A solution to the unexpected day paradox By Albert Frank Several versions of the unexpected day paradox can be find. Here is one: On a Monday morning, a teacher says to his class, "I will give you a surprise examination someday this week. It may be today, tomorrow, Wednesday, Thursday, or Friday at the latest. On the morning of the examination, when you come to class, you will not know that this is the day of the examination." A student reasoned as follows: "Obviously I can't get the exam on the last day, Friday, because if I haven't got the exam by the end of Thursday's class, then on Friday morning I'll know that this is the day, and the exam won't be a surprise. This rules out Friday, so I now know that Thursday is the last possible day. And, if I don't get the exam by the end of Wednesday, then I'll know on Thursday morning that this must be the day (because I have already ruled out Friday), hence it won't be a surprise. So Thursday is also ruled out." The student then ruled out Wednesday by the same argument, then Tuesday, and finally Monday, the day on which the professor was speaking. He concluded: "Therefore I cannot get the exam at all; the professor cannot possibly fulfil his statement." Just then, the professor said: "Now I will give you your exam." The student was most surprised! ++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++ There are a lot of studies about this old paradox. The "classical solutions" tries to proof that the recurrence is valid only for the last day. This looks very dubious. Several logicians, among which Raymond Smullyan had other ideas. Mainly: The teacher said two things: (1) You will get an exam someday this week; (2) The exact day will be a surprise, you won't know on the morning of the exam that this is the day. It is important that these two statements should be separated. It could be that the professor was right in the first statement and wrong in the second … Suppose Friday morning comes and I haven't got the exam yet. What would I then believe? … +++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++ After reading a lot about this paradox, I came to the following conclusion: This paradox is a good example of semantic paradox. In the context, the word surprise does not have a constant meaning, and the use of it (like if it would have a constant same value) is an abuse! In his first sentence, the teacher uses the word surprise with its "Monday's value", in his second sentence with its "Friday's value", and in his third sequence with its "Thursday value". +++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++ Bibliography D. O'Connor, "Pragmatic Paradoxes," Mind 57:358-9, 1948. L. Cohen, "Mr. O'Connor's 'Pragmatic Paradoxes,'" Mind 59:85-7, 1950. P. Alexander, "Pragmatic Paradoxes," Mind 59:536-8, 1950. M. Scriven, "Paradoxical Announcements," Mind 60:403-7, 1951. D. O'Connor, "Pragmatic Paradoxes and Fugitive Propositions," Mind 60:536-8, 1951 P. Weiss, "The Prediction Paradox," Mind 61:265ff, 1952. W. Quine, "On A So-Called Paradox," Mind 62:65-7, 1953. R. Shaw, "The Paradox of the Unexpected Examination," Mind 67:382-4, 1958. A. Lyon, "The Prediction Paradox," Mind 68:510-7, 1959. D. Kaplan and R. Montague, "A Paradox Regained," Notre Dame J Formal Logic 1:79-90, 1960. G. Nerlich, "Unexpected Examinations and Unprovable Statements," Mind 70:503-13, 1961. M. Gardner, "A New Prediction Paradox," Brit J Phil Sci 13:51, 1962. K. Popper, "A Comment on the New Prediction Paradox," Brit J Phil Sci 13:51, 1962. B. Medlin, "The Unexpected Examination," Am Phil Q 1:66-72, 1964. F. Fitch, "A Goedelized Formulation of the Prediction Paradox," Am Phil Q 1:161-4, 1964. T.H. O'Beirne, "Problematic Lies and Unexpected Truths," in _Puzzles_and_ _Paradoxes_, Oxford University Press 1965 (also Dover 1984). R. Sharpe, "The Unexpected Examination," Mind 74:255, 1965. J. Chapman & R. Butler, "On Quine's So-Called 'Paradox,'" Mind 74:424-5, 1965. J. Bennett and J. Cargile, Reviews, J Symb Logic 30:101-3, 1965. J. Schoenberg, "A Note on the Logical Fallacy in the Paradox of the Unexpected Examination," Mind 75:125-7, 1966. J. Wright, "The Surprise Exam: Prediction on the Last Day Uncertain," Mind 76:115-7, 1967. J. Cargile, "The Surprise Test Paradox," J Phil 64:550-63, 1967. R. Binkley, "The Surprise Examination in Modal Logic," J Phil 65:127-36, 1968. C. Harrison, "The Unanticipated Examination in View of Kripke's Semantics for Modal Logic," in Philosophical Logic, J. Davis et al (ed.), Dordrecht, 1969. P. Windt, "The Liar in the Prediction Paradox," Am Phil Q 10:65-8, 1973. A. Ayer, "On a Supposed Antinomy," Mind 82:125-6, 1973. M. Edman, "The Prediction Paradox," Theoria 40:166-75, 1974. J. McClelland & C. Chihara, "The Surprise Examination Paradox," J Phil Logic 4:71-89, 1975. C. Wright and A. Sudbury, "The Paradox of the Unexpected Examination," Aust J Phil 55:41-58, 1977. I. Kvart, "The Paradox of the Surprise Examination," Logique et Analyse 337-344, 1978. R. Sorenson, "Recalcitrant Versions of the Prediction Paradox," Aust J Phil 69:355-62, 1982. D. Olin, "The Prediction Paradox Resolved," Phil Stud 44:225-33, 1983. R. Sorenson, "Conditional Blindspots and the Knowledge Squeeze: A Solution to the Prediction Paradox," Aust J Phil 62:126-35, 1984. C. Chihara, "Olin, Quine and the Surprise Examination," Phil Stud 47:191-9, 1985. R. Kirkham, "The Two Paradoxes of the Unexpected Hanging," Phil Stud 49:19-26, 1986. D. Olin, "The Prediction Paradox: Resolving Recalcitrant Variations," Aust J Phil 64:181-9, 1986. C. Janaway, "Knowing About Surprises: A Supposed Antinomy Revisited," Mind 98:391-410, 1989.