Bernard McKenna & David Rooney University of Queensland Business School, Australia Critical Ontological Acuity as the Foundation of Wise Leadership 6th Annual International Studying Leadership Conference Warwick Business School: Purposes, Politics and Praxis 13th and 14th December 2007 Theme 3: The development of a critical leadership praxis. Contact Dr Bernard McKenna University of Queensland Business School University of Queensland-Ipswich Campus 11 Salisbury Road Ipswich Q 4305 AUSTRALIA Email b.mckenna@uq.edu.au i ABSTRACT Leadership theory has fragmented with various types of leadership (charismatic, transformational, authentic and spiritual etc.) being advocated. Yet, vital issues of global warming, the Iraq imbroglio, and tectonic geopolitical shifts (Islam-West divide; China’s spectacular growth), which impact on our economic and social life are not going to be effectively dealt with using an “empowering” leadership discourse (itself an appropriation from anticolonialist struggle). Furthermore, events like Enron and the SubPrime Mortgage Collapse show that greedy, unethical and stupid behaviours are reflections of the ontologies underlying many normative discourses of business practice. This paper argues that effective leadership theorising needs to be informed by wisdom theory if it is to provide our most powerful leaders with a frame of reference to guide their deliberations and actions (cf. McKenna, Rooney, & Boal, in-press). Our paper presents a case for wise leadership rooted in the neo-Aristotelian principle of eudaimonia, which Nussbaum (1994: 15) understands as "human flourishing". We argue that human flourishing occurs in conditions of life-affirming principles that favour democracy, equality, and equity/fairness, and that these should be markers of business ethics. While wisdom must be founded on firm axiological principles it must equally understand how to manage knowledge and its underlying ontologies in a complex environment (Hunt, Osborn, & Boal, 2007). Using Foucault’s (1972: 191) notion of episteme as “the total set of relations that unite, at a given period, the discursive practices that give rise to epistemological figures, sciences, and possibly formalized systems,” we claim that organisational ii discourse legitimates, valorises and reproduces (usually tacit) ontologies. Heracleous and Barrett (2001: 19) call these discursive deep structures that “are relatively stable, mostly implicit, and continually recurring processes and patterns that underlay and guide surface, observable events and actions”. Furthermore, we argue these organisational discourses are themselves the manifestation of larger isomorphic forces (McKenna, Rooney, & Liesch, 2006; Mizruchi & Fein, 1999). Thus, we argue that wise leaders must be able to understand epistemic structures and their inherent ontologies, a capacity we call ontological acuity. Such a capacity implies that wise leaders are, in a sense, critical discourse analysts who can recognise the potential isomorphism of “common sense” and evaluate normative practice, as needed, by understanding inherent ontologies. In this way they can provide alternative ways of knowing, deciding, and acting. Our interdisciplinary approach incorporates a blend of Aristotelian wisdom theory (McKenna et al., 2006) psychological theories of wisdom (Staudinger & Pasupathi, 2003; Sternberg, 1998); complexity theory (Gardner, Avolio, Luthans, May, & Walumbwa, 2005; Wang & Chan, 1995); structuration theory (Giddens, 1979); and critical discourse theory (McKenna, 2004). Although organisational knowledge comprises multiple, often contradictory assumptions, beliefs, intuitions, memories, cognitions, etc. (Rooney & Schneider, 2005), its discursive stability can be understood by seeing organisations as autonomous self-organising systems that emerge within a bounded context (Chia, 1998; Spender, 1996; Stacey, 2001; Tsoukas, 1996). This implies that wise leaders must understand organisational knowledge not iii as facticity, but as plastic (re-formulating flows and relations within a discursive formation). By understanding wise leadership largely as a capacity for ontological acuity and life affirming ethics, we argue that organisations are more likely to avoid the coercive, mimetic, and normative forces that produce unethical and stupid outcomes. iv CURRENT STATE OF LEADERSHIP THEORY Current leadership theories have drawn on a variety of factors, including ethics, cognitive complexity, connectedness, and reflexivity. All of these area certainly necessary. However, we argue that the essential elements of wise leadership are encapsulated in virtue-based wisdom of a leader who also displays ontologcial acuity. It is this capacity for ontological acuity that this paper focuses on. Leadership theory has fragmented, with various types of leadership (charismatic, transformational, authentic and spiritual etc.) being advocated to enhance managerial and organisational practice. In the past decade, charismatic, transformational, authentic, and spiritual leadership scholars have dealt with issues about ethics, trustworthiness, and the capacity to contribute to the common good (Bass, 1990; Howell & Avolio, 1992; Avolio & Bass, 1995; Bass, 1997; Gardner & Avolio, 1998; Luthans & Avolio, 2003; Avolio & Gardner, 2005; Gardner, Avolio, Luthans, May, & Walumbwa, 2005; Kriger & Seng, 2005). Charismatic theories (e.g., Hinds, 2005; Driscoll & McKee, 2007; Markow & Klenke, 2005) are individualistic, operating on such factors as affect, loyalty, identity, commitment, motivation and performance of the organisational member who are expected to identify with the leader (Boal, 2004). Generally, charismatic leaders emerge because their particular vision is enthusiastically adopted or in times of crisis. Essentially, the success of this leadership depends on the extent to which individuals’ perceived needs and values are articulated through the interpretative framework established by 1 the leader. Transformational leadership (Avolio & Bass, 1988; Avolio & Bass, 1995; Gardner & Avolio, 1998; Avolio, Bass, & Dong, 1999; Harvey, Martinko, & Gardner, 2006), acknowledging that leaders significantly impact on organisational values (Gottlieb & Sanzgiri, 1996; Grojean, Resick, Dickson, & Smith, 2004), is particularly concerned with the ethical dimension of leadership (Bass & Steidlmeier, 1999: 182) and so is different from transactional leadership, which uses contingent reinforcement to direct organisational behaviour. Authentic transformational leadership (Bass & Steidlmeier, 1999; Gardner, Avolio, Luthans, May, & Walumbwa, 2005; Harvey, Martinko, & Gardner, 2006) elaborates transformational leadership theory, but identifies values as a central concern. These values are “connected to friends, family, and community whose welfare may be more important to oneself than one’s own” (Grojean, Resick, Dickson, & Smith, 2004: 186). Not only do authentic leaders “possess self-awareness of, and act in accordance with, their values, thoughts, emotions, and beliefs” (Harvey, Martinko, & Gardner, 2006: 1), they are future-oriented (Luthans & Avolio, 2003). Empathy and emotional sensitivity are important characteristics of authentic leaders (Michie & Gooty, 2005; Kellett, Humphrey, & Sleeth, 2006). Clearly, spiritual leadership is values-based, and considers such matters as transcendence, spiritual practices that develop higher ethical sensibilities, contemplative wisdom, humility (Reave, 2005; Collins, 2001), and timeless qualities (Whittington, Pitts, Kageler, & Goodwin, 2005). It emphasises possibly more than other leadership theories, the significance of balance, harmony, and unity (Kriger & Seng, 2005). 2 Although promoting admirable traits, transformational, charismatic, spiritual and authentic leadership literatures do not effectively show how wise leaders deal with the complexity of contemporary organisations. Boal & Hooijberg’s (2000) Integrative Model of Strategic Leadership combines the key elements of interest in organisational complexity as well as social, behavioural and ethical considerations. However, applying wisdom theory, McKenna, Rooney, & Boal’s (in-press) critique and reconceptualisation of this paper took up the concern of how effective leaders deal with complexity ethically. In this paper, it is assumed that effective leadership incorporates ethical values, selflessness, vision, and transcendent capacities, as well as considerable cognitive capacity. The particular cognitive capacity we identify in this paper is ontological acuity. WISDOM-IN-LEADERSHIP THEORY This paper argues that wisdom needs to be a characteristic of effective leadership theory. Our starting point is to locate ethical considerations as the primary concern. We adopt Aristotle’s virtue ethics and wisdom theory as appropriate guidelines for successful and ethical business in contemporary times. Underlying Aristotle’s virtue ethics is the principle of eudaimonia, which Nussbaum (1994: 15) understands as "human flourishing". Essentially, Aristotle argues that in seeking eudaimonia, or the good life, we will act virtuously because this brings about a fulfilling and happy life - it is rational. Furthermore, virtue is preferred because one should do “what one does just because one sees those actions as noble and worthwhile” (Hughes 2001, p. 89). Thus, we argue that human flourishing occurs in conditions of life- 3 affirming principles that favour democracy, equality, and equity/fairness, and that these should be the affirmed teleological markers of business ethics. Although strongly rooted in Aristotelian theory, our theory of wisdom in leadership is strongly interdisciplinary as it also draws on knowledge theory, psychological theories of wisdom, complexity theory, structuration theory, and critical discourse theory. Aristotelian Wisdom Theory The components of Aristotelian wisdom of most relevance to leadership theory are phronesis (prudence), aesthetics, techné, balance, and virtue. Aristotle proposed phronesis as the form of practical wisdom, and sophia as the form of philosophical wisdom, both of which need to inform wise action (Kekes 1995: 16). By phronesis Aristotle means “intuition and scientific knowledge” [NE, 1141a19], where intuition is more than “gut feeling”. Intuition requires discernment (Schuman, 1980, in Noel, 1999: 279-280) and insight (Dunne, 1997) which are crucial in balanced practical deliberation: phronesis is the means “by which instrumental rationality is balanced by value rationality” (Flyvbjerg, 2004: 285). The dynamic balance that Aristotle espoused is also central to Sternberg’s (1998) psychology-based views of wisdom (see also Labouvie-Vief, 1990). This requires experiential richness, a creative and imaginative capacity, and logical coherence. Apparently contradictorily, balance also requires acknowledgement, not suppression of emotions. Aristotle’s wisdom concepts were entirely in the Hellenistic tradition (apart from the Stoics) in acknowledging the validity of emotions in our judgment and virtuous action: “virtue is expressed not merely in fine action but 4 in fine emotions as well” (Sherman, 1997: 24). Hellenists understood the social construction of emotion, and that there was an underlying psychology of emotion. However, these emotions must be open to scrutiny (Kekes 1995: 10). Anger, for example, may be justified when an injustice occurs, but achieving what is right must be balanced by good judgment (Eflin 2003; see also Sherman, 1997, ch. 2). Because Aristotelian wisdom must be practical, Aristotle identified constructive work (poiesis) as an essential element of our humanity. Techné is the practical knowledge of expert makers who can rationally explain their activity: a person displaying techné “understands the principles … underlying the production of an object or state of affairs” (Dunne, 1997: 244). Hence, techné requires instrumental rationality (Flyvbjerg, 2004: 287). While essential for an organisation to operate, techné alone is inadequate as it must be balanced by phronesis, virtue, and aesthetics. Aristotle understood aesthetics as the psychological and social processes that activate sensoryemotional dynamics that can enhance transcendent knowledge. Thus aesthetics in an organisational sense could be seen as an “aesthetic a priori synthesis of feeling and image within intuition” (Croce, 1995: 31), and as something that is “distinguished … from practical, moral, and conceptual activity as intuition” (p. 49; italics in original). Strati (2000) understands organisational aesthetics similarly, such that rational and intuitive/aesthetic knowledge are not symbiotic, for the “aesthetic approach emphasises that rational analysis neglects extremely important aspects of quotidian organizational practices” (Strati, 2000: 16). To sum up, then, techné needs to 5 be balanced by transcendence, the capacity to go beyond the explicit and the literal, and the norm: “One can go beyond both common sense and present science, to grasp the dynamic structure of our rational knowing and doing, and then formulate a metaphysics and an ethics” (Lonergan 1957: 635). The final component of Aristotelian wisdom is virtue (Aristotle, 1984). This need for virtue, which emerges from an ancient commitment to values and ethics, is consistent with recent psychological theory about wisdom (Sternberg & BenZeev, 2001). For example, integral to Sternberg’s three-part Balance Theory of Wisdom is virtue, or socially valued behaviour: the “balance” that he speaks of “all hinges on values. Values therefore are an integral part of wise thinking” (Sternberg, 2001:231). It manifests as concern for others, being thoughtful and fair, admitting mistakes, and also learning from them (Baltes, Staudinger, Maercker, & Smith, 1995; Sternberg, 1990). Psychological Theories of Wisdom The most important contributions from psychological theory to a theory of wisdom come from Robert J. Sternberg and the Berlin School (the late Paul Baltes and the Max Planck Institute in Berlin). Contemporary psychological theory strongly reinforces the Aristotle’s characterisation of wisdom, the five characteristics of which are outlined in Rooney & McKenna (in press). Three of these shared wisdom characteristics are particularly relevant. Firstly, both Aristotle and wisdom psychology assert that complementing reason there must be a metaphysical quality that does not bind it only to the rules of reason. Psychologists, Baltes and Staudinger (2000), use the concept of a “metaheuristic”, not metaphysics, to describe this feature, which actually 6 combines two heuristics: one that “organizes, at a high level of aggregation, the pool (ensemble) of bodies of knowledge”; and another at a more explicit or detailed level used by “individuals in planning, managing and evaluating issues surrounding the fundamental pragmatics of life” (Baltes & Staudinger, 2000: 132). This implies that wisdom must be practical. A wise person can draw on rich factual, or declarative, knowledge about “the fundamental pragmatics of life” (Baltes & Staudinger, 2000). This declarative knowledge provides the basis of prudence. For Aristotle, a prudent person is “one who is able to deliberate well concerning what is good and expedient for himself [sic] … which are good and expedient for living well [in general]” (Aristotle, 1984: Bk 6, 5: 1140b, 105). These pragmatics include “insight into the social nature and incompleteness of human existence, the variability of life goals, knowledge about oneself and the limits of one’s knowledge, and insight into how knowledge is translated into behaviour” (Staudinger & Pasupathi, 2003: 240). The capacity for “being tolerant of ambiguous situations”—what Sternberg (1996) calls a “progressive style”—is one of the most salient predictors of wisdom according to Baltes & Staudinger (2000: 129). This metaheuristic capacity is also associated with imagination and creativity, enabling those who have this capability to “see” beyond normally held assumptions about reality. This capacity to manage uncertainty arises from a wise person’s understanding that life is contingent, constructed from various perspectives, is ontogenetic, and historically situated (Baltes & Staudinger, 2000). Both Baltes and Staudinger (2000) and Sternberg (1990) assert that wise people realize the limits of human information processing and that the future cannot be predicted through technical applications (Baltes & 7 Staudinger, 2000: 126; Sternberg, 1990: 157). Secondly, wise people, Aristotle claims, while respecting experience and tradition, are epistemologically sceptical (NE: Bk 6, 1142b: 9, 25-28), or at least curious. Sternberg (1990: 157) asserts that wisdom is “more than just cognitive skills” because it requires “an attitude toward knowledge as [much as] knowledge itself”, a form of fluid intelligence (Sternberg, 1990: 323). Thus, a wise person needs, from time to time, to be sceptical of the given “facts”, and of orthodoxy, tradition, majority view, or “common sense”. Furthermore, the wise person may need to evaluate the salience (i.e., relevance and strength) of facts in a given situation. Accepting the validity of a reflexive “gut instinct” is the third feature of wisdom shared by Aristotle and contemporary psychology. This means that sensory and visceral responses can be important and valid components of decisionmaking. Empirical evidence in brain science, consciousness studies, and emotional intelligence (Wade, 1996; Ashkanasy, 2003) supports the proposition that “gut” level intuition can be valuable in making judgments. Baltes and Staudinger’s (2000: 123) research into folk-psychological approaches to wisdom reveals a “coordinated and balanced interplay of intellectual, affective, and motivational aspects of human functioning”. The strong congruence between Aristotle’s theories and modern psychological theories and empirical evidence relating to wisdom provide a strong degree of validity about our model of wisdom. Clearly, it goes far 8 beyond mere knowledge, although knowledge is extremely important. Organisational Knowledge To be a leader, then, requires at least techné (practical knowledge) and phronesis (practical knowledge balanced by non-rational forms of knowing). As the context of this knowing is within organisations, it is important that this context is well understood. Although organisational knowledge comprises multiple, often contradictory assumptions, beliefs, intuitions, memories, cognitions, etc. (Rooney & Schneider, 2005), its discursive stability can be understood by seeing organisations as autonomous self-organizing systems that emerge within a bounded context (Chia, 1998; Spender, 1996; Stacey, 2001; Tsoukas, 1996). This implies that wise leaders must understand organisational knowledge not as facticity, but as plastic (re-formulating flows and relations within a discursive formation). Yet organisations are quite stable, and discourses are relatively consistent because an organisation can be envisaged as “an autonomous self-organizing system that emerges as the outcome of the interaction of different types of knowing within a bound and deliberately created context” (Spender, 1998: 246; Stacey, 2001). Understanding organisational knowledge not as facticity, but as flows, relations, and patterns that are contextualized in particular complex systems has important implications for leaders’ decision making. These flows and relations are articulated through discourse, and as discourse is used at the organizational level (i.e., the texts of conversation, documents, email, websites, etc), we can understand it as situated action (Marshak & Heracleous, 2005). Recent ethnographic research into the finance industry 9 shows how this constructedness of discourse can be seen even in an industry where huge amounts of “objective” data and a strong ethic of individualistic decision-making is assumed to be the norm (Pryke & Du Gay, 2007; see also MacKenzie, 2001; Knorr-Cetina, 2006). According to Fairhurst (2007), successful leaders reflexively “monitor the ongoing character of social life … vis-à-vis specific norms, rules, procedures, and values in interaction with others” (p. 14). In other words, leaders not only have elevated levels of formal knowledge (e.g. a senior engineer in an engineering firm or a senior public servant’s knowledge of policy and regulations), but also have processual knowledge (“know-how” that is situated or context dependent (Gourlay, 2006: 1426) and which incorporates norms, procedures and social patterns), and intuitive knowledge (ability to understand tacit matters, “gut” feelings)1. Organisational Complexity & Epistemic Structures Leaders constantly have to deal with the complexity of organisational knowledge, which is inscribed in organisational discourse. Underlying this discourse is an episteme that comprises an overarching set of historically situated relations that unite the discursive practices that shape fundamental assumptions about reality and what is accepted as reliable knowledge of that It is important to note that intuition is now increasingly recognised as an important leadership requirement for “in extremis” leaders (i.e., people whose jobs involve a heightened possibility of death for them or their followers). Such institutions as the fire brigade and U.S. marine corps and Westpoint Military Academy are incorporating this in their training. There is some debate, however, as to whether the phenomenon is intuition or “recognitional decision making”, based on previously learned (conscious or subconscious) cues. 1 10 reality (Foucault, 1972:191). Because this episteme is an “a priori organising principle” (Bannet, 1989: 164) regulating the boundaries of what is discursively possible in organisational sites, leaders need to be able to reflexively understand and critique the inherent ontologies that inhere in these epistemes. We call this capacity ontological acuity. Possessing this capacity, wise leaders become, even if unwittingly, critical discourse analysts. This acuity provides wise leaders with new insights beyond the isomorphic tendencies of organisational discourse when this is needed. Thus, they can evaluate normative practice and its underlying episteme to provide alternative ways of knowing, deciding, and acting. The inherent complexity of leadership is exacerbated by contemporary extraorganisational conditions such as globalization, geo-political realignments, changing technologies, and the like. As well, organisational leaders increasingly need to respond to public demands for greater ethical and environmental accountability (Doh & Guay, 2004). Within organisations, there is increasing pressure on managers to “leverage intellectual capital into the business equation” (Kridan & Goulding 2006: 213). This “intellectual capital”, or more broadly organisational knowledge, is regarded as a primary resource for decision making (Montibeller, Shaw & Westcombe 2006) because it is the means by which organisations can understand, contemplate, articulate, and manage problems and challenges. However, Rooney and Schneider (2007: 19) make the point that ICT-focused approaches (cf. Alavi and Leidner (2001: 114) to knowledge management are inadequate. They argue that knowledge managers must take advantage of the dynamics at work in knowledge 11 systems, many of which have nothing to do with ICT. Yet managerial discourse about knowledge management is dominated by technological and mechanistic metaphors such as “knowledge repositories” and “knowledge transfer”. This managerial discourse is predicated on a limiting and safe or comfortable ontology of knowledge, but one that fails to acknowledge that sense-making and facilitating knowledgeable actions are more likely to enhance learning, transfer, sharing, and innovation. Approaches to knowledge management that understand ICTs as a significant technology and medium, but which must be understood within a much more broadlyconceived understanding of a knowledge organisation (Brown, Massey & Boling 2005; Edvinsson 1997) are more likely to be effective. Using this orientation to knowledge management requires considerable capability to deal with complexity. Considered from a psychological perspective, leaders need behavioural and cognitive complexity to be able to respond effectively to organisational needs. Behavioural complexity identifies a person’s capacity to cope with “the interplay of a volatile, complex, and potentially ambiguous environment” (Satish, 1997: 2048). Cognitive complexity is founded on differentiation, or the “number of dimensions used by individuals to perceive environmental stimuli”, and integration, “the complexity of rules used by individuals in organising the differentiated dimensions” (Wang & Chan, 1995: 35). However, ontological acuity is not just a cognitive and behavioural phenomenon, although these are necessary components of wisdom. Ontological acuity is a capacity to understand the categorical and epistemic foundations of knowledge systems and the context 12 in which this foundation derives its meaning, or “common sense”. To practice this acuity, a leader needs reflexivity and agency. Reflexivity, in a sense, is a capacity to transcend the here and now. Such an approach implies the important sociological concepts of structure and agency that are better treated in sociological terms than psychological ones. Structuration Theory and Agency Structuration theory is especially appropriate in explaining complex material and discursive organisational interactions that acknowledge relationships of power. According to Giddens’s (1984) theory of human agency, social systems become institutional to the extent that people reproduce practices, which are based on “sets of rules and resources that individual actors draw upon in the practices that reproduce social systems” (Giddens, 1971: 172). These provide structures that both enable and constrain action. In other words, unlike Althusser’s reductive and deterministic concept of the ideological state apparatus (Althusser, 1971: 169), Giddens’s (1984) theory postulates a “duality of structure”, in which structure and agency are intricately related in a “recursive way” (pp. 25ff.). Although agents may decide things intentionally, the social fabric in which they exist is reproduced unintentionally. Thus, despite the claims of some that Gidden’s structuration theory and other “constructionist” theories of organising cannot accommodate the individuality of agents’ intention, knowledge, and rational action (Caldwell, 2005: 110), this is clearly not the case. There are two implications of this for a theory of wisdom. Firstly, structuration theory applied to organisations acknowledges relationships of power in a way that much leadership and wisdom theory has 13 failed to do so far. Secondly, structuration theory lends itself to (critical) discourse theory because the recursivity between organisation and agent primarily manifests in discourse (as well as in material ways). Critical Discourse Theory So far, we have theorised organisational knowledge as flows, relations, and patterns contextualized in particular complex systems that are articulated through discourse (Marshak & Heracleous, 2005). Dominant discourses in an organisation are founded upon an episteme. In short, organisational discourse legitimates, valorises and reproduces (usually tacit) ontologies that inhere within the episteme. Heracleous and Barrett (2001: 19) call these discursive deep structures that “are relatively stable mostly implicit, and continually recurring processes and patterns that underlay and guide surface, observable events and actions”. However, these discourses themselves operate within a wider context of macro-discourses. They are often ideologically based, as McKenna and Graham (2000) show. As well, these organisational discourses often form part of a larger set of discourses that produce isomorphic effects (McKenna, Rooney, & Liesch, 2006; Mizruchi & Fein, 1999). To be able to step outside these ideological and isomorphic strictures requires considerable ability, an ability that we claim strongly characterises wise leadership. Malan and Kriger (1998: 246) acknowledge such a characteristic when they say that a major executive challenge is “to filter and interpret the noise from within their own organizations and determine the salient points on which to act”. Ontological acuity certainly requires that leaders filter the 14 enormous amount of knowledge present in organisational discourse. Such knowledge may often be simply data and information (cf. Cecez-Kecmanovic, 2004), and all knowledge is ideologically invested in some way. Those uncomfortable with the notion of ideology would, nonetheless, accept the proposition that all knowledge makes sense only within an assumed episteme and the appropriate ontological structures that accompany it. For example, the presence of the words quark and gluon would occur in a discourse about subatomic matter within the epistemic framework of quantum field theory, more specifically quantum chromodynamics to explain the interactions between quarks and gluons. Furthermore, the diachronic nature of discourse is evident in the fact that “subatomic” as a concept was not even possible until modern atomic theory was first established by John Dalton in the early nineteenth century, replacing the ancient work of Democritus and the later alchemists, and then elaborated in the twentieth century by Heisenberg. Importantly, quantum scientists readily understand and accept the changing epistemic structure of quantum science even as they work within it. So it seems relatively uncontroversial to argue that wise organisational leaders would also be expected to understand the diachronicity of discourse and the current epistemological assumptions. Rabinow explained discursive diachronicity in this way: from time to time, and always in time, new forms emerge that catalyze previously existing actors, things, temporalities, or spatialities into a new mode of existence, a new assemblage, one that makes things work in a different manner and produces and instantiates new capacities. A form/event makes many other things more or less suddenly conceivable (quoted in McKenzie, 2005: 388). 15 It is important that our notion of ontology is Heideggerian (and Platonic) in the sense that transcendence is acknowledged as “the gateway to ontology” (Pietersma, 2006: 565) and that the claims to knowledge inherent in those ontologies rest on assumptions (Pietersma, 2006: 563). In other words, people who possess ontological acuity have a capacity to transcend the hereand-now to be able to see the logic of categorisation (often tacitly understood) of the material world and their relationships to one another. At a deeper level, one might then pursue the epistemological foundations of such a logic. ONTOLOGICAL ACUITY IN PUBLIC POLICY & PRACTICE Public policy and practice is a site that demands ontological acuity among its leaders. Not only do public administrators have to deal with complex issues on a day-to-day basis, but they also are publicly accountable, and have to negotiate the nuances of their political masters who themselves seek public endorsement through re-election to government. In October 2007, a major news item shocked Australia. A two-year old boy had been found murdered and placed inside a suitcase that was dumped in a public place. The mother was charged with the murder. Ensuing news items claimed the paternal grandmother had sought help from the New South Wales (state) Department of Community Services [DOCS]. The father, an indigenous man, who was separated from the mother, had only recently been released from jail on parole. The child lived with the paternal grandmother, and had been murdered by the mother during an access visit (Baker, 2007). DOCS then became the focus of a media campaign, some of it critical arguing that the lack of care and capability provided by the department’s officers had contributed to the child’s death. 16 Clearly, a range of people from the case officer up the chain of administrative command to the senior public servant and the minister responsible for the department some role to play in answering questions about the case. A respected radio current affairs station ran a story (Kerin, 2007), the contents of which should have indicated that, regardless of the case officer’s culpability or otherwise, the context in which such a horrible event could occur needs to be seriously considered. The Minister admitted that his department had received a number of calls about the boy and stated that he would have an internal investigation. It was also revealed that the department’s helpline receives 240,000 calls each year, or 657 a day, and that the caseworkers are “at the front line … dealing with children [within] dysfunctional families”. This figure represents one in 15 children in New South Wales reported to DOCS every year. How would a leader show ontological acuity in this sort of case? Without knowing more of the specifics, it is hard to be explicit. However, from the outside, the major concerns would be to look at the way in which organisational discourse and practice operated in these circumstances. A departmental inquiry would be held as well as a coronial inquiry, as is appropriate. But what would we learn from such inquiries if the case worker had in fact performed her duties in the manner specified by the department? How would New South Wales society be any better off for such inquiries being held? These are the more complex issues that an ethical public administrator with ontological acuity would need to ask. From a discourse perspective, one 17 would ask what episteme underlies the formalised systems that guide DOCS caseworkers in the field. What assumptions underlie DOCS guidelines to caseworkers for making decisions2. For example, in the realm of rights and responsibilities, is there an assumed right of a mother to have access to her child even when the mother is seriously drug-dependent or psychologically troubled? If so, why? From what assumptions and values does this assumed right derive? Given the father’s indigineity, what cultural issues of family roles (e.g., the paternal grandmother took responsibility for the child, but lived in a country town) should be considered? To what extent does a caseworker have to balance compassion, the rights of the child and parent, responsibility to society, legal sanction, judgments about good intentions and the like in every case they attend. Given the 657 new helpline calls a day, how much time does a caseworker have to make these judgments? Do they become burntout and tired so that their judgment is impaired? Should they be debriefed? These are the more immediate issues that a humane and competent senior public servant or government minister would address. But they would not be sufficient to indicate wise judgment. There are wider issues of political and social context that are beyond the agentic control of the case worker, and must be considered by those in authority. For example, if it is true that DOCS is understaffed, is this because of a government commitment to “small government” that is inherent in the New Public Management (NPM) that became the orthodoxy for most Western governments from the 1980s (Lane, Please note that I am making absolutely no assumptions or judgments about this particular case or the people involved as I have no knowledge other than that obtained from the media. These are questions that I believe should arise when such a terrible event occurs. 2 18 2000; See also Peters, 1991; Christolph, 1992; Minogue, 2000)? If so, do those responsible for adhering to the epistemic propositions of NPM acknowledge the fundamental shifts away the prior form of governance that produced: socioeconomic progress, law and order, poverty alleviation, employment generation, and public well-being; and the maintenance of values such as impartiality, equality, representation, integrity, fairness, welfare, citizenship, and justice (Haque, 2000: 600). One might also ask whether the justification for such changes to NPM are even appropriate for representative government. Indeed, there is a growing critique questioning whether applying business principles and practices to the public sector is appropriate (Haque, 2000: 600; see also Richards, 1996), and considerable evidence to show that many neo-liberal ideals tend to conflict with the values and beliefs of a society committed to providing a reasonable standard of living including good health care and other services for all regardless of means. In particular, neo-liberalism assumes that individuals are seen as “economically motivated, autonomous, and equally equipped to compete for resources with little responsibility for the well-being of others” (Petera et al., 2007; see also Coburn, 2000). From this individualist perspective, it also assumes that the free-market forces and private motive are more appropriate than the collective public good. Given that there is increased inequality in an economy that is strongly market-based and opposed to welfare and public expenditure and that inequality reduces social cohesion and reduced quality (even length) of life (Davey-Smith, 1996; Kaplan et al, 1996), there are clearly grounds to challenge the ontological assumptions that inhere in the orthodox discourse of contemporary public 19 administration. Having considered the wider social and political context within which a departmental officer such as a DOCS caseworker has to operate, it is now important to consider another two elements of wisdom that must accompany ontological acuity, judgment and balance. Even relatively traditional accounts of public administration identify judgment and balance as vital to the role of public servants especially at senior ranks. Bertelli and Lynn (2006: 44), for example, claim that these characteristics are needed because “No combination of structures and processes for enforcing administrative responsibility can extinguish the element of judgment from public management”. Harold Laski (1923) also spoke of a necessary “administrative discretion” as “the essence of the modern State" (quoted in Bertelli and Lynn, 2006: 32). Balance, too, is a necessary requirement because a senior public servant does not and should not make judgments on limited criteria such as profit motive. In a “pragmatic democracy”, as Arthur Macmahon called it, there are various factors to consider including the publicly expressed will of the people represented by the type of government elected, contesting laws, the ongoing role of the organisation (to surveil, provide, administer, police, etc.) vested interests, and competing groups. Responsible and balanced judgement, Bertelli and Lynn (2006: 44) claim, is often best exercised “in the absence of definitive rules [which] is not a sign of regime failure … rather, that public managers recognize and accept their responsibilities, allowing them to credibly commit to responsible judgment.” Such capacities reinforce DuGay’s argument that much of the NPM discourse is simply 20 incommensurate with the discourse of good administrative governance, and in many instances should be rejected. The accountability to which public administration is subjected is both a necessary requirement in a democracy, but when pushed to an extreme where regulations and procedures and the threat of (quasi-)judicial action govern every aspect of decision-making, accountability becomes disabling for those wishing to exercise good judgment and balance. As Bertelli and Lynn (2006: 43) argue, the “density of such controls and interests is erroneously thought to ensure democratic control of administration”. This is because wise judgment based to some extent on intuition and ethical outcomes would often not be legally defensible. CONCLUSION We have proposed that wise leadership requires, among other things, a commitment to virtuous action, cognitive complexity, and the capacity for ontological acuity. This acuity is evident in a leader’s capacity, at appropriate times, to understand the episteme that is inscribed in organisational discourse and practised in the enactment of formalised systems. It is this discourse and daily enactments that describe the boundaries of orthodox practice. To critically evaluate the discourse and the articulated justification of practice means that the wise leader must ask: what do I need to believe, explicitly or implicitly, to allow this statement to be true? Similarly, one would need to ask what values need to be embraced to desire a particular outcome. Are these reasonable beliefs and values? To be able to ask such questions requires a 21 transcendent capacity, the ability to step outside the boundaries of one’s usual discourse and to understand it from a naïve perspective. We have considered this in the case of public administration and a particular case where a child under administrative surveillance was, nonetheless, murdered. The administrative and political responses were predictable, although necessary. The case would be investigated both internally and independently by a coroner. Perhaps blame will be laid with the caseworker or a superior or with administrative processes, and public declarations will be made about learning from this tragedy. Things will take their course. But it is unlikely that senior administrators will be encouraged to be reflexive, to question the whole edifice on which a set of procedures was built. To challenge the political assumptions might be regarded as treacherous, or, at the very least, politically naïve. Clearly, such deep reflexivity must be balanced by the need for administrative processes to remain operative, resting on a given deep epistemic structure, and so there must be discretion in the use of reflexive practice. Nonetheless, it is crucial for wise practice to occur that those in leadership positions be allowed to develop such reflexive capability. This implies sufficient agency within a supportive environment. Whether there are governments brave enough to allow this to occur is a matter of conjecture. 22 REFERENCES Alavi, M & Leidner D.E. (2001) Review: Knowledge management and knowledge management systems: Conceptual Foundations and Research Issues, MIS Quarterly, vol. 25, no. 1, 107-136. Althusser, L. (1971) Ideology and Ideological State Apparatuses (Notes towards an investigation) (B. Brewster, Trans.). In Lenin and Philosophy and Other Essays (pp. 127-186). New York and London: Monthly Review Press. Aristotle. (1984) Nicomachean Ethics (H. G. Apostle, Trans.). Grinnell, IO: The Peripatetic Press. Ashkanasy, N. M. (2003) Emotions in Organizations: A Multilevel Perspective. In F. Dansereau & F. J. Yammarino (Eds), Research in Multi-Level Issues, vol. 2, Multi-Level Issues in Organizational Behavior and Strategy (Vol. 2, pp. 9-54). Oxford, UK: Elsevier Science. Avolio, B. J., & Bass, B. M. (1995) Individual consideration viewed at multiple levels of analysis: a multi-level framework for examining the diffusion of transformational leadership. Leadership Quarterly, 6, 199-218. Avolio, B. J., Bass, B. M., & Dong, I. J. (1999) Re-examining the components of transformational and transactional leadership using the multifactor leadership questionnaire. Journal of Occupational and Organizational Psychology, 72(4), 441-462. Avolio, B. J., & Gardner, W. L. (2005) Authentic leadership development: Getting to the root of positive forms of leadership. Leadership Quarterly, 16(3), 315-338. Baker. J. (October 23, 2007) Daughter pleaded for help, says grandma. Sydney Morning Herald. URL: http://www.smh.com.au/news/national/daughter-pleaded-for-help-saysgrandma/2007/10/22/1192940986343.html Baltes, P. B., & Staudinger, U. M. (2000) A metaheuristic (pragmatic) to orchestrate mind and virtue toward excellence. American Psychologist, 55(1), 122-136. Baltes, P. B., Staudinger, U. M., Maercker, A., & Smith, J. (1995) People nominated as wise: A comparative study of wisdom-related knowledge. Psychology and Aging, 10(2), 155-166. Bannet, E. T. (1989) Structuralism and the logic of dissent: Barthes, Derrida, Foucault, Lacan. Urbana & Chicago: University of Illinois Press. Bass, B. M. (1990) From Transactional to transformational Leadership: Learning to Share the Vision. Organizational Dynamics, Winter, 99119. Bass, B. M. (1997) Does Transactional/Transformational Leadership Transcend Organizational and National Boundaries? American Psychologist, 52, 130-139. Bass, B. M., & Steidlmeier, P. (1999) Ethics, character, and authentic transformational leadership. Leadership Quarterly, 10(2), 181-217. Bertelli, A.M. & Lynn, L.E. Jr (2006) Public Management In The Shadow Of The Constitution. Administration & Society,(38), 1, 31-57 Boal, K. B. (2004) Learning, Leadership, and Ties. Paper presented at the IMD Conference on Strategic Leadership 23 Boal, K. B., & Hooijberg, R. (2000) Strategic leadership research: Moving on. Leadership Quarterly, 11(4), 515-549. Brown, J.P., Massey, A.P., & Boling, E. (2005) Evaluation of knowledge management systems: Insights from the study of a technical support knowledge base, Knowledge Management Research & Practice, vol. 3, no. 2, pp. 49–59. Caldwell, R. (2005) Things fall apart? Discourses on agency and change in organizations. Human Relations, 58(1), 83–114. Cecez-Kecmanovic, D. (2004) A sensemaking model of knowledge in organisations: a way of understanding knowledge management and the role of information technologies, Knowledge Management Research & Practice, vol. 2, no. 3, pp. 155–168. Chia, R. (1998) From Complexity Science to Complex Thinking: Organization as Simple Location. Organization, 5(3), 341-369. Christoph, J.B. (1992). The Remaking of British Administrative Culture, Administration and Society, 21 (2), 163–181. Coburn, D. (2000) Income inequality, social cohesion and the health status of populations: The role of neo-liberalism. Social Science & Medicine, 51,1 135–146. Collins, J. C. (2001) Good to Great: Why some companies make the leap ... and others don't. New York: Harper Collins. Croce, B. (1995). Guide to Aesthetics (P. Romanell, Trans.). Indianapolis: Hackett. Davey Smith, G., 1996 Income inequality and mortality Ð why are they related Ð income inequality goes hand in hand with underinvestment in human-resources. British Medical Journal 312, 987-989. Doh, J. P., & Guay, T. R. (2004) Globalization and corporate social responsibility: How non-governmental organizations influence labor and environmental codes of conduct. Management International Review, 44, 7-29. Driscoll, C. & McKee, M. (2007) Restorying a Culture of Ethical and Spiritual Values: A Role for Leader Storytelling. Journal of Business Ethics, 73(2), 205-217. Dunne, J. (1997) Back to the rough ground: Practical judgement and the lure of technique. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press. Eflin, J. (2003) Epistemic presuppositions and their consequences. Metaphilosophy, 34(1/2), 48-67. Fairhurst, G. (2007) Discursive leadership: In conversation with leadership psychology. Los Angeles: Sage. Flyvbjerg, B. (2004) Phronetic planning research: Theoretical and methodological reflections. Planning Theory & Practice, 5(3), 283-306. Foucault, M. (1972) The archaeology of knowledge. London: Tavistock. Gardner, W. L., Avolio, B. J., Luthans, F., May, D. R., & Walumbwa, F. O. (2005) "Can you see the real me?" A self-based model of authentic leader and follower development. Leadership Quarterly, 16, 343-372. Gardner, W. L., & Avolio, B. J. (1998) The charismatic relationship: a dramaturgical perspective. Academy of Management Review, 23, 3258. Giddens, A. (1981) Agency, institution and time-space analysis. In K. KnorrCetina & A. V. Cicourel (Eds), Advances in social theory and 24 methodology: Towards an integration of micro- and macro-sociologies (pp. 161-174). London: Routledge and Kegan Paul. Giddens, A. (1984) The constitution of society: Outline of the theory of structuration. Cambridge: Polity Press. Gottlieb, J. Z., & Sanzgiri, J. (1996) Towards an ethical dimension of decision making in organizations. Journal of Business Ethics, 15, 1275-1285. Gourlay, S. (2006) Conceptualizing Knowledge Creation: A Critique of Nonaka’s Theory Journal of Management Studies 43(7), 1415-1436. Grojean, M. W., Resick, C. J., Dickson, M. W., & Smith, D. B. (2004) Leaders, values, and organizational climate: Examining leadership strategies for establishing an organizational climate regarding ethics. Journal of Business Ethics, 55, 223-241. Haque, M. S. (2000) Significance of accountability under the new approach to public governance International Review of Administrative Sciences, 66 (4), 599-617. Harvey, P., Martinko, M. J., & Gardner, W. L. (2006) Promoting authentic behavior in organizations: An attributional perspective. Journal of Leadership & Organizational Studies, 12(3), 1-11. Heracleous, L., & Barrett, M. (2001) Organizational change as discourse: Communicative actions and deep structures in the context of IT implementation. Academy of Management Journal, 44(4), 755-778. Hinds, R. S. (2005) Consideration of the Relationship Between Spiritual WellBeing and Transformational Leadership. Journal of Applied Management and Entrepreneurship, 10(2), 124-139. Howell, J. M., & Avolio, B. J. (1992) The Ethics of Charismatic Leadership: Submission or Liberation? Academy of Management Executive, 6, 4352. Hughes, G. J. (2001) Aristotle on Ethics. London: Routledge. Hunt, J. G., Osborn, R. N., & Boal, K. B. (2007) The Architecture of Strategic Leadership Near the Edge of Chaos. Paper presented at the Festschrift for Jerry Hunt. Kaplan, G.A., Pamuk, E.R., Lynch, J.W., Cohen, R.D., Balfour, J.L., (1996) Inequality in income and mortality in the United States: analysis of mortality and potential pathways. British Medical Journal 312, 9991003. Kekes, J. (1995) Moral wisdom and good lives. Ithaca & London: Cornell University Press. Kellett, J. B., Humphrey, R., & Sleeth, R. G. (2006) Empathy and the Emergence of Task and Relations Leaders. Leadership Quarterly, 17, 146-162. Kerin, L (22 October , 2007) Community Services scrutinised over toddler suitcase death. ABC. The World Today. URL: http://www.abc.net.au/worldtoday/content/2007/s2066100.htm Knorr-Cetina, K. (2006) The Market Theory. Culture & Society 23(2), 551– 556. Kridan, AB & Goulding, JS (2006) A case study on knowledge management implementation in the banking sector, VINE: The Journal of Information and Knowledge Management System, vol. 36, no. 2, pp. 211-222. 25 Kriger, M., & Seng, Y. (2005) Leadership With Inner Meaning: A Contingency Theory of Leadership Based on the Worldviews of Five Religions. Leadership Quarterly, 16, 771-806. Labouvie-Vief, G. (1990) Wisdom as Integrated Thought: Historical and Developmental Perspectives. In R. J. Sternberg (Ed), Wisdom: Its Nature, Origins, and Development (pp. 52-83). New York: Cambridge University Press. Lane, J-E. (2000) New public management. London; New York. Routledge. Lonergan, B. J. F. (1957) Insight: A Study of Human Understanding. London: Longmans, Green & Co. Luthans, F., & Avolio, B. J. (2003) Authentic leadership development. In K. S. Cameron, J. E. Dutton & R. E. Quinn (Eds), Positive organizational scholarship (pp. 241-261). San Francisco: Barrett-Koehler. MacKenzie, D. (2001) Physics and Finance: S-terms and modern finance as a topic for science studies. Science, Technology and Human Values, 26(2), 115-144. Malan, L.-C., & Kriger, M. P. (1998) Making sense of managerial wisdom. Journal of Management Inquiry, 7(3), 242-251. Markow, F. & Klenke, K. (2005) The Effects Of Personal Meaning And Calling On Organizational Commitment: An Empirical Investigation Of Spiritual Leadership. International Journal of Organizational Analysis, 13(1), 827. Marshak, R. J. & Heracleous, L. (2005) A discursive approach to organization development. Action Research, 3(1), 69-88. McKenna, B. (2004) Critical Discourse Studies: Where to from here? Critical Discourse Studies, 1(1), 1-31. McKenna, B.J. & Graham, P. (2000) Technocratic discourse: A primer. J of Technical Writing and Communication, 30 (3), 219-247. McKenna, B., Rooney, D., & Boal, K. B. (in-press) Wisdom Principles as a Meta-theoretical: Basis for Evaluating Leadership. Leadership Quarterly. McKenna, B., Boal, K. B., & Rooney, D. (2006) Using Wisdom Principles To Guide Authentic Leadership Research. Paper presented at the Submission to the Second Biannual Gallup Leadership Institute Summit, Gallup World Headquarters, Washington DC. McKenna, B., Rooney, D., & Liesch, P. (2006) Beyond knowledge to wisdom in international business strategy. Prometheus, 24(3), 283-300. McKenzie, A. (2005). Problematising the Technological: The Object as Event? . Social Epistemology, 19(4), 381-399. Michie, S., & Gooty, J. (2005) Values, Emotions, and Authenticity: Will the Real Leader Please Stand Up. Leadership Quarterly, 16, 441-457. Minogue, M. (2000) Changing the state: concepts and practice in the reform of the public sector. In M. Minogue, C. Polidano & D. Hulme (eds), Beyond the New Public Management: Changing Ideas and Practices in Governance. (pp. 17-27) Edward Elgar.. Mizruchi, M. S., & Fein, L. C. (1999) The Social Construction of Organizational Knowledge: A Study of the Uses of Coercive, Mimetic, and Normative Isomorphism. Administrative Science Quarterly, 44(4), 653-683. 26 Montibeller, G, Shaw, D & Westcombe, M. (2006) Using decision support systems to facilitate the social process of knowledge management, Knowledge Management Research & Practice, vol. 4, no. 2, pp. 125– 137. Muntaner, C., Lynch, J., (1999) Income inequality, social cohesion, and class relations: a critique of Wilkinson's neo-Durkheimian research program. International Journal of Health Services, 29 (1), 59-81. Noel, J. (1999) On the varieties of Phronesis. Educational Philosophy and Theory, 31(3), 273-289. Nussbaum, M. (1994) The Therapy of Desire: Theory and Practice in Hellenistic Ethics. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Petera, E., Spalding, K., Kenny, N., Conradd, P., McKeever, P., & Macfarlane, A. (2007) Neither seen nor heard: Children and homecare policy in Canada Social Science & Medicine, 64, 1624-1635. Peters, B.G. (1991) Morale in the Public Service: A Comparative Inquiry, International Review of Administrative Sciences, Vol. 57, 421–440. Pietersma, H. (2006) What happened to epistemology in our tradition? Review of Metaphysics, 59(3), 553-576. Pryke, M., & Du Gay, P. (2007) Take an issue: Cultural economy and finance. Economy and Society, 36(3), 339-354. Reave, L. (2005) Spiritual Values and Practices Related to Leadership Effectiveness. Leadership Quarterly, 16, 655-687. Richards, G. (1996) Businesslike Government: The Ultimate Oxymoron? Optimum: The Journal of Public Sector Management 27(1): 21–25. Rooney, D., & McKenna, B. (in-press) Wisdom in Public Administration: Looking for a Sociology of Wise Practice. Public Administration Review. Rooney, D & Schneider, U. (2007) Re-Theorising the Tacit Dimension: Towards a New Treatment of Tacit Knowledge, Paper presented at the Second European Conference on Knowledge Management, Bled, Slovenia. Satish, U. (1997) Behavioral complexity: A review. Journal of Applied Social Psychology, 27(23), 2047-2067. Sherman, N. (1997) Making a necessity of virtue: Aristotle and Kant on virtue. Cambridge & New York: Cambridge University Press. Spender, J.-C. (1996) Organizational Knowledge, Learning and Memory: Three Concepts in Search of a Theory. Journal of Organizational Change Management, 9(1), 63-78. Stacey, R. D. (2001) Complex Responsive Processes in Organizations: Learning and Knowledge Creation. London: Routledge. Staudinger, U. M. & Pasupathi, M. (2003) Correlates of wisdom-related performance in adolescence and adulthood: Age-graded differences in "paths" toward desirable development. Journal of Research on Adolescence, 13(3), 239-268. Sternberg, R. J. (1990) Understanding wisdom. In R. J. Sternberg (Ed), Wisdom: Its Nature, Origins and Development (pp. 3-9). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Sternberg, R. J. (1996) Styles of Thinking. In P. B. Baltes & U. M. Staudinger (Eds), Interactive Minds: Life-Span Perspectives on the Social 27 Foundation of Cognition (pp. 347-365). New York: Cambridge University Press. Sternberg, R. J. (1998) A Balance Theory of Wisdom. Review of General Psychology, 2(4), 347-365. Sternberg, R. J. (2001) Why schools should teach for wisdom: The Balance Theory of Wisdom in educational settings. Educational Psychologist, 36(4), 227-245. Sternberg, R. J. & Ben-Zeev, T. (2001) Complex cognition: The psychology of human thought. New York, Oxford: Oxford University Press. Strati, A. (2000) The aesthetic approach in organization studies. In S. Linstead & H. Höpfl (Eds), The aesthetics of organization (pp. 13-34). London: Sage Tsoukas, H. (1996) The Firm as a Distributed Knowledge System: A Constructionist Approach. Strategic Management Journal, 17(Winter Special Issue), 11-25. Wade, J. (Ed) (1996) Changes of Mind: A Holonomic Theory of the Evolution of Consciousness. New York: State University of New York Press. Wang, P., & Chan, P. S. (1995) Top management perception of strategic information processing in a turbulent environment. Leadership & Organization Development, 16(7), 33-43. Whittington, J. L., Pitts, T. M., Kageler, W., & Goodwin, V. L. (2005) Legacy Leadership: The Leadership Wisdom of the Apostle Paul. Leadership Quarterly, 16(5), 749-770. 28