasi-integration arrangements are associated with two indicators of the extent of investment in specialized tools and equipment, and, in another study, that full integration is associated both with an indicator of the extent of specialized knowhow involved in developing and engineering the component, and with an indicator of the extent to which the component's design Wiggins distinguishes transactions and relationships that are “integrated” from those that aren't 13 by noting that the former are arrangements “where both monitors are compensated out of a common residual income stream.” (Wiggins, 1991, p. 615.) In other words, to be “in” the firm, rather than to be on the outside contracting with the firm, means to be sharing in a “common residual income stream.” The notion of a common residual income stream only makes sense if there are cospecialized assets generating that common income stream. Wiggins notes that, with a given set of demand and supply functions for participating parties, simple long-term contracts can be devised that can give both parties to a transaction incentives to make the optimal ex ante transaction-specific investments. But, he says, “the compensation arrangements that solve the effort problem undermine the parties' ability to adjust output under the contract to reflect cost shocks.” Integration, he claims, can overcome “the incentive to distort shocks by compensating both monitors out of the common residual of the integrated firm.” This comes, of course at a cost of some of the intensity of the incentives facing both parties.(p. 617) 12 affects the performance and packaging of other components, a feature they refer to as the component's “system effects.” Similarly, Masten, Meehan, and Snyder (1989) find that, in 14 regressions in which both investments in specialized knowledge and investments in specialized equipment are used to explain vertical integration, investments in specialized knowledge have much more explanatory power. 15 Neither Williamson, nor Klein, Crawford, and Alchian offer much insight into how it is that organizing production within a firm solves the hold-up problem associated with firmspecific investments by multiple parties, nor which of several participants in an enterprise should be the “owner” of an integrated enterprise. Grossman and Hart (1986) address this gap. They argue that organizing production in a firm solves the incomplete contracting problems by assigning to one party -- the “owner” -- all of the “residual” control rights over the use of the assets in the firm – those rights that are not specifically contracted away to other participants. Under the terms of the Grossman and Hart theory, firms are defined as bundles of assets under common ownership, where ownership implies control over the use and disposition of the assets. 16 See Monteverde and Teece (1982a, and 1982b). 14 See Masten, Meehan and Snyder (1989). 15 Grossman and Hart's arguments have been called the “property rights theory of the firm,” but, 16 even though the first sentence of their 1986 paper asks “What is a firm?” (See p. 691.), their story is not so much a theory of the firm, but a theory of role played by ownership rights in solving complex contracting problems. Hart and Moore (1990) show how ownership rights over a firm's physical assets -- specifically, the ability to exclude others from the use of the assets -- enhance the ability of the owner to control the workers who work with those assets. If the workers require access to the assets to be productive, they will have an incentive to do what the "owners" of those assets want them to do. Thus Hart and Moore add to the notion of ownership a theory about what it means to be in or out of the firm (an “employee” or a “contractor”). 13 Grossman and Hart's model considers a situation in which participants in an enterprise must make firm-specific investments that are very difficult or impossible to contract over. Their model leads to the conclusion that the ownership rights in the firm should go to the party whose firmspecific investments add the most value to the enterprise, but are the most difficult or impossible to contract over. Ownership rights ensure the party who must make these investments that her claim to a share in the rents generated by the investments will not be expropriated ex post by the other participants. Hence, they help ensure that she will have the ex ante incentive to invest optimally. Williamson's early work acknowledged that human capital, as well as physical capital, can be transaction-specific. In later work, he identifies some features of organizations, such as team accommodations, informal process innovations, and knowledge of codes and procedures, that tend to make incumbents more valuable to employers than workers hired on spot markets might be. And, 17 he argues that transactions in which investments in specific human capital are important must include some sort of safeguard for those investments, noting in particular that in such transactions, “continuity between firm and worker are valued.” Firm-specific human capital, he says, must be “imbedded in a protective governance structure lest productive values be sacrificed if the employment relation is unwittingly severed.” 18 Williamson himself devotes little intellectual energy to identifying, or assessing the safeguards or protective governance arrangements that, according to his theory, should exist in relationships between employees and firms that employ them. He mentions severance pay, and job security (of the kind commonly thought to exist for employees of Japanese corporations) in passing, as mechanisms for protecting worker investments in firm-specific skills, and he mentions pensions as a mechanism for providing incentives that discourage employees with specialized skills from quitting. He also argues that collective bargaining through unions and “internal governance 19 structures” (such as job ladders, grievance procedures, and pay scales) can serve efficiency purposes by providing a protective governance structure for idiosyncratic investments in skills by workers. 20 But Williamson's work on these issues follows the tradition of labor theorists (see discussion above) in treating employees as contracting with the firm, where the firm is understood to be a well-defined entity on the other side of that contract. 21 See Williamson (1985), pp. 246-247. 19 See Williamson (1985), pp. 254-256. See also Williamson, Wachter and Harris (1975). 20 Williamson also notes that when the intensity of firm-specific human capital is high, unions may actually be inefficient mechanisms for protecting that human capital. "Among other things, a single union operating under a uniform agreement will have difficulty aggregating the preferences of a disparate membership. To negotiate discriminating terms is at variance, however, with the egalitarian purposes of unions." See Williamson (1985), p. 265. See also Epstein (1985) for a discussion of the contracting inefficiencies supposedly caused by unionization under protective regulation. Epstein believes unions would not survive without protective legislation, because, he claims, "at will" contracts are so much more efficient. Nonetheless, Epstein concedes that "at will" contracts will not suffice in situations where "one party to the employment relationship has to make a very substantial capital outlay at the outset," or in situations where "the difference between the contract wage and the market value of the services [is] very large." (See p. 138.) Of course, significant investments in firm-specific human capital lead to exactly these circumstances. In fact, Williamson apparently assumes either that the protections that are available to 21 employees for their firm-specific investments, whether explicitly contractual or institutional, are fully adequate to protect them, or possibly that those investments are of less significance than the investments made by those who contribute equity capital. This assumption is implicit, for example, in his analysis of the transactions cost benefits of corporate governance arrangements that give the right to elect board members to shareholders, and not to other constituents: "Stockholders as a group bear a unique relation to the firm," he asserts. "They are the only voluntary constituency whose relation with the corporation does not come up for periodic review. . . . Stockholders. . . invest for the life of the firm, and their claims are located at the end of the queue should liquidation occur." See Williamson (1985), p. 304-305. This assertion ignores the fact that, since investments in firm-specific human capital can't be 15 2. Team production. Alchian and Demsetz argue that the role of the firm is to organize team production, which they characterize as “production in which 1) several types of resources are used and 2) the product is not a sum of separable outputs of each cooperating resource, . . . [and] 3) not all resources used in team production belong to one person.” The problem raised 22 by team production, according to Alchian and Demsetz, is one of metering output (where the output of any one individual is not separable from the output of his or her teammates) and issuing rewards in ways that will motivate team members to exert effort. Advantages arise from team production if the team members can accomplish substantially more by working together than they could accomplish by working separately. If this extra productivity exceeds the cost of monitoring and motivating team members to exert effort, then team production will be chosen over individual production methods. Alchian and Demsetz go on to argue that, where team production is preferred, the metering and reward problem can be solved by having one team member specialize in monitoring, and by giving that individual both the authority to hire and fire team members, and a claim on the earnings from the enterprise, (net of payments to providers of other inputs, who are assumed to be paid their redeployed (by definition), they too are invested for life. Employees can deprive the firm of their use, but they cannot get any benefit from doing so since the skills have no value anywhere else. Hence, it is not clear how much protection is provided even by a continuing opportunity for renegotiation. Moreover, employees have no claim at all, except for past wages, if the firm is liquidated. Although we do not have precise estimates of the aggregate value of investments in firmspecific human capital, there are reasons to believe that it is large, and possibly of the same order of magnitude as the aggregate value of equity capital. See footnote 6 and associated text above. Williamson's dismissal of the importance of firm specific human capital for corporate governance has, nonetheless, been echoed by numerous legal scholars. See, e.g., Roberta Romano (1996), at p. 3. See Alchian and Demsetz (1972), p. 779. 22 16 opportunity cost). Thus they claim that their story provides an explanation for capitalist ownership and control of firms. Alchian and Demsetz's story focusses attention on the contracting relationships among the participants within firms, and provides an explanation for hierarchical structures. From that beginning, numerous other authors have addressed the contracting problem between so called “principals” (the entrepreneur or central, capitalist authority figure in Alchian and Demsetz's story) and “agents.” 3. Principal-agent theory. In principalagent models, employees are viewed as agents of the firm, and the managers of firms are viewed as agents of the shareholders. The contractual problem is to design the terms of the relationship in a way that will encourage the agents to make decisions and otherwise behave in ways that benefit the principals. Jensen and Meckling (1976) introduced the principal-agent approach to the theory of the firm in their classic article in which the firm was viewed as a contracting mechanism between providers of equity capital (the principals) and managers (the agents) designed to minimize the agency costs of this relationship. 23 In recent years, principal-agent models have been very influential in studies of corporate governance arrangements and performance, and have formed the basis of a huge literature on the “market for corporate control,” and on incentive compensation structures in firms. Principal-agent theory has also been influential in research on labor relations in firms. Jensen and Meckling argued that organizations “are simply legal fictions which serve as a 23 nexus for a set of contracting relationships among individuals.” (p. 310. Emphasis in original.) Hence they are generally credited as the source of the view of the firm as a “nexus of contracts.” 17 The canonical principal-agent problem involves a transaction between two parties, one of whom must take an action that affects the other. For some reason, however, the principal cannot compensate the agent directly for the action itself. This may be because the action itself is not observable to the principal, or because the principal does not have the information or knowledge necessary to evaluate the action itself. Another complication is that the consequences or observable output of the agent's action is not a determinate function of the action. Otherwise, it would be possible for the principal to infer the action taken by observing the consequences. Instead, in the principal-agent problem, the output is assumed to be a stochastic function of the agent's action, and/or it is assumed to be measured with error. Since the principal can't pay the agent for the action, he or she must devise a way to pay for the observable output or consequences of the action. The problem for the principal, then, is to set the fee schedule in a way that gives the agent incentives to choose actions that benefit the principal. If the agent is risk neutral, the agent can be induced to choose an optimal action if he is awarded the full payoff from the action. But if the agent is risk-averse, then this arrangement is 24 generally not optimal, and the optimal incentive structure will be some function of the payoff in which the agent and the principal share the risks. The sharing of risks gives a riskaverse agent higher utility for a given expected value of the payoff, but it inevitably reduces the effectiveness of the incentives provided by the fee schedule. Other devices that can be used to induce effort by the agent include flat fees, accompanied by a threat of termination if the agent is caught shirking. Risk-sharing fee schedules have been discussed extensively in the literature on incentive compensation systems for corporate executives, while flat fees accompanied by threat of termination This solution, of course, depends on the payoff being transferrable from the principal to the 24 agent. 18 form the basis for both the literature on the market for corporate control as a mechanism for inducing managerial effort, and for the “efficiency wage” stories in labor theory. 25 But while principal-agent models have been useful in delineating certain kinds of contracting problems, they do not go to the essence of the nature of the firm itself. In fact, they just assume the existence of the principal, or the employer -- the entity on the other side of the contract with management or labor. 4. Team production with long-term contracts. By itself, the Alchian and Demsetz story offers no particular reason why the membership of the team couldn't change from day to day, or hour to hour. In fact, they claim, “long-term contracts between employer and employee are not the essence of the organization we call a firm.” They argue, rather, that the relationship between firm and employee is equivalent to a series of short-term contracts: “the employer is continually involved in renegotiation of contracts on terms that must be acceptable to both parties.” 26 But we know that fairly long-term relationships are the norm in large corporations rather than the exception. So their story seems, at best, incomplete, for explaining the actual way that large corporations typically operate. The Alchian and Demsetz story can be improved by allowing for investments in firm-specific human capital, or other factors which might make it advantageous to keep a particular team working together. Demsetz himself has moved in this direction in more recent work. An important aspect of the “nexus of contracts,” that makes up a firm, he says, “Efficiency wages” refer to a class of arguments in labor theory in which employees are 25 induced to perform well by making it costly for them if they get laid off -- generally by paying them more than their opportunity cost. See discussion above of non-market clearing wages. See also Weiss (1990) for a thorough review of the efficiency wage literature. See Alchian and Demsetz (1972), p. 777. 26 19 “is the expected length of association between the same input owners. Do the contractual agreements entered into contemplate mainly transitory, short-term association, which in the extreme would be characterized by spot market exchanges, or do these agreements contemplate a high probability of continuing association between the same parties. The firm viewed as team production exhibits significant reassociation of the same input owners.” 27 Demsetz, in fact, goes on to define a firm as “a bundle of commitments to technology, personnel, and methods, all contained and constrained by an insulating layer of information that is specific to the firm, and this bundle cannot be altered or imitated easily or quickly.” 28 In the types of team production that are characteristic of real world firms, then, the human capital of the team members is worth more when applied together with the human capital of the other team members than it is when applied alone. With specific human capital, the productivity of a particular individual depends not just on being part of a team, but on being part of a particular team engaged in a particular task. But if it matters who is on the team, this complicates the Alchian and Demsetz story because it is no longer clear that team members who invest in specialized skills and who know they are especially valuable when deployed with this particular team will be willing to accept only their (short-run) opportunity cost in wages. Hence it is no longer obvious that the monitor will be able to collect all of the economic surplus (the rents and quasirents) from the enterprise. In some ways, the problem raised by investments in firm-specific human capital is analogous to the principal-agent problem. The employee must take some action (e.g., acquire some skills, accumulate some special knowledge, develop some special relationships with co-workers) which the firm cannot directly measure and for which it cannot directly compensate the employee. The firm Harold Demsetz, “The Theory of the Firm Revisited,” in Oliver Williamson and Sidney 27 Winter, eds., The Nature of the Firm, Oxford University Press, 1991, pp. 170. Demsetz (1991), p. 16. 28 20 can only observe (perhaps imperfectly) the outcomes of such investments. Wiggins stresses the 29 similarities between the principal-agent problem and the problem of firm-specific investments by noting that, whenever “one party performs first, he effectively makes an investment specific to the trading relationship; he invests in a specific asset. After investment, he relies on the other party to perform. The problem is that the second party can only make limited commitments to follow through.” 30 But the firm-specific investment problem is different from the canonical principalagent problem in a critical way: it is symmetric. With firm-specific investments, actions of both parties can affect the payoff from the investment. In the canonical principal-agent problem, there is an implicit assumption that, once the fee schedule has been determined, the actions of the principal have no further effect on the outcome of the variable to which the fee schedule is tied. The outcome is realized, the fees that were promised to the agent are determined as a function of that outcome, and the agents are promptly paid. 31 In the firm-specific human capital story, by contrast, the employee takes an action that affects the payoff for the firm, but the firm, in turn, can take actions that not only affect the fee that the employee gets, but that affect the stream of rents and quasi-rents generated by that action. The “The employment relation in general is one in which effort and ability acquired through 29 training and self-improvement are hard to observe,” notes Kenneth Arrow. “In one view, firms exist as a means of measuring effort.” See Arrow (1985), p. 39. Wiggins goes on to suggest that firms, contracts, and government regulations are, or can be, 30 alternative mechanisms for solving these problems. See Wiggins (1991), p. 604. Wiggins notes that agency theory implicitly “makes a strong assumption about the credibility 31 of these two parties [the employer and the employee], and this assumption drives all the results. The general contracting problem, however, is to specify how promises are enforced, and then derive the structure of the contract in a consistent manner from that specification.” See Wiggins (1991), p. 646-647. firm can decide to close the plant where the employee works, and suddenly there is no opportunity for the payoff to be realized, for example. Or the shareholders can sell the firm to someone else who can fire the manager or dismantle the firm. 32 Hence, if firm-specific human capital is an important input in corporate enterprises, the classical principal-agent model may be too one-sided to be adequate to the task of describing the fundamental features of the employment relationship, and of the firm itself. Becker (1964) was clearly aware of this problem. See pp. ??. The point is also close to that made by Shleifer and Summers (1988) in their critique of hostile takeovers. Although Shleifer and Summers do not appeal explicitly to investments in firm-specific human capital as the basis for the implicit contracts that they argue are breached by takeovers, such investments would be one explanation of the quasi-rents that are supposedly up for grabs in their story. 22 III. Contracting problems raised by firm-specific human capital: The potential “holdup” problem presented by firm-specific investments of all kinds was discussed at some length above. The hold-up problem makes such investments risky. But investments in firm-specific human capital present other contracting problems too. A. Risk-sharing. Firm-specific human capital is subject to two kinds of risks, the risks that the rents and quasirents it generates will be expropriated (the hold-up problem), and the risks that its actual value (its ability to generate rents and quasirents) will fluctuate. The risks to actual value can be further subdivided into the risks that the particular skills will no longer be as useful in a given firm, and the risks that the firm itself will no longer generate as much in total rents. Finally, the firm's risk can be subdivided into idiosyncratic risks and systemic risks. Much has been made of the idea that the corporate form facilitates a division of labor in which managers specialize in decision-making, and outside investors specialize in risk-bearing. 33 This approach to thinking about the nature of the firm and the contracting problems in the firm, however, essentially ignores the risks borne by employees with firm-specific human capital. At least two of the categories of risk facing employees are risks that outside shareholders could not, even in principle, protect employees from. These are the portion of the risks to underlying actual value that are due to systemic risks, and the risks of expropriation, which are inherent in the contracting problem between employees and firms. Numerous scholars have argued that employees are protected from the risks of expropriation by the fact that the firm must be concerned about its reputation for fairness. A good reputation See Fama and Jensen (1983) for the classic article that makes this argument. 33 23 enables it to contract on favorable terms with other employees in the future. In other words, the 34 firm is assumed to have a longer time horizon than the employees. But for the firm to play this role in the relationship, for it to be an effective bearer of reputation, the identity of the firm must be reasonably stable. While corporations have the potential of perpetual existence under the law, in recent years, corporations in the U.S. have undergone dramatic structural and identity changes at a very rapid pace. It seems likely that these changes have undermined the effectiveness of reputation as a mechanism for ensuring employees of most firms that the firms value their reputation, and will not renege on their end of the deal. In practice, employees are also not given significant protections against the risks of decline in the actual long-term value (rent-generating capacity) of their firm-specific skills, and it is difficult to imagine how such protection could be provided in any company over an extended period of time. But if employees share in the valuation risks, this inevitably increases the expropriation risk 35 Milgrom and Roberts note, for example, that “the value of a good reputation increases with the number of times it may be used. Thus, if one party to a relationship has a longer horizon than another, the first party, when put in a position of power, will have a stronger incentive to build and maintain a reputation . . . for using power well. This argues for giving the residual power to whichever party to a relationship has the longer horizon.” See Milgrom and Roberts (1992), p. 331. See Kreps (1990) for a general discussion of the role of norms, reputation, and corporate culture. Finally, see also Williamson (1985), p. 261: “Employers who have a reputation for exploiting incumbent employees will not thereafter be able to induce new employees to accept employment on the same terms. A wage premium may have to be paid; or tasks may have to be redefined to eliminate the transaction-specific features; or contractual guarantees against future abuses may have to be granted. In consideration of those possibilities, the strategy of exploiting the specific investments of incumbent employees is effectively restricted to circumstances where (1) firms are of a fly-bynight kind, (2) firms are playing end games, and (3) intergenerational learning is negligible.” Employees with a “fixed wage” arrangement are protected from the month-tomonth, or year35 to-year fluctuations in the rents generated by their specific skills. But there are few if any protections for employees if the present value of the stream of rents their specific skills can generate falls below the present value of the stream of wage premia they are receiving. 24 they face. This is because it is much harder to enforce “fairness” in an employment agreement whose terms can be renegotiated as business conditions facing the firm vary. As Milgrom and Roberts note: “The firm's management may be tempted to exaggerate financial difficulties in order to justify paying lower wages to workers.” 36 On the other hand, totally insulating employees against risks might discourage them from doing the things that are under their control to pull resources out of lowervalue investments and move them to higher-value investments, by retraining, for example. B. Monitoring. The disincentive effects of mechanisms that shelter employees from some of the risks inherent in making specialized investments can possibly be counteracted with more intensive monitoring. But monitoring, in turn, can present serious measurement, verification, and evaluation problems. The monitor must focus on the measurable dimensions of performance, 37 which may lead employees to focus on those “monitored” dimensions to the exclusion of nonmeasurable dimensions that may also be important to productivity. 38 See Milgrom and Roberts (1992), p. 334. See also Rosen (1985), for a good summary of risk36 sharing issues in implicit employment contracts. Hashimoto (1981) argues that investments in firm-specific human capital are likely to present 37 such a severe problem in evaluating, verifying and agreeing on workers' productiveness that the monitoring solution cannot be effective by itself. He models Becker's argument that employee and employer should share the costs and returns from such investments, using a sharing rule that explicitly gives employees a fluctuating share in the rents, rather than a fixed wage. See Holmstrom and Milgrom (1991). These authors focus on the problems caused by pay for 38 performance schemes that tie compensation to quantifiable measures of performance but exclude consideration of other, less quantifiable indicators of performance. They argue that monitoring can help to counteract the potential for perverse incentive effects from such schemes. But monitoring is subject to the same kinds of perverse incentive problems as pay for performance schemes if all of the dimensions of performance are not equally observable, quantifiable, and verifiable, and therefore susceptible to monitoring. 25 C. Quantifying the value of residual claims. One of the contracting problems raised by investments in human capital in general, and by specific human capital in particular, is the problem of understanding and quantifying all the forms that the returns to those investments can take. Whereas the returns to physical capital investments can generally be measured in monetary terms, some of the returns to investments in human capital may take other forms. Human capital may not depreciate with use, for example, but may, instead, appreciate. Like muscles, knowledge and skills that are used may build on themselves and become more useable. If so, the returns to tenure may go well beyond just the returns from skills accumulated up to a particular point in time (and by extension, the losses from premature job separations may be much larger than that implied by the stream of rents being generated today). The losses may also include a component that is like an option. If the employee stays with his present employer, he will have an opportunity to acquire skills tomorrow that build on the skills acquired through today. Those skills would generate an additional stream of returns on top of the stream of returns from the skills accumulated through today. If the employment relationship is prematurely severed, that option value is lost. The complex nature of the returns to human capital may make it impossible, Milgrom and Roberts note, “to identify any individual or group that is the unique residual claimant [in a firm], or, indeed, to identify the benefits and costs accruing to any decision and so compute the residuals.” 39 The difficulty of computing and assigning residuals complicates the problem of bargaining between any employee and the firm over the allocation of residual claims, or over any scheme of payments See Milgrom and Roberts (1992), p. 315. See also Holmstrom (1982) for a general discussion 39 of a related problem with team production, the problem of allocating returns from team efforts in ways that discourage “free-riding” by individual members of the team. 26 that might be devised to encourage both parties to the relationship to take into account the impact of decisions by one on the other. D. A Counter Argument. Dow argues that employees don't generally make any sacrifices when they acquire firm-specific skills -- that, instead, they acquire such skills as a byproduct of participating in production tasks, a job they are being paid to do anyway. Thus, he says, “there is no need for explicit contracts whereby workers commit themselves to invest in specialized skills,” and therefore, the “non-contractibility of investments in human capital does not raise an insuperable obstacle for capitalist firms.” But this argument seems too facile. Even if employees don't have to 40 make great sacrifices to acquire firm-specific skills, those skills may still have value, to the firm, or to the employee or to both, and hence, it may be socially valuable to provide protective contractual arrangements or governance devices. 41 See Dow, “Why Capital Hires Labor: Reply,” undated working paper, University of Alberta. 40 If someone inherited a piece of land, the fact that they acquired that piece of land without 41 expending any special effort or resources does not mean that the value of the land should not be protected. 27 IV. Institutional Arrangements that Address These Contracting Problems. Since the contracting problems surrounding investments in firm-specific human capital are so large and pervasive, it should not be surprising to find that the providers of human and financial capital have found other, non-contractual mechanisms for encouraging and protecting firm-specific investments. Some of these mechanisms have been studied by labor economists but while versions of them are found in most large corporations, they have not generally been treated by economists as being part of the institutional nature of the firm itself. A. Long-term employment relationships. Customs and practices that encourage longterm employment relationships have a variety of benefits that support, or are perhaps complementary with investments in firm-specific human capital. Milgrom and Roberts cite “an increased opportunity to invest profitably in firm-specific human capital, the greater efficacy of efficiency wage incentives contracts in long-term relationships, and the enhanced ability to make an accurate assessment of an employee's contributions to long-term objectives by monitoring performance over a longer period of time.” To this could be added reputational considerations. As argued above, good 42 reputations are more valuable the longer the time-horizons of the contracting parties, so that in a longer-term relationship, both sides to any given transaction within that relationship will have stronger incentives to perform fully. B. “Hostages” or Performance Bonds. A “hostage” is anything of value that is pledged by one party to a transaction, and that will be forfeited to the other party if the first party fails to perform his or her end of the contract. One version of the “efficiency wage” arguments, for example, is based on a “hostage” argument. That argument says that workers accept wages that are See Milgrom and Roberts (1992), p. 363. The classic discussion of the role played by long42 term employment relationships is Doeringer and Piore (1971). 28 lower than their opportunity cost in the early years of their employment relationship, and that this serves as a performance bond that is later repaid in the form of wages that are higher than their opportunity cost. Severance pay commitments, and their gilt-edged cousins, golden parachutes, can be thought of as “hostages” provided by the employer. Penalties for certain kinds of changes in the contract terms may perform a similar function. Milgrom and Roberts argue, for example, that employment contracts might be designed to impose a penalty of some sort on the employer for invoking a claim of hard-times in an effort to negotiate lower wages, so that the employer will not be tempted to use this claim frivolously in negotiations. 43 The administration and enforcement of performance bond agreements, however, requires that third parties be able to observe and verify certain measures of performance, and certain triggering events. Hence performance bonds by themselves seem like poor candidates for solving the contracting problems presented by the accumulation of specialized human capital unless they are imbedded in institutional arrangements that also foster trust, or that make reputations valuable. C. Job ladders, career paths, and seniority rules. A number of scholars have argued that career paths and job ladders are important mechanisms for encouraging employees to make investments in firm-specific human capital and for ensuring that the firm shares the rents generated by those investments with employees. Seniority rules are a related mechanism that provides some 44 protection for employees from the possibility that the firm will renege on its implicit agreement to compensate the employee for his or her firm-specific investments by paying them a higher wage See Milgrom and Roberts (1992), p. 334. 43 See, for example, Koike (1990), and Prendergast (1993). 44 29 during their later years, perhaps even a wage that exceeds their productivity during those years. Seniority rules protect the high-tenured worker by requiring the firm to lay off lowtenured workers first. Both seniority rules and job ladders can be seen as mechanisms that help ensure that the employee will be appropriately compensated for his or her investments over time. But such promises would have no incentive benefit if employees did not believe that the employing organization would continue to exist over the relevant period of time. So these mechanisms are not useful by themselves, but must be embedded in a relationship that is understood to be long-term, with an entity that is long-lived. D. Unionization. One effect of unions is to substitute “voice” for the right of “exit” (i.e., the “at will” contract) for both sides to the employment relationship by providing protections for employees such as protection from dismissal, except “for cause.” Other terms in the typical collective bargaining agreement, in turn, help prevent firms from driving out an unwanted employee without actually dismissing him. These take the form of rules designed to protect wages, benefits, and job assignments, as well as protection against layoffs. These sorts of protections have been criticized because they impose rigidities that can have negative implications for efficient adaptation to changed circumstances. But these costs must be weighed against incentive benefits union 45 agreements may provide. See Epstein (1985), p. 147. “The organizational difficulties of collective bargaining are the 45 price that union workers pay in order to extract monopoly profits, or at least firmspecific rents, from their employers and through them the consuming public at large,” Epstein claims. See also Klein, Crawford and Alchian (1978). Epstein's argument involves an unstated assumption that the “firmspecific rents” at stake belong to the employers rather than to the employees in the first place. 30 E. Corporate culture, norms, and goals. Milgrom and Roberts note that “workable principles and routines . . . create shared expectations for group members.” The advantages of such principles are that they “help guide managers in making decisions”; that they provide “a set of clear expectations for everyone in the organization”; and that they “provide a set of principles and procedures for judging right behavior and resolving inevitable disputes.” As Kreps (1990) first 46 argued, these aspects of corporate culture may serve as “focal points” around which participants in the firm can arrive at stable patterns of interacting that are Pareto superior to patterns they might lapse into without the benefit of the common norms. Hence, corporate culture can help to support 47 investments in firm-specific human capital by fostering trust. Corporate culture can also be seen as part of the firm-specific capital of the firm -- the organizational capital if you will. Nelson and Winter argue that the knowledge of how to do things is often implicit in the routines that make up the daily activities of the people in the firm. As such, 48 it is neither articulable, nor alienable, but is embodied in the people and in their relationships to each other. Similarly, Jacoby writes about the “socialization of the workplace itself, which relies on consensual methods of inculcating norms and goals, such as ideologies or authority that must be seen as legitimate if they are to be persuasive.” 49 F. Ownership and control rights. Milgrom and Roberts (1992), p. 265. 46 Kreps (1990) provides an extensive analysis of the role of corporate culture using game47 theoretic arguments. Nelson and Winter (1982). 48 See Jacoby (1990), p. 332. 49 31 Hart has argued that “ownership” should be defined as possession of “residual” control rights -- the right to make all decisions that have not been specified by contract. Organizing a 50 transaction within a single firm has the effect of assigning all residual control rights over the nonhuman assets used in that transaction to a single entity, Hart suggests. And it is this 51 concentration of control rights that makes it possible to accomplish things that could not be accomplished through market-mediated transactions among individual actors, each of whom controlled only the physical assets with which he or she worked. In particular, Hart has noted, “ex post residual rights of control will be important because, through their influence on asset usage, they will affect ex post bargaining power and the division of ex post surplus in a relationship. This in turn will affect the incentives of actors to invest in that relationship.” 52 Hart has argued that “co-specialized” assets should be owned in common. If they are not, then the separate parties who own each asset will have reason to fear that the other parties will expropriate “too much” of the rents earned by the assets, and will tend to underinvest. But of 53 See Hart (1989). 50 Wiggins asserts that “in principle, parties could agree to any contract between firms that could 51 be entered into internally.” See Wiggins (1991), p. 661. This is the inverse of the proposition put forth by Coase that, in principle, all of the arrangements that are available to contracting parties outside the firm should be available within the firm, and then some. By extension, organizing economic activity within firms would always be more efficient than organizing activity between autonomous units. Coase asked what it is that makes organizing economic activity within firms more efficient in some circumstances, and organizing activities through contractual or market agreements between autonomous parties more efficient in other circumstances. See Coase (1937). Wiggins suggests that the difference has to do with which form makes it easier or less costly to enforce the contracts or terms of the relationship. Almost by definition, “residual” control rights are the non-contractible ones. Under common “ownership,” these residual control rights reside with the same party. See Hart (1989), p. 1766. 52 See Hart (1989), p. 1757-1774. 53 32 course, neither the firm, nor any other participant in the enterprise that the firm directs, can “own” the human capital that may be co-specialized with the other assets of the firm. Hence, where firmspecific human capital is important, such arguments might in some cases point toward employee control of the enterprise, or at least participation in management, rather than capitalist ownership and control. 54 1. Labor-managed firms. A number of scholars were inspired by the Yugoslavian experiment with labor-managed firms in the 1960s to consider the advantages and disadvantages of organizing production in this way. This produced a small, but lively debate in which neoclassical economists argued that employee-controlled firms would be inefficient for a variety of reasons. 55 Various scholars have answered these criticisms by pointing out that, in each case, the supposed inefficiencies are a product of peculiar modeling assumptions made by the critics. But, as an 56 empirical matter, employee-controlled firms remain rare, and absent obvious legal restrictions In noting the advantages of the partnership form of organization, Milgrom and Roberts point 54 out that “human capital is not easily tradable, and if the residual returns on that capital belong to the humans who embody it, then the usual arguments about ownership rights suggests that the residual control should be assigned to them too.” See Milgrom and Roberts (1992), p. 523. See also Hansmann (1988), p. 292, Putterman and Kroszner (1995), p. 19, and Blair (1995), for discussions of employee ownership as a mechanism for protecting investments in firm-specific human capital. Vanek (1977) and Meade (1972) argued that labor-managed firms would maximize net 55 revenues per worker rather than maximizing profits, for example. Jensen and Meckling (1979), Furobotn and Pejovich (1974), and Vanek (1977) argued that employee-controlled firms would not have the right incentives to adequately maintain their physical capital. Williamson (1975, 1985) argued that democratically-run firms would be inefficient because hierarchies are needed for efficient processing of large amounts of information. See e.g., Putterman (1984), Wolfstetter, Brown and Meran (1984), Ellerman (1986), and Dow 56 (1993). 33 against them, economists generally assume take their absence to mean that this form is not economically viable for a variety of reasons. 57 2. Labor participation in management. Corporate governance systems in Japan and Europe seem to feature institutional arrangements that provide mechanisms by which employees are given a direct voice in management. Although it is beyond the scope of this paper to discuss these alternative systems, Japanese scholars, especially, have credited these arrangements with providing incentives and protection for employee investments in firm-specific human capital. 58 Germany's co-determination system has also attracted the attention of policy-makers and scholars in this regard. 59 3. Equity ownership by employees. Compensating employees with equity stakes in corporations might provide a mechanism for fostering and protecting investments in firm-specific human capital. Equity ownership by employees serves as a kind of “hostage,” helping to make the firm's promise to share in the rents credible. It also gives employees some control rights (by virtue of their equity holdings rather than by virtue of their status as employees), while at the same time, helping to align their interests with those of outside equity holders. And if equity claims are substituted for the wage premium that firm-specific human capital supposedly earns, the wages will come closer to reflecting opportunity cost, and thereby send the correct economic signals to decision-makers within the firm to guide hiring and firing decisions. See Dow and Putterman (1997) in this collection. 57 The literature on this is large, but see, e.g., Aoki (1988), and Matsuyama (1996). 58 See, e.g., Baums and Frick (1997) and Pistor (1997) in this collection. 59 34 There is substantial evidence that the use of equity-based compensation systems is growing in U.S. corporations, although no definitive empirical studies have linked employee ownership in publicly-traded firms to investments in firm-specific human capital. 60 4. A Case Against Employee Ownership. Hansmann has argued that the disadvantages of collective decision-making by heterogeneous employees, however, might easily outweigh the advantages of common ownership of the capital and labor inputs. He argues that the feature that distinguishes employee-owned enterprises from those owned by outside investors is the homogeneity of the workforce, rather than the specificity of the human capital possessed by that workforce. Other scholars have argued that the fact that capitalists have more wealth and better 61 access to credit markets than workers do, and the fact that capitalists can diversify risks better than workers can, also argue against employee ownership. See Blasi and Kruse (1991) for the most comprehensive evidence of the growth of employee60 ownership in publicly-traded firms. See Hansmann (1995). 61 35 V. New Thinking about the Theory of the Firm. The foregoing review of the role played, and problems raised by, investments in firmspecific human capital suggests that the nature of the employment relationship is, indeed, central to understanding the nature of the institutional arrangements that are at the essence of modern, large corporations. The idea that the firm is a “nexus of contracts,” was a significant insight that helped push our understanding of firms forward because it got scholars thinking about the terms of the relationships among the various participants in firms. But scholarly work on this idea has perhaps been hung up for too long in a fixation on one particular relationship (that between shareholders and managers) and on an approach to modeling that relationship (principal-agent models) that is too onesided. Economic theorists, however, are moving in some new directions that acknowledge more directly the complex nature of the way employees participate in firms. These theoretical contributions take steps toward defining the firms themselves in terms of the institutional arrangements developed to elicit contributions by employees to the joint productive effort of the enterprise. If the full range of contributions needed could be adequately elicited through market relationships or explicit contracts, perhaps they would be. But it is the very fact that they can't that calls forth complex organizational forms such as modern corporations. A. The Firm as a System of Incentives. Holmstrom and Milgrom (1994) propose that firms should be viewed as incentive systems. Their model explores why “the attributes of an employment relationship differ in so many ways from the attributes of a contractor relationship.” In comparing the terms on which in-house sales agents typically operate, to the terms on which independent sales agents typically operate, for example, Holmstrom and Milgrom note that, relative to relationships with subcontractors, employment relationships typically involve lower-powered 36 incentives (a fixed base salary and lower commissions, for example), ownership of key assets by the employer (rather than by the employee), and more restrictions on mode of operation of the employee. Holmstrom and Milgrom's contribution utilizes a multitask principal-agent model designed to address the problems that arise when the tasks the worker is supposed to do are multidimensional, and performance difficult to measure in some or all of those dimensions. As the authors had discussed in previous work, when agents must perform a number of tasks, and their choices about effort and allocation of their time can affect many dimensions of the firm's performance, highpowered incentive structures that reward performance in some dimensions (but neglect performance in other dimensions) can greatly distort the behavior of the agent. 62 Of course, a key feature that distinguishes agents who are “in” the firm from agents who are on the outside and merely contracting with the firm, is the structure of the compensation agreement. In particular, compensation for contractors generally provides for task-specific payments, with all risks of nonperformance borne by the agent, whereas with employees, such risks are generally pooled (and borne collectively by the firm itself, and ultimately by various participants in the firm), so that the agent is paid a regular wage or salary for the duration of employment, regardless of the actual tasks performed. The Holmstrom and Milgrom model implies that, under certain conditions, an optimal incentive structure “may require the elimination or muting of incentives which in a market relationship would be too strong.” Thus, they conclude, “the use of low-powered incentives within See Holmstrom and Milgrom (1991). 62 37 the firm, although sometimes lamented as one of the major disadvantages of internal organization, is also an important vehicle for inspiring cooperation and coordination.” 63 Within the world of insurance agents that Holmstrom and Milgrom consider, they find that the choice between structuring the relationship as an employment one, versus structuring it as one of an independent contractor type, appears to be driven by the relative ease or difficulty of measuring key aspects of performance, more than by the extent of investments in firm-specific human capital. But it seems unlikely that this factor drives this choice in other cases. Consider production line workers, for example. Assembly line workers who work on large, highly capitalintensive automated assembly lines are typically paid hourly wages, and a variety of other institutional arrangements are used (such as pension funds and collective bargaining) to discourage turnover. By contrast, workers in garment factories are more likely to be paid piece rates, turnover rates in sweat shops are high, and there are fewer institutional arrangements designed to reduce turnover. In other words, apparel workers are often compensated and treated more like subcontractors than employees. In both cases, the activities of the worker should be very easy to measure. But in the garment factory, where apparel is assembled at separate sewing machines, individual workers can set their own pace, whereas in large automated factories, individual workers cannot set their own pace, but must learn to function at a pace set for them by the machines and by the rest of the team with which they work. Holmstrom and Milgrom's model might be used to test the hypothesis that the differences in compensation systems and institutional arrangements between, say, auto factory workers and garment factory workers, are accounted for by the fact that workers on automated assembly lines See Holmstrom and Milgrom (1994), p. 989. 63 38 must make a higher level of investment (that is, exert more “effort”) in learning to work with the particular equipment in the factory and with the particular teammates on the assembly line. The Holmstrom and Milgrom paper illuminates the importance of considering the whole mix of incentives facing employees, and moves theory away from viewing firms as “bundles of assets,” toward a view of firms as constellations of institutional arrangements designed to provide appropriate incentives where cooperation and coordination are especially important. Their modeling approach, however, falls within the principal-agent paradigm, and as is generally the case with principal-agent models, it does not take into account the incentives facing the principal to renege on the promised payment scheme, or to alter the job design in ways that reduce the payoff to the agent ex post. It also does not explain two other features that distinguish the employment relationship from the independent contractor relationship -- features that have been cited as evidence that investments in firm-specific human capital are important. These are the longevities typically observed in the employment relationship relative to independent contracting relationships, and the wage premia associated with tenure. B. The Firm as a Nexus of Specific Investments Another very new contribution to the literature, by Rajan and Zingales (1996), treats firmspecific investments, especially in human capital, as the defining feature of a firm. This approach 64 is reminiscent of Aoki (1984), who defined the firm as “an enduring combination of firm-specific The authors suggest that a firm should be defined not as a “nexus of contracts,” as previous 64 scholars have proposed, but as a “nexus of specific investments.” (Although the authors have produced a revised version of the working paper cited in this article, with the same title, but dated November, 1996, the revised version compresses some important arguments that I want to emphasize in this article. The authors have explained to me that they intend to pursue those compressed ideas in other papers.) 39 resources.” Rajan and Zingales use an optimal-contract modeling approach that is similar to, and 65 builds on the approach used by Grossman and Hart in their landmark piece (discussed above). 66 In Rajan and Zingales's model, there is a physical asset that is specific to the enterprise, and two individuals. The total productivity of the enterprise will be maximized if both individuals make specific investments in human capital. But each individual must have access to the physical asset in order to “specialize.” If either individual fails to specialize, an unspecialized outsider can be substituted for that individual without loss of total productivity. Rajan and Zingales distinguish between “ownership” and “power.” “Ownership” of the enterprise, in their model, gives the owner the right to exclude other individuals from access to the physical asset, and the right to sell the physical asset to some third party. These rights give the 67 “owner” significant “power” in bargaining over the ex post distribution of rents. But participants can also get “power” in another way. Investment by either individual in firm-specific human capital also gives that individual bargaining power in the relationship, because his investment in human capital means that there will be more total rents to share if he stays in the coalition and uses his human capital in the enterprise. Aoki (1984), p. 119. Aoki argued that firms should be regarded as combinations of specific 65 labor and capital, and that management should be viewed as mediating between these two interests in making decisions about output levels, investments, and sharing of firm-level rents. His model takes the relative power of labor and capital as parameters, and models the decision-making process of management. Rajan and Zingales, as we shall see, derive a similar structure for firms from more primitive assumptions about the nature of the technology and the incentives of the individual participants. Grossman and Hart (1986). 66 Grossman and Hart (1986) define ownership only in terms of the ability of the owner to 67 exclude others from access. Their model does not allow for the owner to sell the asset into any kind of external market. 40 Grossman and Hart (1986), and Hart and Moore (1990) argued that ownership of the physical asset would increase the ex ante incentive for the owner to make the optimal investments in human capital. But Rajan and Zingales point out that ownership of the physical asset also enables the owner to sell the asset, or to share in the rents from the enterprise even if he fails to make firmspecific investments. Hence ownership rights over the physical asset, in their model, has a doublededged effect. It increases the bargaining power the owner has, and therefore increases his incentive to “specialize” by assuring him that his share of the rents generated by the enterprise will not be expropriated ex post. This is the Grossman-Hart, and Hart-Moore effect. But it also raises his opportunity cost for specializing, since he can extract rents even if he doesn't specialize. If the negative effects of ownership by either individual dominate the positive incentive effects, Rajan and Zingales show that the optimal investment decisions and production levels cannot be achieved if either of the two potential “specializers” own the physical asset. But, remarkably, if the physical asset is owned by an otherwise passive third party, optimal investment decisions and production levels can still be achieved. In this situation, the two individuals who want to participate in the firm would form a coalition and bid collectively for access to the asset, and the right to use the asset in production. Third-party control over the physical asset helps to encourage both individuals to make the optimal firm-specific investments, because it, in effect, enables the two individuals to make a binding commitment not to use control over the asset strategically to try to extract rents from the other individual. Rajan and Zingales have, thus, brought us full circle, back to the Alchian and Demsetz story about the importance of team production, and the need for a third party to monitor the inputs of the team members. But because they assume that the individual members of the team are not generic inputs, but specialists who got that way because they invested in learning things that only have value 41 when used by this particular team, they reach a very different conclusion about the division of rents from team production, as well as about the role played by the third party “monitor.” Rajan and Zingales's third party has no special knowledge or insights about how the work is divided up between the two individuals in the coalition, nor how they divide up the rents between them. Their third party is assumed to get an arbitrarily small fraction of the total rents, and his only task is simply to select from among multiple coalitions bidding for access rights to the physical assets. He naturally selects the coalition that will produce the highest total rents, the bulk of which go not to the third party monitor (as in Alchian and Demsetz), but to the coalition members who have invested in specialized human capital. “Before investment [in specialized human capital] takes place, the firm is defined by who holds the ownership rights to the physical assets that are required for production and by who is given access to the physical assets,” Rajan and Zingales argue. “After specific investment has been undertaken, the firm is defined by the ownership of the physical assets and the power that accrues to those who have made specific investments.” 68 Rajan and Zingales interpret their model as offering an economic rationale for the separation of “ownership” from “control,” although this seems like a curious interpretation since they define “ownership” to mean control rights over the use of physical assets. One right that outside shareholders of large corporations definitively do not have is control over the physical assets of the corporation. An alternative interpretation of Rajan and Zingales's work might be that it provides insight into the role played by independent boards of directors with fiduciary obligations to their firms. The The authors go on to argue that, with their model, there can be a firm even if there are no 68 physical assets, although in such a case there is also no role for a third party “owner.” 42 function of the “passive” third-party “owner” in their model is not to “maximize the value” of his stake. In fact, the third party owner in this story is restricted to receiving an arbitrarily small return because he does not provide anything critical to production. His role could be played by anyone (except, notably, any of the active participants in the enterprise). His function instead is to keep control of the assets out of the hands of any of the active participants in the firm, precisely so that those active parties won't use control over the assets to gain strategic advantage for themselves at the expense of the other participants, and thereby cause the coalition to fall apart. C. Future Directions. Rajan and Zingales have taken a significant step toward integrating models of the employment relationship (and the associated incentive issues raised by investments in firm-specific human capital) into a theory of the firm. But their model is still limited by the fact that it follows the two-period structure of most bargaining models. In such models, contracts are written, investment 69 decisions are made, production proceeds, and rents are realized and divided up. End of story. There is no second round, let alone third or fourth or more rounds, so that there is no place in the model for reputations to be built up, or for learning from experience, or for investments made in previous rounds to expand the options for the participants in subsequent rounds. Models that have such features can become intractable very quickly, and theorists who have struggled with repeated game models find that they are plagued by multiple equilibria, and are often very sensitive to assumptions about who has what information when. Nonetheless, the basic 70 insight from infinitely repeated game models is that the chance to benefit from a relationship in the Technically, there are three periods in the Rajan and Zingales model, but that is because they 69 have made the decisions by the two individuals to specialize sequential instead of simultaneous. See Kreps (1996) for an interesting discussion of these issues. 70 43 future can mitigate tendencies that parties to the relationship might have in the present to attempt to expropriate short run returns. From the perspective of repeated games, each act of self-restraint on the part of participants in the firm can be seen as a “firm-specific investment” whose value can be realized if the coalition stays together, but not if it falls apart. The cumulative result of a large number of such acts of selfrestraint could represent a sizeable investment in a type of firm-specific human capital that we might call “trust,” or “culture.” As in Rajan and Zingales, the firm can be viewed as a nexus of these investments, and for the full value of the investments to be realized, the coalition of key participants in the firm must be kept together. Also, as in Rajan and Zingales, keeping the coalition together may require the services of an otherwise neutral third party with critical control rights. Again, the role is more suggestive of an independent board of directors than of outside shareholders. VI. Implications for Legal Scholarship. In the last two decades, the idea that a corporation is a “nexus of contracts” has strongly influenced legal scholarship. The idea was seen as a substitute for an “entity” view of the corporation, a view which had been prevalent in legal theory prior to about the 1970s. Under the entity view of the firm, a corporation is understood to be something apart from each of its participants that managers could raid or abuse if they were not subject to constraints imposed by their fiduciary duties and corporation law. The “nexus of contracts” view, by contrast, offered a view of corporations that stresses the willing participation by all parties, and the ability of all parties to protect their interests by contractual means. The legal implication of the nexus of contracts view was taken to be that if the courts and the legislatures would restrict themselves merely to enforcing contracts, the interplay of freely contracting individuals and free markets would lead individuals to enter into relationships that 44 optimally balanced claims to returns and control rights. Contracts freely entered-into, moreover, could be assumed to be economically efficient. 71 In this stark form, however, the contractarian view fails to recognize that, no matter how beneficial they might be, certain kinds of multilateral, and multidimensional relationships and agreements among individuals may only be possible in a legal environment that grants separate legal status to the entity that serves as the repository of the specific investments involved in the relationship. It may also be necessary that the law assign fiduciary responsibilities to the individuals whose job is to govern this entity. The theoretical work discussed above suggests that, as we come to understand better the full and complex dimensions of the contracting problem involved in organizing production, we may develop a renewed appreciation of the entity view of firms in the law, and with that, perhaps even of the role of legal constraints on managerial behavior and of enforceable fiduciary obligations on the part of directors. See, Butler (1989) for a discussion of the “nexus of contracts” view of the firm as the basis for 71 a contractarian approach to corporate law. 45 Bibliography Alchian, Armen A., and Harold Demsetz. 1972. “Production, Information Costs, and Economic Organization.” American Economic Review 62: 777-795. Aoki, Masahiko. 1984. The Co-operative Game Theory of the Firm, Oxford: Clarendon Press. ------------. 1988. Information, Incentives, and Bargaining in the Japanese Economy, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Arrow, Kenneth J. 1985. “The Economics of Agency.” In Principals and Agents: The Structure of Business, edited by John W. Pratt and Richard Zeckhauser, 37-51. Boston: Harvard Business School Press. Baker, George, Robert Gibbons, and Kevin Murphy. 1996. “Implicit Contracts and the Theory of the Firm.” Working Paper, April, 1996. Baums, Theodor, and Bernd Frick. 1997. “Co-determination in Germany: The Impact of Court Decisions on Stock Price,” (in this collection) Becker, Gary S. 1964. Human Capital: A Theoretical and Empirical Analysis, With Special Reference to Education. New York: National Bureau of Economic Research. Blair, Margaret M. 1995. Ownership and Control: Rethinking Corporate Governance for the Twenty-First Century. Brookings. _______________. 1996. Wealth Creation and Wealth Sharing: A Colloquium on Corporate Governance and Investments in Human Capital. Brookings. Blasi, Joseph Raphael, and Douglas Lynn Kruse. 1991. The New Owners: The Mass Emergence of Employee Ownership in Public Companies and What it Means to American Business, HarperCollins Publishers. Butler, Henry N. 1989. “The Contractual Theory of the Corporation,” George Mason U. L.Rev.11(Summer): 99. Castanias, Richard P., and Constance E. Helfat. 1992. “Managerial and Windfall Rents in the Market for Corporate Control.” Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization 18 (July): 153184. Coase, R. H. 1937. “The Nature of the Firm.” Republished in Oliver Williamson and Sidney Winter, eds., The Nature of the Firm, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991. Demsetz, Harold. 1991. “The Theory of the Firm Revisited,” in Oliver Williamson and Sidney Winter, eds., The Nature of the Firm, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. 46 Dickens, William T., and Kevin Lang. 1993. “Labor Market Segmentation Theory: Reconsidering the Evidence.” In Labor Economics: Problems in Analyzing Labor Markets, edited by William Darity, Jr., 141-180. Boston: Kluwer Academic Publishers. Doeringer, Peter B., and Michael J. Piore. 1971. Internal Labor Markets and Manpower Analysis. Lexington, Massachusetts: D.C. Heath and Company. Domar, Evsey. 1966. “The Soviet Collective Farm as a Producer Cooperative,” American Economic Review, Vol. 56, pp. 734-57. Dow, Gregory K. 1993. “Why Capital Hires Labor: A Bargaining Perspective.” American Economic Review 83 (March): 118-34. Dow, Gregory K., and Louis Putterman. 1997. “Why Capital (Usually) Hires Labor: An Assessment of Proposed Explanations,” (in this collection). Ellerman, David P. 1986. “Horizon Problems and Property Rights in Labor-Managed Firms,” Journal of Comparative Economics, Vol. 10, pp. 62-78. Epstein, Richard A. 1985. “Agency Costs, Employment Contracts, and Labor Unions.” In Principals and Agents: The Structure of Business, by John W. Pratt and Richard Zeckhauser, 127148. Boston: Harvard Business School Press. Fama, Eugene F., and Michael C. Jensen. 1983. “Separation of Ownership and Control.” Journal of Law and Economics 26 (June): 301-325. Furubotn, Erik G., and Svetozar Pejovich. 1974. “Property Rights and the Behavior of the Firm in a Socialist State: The Example of Yugoslavia.” In The Economics of Property Rights, edited by Furubotn and Pejovich. Cambridge, Mass.: Ballinger Publishing Co. Grossman, Sanford J., and Oliver D. Hart. 1986. “The Costs and Benefits of Ownership: A Theory of Vertical and Lateral Integration.” Journal of Political Economy 94 (August): 691-719. Hansmann, Henry. 1988. “Ownership of the Firm,” Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, Vol. 4, No. 2, Fall, pp. 267-305. Hansmann, Henry. 1996 (forthcoming). The Ownership of Enterprise. Harvard University Press. Hart, Oliver. 1989. “An Economist’s Perspective on the Theory of the Firm.” Columbia Law Review 89: 1757-74. Hart, Oliver, and John Moore. 1990. “Property Rights and the Nature of the Firm,” Journal of Political Economy 98 (6): 1119-58. 47 Hashimoto, Masanori. 1981. “Firm-Specific Human Capital as a Shared Investment.” American Economic Review 71 (June): 475-482 Holmstrom, Bengt. 1982. “Moral Hazard in Teams.” Bell Journal of Economics, Vol. 13, No. 2, Autumn, pp. 324-340. Holmstrom, Bengt, and Paul Milgrom. 1991. “Multi-task Principal-Agent Analyses: Incentive Contracts, Asset Ownership, and Job Design.” Journal of Economics and Organization 7 (Special Issue): 24-52. ________. 1994. “The Firm as an Incentive System.” American Economic Review 84 (September): 972-91. Jacobson, Louis S., Robert J. LaLonde, and Daniel G. Sullivan. 1993. “Earnings Losses of Displaced Workers.” American Economic Review 83 (September): 685709. Jacoby, Sanford M. 1990. “The New Institutionalism: What Can It Learn from the Old?” Industrial Relations 29 (Spring): 316-359. Jensen, Michael C., and William H. Meckling. 1976. “Theory of the Firm: Managerial Behavior, Agency Costs and Ownership Structure.” Journal of Financial Economics 3 (October): 305-60. ________. 1979. “Rights and Production Functions: An Application to LaborManaged Firms and Codetermination.” Journal of Business 52 (October): 469-506. Katz, Lawrence F., and Lawrence H. Summers. 1989. “Industry Rents: Evidence and Implications.” Brookings Papers on Economic Activity: Microeconomics: 209-275. Klein, Benjamin, Robert A. Crawford, and Armen A. Alchian. 1978. “Vertical Integration, Appropriable Rents, and the Competitive Contracting Process.” Journal of Law and Economics 21 (October): 297-326. Koike, Kazuo. 1990. “Intellectual Skill and the Role of Employees as Constituent Members of Large Firms in Contemporary Japan.” in The Firm as a Nexus of Treaties, edited by Masahiko Aoki, Bo Gustafsson, and Oliver E. Williamson, 185-208. Sage Publications. Kreps, David M. 1990. “Corporate Culture and Economic Theory.” In Perspectives on Positive Political Economy, edited by James E. Alt and Kenneth A. Shepsle, 90-143. Cambridge University Press. _____________. 1996. “Markets and Hierarchies and (Mathematical) Economic Theory.” Working Paper. Krueger, Alan B., and Lawrence H. Summers. 1988. “Efficiency Wages and InterIndustry Wages Structure.” Econometrica 56 (March): 259-293. 48 Masten, Scott E., James W. Meehan, and Edward A. Snyder. 1989. “Vertical Integration in the U.S. Auto Industry: A Note on the Influence of Transaction Specific Assets.” Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization 12 (October): 265-273. Matsuyama, Kenji, 1996. “Corporate Governance: A Perspective on the Japanese System,” Japan Research Institute, unpublished paper. October. Meade, J. E. 1972. “The Theory of Labor-Managed Firms and of Profit Sharing.” Economic Journal 82 (March supplement): 402-28. Milgrom, Paul, and John Roberts. 1992. Economics, Organization and Management. New Jersey: Prentice Hall, Inc. Monteverde, Kirk, and David J. Teece. 1982. “Supplier Switching Costs and Vertical Integration in the Automobile Industry.” The Bell Journal of Economics 13 (Spring): 206-213. ________. 1982. “Appropriable Rents and Quasi-Vertical Integration.” The Journal of Law and Economics 25 (October): 321-328. Nelson, Richard R., and Sidney G. Winter. 1982. An Evolutionary Theory of Economic Change. Harvard University Press (Belknap). Pistor, Katherina. 1997. “Co-determination in Germany: A Socio-Political Model with Governance Externalities.” (in this collection). Prendergast, Canice. 1993. “The Role of Promotion in Inducing Specific Human Capital Acquisition.” The Quarterly Journal of Economics 108 No. 2 (May): 523 534. Putterman, Louis. 1984. “On Some Recent Explanations of Why Capital Hires Labor.” Economic Inquiry 22 (April): 171-87. Putterman, Louis, and Randall S. Kroszner. 1996. “The Economic Nature of the Firm: A New Introduction.” In The Economic Nature of the Firm: A Reader (Second Edition) edited by Putterman and Kroszner, 1-31. Cambridge University Press. Rajan, Raghuram G., and Luigi Zingales. 1996. “Power in a Theory of the Firm.” Working Paper. Romano, Roberta. 1996. “Corporate Law and Corporate Governance,” paper prepared for Conference on Firms, Markets and Organizations at University of California at Berkeley, Haas School of Business, and scheduled for publication in a special issue of Industrial and Corporate Change, Vol. 5, No. 3 (1996). Rosen, Sherwin. 1985. “Implicit Contracts: A Survey.” Journal of Economic Literature, Vol. XXIII, September, pp. 1144-1175. 49 Shleifer, Andrei, and Lawrence H. Summers. 1988. “Breach of Trust in Hostile Takeovers.” In Corporate Takeovers: Causes and Consequences, edited by Alan J. Auerbach, 33-56. University of Chicago Press. Topel, Robert C. 1990. “Specific Capital and Unemployment: Measuring the Costs and Consequences of Job Loss.” In Studies in Labor Economics in Honor of Walter Y. Oi, edited by Allan H. Meltzer and Charles I. Ploser, 181-214. Amsterdam: North Holland. ________. 1991. “Specific Capital, Mobility, and Wages: Wages Rise with Job Security.” Journal of Political Economy 99 (February): 145-176. Vanek, Jaroslav. 1970. The General Theory of Labor-managed Market Economies. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press. ------------. 1977. “The Basic Theory of Financing of Participatory Firms.” In The Labor-Managed Economy: Essays by Jaroslav Vanek, edited by Vanek, 186-98. Cornell University Press. Ward, Benjamin. 1958. “The Firm in Illyria: Market Syndicalism,” American Economic Review, Vol. 48, pp. 566-89. Weiss, Andrew. 1990. Efficiency Wages: Models of Unemployment, Layoffs, and Wage Dispersion. Princeton University Press. Wiggins, Steven N. 1991. “The Economics of the Firm and Contracts: A Selective Survey.” Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics 147 (December): 603-61. Williamson, Oliver E. 1975. Markets and Hierarchies: Analysis and Antitrust Implications. Free Press. ________. 1985. The Economic Institutions of Capitalism: Firms, Markets, Relational Contracting. New York: The Free Press. Willia