Market Structure and Political Law Zephyr Teachout and Lina Khan Table of Contents 1. Overt Political Investments .................................................................1 2. Structural Dependencies and TBTF....................................................1 3. Regulation.............................................................................................1 4. Feudal Politics ......................................................................................1 5. Taxing....................................................................................................1 Infinite Guises ..........................................................................................1 Dynamic Interactions Between Factors .................................................1 Incidental Political Impacts .....................................................................1 Structural Intervention ............................................................... 1 Introduction Market structure is deeply political. One reason is that all markets are governed by law.1 In other words, the structure of a market at any given time is the product of political decisions – made and not-made – about how players in that market will be allowed to user their power. Another reason is that market structure affects us as citizens. It inscribes what we can and cannot do, and hence acts as a form of governance. Our lives are governed by the dominant economic players to whom we are subject. Corporate size and concentration undercut democratic self-governance by imposing on citizens a form of 1 Karl Polanyi, The Great Transformation, Beacon Press; 2 edition (March 28, 2001). 1 Market Structure and Political Law private governance unaccountable to the public. In competitive markets, the freedom to choose among buyers or sellers limits the power of any one actor. In highly concentrated markets, meanwhile, a few dominant companies can assume enough power to restrain and even control the actions of others. One of the most powerful American democratic ideas is that legal rules--like those found in antitrust, or the public purpose doctrine in the FCC--can divest concentrated economic power when it threatens to overpower the political system. This premise, shared by Thomas Jefferson, Woodrow Wilson, and Louis Brandeis, is based on the understanding that decentralized economic power and democratic self-government are deeply intertwined. Monopolization or oligarchy in one realm (political or economic) leads to monopolization and oligarchy in the other (political or economic). Unfortunately, the idea has fallen into desuetude in law as legal scholarship has built up a division between the study of economic and political power. The separation constitutes an unnecessary--and arguably ideological--division that has undermined the capacity of both economic and political laws to be as effective as they can be. Therefore, the regulation of one must be understood in terms of its impacts on the other. Decentralization economic power in most areas of commerce is an essential underpinning of political freedom: a society with strong voting rights, speech protections, and fair elections is not incompatible with an oligarchic economy. For law this means taht antitrust and other deconcentration rules should be understood not solely as part of corporate law, but also as part of political law. In this light, a revival of antitrust policy be one of the most effective forms of improving democratic self-government in ways that are typically associated with campaign finance reform. The goal of this paper is not to prove that we live in an increasingly oligarchic and monopolist economy, but to explain why market structure is innately political. It provides a taxonomy of the ways in which concentrated market structure enacts a form of private governance that threatens democratic self-government. Not all monopolists engage in all of these levers of power--that is not the point. The purpose is to create an integrated vantage point through which to see the political effects of monopolization. Our goal is to expand our understanding of how corporate power perverts the political process, beyond money-in-politics, and to argue that those concerned with preserving authentic democratic self-governance also focus their efforts on restoring antitrust policy. We also hope to be part of opening up a new frontier in the debate about the scope of antitrust, joining a growing body of scholarship in this area. We join and build on scholars like Maurice Stucke, Rudy Peritz, Tom Horton, working on expanding a field which has for decades essentially addressed itself to consumer welfare. We also, however, build on scholars in fields that aren’t traditionally thought of as “competition policy,” like Simon Johnson and Susan Crawford. Several other scholars have thoroughly explored the history of political antitrust, and explained why the modern “efficiency and consumer welfare” model of antitrust is “bad history, bad policy, and bad law.”2 We open by documenting the connections between size and political power, and explaining why more concentrated companies will be more likely to purchase political power, more likely to spend greater percentages of their assets on the purchase of political power, and are likely to be able to get more political power for each dollar spent. 2 Robert Pitofsky, The Political Content of Antitrust, 127 U. PENN. L. REV. 4 (1979). 2 Market Structure and Political Law First, the amount of corporate money spent on influencing political outputs would likely be less in a less concentrated economy, because of the size-related incentives to spend money on political power. Second, the money spent by corporate teams would be more likely to be horizontal—money spent on attempting to oust a rival—because of the intensified competition that exists in more broken up regimes. Third, the range of political visions expressed in political expenditures will likely be greater with more and less concentrated companies. More parts of the country will be represented, and more executives’ political ideas will be represented. Moreover, more competition would likely mean lower profits and lower CEO pay; which is less cash available to the executives. Equally importantly, larger companies in uncompetitive industries will be more able and likely to impose private forms of governance over citizens in ways that enclose them. The political implications of monopoly threaten democratic self-government in ways that also go unaddressed by campaign finance rules. The ability of citizens to govern their own lives is endangered in an economy dominated by a handful of big companies. Absent competition, companies exert power over citizens in explicit and implicit ways, all of which constrain their freedom of action and undercut their political agency. This power manifests in a variety of ways, and its character and form vary depending on the particular market structure and specific economic arrangements. In each case, though, the power is born of size and dominance, and threatens the practice of democratic self-government Throughout, we discuss size and concentration. In our minds, they are connected. Our concern with size is not absolute, but size relative to the total economy, so even size discussions are discussions about the market role of a company in the market structure of the larger economy. Moreover, the political power is at its apex when companies are both large in terms of the economy and play a dominant role in their own markets. Because of this history, and these forms of power, we argue that corporate market structure rules should be understood as political rules. The mutual segregation of corporate law and political theory has undermined each field’s capacity to explain, understand, and propose solutions. Therefore, scholars and lawmakers ought treat a certain category of corporations (as defined by structure and size) as political organizations, and treat the rules governing those corporations as “political rules.” Our goal is not to sketch out solutions, but create a way of thinking about the problem. A political economy dominated by large companies, along with economies of scale in the purchase of political power, is a problem for representative democracy. For political purposes, an economy dominated by many small businesses is preferable to an economy populated by large and concentrated industries. This is because excessive corporate size tends to hurt democratic self-government enables a handful of actors both to purchase disproportionate political power and to subject citizens to systems of private governance that become less accountable the bigger and fewer the corporations. Historical Roots The idea that companies can act as a form of private government is not new. “Monopoly” was originally used to describe an exclusive grant of power from the government to work a particular trade or sell a specific good. In Britain monarchs would sometimes abuse this power. Dissatisfied with the funds Parliament allocated her, Queen 3 Market Structure and Political Law Elizabeth routinely issued royal monopolies as a revenue-generating scheme. Citizens protested that these exclusive trade privileges imposed an undue burden on them, in addition to the burden they already bore paying taxes to Parliament. When paying higher prices to the royal monopoly they were paying, in essence, a private tax that accrued to the Queen.3 Thomas Jefferson was openly anti-monopoly because of his fear of the role that patents played in distorting power in the political marketplace. While the whigs and the democrat-republicans disagreed on how important monopolies were, even the most whiggish centralizer assumed that for most industries, a widely distributed array of producers was necessary. A widely spread economic text book from the 1860s said that “A general Distribution of Capital is a matter of prime importance. By this is meant such a condition of things that the capital of a country shall be in many hands rather than few. . . The great aggregation of capital in the possession of individuals is disadvantageous because it leads inevitably to despotic assumption.”4 Articles in the Harvard Law Review and the North American Review condemned the growth of concentrated economic power as “feudalism” and a “great, unscrupulous, powerful plutocracy.”5 One contemporary wrote about the “political menace that was resident in these stupendous aggregations of wealth.”6 The belief that decentralized economic power was essential for (and inextricable from) political liberty were mainstays view of the day. The first federal antitrust law, The Sherman Act, was understood at the time in terms that we now relate to campaign finance laws. When the Sherman Act passed the U.S. Congress in 1890, Senator John Sherman called it “A bill of rights, a charter of liberty,” and crowed about its importance in both economic and political terms.7 Senator Sherman viewed the monopolist as just another form of monarch. On the floor of the Senate in 1890, he declared, “If we will not endure a king as a political power, we should not endure a king over the production, transportation, and sale of any of the necessities of life. If we would not submit to an emperor, we should not submit to an autocrat of trade, with power to prevent competition and to fix the price of any commodity.” Law Professor James May’s exploration of the Bill’s intellectual antecedents shows that for Sherman and the Congressional supporters, economic and political freedoms were seen as part of a piece. May summarizes the debates around the enactment of the Sherman Act as indicating a “widespread congressional commitment to the longestablished ideals of economic opportunity, security of property, freedom of exchange, and political liberty, and considerable hope that antitrust law might prove to be an effective vehicle for their substantial, simultaneous realization.”8 Or as earlier historians claimed, the “primary motivation of Congress in enacting the Sherman Act and every significant amendment was concern about the abusive behavior of economic giants, real Steven G. Calabresi & Larissa Price, “Monopolies and the Constitution: A History of Crony Capitalism,” Northwestern University School of Law (2012). 3 4 F. Wayland, THE ELEMENTS OF POLITICAL ECONOMY 177 (1860). Hudson, Modern Feudalism, 144 NO. AM. REV. 277, 290 (1887); Mickey, Trusts, 22 AM. L. REV. 538, 549 (1888). We are indebted to John Millon for these quotes. See generally John Millon, The Sherman Act and the Balance of Power, 61 S. Cal. L. Rev. 1219, 1220 (1988). 6 Andrews, Trusts According to Official Investigations, 3 Q.J. ECON. 117, 150 (1889) 7 21 CONG. REC. 2461 (1890). 8 James May, Antitrust in the Formative Era, 50 OHIO ST. L.J. 257, 288 (1989) 5 4 Market Structure and Political Law or imagined, and sympathy for their victims, consumers and businessmen deprived of alternatives and opportunities.” 9 The Act grew out of a long “tradition that aimed to control political power through decentralization of economic power.”10 This view of the Sherman Act persisted for several decades. In 1906, President Taft argued that the Sherman Act had saved the nation from a potential “plutocracy” and described the bill as a protection of economic and political freedoms.11 This ideology persisted in related legislation of the early 20th century. In 1914, during the passage of the Federal Trade Commission Act, one Senator explained that “we must do something to preserve the independence of the man as distinguished from the power of the corporation; that we must do something to perpetuate the individual initiative.” Senator Cummins argued against simply adopting the idea that cheaper commodities were worth a great deal—conceding the point that aggregations of capital might lead to cheaper goods he argued that “we can purchase cheapness at altogether too high a price, if it involves the surrender of the individual, the subjugation of a great mass of people to a single master mind.” Passed in 1914, the Clayton Act prohibited a corporation from acquiring another when the acquisition would result in a substantial lessening of competition between the acquiring and the acquired companies, or tend to create a monopoly in any line of commerce. The debates around the Clayton Act—again, explored nicely by Professor May—show the same political cast. The House committee report on the bill argued that “the concentration of wealth, money, and property in the United States under the control and in the hands of a few individuals or great corporations has grown to such an enormous extent” and it must be stopped lest it “threaten the perpetuity of our institutions.”12 One Congressman explained that “Enterprises with great capital have deliberately sought not only industrial domination but political supremacy as well.. . . Great combinations of capital for many years have flaunted their power in the face of the citizenship, they have forced their corrupt way into politics and government, they have dictated the making of laws or scorned the laws they did not like, they have prevented the free and just administration of law.”13 Senator Taft’s 1914 book about the Sherman Act echoed these themes, arguing that antitrust was essential in fighting the “plutocracy” of the “great and powerful corporations which had, many of them, intervened in politics and through use of corrupt machines and bosses threatened us.”14 Ironically, the greatest burst of antitrust enforcement—as distinguished from the antitrust laws themselves--was accompanied by an effort to tone down the political content. Thurman Arnold, who brought antitrust and competition policy to the center of the Roosevelt Administrations’ economic policy, himself downplayed the political Harlan Blake & William Jones, In Defense of Antitrust, 65 COLUM. L. REV. 377, 385 (1965) John Millon, The Sherman Act and the Balance of Power, 61 S. CAL. L. REV. 1219, 1220 (1988) 11 The first laws limiting corporate spending on elections appeared in 1907, after a 1904 scandal—Congress said that Corporations could not spend any money in association with a campaign for Presidency or Congress. In 1910 and 1911, Congress passed bills limiting the amount that could be contributed to campaigns. 12 H. R. REP. NO. 627, 63d Cong., 2d Sess. 19 (1914). 13 51 CONG. REC. 9086 (1914). 14 Robert Taft, THE ANTI-TRUST ACT AND THE SUPREME COURT (1914). 9 10 5 Market Structure and Political Law problems of scale and concentration, and focused on the economic harms. Arnold is widely recognized for giving antitrust laws power and the staffing and commitment necessary for enforcing the general principle. It is unclear what we should make of Arnold’s agnosticism about the political impacts of antitrust. On the one hand, one could see Arnold as redefining antitrust for the country and giving him an authorship role (including the capacity to re-author antitrust laws in an economic light). On the other hand, one could see him as finally enforcing a policy that the public had long clamored for—the fact his own emphasis was on economy instead of politics and power is of little import. Regardless of Arnold himself, the law maintained a political cast after World War II. Courts, while looking at market share, did not limit themselves to economic analysis, but saw the role of antitrust in terms of limiting concentrated power which could be used in both the economic and political spheres. Cartels and dominant business interests were associated with the political economies of Japan and Germany. Anti-big business suspicion may have come from experience with business cartels associated with harsh World War I governments in Germany and Japan. In 1941, the Supreme Court in United States v. Hutcheson openly read the antitrust statutes in light of, and to be harmonized with, earlier labor acts which had declared the public policy of the United States to In the major antitrust tract of the late 50s, Karl Kaysen and Donald Turner wrote about the goals of antitrust. Kaysen and Turner were both Harvard Law Professors; Turner later became the chief antitrust lawyer for President Johnson’s Antitrust. They argued that that the goal of antitrust was a “proper distribution of power” in the economic sphere. 15 This goal, they said, derived from Jefferson and principles of autonomy that were central to American political ideology. Moreover, concentrated power posed threats. They argued that “business units are politically irresponsible, and therefore large powerful business units are dangerous.” 16They saw the goal of the Sherman act to “protect equal access and equal opportunity for small business for noneconomic reasons: concentration of resources in the hands of a few was viewed as a social and political catastrophe.”17 Turner and Kaysen’s view was reflected in the court cases, although of course the courts were more constrained by the text. In 1945, Judge Learned Hand in United States v. Aluminum Company of America first discussed the economic arguments against monopoly but endorsed the “belief that great industrial consolidations are inherently undesirable, regardless of their economic results.” 18 He referred to Sherman’s stated concerns about limiting aggregated capital because of the “helplessness of the individual before them.” Moreover, he noted that later statutes including the Surplus Property Act and the Small Business Mobilization Act had been right interpreted in Hutcheson to shape the meaning of the antitrust acts. “Throughout the history of these statutes it has been constantly assumed that one of their purposes was to perpetuate and preserve, for its own sake and in spite of possible cost, an organization of industry in small units which See Carl Kaysen and Donald F. Turner, ANTITRUST POLICY: AN ECONOMIC AND LEGAL ANALYSIS (1959). 16 Id. 17 Id. 18 Alcoa, 148 F.2d at 428-29 15 6 Market Structure and Political Law can effectively compete with each other.”19 Antitrust as a force for decentralization was important “for its own sake and in spite of possible cost.”20 In 1948 in U.S. v. Columbia Steel Co, Justice Douglas explained that: “We have here the problem of bigness …The philosophy of the Sherman Act is that … all power tends to develop into a government in itself. Power that controls the economy … should be scattered into many hands so that the fortunes of the people will not be dependent on the whim or caprice, the political prejudices, the emotional stability of a few self-appointed men. The fact that they are not vicious men but respectable and social minded is irrelevant. That is the philosophy and command of the Sherman Act.”21 In 1950, Congress amended the antitrust laws by passing the Clayton Antitrust Act, in response to a burst of merger activity. Like Sherman, the precise definitions were lacking, but the goals blended political and economic aims. In this era, the Antitrust division tended to be very successfully in blocking mergers—and the political vision persisted. In 1959, Carl Kaysen and Donald Turner proposed “no fault” concentration legislation. In Brown Shoe in 1962, the Supreme Court said that Congress’ vision in the Sherman act was to “promote competition through the protection of viable, small, locally owned business.”22 Congress understood that this vision might lead to higher costs and prices,” because of costs associated with “fragmented industries and markets.” However, Congress “resolved these competing considerations in favor of decentralization.”23 Likewise, in United States v. Philadelphia National Bank, the Supreme Court upheld a block of a bank merger between the second and third largest regional banks, which would have led to one bank controlling 30% of commercial banking. Despite the lack of evidence that this 30% interest would have negative effects on competition, the Court held that they need not have “elaborate proof of market structure, market behavior, or probable anticompetitive effects.” Instead, the high market share alone showed “inherently anticompetitive tendency.” Clayton barred “anticompetitive mergers, benign and malignant alike,” and in interpreting the statute, the court recognized that there were concerns about concentration that were not directly measurable. From the mid-60s to the early 1980s, there was a sea change in the understanding of antitrust, and a hard-fought intellectual battle over its purposes. Richard Posner and Robert Bork argued that current doctrine was based on flawed economic ideological premises and that efficiency and consumer welfare—not the goal of aiding small 19 When the Norris-LaGuardia act of 1932 was passed, not an antitrust act itself but a labor right act, the law is important because it explained that it was the “public policy of the United States”, to protect individual unorganized workers in the face of corporate power. Norris-Laguardia explained corporate power in terms of “prevailing economic conditions, developed with the aid of governmental authority for owners of property to organize in the corporate and other forms of ownership association.” 20 U.S. v. Aluminum Co. of America, 148 F.2d 416, 429 (2nd Cir. 1945). 21 U.S. v. Columbia Steel Co., 334 U.S. 495, 535 (1948) 22 Brown Shoe Co. v. United States, 370 U.S. 294, 344 (1962) 23 Id. 7 Market Structure and Political Law businesses or having a decentralized economy—were the only legitimate goals of the antitrust statutes. Posner argued that there was no justification for “using using the antitrust laws to attain goals unrelated or antithetical to efficiency, such as promoting a society of small tradespeople.” Bork, similarly, argued that any political or social concerns were necessarily indeterminate and created unmanageable standards, and were normatively unjustifiable.24 In every important way, they won the war. However, the political vision of antitrust, and of an economy with few massive companies, was still an essential part of the antitrust lawyer’s self-understanding at least through the early 1980s. While the courts turned away from anything but bad behavior, politicians with a different economic vision, and concern about concentration qua concentration, continued to fight for decentralizing economic laws. In 1968, a White House Antitrust Task Force recommended limiting mergers for companies with more than $500 million in assets. In 1972, Senator Hart proposed no fault de-concentration that would have set an absolute cap on how concentrated industries could become. In 1979, Ted Kennedy introduced a bill that would have limited mergers of companies with over $2 billion assets (close to $6 billion in today’s dollars). There was a fierce intellectual debate over the bill, coming as it did when the law and economics models were gaining strength, and when the traditional, political antitrust people still had significant political power. Donald Turner, among others, argued that antitrust had always had a quasiconstitutional dimension, and that it would and did always reflect the economic views of the country. As such, he argued, the Kennedy Bill was an important reflection of a cultural commitment to decentralized political and economic power. But by this late date, Turner was increasingly isolated, as the dominant figures in the field adopted variations of the Posner and Bork model, and rejected any limitations on corporate size, or arguments for decentralized corporate competition. Unfortunately, when the Posner/Bork model came to dominate antitrust, it did not just infect the particular field of antitrust law, but the larger understanding of the relationship of corporate and political law. We have lost, therefore, the intellectual habit of seeing that the earlier political antitrust provided. We see political problems in isolation from economic ones, diminishing our capacity to analyze either arena accurately. The ideological radicalism of these public choice theorists may not have been their commitment to “efficiency” and modeling, but the core commitment to the idea that politics and economics are severable. While their sub-theories were debated and discussed at the time, and the empirical evidence for their claims successfully challenged, the great success of the “law and economics” movement (along with other related trends) was in shaping the taxonomies of study. Economics and business are one area of study; constitutional law and election law are another. This separation of economic and political thinking goes very deep, and has shaped newspapers, political rhetoric, and activists. Since the 1970s, reformers from left and right have turned their energies towards laws governing the shape of the governing institutions (like Congress), instead of laws governing the creation and shape of the influencing institutions (like Bank of America). While they have different sets of beliefs about corporate law and liabilities, it is rare that either left or right democracy reformers 24 Robert Bork, THE ANTITRUST PARADOX (1978). 8 Market Structure and Political Law focus on antitrust or corporate size and structure. This is not merely intellectually troubling, it is historically strange; prior to the 1970s, reformers would talk about money and politics in terms of market structure as something government could do something about. It is no accident that the law and economics movement started in antitrust, which seemed a bit of a backwater—and spread from antitrust out into other parts of business law. If the law and economics scholars could convince others that antitrust—the most political of economic laws—had nothing to do with political culture or elections, with representative democracy and power—then it was far easier to convince them that other factors of corporate law and structure were also fundamentally non-political. When politics was taken out of economics, economics was taken out of politics. frameworks for thinking about capture, rent, and campaign finance have limited our sense of possibility—the same players return with different sets of tools (or the same set, repackaged) back to the same sandboxes, over and over again, without looking out over the playground. But this is not the only sandbox. The tendency to “study markets in splendid isolation from such political acts,”25 can limit the imagination of the person involved in questions of democratic design, and lead to problematically wrong descriptions of the way the market, and government, actually works. Instead of seeing political organizations—like Congress or political parties—as the only place in which we might make political rules, we ought also see corporations as the place to make political rules. In order to open up corporate structure rules to political conversations, we must first recognize that corporations are sometimes political organizations. Five Forms of Political Power It is beyond the scope of one paper to explore all the political-economic repercussions of an economy dominated by large companies. Instead, we will focus on five ways in which companies might exercise political power. We aim to separate out those companies who are deeply, constitutionally, political, from those who are incidentally engaged in the exercise of power. When a company is heavily invested in, or capable of exercising these forms of power, they may qualify as a political organization. The categories we identify are: 1. 2. 3. 4. 5. Direct Political Investments TBTF Regulation Political Punishment Taxing We discuss each in turn. In business law, these five forms of power might be called a subset of “nonmarket” strategies. As David Bach and David Bruce Allen wrote recently in the MIT Sloan Management review, in an article entitled, “What every CEO needs to know about nonmarket strategy”: 25 Rudolph Peritz, Competition Policy in America (1996) Page 241. 9 Market Structure and Political Law Nonmarket strategy recognizes that businesses are social and political beings, not just economic agents. Because companies create and distribute value, a plethora of actors seek to influence them — formally, through laws and regulation, and informally, through social pressure, activism and efforts to shape the public perception of business. Companies can’t escape this. Smart executives, therefore, engage with their social and political environment, helping shape the rules of the game and reducing the risk of being hemmed in by external actors. Yet, few companies are prepared to do the hard work and commit long term to developing an effective nonmarket strategy. Fewer still understand how to integrate market and nonmarket strategies to sustain competitive advantage.26 Nonmarket strategy includes public relations, lobbying, legal change, and market structure. Or, as Bach and Allen write, “Nonmarket issues can play out in multiple settings, from courtrooms and regulatory proceedings to parliamentary committee hearings and industry forums all the way to the news media, the public domain or the blogosphere.” While we do not discuss every nonmarket strategy here (most importantly, we do not engage in the complicated political role of direct to consumer advertising), the word “nonmarket” is helpful, because it signals that regulatory interference--in the form of antitrust laws or other rules--would not interfere with “the market,” even according to the terms of the market participants. However, our investigation necessarily differs from that of strategy in a few ways. First, we are examining the political role of companies, not simply the political choices facing an individual company. Second, we are less interested in the actual strategic choices made, and more interested in the exercise of power. When it comes to democracy, the accidental feudal lords are every bit as important as those who set out to gain political power. Therefore, our portrait assumes the unity of the ‘company,’ instead of treating shareholders and insiders differently. We are persuaded by the work of John Coates and others that as a strategic matter, many of these nonmarket decisions--including the decision to invest in politics, or to merge--are driven by desires of the managers where they diverge from those of insiders. However, again, for our purposes, we are interested in the exercise of power itself, not the reasons for it. When describing the source of power, we use terms like “dominant,” “monopolistic,” and “oligopolistic.” Our use of these terms is deliberately imprecise. Because we are interested in categorizing the forms of power born of size and concentration, debates about the technical contours of these terms is secondary, and possibly irrelevant, to our work. 1. Overt Political Investments The first way in which companies exercise political power is the most obvious. These are include all the overt use of financial resources to shape public policy in a way favorable to the company. The open goal of these efforts is to influence the traditional political process. Companies spend a lot of money in politics, in a variety of ways. During the financial reform bill fight of 2010, the financial industry officially employed 2,565 lobbyists, used 26 MIT Sloan Management, Spring 2010. 10 Market Structure and Political Law media campaigns--JP Morgan’s was “The Way Forward” to explain how the crisis happened--and donated generously to candidates. Companies may lobby elected officials directly, they lobby regulators, they either create PACs which spend money on campaigns, making access to decision-makers easier, or use SuperPACs or LLCs to spend independently. They may play a large role in a trade association that lobbies. The range extends to charities. While some socially responsible spending is done for nonpolitical reasons, some is done to enable political power. David Cohen oversees government affairs at Comcast, but also runs its charitable foundation, which gave $320,000 to the Hispanic Chamber of Commerce over a five year period. When the Comcast merger was announced, the New York Times reported on the connection, noting that one of the first supporters of the merger was the Hispanic Chamber.27 Bach and Allen encourage this kind of political involvement, pointing to Toyota’s successful lobbying to get California to give low-emissions vehicles preferred HOV lane access. “With minimum financial investment, Toyota managed to give its product a decisive competitive advantage.28 Some part of this strategy may include influencing voters through media. Some could include efforts to get unmediated access to decision-makers, and then using that access in order to push a particular policy or general ideology. (You can see examples of this in Google’s corporate leadership creating close ties to the Obama administration.) 2. Structural Dependencies and TBTF Corporate sizes relative to the economy, or a limited number of provider of essential services, will create political dependencies not based on lobbying resources, but based on economic dependencies. Bank of America's assets are around 1/7th of the United States GDP. Exxon Mobil made $45 billion dollars in profits in 2008. Bank of America, Goldman Sachs, JP Morgan Chase and Citigroup each have debts—not including the money they owe depositors—that are over 2% of U.S. GDP. Lockheed has $35 billion in assets. When the relative size is significant—like 2%—democratic choices become constrained by the self-interest of the individual corporation. Even in the absence of resources devoted to purchasing political influence, the company with a large relative size will have power. The relative size makes it incumbent upon legislators to design laws that will at a minimum ensure the stability of the company. If Lockheed goes under and lays off all its employees, that has an impact on the entire economy. Therefore, Lockheed, even without lobbying, can make demands of government based on the threat of its own failure. (At the state level, the disparity is more striking. In some states, companies have assets are as much as 10% of the GDP. The non-lobbying power of those companies is enormous. Regardless of the politics of a state, and the desires of its citizens, individual, company-specific favors and earmarks will flow to those companies.) Lipton, Comcast’s Web of Lobbying and Philanthropy, New York Times, February 10, 2014. 27 Eric 28 See Bach and Allen, supra note __/ 11 Market Structure and Political Law Companies that are large relative to the size of American GDP can control politics by threatening to collapse or leave if their demands aren’t met. After the recent financial crisis, because of the size (relative to the economy) of the biggest firms, and because of their absolute size, politicians made the decision that they should not be allowed to fail and bring the country down with them. Putting aside the banks causal role in the crisis (which is itself arguably a function of relative size), imagine that there were 10,000 banks, instead of 5, facing restructuring. The government could have allowed some to fail while others were restructured. While the government might still have chosen to provide a bailout, it could have had more bargaining power with the banks in determining the size of the bailout. (This leads to a market distortion, as well, as large enough companies can borrow capital more cheaply than merely big companies, because lenders see them as backed up by the U.S. government—whether or not they are efficient or skillful. This hurts smaller companies who have to compete. The structure rewards scale for scale's sake instead of skill and creativity.) Dominant firms breed uncertainty and instability in key resources—and that uncertainty leads to political power.29 You can think of this kind of size as the “too big to fail” rent, a promised subsidy that enables cheap capital and cheapens the cost of seeking political power. 3. Regulation As we describe above, large companies routinely win favorable regulations by influencing the political process through lobbying and revolving door tactics. A more direct and less visible way to set regulations is to be a monopolist. The standards a dominant company sets can determine the course of an industry much like a government agency does. If Pfizer, whose Advil holds over 50 percent of the market for ibuprofen, chose to stop using propionic acid, a key ingredient, the effects of its decision would resemble a regulatory prohibition by the Food and Drug Association. And the more concentrated the market, the greater the governing power. For example, if we have a competitive shampoo market, whether there are toxins in our shampoo will be determined by hundreds of executive teams at hundreds of firms with competing interests. But if our shampoo market is monopolized by one company, that same decision will be made by a few executives sharing one common interest. In this second case, the shampoo company enjoys power akin to a government, without being accountable to the public. A recent example of how dominant companies become de facto regulators centers around Zilmax, the feed hormone used to bulk up cattle in the final weeks of their lives. Though the additive hit commercial markets in 2007, research showing it harmed the quality of beef kept feedlot owners from buying it. Enter Tyson, JBS, Cargill, and the National Beef Packing Company. Once the four meatpackers, which control 85 percent of the market, began accepting Zilmax-fed animals, its adoption rapidly spread across the 29 As Simon Johnson and James Kwak argued in their book and blogs and articles, this structure reeks of oligarchy. Gigantic firms are a real threat to self-government. If big corporations can demand bailouts and dictate policy it takes away the ability of people to choose the policies they most want. The policy is “chosen” by the people in the same way that someone with a gun to their head “chooses” to do what the holder of the gun tells them to. Simon Johnson and James Kwak, Thirteen Bankers (2010). 12 Market Structure and Political Law whole industry. By late 2012, even feedlots leery of its side effects realized they’d have to start using it if they wanted to stay in business.30 But when reports surfaced that cattle fed with Zilmax were struggling to walk and displaying strange side effects, its abandonment was equally swift. On August 9, 2013 Tyson, the biggest meat company in the world, announced it would no longer buy Zilmax-fed livestock. On August 16, Zilmax-producer Merck said it was suspending sales.31 No government agency intervened at any point; it was a handful of executives that governed the contents of our beef supply. Meanwhile, policies set by Facebook regulate the online privacy of over 1.2 billion users worldwide. Three airline companies govern which cities in America receive affordable and regular air service and which are cut from the grid. Rules decided by the Chicago Mercantile Exchange – which has swallowed up the Chicago Board of Trade, the Kansas City Board of Trade, and the New York Mercantile Exchange – now determine how our corn, wheat, and oil are priced. This observation about de facto regulatory power is different from a critique of deregulation. We are not arguing that companies are presently making decisions that ought to be made by government. We are saying that when you have one or very few dominant companies making decisions that effectively set standards for the rest of the industry, those outcomes take on the character of governance. The crucial difference being, of course, that corporations, unlike government, are not accountable to the public. 4. Feudal Politics Dominance and lack of competition also empowers companies to direct the political choices made by employees and suppliers. This exercise of power is more common in monopsony situations than monopoly. Our livelihoods are more vulnerable than the goods we buy. Take chicken farming. Four poultry processors control around 53 percent of the US market. Regionally, concentration is even higher. Practically this means that chicken farmers are often beholden to a single company, with scant bargaining power to negotiate terms of their contract. The industry is vertically integrated, which means processors hatch the chicks, mix their feed, slaughter the birds, and package the meat for market. They leave farmers to actually raise the birds, the riskiest and most capital-intensive part of the business. Farmers usually take on hundreds of thousands of dollars in loans to build poultry houses and purchase heaters to warm the birds and ventilation systems to cool them, all to the company’s specifications. Meanwhile, their pay is unpredictable and occasionally arbitrary. That’s because chicken processors like Tyson pay farmers through the “tournament system,” which pits farmers against one another by pegging their pay to their ranking, with no accountability or transparency. Farmers know that if they protest or challenge the company, it can cut them off – and sink their livelihood. In 2009, the Obama administration announced it would convene a series of workshops to assess the state of consolidation in agricultural markets. Attorney General Eric Holder and Agriculture Secretary Tom Vilasck toured the country to hear directly Christopher Leonard, “Why Beef Is Becoming More Like Chicken” Slate, Feb. 14, 2013 31 Theopolis Waters and Tom Polansek, “Amid cattle health concerns, Merck halts Zilmax sales” Reuters, Aug. 16, 2013. 30 13 Market Structure and Political Law from farmers about the conditions they faced. For many farmers, the opportunity was a lifeline. But in the days before the poultry hearing in Alabama, representatives from Tyson and Pilgrim’s Pride visited farmers to warn them that if they spoke out at the hearing they would face retaliation.32 As farmers at the hearing recounted, scores others had not shown up or were afraid to speak up because of the companies’ threats.33 Their economic dependence lost them their right to free speech and assembly. In other instances, companies like Tyson don’t need to exert their power; its sheer existence quells dissent. As Christopher Leonard describes in The Meat Racket: "[Perry] Edwards did not see any evidence that Tyson Foods delivered sick birds to Jerry and Kanita Yandell to retaliate against them for any perceived bad behavior. But what he observed was that the company had the ability to do so if it wanted to. Farmers around Waldron did not have the front-seat view of this power that Edwards was afforded. But they knew it existed. They felt it. They perpetually feared it. And for that reason, they often stifled their complaints and took what Tyson gave them."34 Political suppression is also common in union fights. For example, in 2012 a federal judge found that Target managers had threatened to discipline employees who talked about the union and threated to shut the store if workers voted in favor of unionization.35 Political power is also expressed through direct communication to employees about the political preferences of CEOs (an expression enabled by Citizens United). While the letters may not, according to law, intimidate the employees, they can strongly communicate a preference and give reasons. During the 2012 election, asked business owners to use their power in this way: "I hope you make it very clear to your employees what you believe is in the best interest of ... their job ... in the upcoming elections." Real estate developer David Siegel sent a long letter to his employees, telling them that if Obama won, he’d probably end up on a beach “without employees.” Steve Wynn sent a long voter guide to his employees. It is not clear that the crude tactic works: One Wynn resorts employee said, "Now that I'm being told who to vote for by my overlord, maybe I'll just vote for Obama." However, if employees either feel pressure, or are shaped in their choices, these communications act as a form of employer-employee political power. 5. Taxing It is widely established – both in antitrust theory and the world around us – that size and concentration correspond with market power. Market power enables a company to raise what it charges consumers and lower what it pays suppliers. The higher margins Lina Khan, “Obama’s Game of Chicken” Washington Monthly (November 2012). DOJ/USDA “Public Workshops Exploring Competition in Agriculture” http://www.justice.gov/atr/public/workshops/ag2010/alabama-agworkshop-transcript.txt 34 Christopher Leonard, The Meat Racket (2014), p. xx. 35 Steven Greenhouse, “Union Gets New Election at Target” New York Times, May 21, 2012. 32 33 14 Market Structure and Political Law that it pockets as a result transfer wealth from its business partners to its own account. It imposes a tax on those subject to its power. This wealth transfer empowers the company at the expense of its customers and suppliers, both politically and economically. Often times these transfers will accrue in fractions of pennies, almost imperceptibly. Barry C. Lynn recounts how Henry Osborne Havemeyer, after rolling up seventeen sugar refineries, astutely asked, “Who cares for a quarter cent of a pound?”: Havemeyer meant that he did not intend to use the power he had amassed over our supply of sugar to gouge us suddenly and violently. Rather, he intended to collect his quarter of a penny tax from us quietly and steadily, the same way our local governments collect a few pennies from us quietly and steadily every time we buy a Slurpee at 7-Eleven … For many decades, every time an American sprinkled some sugarcane crystals into his or her tea, Havemeyer and his family became just a bit richer and hence a bit more politically powerful than you and me.36 These wealth transfers are all the more subtle in dull and quotidian industries like, for example, container board, the corrugated material we use to box over 95 percent of all delivered packages in the US. As noted in a recent Goldman Sachs memo, steady consolidation since the 1990s has handed the top four companies control over 70 percent of the market, with the largest player alone holding 33 percent. In subsequent years the firms restricted supplies and raised prices. Margins spiked from 10 percent in 2003 to 18 percent last year – while the containerboard prices we all pay jumped 90 percent. Or take the seed industry, in which Monsanto controls upwards of 85 percent of genetic traits embedded in corn and soybeans, and together with DuPont sells 70 percent of all corn seed. Since its roll-up of independent seed companies, its net profits have grown from $2.67 million in 2003 to $2.5 billion last year – a staggering tenfold increase over ten years.37 The price farmers pay for corn seed, meanwhile, has shot up 166 percent since 2005.38 The wealth transfers in concentrated markets are political because they make big companies bigger, and hence more politically powerful. A robust antitrust regime that kept companies from ballooning into giants that extract monopoly rents would check their political power. Infinite Guises Our taxonomy illustrates how size absent competition can impose on the public a form of private governance. The power a dominant company exerts is unaccountable to citizens, yet determines and even constrains their actions. The first category – direct Barry Lynn, Cornered: The Rise of Monopoly Capitalism and the Economics of Destruction (2010), p. 48. 37 Emiko Terazono & Neil Munshi, “Monsanto at centre of intensifying debate on food” Financial Times, Feb. 26, 2014. 38 Jacob Bunge, “Big Data Comes to the Farm, Sowing Mistrust” Wall Street Journal, Feb. 25, 2014. 36 15 Market Structure and Political Law political intervention, and lobbying and media – capture how companies strive to influence the political process. This power is most discrete and discernible; projects like opensecrets.org devote significant resources tracking it. The last four categories – TBTF, regulation, and political punishment and tax – illustrate forms of political power exercised outside the traditional political process. This influence is won not just through size and capital but also – crucially – market structure. These forms of corporate power can undercut democratic self-governance in ways untouched by campaign finance reform. The political process isn’t the only highway to undue political control. In addition to operating outside of the traditional political process, this type of power is notable because its application doesn’t always require its active exercise. Power can arise purely out of dominance. As Justice Louis Brandeis expressed it: Restraint of trade may be exerted upon rivals; upon buyers or upon sellers; upon employers or upon employed. Restraint may be exerted through force or fraud or agreement. It may be exerted through moral or through legal obligations; through fear or through hope. It may exist, although it is not manifested in any overt act, and even though there is no intent to restrain. Words of advice, seemingly innocent and perhaps benevolent, may restrain, when uttered under circumstances that make advice equivalent to command. For the essence of restraint is power; and power may arise merely out of position. Wherever a dominant position has been attained, restraint necessarily arises.” In other words, power can be experienced without being exercised. Our taxonomy is not exhaustive, and could never be, precisely because power exerts itself in infinite and subtle guises. That this power still threatens democratic self-government – even when it doesn’t manifest as a concrete schemes or donation – suggests that reformers should look beyond simply policing activity. They should also target structural advantages that derive from concentration and size. Dynamic Interactions Between Factors In our view, these five sources of power are likely to interact dynamically with each other. There are several factors that should influence the decision of whether to invest explicitly in politics, including: the potential value of the political decision, the presence of powerful allies, the ease of organizing competitors within industry, the degree to which opponents are organized, the size of perceived threat to decision-makers, the absolute cost of political spending, the relative cost of political spending as compared to opponents, the economies of scale of political spending, the creation of political connections that can be re-used, the degree to which subsidy-enabled growth will decrease future political spending, and the society-wide economic dependency upon the company. Many of these factors are a function of, or correlated with, company size or market concentration. Likewise, control over suppliers, influence over employers, the capacity to tax, and structural dependencies are correlated with each other and arguably functions of each other. In The Logic of Collective Action, Olson explained why a small, wellorganized group, is more likely than a large, dispersed group, to invest in political 16 Market Structure and Political Law activity.39 It is simpler and cheaper to organize a group when the potential members are few--in other words, when the market is monopolistic or oligopolistic.40 Because of fewer actors the industries can more easily solve collective action problems. They can more easily make joint strategic decisions about what to demand, and create a shared, consistent message when lobbying and in meetings. They can more cheaply share the costs of identifying shared needs, the costs of coordinated timing, the cost of identifying and punishing free-riders (though free riding seems to operate in lobbying in a different way), and it makes it easier to share fixed costs, like writing legislation, identifying targeted politicians, and producing effective messaging. With these shared political goals, transaction and coordination costs would be less in a concentrated industry than in a highly distributed industry. The concentrated industry therefore can more cheaply seek out shared goals, including increasing barriers to entry to the industry, decreasing taxes for the industry, increasing subsidies for the industry, and creating public insurance for the industry. Furthermore, there are several aspects of overt political investment that require intensive start up costs, and bear fruit only after several years of investment. Lobbying can be an extraordinarily lucrative investment. A recent study last year found the rate of return on lobbying expenditures (on a corporate tax break) at about 220:1.41 However, in other areas there is relatively little payoff, and changing political climates make it risky. The same can be said for all political ventures--external factors, and the essential uncertainty, can make political engagement dangerous for companies that cannot ride out major political upheavals. Therefore, economies of scale, capital cushions, and external sources of stability could be important in both explaining who lobbies, and predicting who will lobby in the future. The relationship between size, scale and concentration has been the subject of empirical research for years. While the results are equivocal, some evidence suggests that concentration and lobbying activity are related.42 Another study showed that companies in more concentrated industries make greater campaign contributions.43 However, the weight of the evidence suggests that size and political activity are related. In a 2003 study, sample firms with PACs had assets significantly higher than sample firms without PACs (slightly under twice as large), though the largest firms did not have PACs.44 39 Several years later he described the pathologies of the rent-seeking political culture in The Rise and Decline of Nations. Taking Olson seriously, then, Wesee our task as solving collective action problems for those who most need it, and creating collective action problems to make rentseeking more difficult. 40 Mancur Olson, Logic of Collection Action, 9-16, 22-65 (1971) 41 Raquel Alexander, Stephen W. Mazza, Susan Scholz, Measuring Rates of Return on Lobbying: Empirical Case Study of Tax Breaks for Multinational Corporations, 25 J. L. & POLITICS 401 (2009). 42 See Jeffrey Drope and Wendy Hansen, New Evidence for the Theory of Groups: Trade Association Lobbying in Washington, D.C., 62 POLITICAL RESEARCH QUARTERLY 2 303-316 (2009). Wewill augment this in future drafts. 43 Pittman (1976); Hill (2011). 44 Sanjay Gupta and Charles W. Swenson, Rent-Seeking by Agents of the Firm, 46 J.L. & ECON. 253, 260 (.2003) 17 Market Structure and Political Law The number of corporations that regularly engage in federal lobbying is under 500, and almost all of them are extremely large. A recent survey of lobbying in the United States found that about one in 10 firms engage in lobbying, but that the strongest determinant of the likelihood of lobbying was firm size. There are about 300 persistent repeat players in lobbying in Washington, and they are all large, and they tend to lobby year after year. The likelihood that a firm will lobby, in short, is defined by size and whether it lobbied the prior year.45 It appears that there is an initial decision, largely driven by the high fixed costs associated with lobbying, to become a political organization; once a corporation has made that commitment, it does in effect become a political organization, as opposed to an ad-hoc purchaser of political goods. An in-depth study of over 6,000 publicly traded companies’ reported lobbying activity from 1999 to 2006 showed that corporate lobbying is directly related to firm size.46 Much of the research is in “transitional economies.” One recent study of 3,954 firms in 25 transition economies found that size was the most significant factor predicting whether or not a firm would be part of a lobby group. They coded large firms as firms with greater than 200 employees, and medium firms as firms with between 50 and 199 employees. They found that the firm being a large size increased the likelihood of joining a lobby by between 15 and 17%.47 Larger firms are also likely to have more politically connected directors.48 Economies of scale in rent-seeking have been noticed in the oligarchical efforts of the Argentinian patria and the transition-era oligarchs in Russia.49 Unfortunately these studies represent the best research on industry size, structure, and rent-seeking50 More research could be done around concentration and rent-seeking (although still spare), using a variety of tools to measure market structure, and more research could be done around mixed strategies, instead of looking at merely isolated forms of political involvement (lobbying or campaign contributions). Companies treat these strategies as tools, not the strategy themselves, so studies comparing “tool use” are less valuable than studies that look at overall political investment. 45 William R. Kerr, William F. Lincoln, PrachweMishra, The Dynamics of Firm Lobbying, NBER Working Paper Series (Nov. 11) http://www.nber.org/papers/w17577. 46 Matthew D. Hill, G. Wayne Kelly, G. Brandon Lockhart, and Robert A. Van Ness, Determinants and Effects of Corporate Lobbying (published on SSRN). Wehave included a copy of Hill et al’s table on the last page so that the numbers can be examined critically. They measure size in terms of assets. 47 Nauro F. Campos, Franceso Giovannoni, Lobbying, Corruption, and Political Influence, 13 PUBLIC CHOICE 1-21 (2007). 48 Agrawal and Knoeber (2001). 49 http://mpra.ub.unimuenchen.de/22561/1/THE_ECONOMIC_TRANSITION_OF_CHINA_AND_USSR.pdf (discussing economies of scale in rent-seeking in transitional Russia); COLUMBIA JOURNAL OF EUROPEAN LAW SPRING, 2010 Article REEVALUATING THE EVIDENCE FOR ANTICOMMONS IN TRANSITION RUSSIA Brian Sawers (2010). http://nd.edu/~kellogg/publications/workingpapers/WPS/250.pdf (discussing efforts to maximize economies of scale in rent-seeking in 90s Argentina) 50 This is much lamented, but little corrected. See, e.g., DanweRodrik Political Economy of Trade Policy, (1995) (“On industry structure it is perhaps disappointing that the empirical literature is not more clear cut on the political advantages of high concentration…”) 18 Market Structure and Political Law When Are Corporations Political Organizations? There is no consensus on what constitutes “political,” 51yet there is relatively little debate about what constitutes political organization. There are different ways to come at the question, “What is political?” We might, for instance, reject the idea of the nonpolitical altogether, in which case every corporation, regardless of its features is political, along with every other societal institution. One version of this thesis – which appears glibly as “the personal is political” – is grounded in the fact that all human interactions involve some degree of (by virtue of inter-action) of influence. Another version is more contextual, and notes that all private power in a modern democracy is backed by police power. We might, alternately, name that as political only those institutions which are either cloaked in authority, or are designed to overtly influenced those in authority. Ayn Rand, exhibiting the second view, argued that: "The difference between political power and any other kind of social “power,” between a government and any private organization, is the fact that a government holds a legal monopoly on the use of physical force.” We find both of these characterizations unsatisfactory. The first may be true, but collapses the social role of the word “political” and makes it unintelligible and not useful. We disagree with Rand in this way: When a corporation starts establishing a monopoly, it starts to become political. For instance, if there is only one seller of all books, that seller starts to become like the government. It is capable of exercising arbitrary power over the content of our books. It is less troubling than governmental power, because it is not backed by physical force (no one gets shot who sells alternative books) but it is more troubling than government because it is unaccountable. If it is the only bookseller with capacity to distribute, it could choose to distribute only Ayn Rand, or no Ayn Rand at all. The fact that a theoretical market entrant might exist, when as a practical matter none does, means that we are subject to arbitrary power. Instead, we turn to the dictionary. The political encompasses: “the activities associated with the governance of a country or other area, especially the debate or conflict among individuals or parties having or hoping to achieve power.” Using this definition, we are interested in corporations that either seek to control government, or seek to govern themselves. We also turn--with no little irony--to the Supreme Court’s explicitly conclusion that corporations are political entities. In Citizens United, the Court held that a law limiting uncoordinated speech that was designed to elect or defeat candidates violated the First Amendment. The Court rested its opinion on a few concerns. First, the court was concerned about the engagement of government in deciding who can and cannot speak. Second, the Court was concerned about limiting the associational rights of corporations. Third, the Court was troubled that limitations by the state would undermine. In expressing these concerns, the Court did not deny that corporate spending might have an 51 Amitai Etzioni, What is Political? 19 Market Structure and Political Law impact on legislators. However, because that impact would not be explicitly corrupting, the impact did not weigh against the speech interest. But for the purposes of this paper, what is most important is that the court adopted a view that corporations should be political organizations in order to question, and check, the power of government. The court called corporate independent spending “indispensable to decision-making” in a democracy.52 The Supreme Court legitimated and elevated political activity by corporations. In this passage, for instance, the Court gives moral meaning to political engagement: “By suppressing the speech of manifold corporations, both for-profit and nonprofit, the Government prevents their voices and viewpoints from reaching the public and advising voters on which persons or entities are hostile to their interests.”53 After Citizens United v. FEC, the official political theory of the United States is that corporations are much like—if not exactly like—political parties or labor unions or other entities that are an essential part of the political architecture of the country. The irony, of course, is that in validating and elevating corporate political life, the opinion greatly enhanced the instances of corporate political life. It made it much easier to use money for political influence, and makes political engagement (that was previously barely legal) much less risky, because it lessens the risk of litigation. It had an indirect impact on the political culture of corporations. It turned corporate involvement in elections from a loophole-seeking practice to a practice endorsed by the Supreme Court. Inasmuch as corporate management avoids political engagement, the Court’s endorsement sends a signal to corporate leaders that political engagement is not a barelylegal activity, but a fully endorsed aspect of corporate structure, and might be mandatory. However, under any theory, not all corporations are political. Colgate, Apple, Microsoft, Lockheed Martin—all are corporations that have committed to political activity and have made political activity and the effort to influence governmental decision-makers an essential part of their institutional structure. They do not claim a general authority to legislate over the society, but they are structured in part to influence those bodies who do claim a general authority, and exercise real, meaningful political power. They sometimes exert this influence in sophisticated and indirect ways, through funding nonprofit groups who then lobby in favor of their position.54 In function, therefore, it makes sense to describe them as political organizations. The archetypal political organization is the political party, but close to that core are labor unions, PACs, and policy groups with a legislative agenda. Political philosopher Joseph Raz has defined political organizations55 in contrast to political institutions. Political institutions make claims to authority and legitimacy, whereas political organizations do not.56 “By political institution,” he writes, “We refer to the state and its organs, but also, more broadly, to all public authorities.” Therefore, “not all political organizations are political institutions.”57 In his definition, a political organization 52 53 Id.(citing Bellotti, 435 U. S., at 777) Id. Eric Lipton, “Comcast’s Web of Lobbying and Philanthropy” New York Times, February 20, 2014 http://www.nytimes.com/2014/02/21/business/media/comcasts-webof-lobbying-and-philanthropy.html 54 55 Josef Raz, The Morality of Freedom p. 5 (1988) 56 Id. 57 Raz, supra p. 3. 20 Market Structure and Political Law attempts to pressure political institutions through elections, lobbying and media engagements. Raz provides a negative starting point, but he was defining political organization in order to cordon it off from political institution, not so much to investigate the shape of what constitutes a political organization. 58 Instead, for the term “political organization” to have meaning, there should be some measure of non-incidental political entanglement. One could, for instance, measure purpose as evidenced by institutional structure. In other words, a medium sized company with no lobbying arm, no public affairs department, no PAC, and no policy pushed through media would not be a “political organization.”59 By this defintion, most American companies are not political organizations. However, a tiny arms sales company that is set up in order to lobby for specialized contracts from the government, but fails in such efforts, would be a political organization. So is a company like Comcast, that exercises monopoly power in many markets, or a company like Tyson, that uses its relationship to its producers for political ends. Substantial direct political expenditures are a sign that something is a political organization. For our definition, a political organization is an institution that: (a) does not claim a general authority to legislate over the society and (b) is structured in part to influence those bodies who do claim a general authority or (c) despite not being so structured, is routinely protected by authority-wielding figures.60 or (d) by the nature of control it exerts over society, partially governs it. In short, a political organization is one with a power-seeking structure, or actual power, but that lacks public authority. The “structure” test, (b), is suited to current understanding of the term political. The “political impacts” test, (c) allows for considering a large company whose presence was constantly on the mind of, and influencing the decisions of, lawmakers. (Otherwise that would not be a “political organization”, and the small, impotent, political party would not be a “political organization.”) Some economic research suggests that indirect and direct forms of political control are connected. Mara Faccio showed how politically connected firms have higher 58 He was interested in the relative lack of accountability of political organizations as compared to political institutions, but, interestingly, assumed a level of internal political accountability in passing when discussing political organizations (see, Morality of Freedom, “The power of these organizations means that their actions impact many. They must therefore give adequate weight to the interest of those individuals when deciding on their actions.”) 59 Weleave aside for now the question of whether search engines and other content-rich companies with strong first amendment roles might be “political organizations” in another sense. E.g., whether Facebook was a political organization prior to setting up a public affairs office in DC. 60 (This is not to be confused with the statutory definition of political organization, which are “organized and operated primarily to accept contributions and make expenditures for the purpose of influencing the “selection, nomination, election, or appointment of any individual to Federal, State, or local public office or office in a political organization, or the election of Presidential electors.”) See 527 21 Market Structure and Political Law market shares.61 One would anticipate that, in part as a matter of personality--those insiders who are involved in business as a form of power, instead of as a form of entrepeneurship, are more likely to be drawn to direct political investment and capturing a controlling market share out of the same impulse. Alternatively, the correlation could be merely a function of Mancur Olson’s thesis: large market share makes the purchase of power easier. Regardless of the mechanism, the overlap between different forms of power makes it easier to classify those corporations which are fundamentally, structurally political, and separate them from those who are fundamentally, structurally non-political. Incidental Political Impacts So far we have talked about when individual corporations are political. However, there are other incidental political impacts of market structure on political society as a whole, that are not captured by the five ways in which power is directly impacted. The non-strategic use of the revolving door leads to ideological change within regulatory agencies exercising power. In a concentrated market, regulators pull from a small set of companies to staff their work. Those companies--such as Goldman Sachs--tend to inculcate their employees with a set of beliefs about the way the world works. Furthermore, for democratic self-government to work, society must be populated by people who are educated enough to know the relationship between policies and their impacts, and be somewhat capable of imagining other policies or other impacts. There is something harder to capture than information alone that is critical for successful selfgovernment—it is a sense among the governed that they are fundamentally competent to challenge the decisions of the representatives, and that they experience actual power in the political process. Without this experience of power citizens will engage in the most trivial of ways—voting—and their ability to govern themselves will be limited by the choices presented by those in power. The experience of power cannot be taught by a textbook—it is a habit of power, and judgment, and decision-making. Of course the most extreme Jeffersonian view is that self-government requires a country of yeoman farmers, who are trained and accustomed to power.62 John Stuart Mill and William Greider have also argued that the experience people have 364 days a year necessarily impacts how they conduct themselves on the one day a year when they vote; if someone is constantly told what to do, not allowed to question authority, punished for raising complaints and rewarded for docility in all other aspects of their lives—how should we expect them, when they encounter a Congress member on the street, to ask about why the new health care law does not provide for dental policy, even if the daily obsession with their private life is the inability to pay for dental care, and rants to her husband about the inanity of the policy?63 This experience of power is directly related to corporate structure. When there are bigger businesses, there are fewer people in management positions, and more people who have no daily relationship to power. There are fewer people who work with and witness Mara Faccio, Differences between Politically Connected and Non-Connected Firms: A Cross-Country Analysis, 39 Fin. Mgt. 905-927 61 Benjamin F. Wright, "The Philosopher of Jeffersonian Democracy," American Political Science Review Vol. 22, No. 4 (Nov., 1928), pp. 870-892. 63 See, e.g. William Greider, WHO WILL TELL THE PEOPLE (Simon & Schuster, 1993). 62 22 Market Structure and Political Law executive decision-making. Imagine 5 major tire companies in this country, instead of 1,000, and 5 executives instead of 1,000. If evenly distributed over the 50 states there would be 20 executives in each state willing to challenge political power, instead of 5 states with executives, and 45 with none. Setting aside their expertise in tires, those 20 executives can be political presences in every major city in the country, both exhibiting and modeling the vibrant sense of self that is required for true self-government. If one out of every 20 people in a society is in a decision-making role, that mode of thought—of responsibility taking—has a chance of being part of the civic culture. The culture of responsibility taking infuses itself in deep ways into our lives, and changes our internal grammar from “x is happening to me” to “I am part of changing x.” That habit of grammar then translates from one sphere of power to another. Hannah Arendt equates politics is freedom, and what happens when people come together and ask, “what should we do?” expressing their own freedom to ask that question and then follow that question with action.64 The habit of that freedom in economic life is not easily separated from that habit of freedom in public life. The internal grammar of the private decision-maker bleeds into the internal grammar of the citizen—when it is fluent with power in one sphere, it bleeds to the other. Structural Intervention To reiterate the argument of the introduction, our goal is to understand market structure as part of democratic design. Once we see institutions as political, instead of non-political, different forms of structural intervention might seem legitimate that might be cast as illegitimate if they were mere market intervention. Elections are political institutions, and the particular design choices about them have deep political impacts. For example, the date of elections, the form of the ballot, the form of registering to vote, and questions about who can appear on the ballot are deeply important questions of democratic design. Congressional districts are political institutions, and over the last 200 years, their size, shape, and type (single member/multimember) have been changing. Congress is a political institution, and each state house is a political institution, and municipal governments are political institutions. In designing their size, qualifications, and rules regarding government are fundamental questions of democratic design. In shaping political institutions, questions of size and scale are recurrent themes. Since the days of Aristotle, who believed that a polity should never be so large that all its citizens couldn’t hear the same morning bugle, these highly technical questions of size have been front and center in institutional design. Should a state legislature have a representative for every 5,000 people, or 50,000? How should campaigns be funded, and what should be the maximum amount of contributions allowed by individuals? How frequently should elections be held? How should district size be determined? All of these are basic questions of democratic design surrounding political institutions. Similar kinds of questions should be addressed to corporate size. Given this proposed definition, there are actually relatively few corporations that are political organizations in the United States, and most of them are very large and most 64 Hannah Arendt, THE PROMISE OF POLITICS (Random House Digital, Inc., Jun 19, 2007). 23 Market Structure and Political Law of them have hints of monopolization. Corporations’ role as potential political organizations was endorsed by the political theory of the majority of the United States Supreme Court in Citizens United v. FEC. “Corporations and other associations, like individuals, contribute to the ‘discussion, debate, and the dissemination of information and ideas’ that the First Amendment seeks to foster.”65 A great deal of thought has gone into how political parties are structured, how they are funded, and their relationships to candidates. Their status as political organizations has been enshrined by the Supreme Court, which recognizes a special role for political parties, considering them essential in modern American democracy. Once we understand corporations as political organizations, the same kind of attention to their structure is merited. However, up to now, in the public debate about money, power, influence politics, most structural reforms have focused on Congress, and on the laws governing elections. Publicly funded elections, filibuster reform, and transparency tend to be congress-centric. Alternatively, laws designed to increase ballot box access, reform gerrymandering, or include mail-in ballots are election-process centric. Election law scholars debate how campaigns should work to minimize corruption, what role parties should have, and the role of the media. But in all these areas the attention is focused on one or two discrete kinds of levers. Moreover, scholars who might otherwise be interested in the problems caused by asymmetrical lobbying, instead throw up their hands because when it comes to lobbying, it is hard to imagine anything but transparency doing any good, and it is unclear that transparency has any meaningful effect. In fact, outside of campaign finance, scholars might be willing see a problem, but throw up their hands and return to questions of campaign finance restrictions, because it is inconceivable that there would be restrictions on lobbying.66 Consider the two dominant trends within democracy reformers: public choice deregulators and progressive campaign finance reformers. To date, the classic public choice response has tended to be recommending a diminution of regulatory power—the idea being that the less power there is to be exercised, the less that companies will spend energy rent-seeking.67 This solution has so dominated the discourse that the two are seen as intertwined. The more left wing campaign finance reformer has tended to focus on laws limiting spending and donations and certain kinds of coordinated activity. Enormous creativity has gone into exploring rules which might discourage certain kinds of flows of money into the political system.68 These efforts have undoubtedly had some impact, but the ability of the campaign finance reformer to enact limits on money flowing into politics has been hobbled since Buckley v. Valeo, and the recent Citizens United Supreme Court decision gave the Supreme Court’s imprimatur to unlimited corporate spending Citizens United v. FEC, 130 S.Ct. 876, 900 (U.S.,2010)(quoting Bellotti, 435 U.S., at 783, 98 S.Ct. 1407)). 66 Kathleen Sullivan, Political Money and Freedom of Speech, 30 U.C. Davis L. Rev. 663, 673 (1997). See also Briffault, supra. 67 See, e.g. George J. Stigler, ed, Chicago Studies in Political Economy (U Chicago, 1988); Dennis Meuller Public Choice IIWe(2003). 68 The ones Wefind most compelling are those that provide matching funds for low dollar contributions, as they incentivize the most responsive politicking. 65 24 Market Structure and Political Law around elections. The Super PACS that are dominating the 2012 Presidential campaign are evidence that existing limits on corporate spending in politics are likely not that effective over time. “Like water seeking its own level, private money will inexorably flow around reformist barriers to overwhelm the political process.”69 The public choice theorist has tended to reject campaign finance laws, and the campaign finance reformer has tended to ignore lobbying—despite the evidence that companies spend more on lobbying than they do on funding campaigns.70 Arguably, the avoidance of each of these areas derives from a sense of hopelessness in the face of First Amendment protections, which in turn leads to intellectual avoidance.71 Joseph Stiglitz defended the avoidance in a way that might speak to both groups: Redistributions are the consequences of special interest groups using the powers of the state to reap private gains at the expense of the general public. These redistributions are not only inequitable, they are also inefficient. They are not only inefficient because of the rent-seeking expenditures that the special interest groups make in the quest for special treatment; they are also inefficient because the equity constraint results in government programs that are ill-suited to any “rational” objective. There is, alas, no way in a democratic society to proscribe such activities. There is no obvious way to distinguish these activities from more “legitimate” activities.72 Faced with this sense that there is “no obvious way to distinguish” between “good” and “bad” lobbying, there is a limit to what government-facing government reform can do. Reformers from the left tend to propose contribution limits, transparency, and matching funds’ systems. Reformers from the right tend to propose limiting the size of government. Both have been stymied in recent years as the regulatory state grows, and limits on campaign cash have proven weak. Instead of government facing rules, then, we should start looking at structural corporate rules that dis-incentivize rent-seeking and encourage entrepreneurialism. Both groups have focused far less on corporate law itself, and it is the argument of this paper that perhaps corporate structure might help the left and right both achieve theirs stated goals. An explicit recognition that many corporations are political organizations opens up a new category of structural changes that might improve representative government and engagement. It enables one to think about incentives and disincentives for investment in lobbying, for example, not by focusing on lobbying, but 69 Voting with Dollars, A New Paradigm for Campaign Finance, Ian Ayres and Bruce Ackerman, The dominant casebook on the law of the political process, does not include a discussion of lobbying in the section on money and politics. Isacharoff, Karlan, and Pildes, The Law of Democracy (3rd Edition, 2007). 71 Since the early 20th century, lobbying laws have been largely off-limits, except inasmuch as they require transparency. This was not always true—many states outlawed lobbying in the 19th century, and the Supreme Court once refused to enforce a contract to lobby as deeply repugnant to civic decency and threatening to our political institutions. See Trist v. Child, 88 U. S. 441 (1974). 72 Stiglitz (1989). This is a version of what Justice Kennedy argued in Citizens United—there is no way to distinguish between the corporate-owned New York Times spending money around elections and the corporate-owned Bank of America spending money around elections. 70 25 Market Structure and Political Law by looking at how corporate size, scope, and industry concentration interacts with lobbying to either encourage more or less of it. The corporate form is a tool that encourages a particular set of structures. It provides subsidies for certain business activities in exchange for public goods that would not be created by the government. Corporate charters can be as expansive or restrictive as we want them to be – they can have charters that expire after 5 years – the liability can be as limited as we want it to be. If we want, groups can only get corporate charters for carbon-neutral businesses. Instead of focusing solely on Congress, the recognition of the corporation as a potential political organization allows for a more imaginative approach to the puzzles of representation. In teaching the law of politics, it is difficult to paint a fair picture of the ecosystem of forces that interplay around an election without a deeper understanding of the political organizations of corporations, yet the classic portrait painted in election law course-books spends most of its energy on the internal structure and decision-making of one set of important political actors—those with the political organizations known as political parties—and only a passing glance at the internal structure and decision-making of other sets of important political actors, like media companies and corporations. This leads to extensive examination of the rules governing one set of political actors, and almost no examination of the rules governing another. Conclusion The foregoing suggests that democracies with a small number of large corporate enterprises will be less representative than democracies with a large number of companies, none of which are too big to fail, but which compete against each other. Larger companies in non-competitive industries are less likely to spend their energies on product development than on political capture—therefore leading to individuals and noncorporate associations having a greater relative voice. One would expect that a concentrated economic structure would have a much smaller percentage of the total money spent on getting political favors coming from citizens, instead of companies. There are different ways to get to a political economy dominated by small businesses through limits. One could, for example, institute a tax policy that put a tax on bigness—it could be a sliding scale, to disincentive size. Or one could act merely in regard to companies of the future, and have a strong anti-merger policy. Or one could criminalize large size. In addition to targeting size, one could also try to limit political economic dominance. The political power that companies exercised in the examples above derived from their dominance – or the degree to which other actors depended on them –not just their size. To address dominance regulators could learn from network dependence theory, for example, which assesses the level of power any one player has over another by viewing their structural dependency. An approach that included this wider frame would be equipped to tackle monopsony, a major blindspot in current antitrust practice. Most of this paper has been theoretical, but the issues it addresses are very current. Six banks largely control the financial industry. In agriculture, retail and manufacturing there are relatively few companies, each of which has enormous political and economic 26 Market Structure and Political Law power. Mammoth companies are not creating enough social value to merit the costs of their size, increasingly spending their money on rent-seeking. Existing antitrust is far too feeble for the task. The public choice theorists who effectively killed it didn’t realize that true antitrust, was actually their own intellectual father—the tool that could lead to market competitiveness and reduce the amount of concentrated money spent influencing government at the same time. And yet the ghost of antitrust has never quite fully realized haunts the landscape. Brandeis was skeptical of size, in part because he thought gigantism was a kind of mark of Cain—a company couldn’t get large but through sinning of some kind. After the Supreme Court’s decision in Citizens United there are no meaningful limits on how much money a company can spend influencing elections, and all forms of electioneering are considered virtuous according to the Court. But now we are dealing with virtuous monsters like Google, or Apple, along with the less virtuous ones who may or may not have committed securities fraud. You can see the American impulse to antitrust appearing in Jonathan Macey’s recent article about limiting bank size, in Tim Wu’s concerns in the Master Switch, in the financial journalist Barry Lynn’s book Cornered, in Robert Reich’s support for breaking up banks, even in Alan Greenspan suggesting that companies too big to fail are too big to exist. And this impulse is gradually creeping out and finding its way into legislation. During the financial reform fight, Senator Sherrod Brown of Ohio and Senator Ted Kaufman of Rhode Island proposed a simple new law that the New York Times endorsed. They wanted to put a cap on bank size. Brown/Kaufman would have made it illegal for any financial institution to have non-deposit liabilities (basically debts and obligations) bigger than 2-3% of GDP. This is a good start but far too small. The largest limited liability companies are too complex to manage, too difficult to regulate, and are often effectively immune from criminal prosecutions. Their size allows them to operate outside of normal democratic constraints, and their use of their economic power for political rents undermines our democracy. We should turn to a true, new antitrust to break them up. 27