1 I, Burocrat Rough Draft not well known. According to the Three Laws a public administrator must: Abstract I argue for a distinction between accountability and responsibility, revisiting the historic Joachim Friedrich-Herman Finer on the nature of public administration. In these pages “accountability” means giving an account for one’s actions or inactions to another. In the case of public administration that other is the hierarchically superior, the ultimate superior being the government of the day embodied in a minister. “Responsibility” means feeling responsible for one’s action or inactions so as to insure that they met a professional, external standard which includes neutrality. Accountability serves best to limit actions and insure a minimum compliance. It is one proof against corruption. Responsibility serves to elicit dedication and creativity from public administrators to deal with the complexities of reality. The conclusion is that both have a role to play that is best understood if they are distinguished. The argument is made through a fictitious Wikipedia entry from the future which assumes that only accountability counts! Sometimes we best understand the value of something we take for granted when it is gone. In this entry responsibility has evaporated. “I, burocrat” Wikipedia entry, 2076 The purpose of this Wikipedia entry is to recover the origins of the Three Laws of burocratics. For while the laws are the backbone of our system of government their origin is 1. not harm a minister, or, through inaction, allow a minister to come to harm. 2. obey the orders of a minister except where such orders would conflict with the First Law. 3. protect its own existence, as long as such protection does not conflict with the First or Second Law. Each law is set within the knowledge a public administrator has at the time. The origin of the Three Laws begins more than a hundred years ago. The story begins in 1937 when Carl Friedrich, a professor of political science at Harvard University, initiated, apparently unintentionally, a sharp debate with Herman Finer on the relationship between ministers and public servants. Because Friedrich wrote from an American context and Finer in the English context, there were differences of nomenclature. To be clear, let us start with definitions of these basic terms. In this entry a minister is a politician who is a member of cabinet either by election to a seat and selection for cabinet or is appointed to cabinet by an elected politician like the United 2 States president. On the other hand, an administrator is a professional public servant. This distinction is made all the more important by the long running Canadian practice of referring to the administrative department head, who is a professional public servant, as the deputy minister. Let us set aside that confusion. In what follows a minister is a politician and an administrator is a career public servant. The few remaining historians of public administration trace the Three Laws of Burocratics back to this obscure debate. What was the debate about? The central issue in the debate can be phrased as a tension between accountability and responsibility. Friedrich inadvertently opened the debate saying that “a responsible person is one who is answerable for his acts to some other person or body, who has to give an account of his doings and therefore must be able to conduct himself rationally” (1935, 30). Finer, in commenting on this passage draws the conclusion that responsibility involves “a relationship of obedience” [emphasis added] to “an external controlling authority” (1936, 580). Friedrich goes on to say that “political responsibility based upon the election of legislatures and chief executives [has not] succeeded in permeating a highly technical, differentiated government service any more than the religious responsibility of well-intentioned kings” (1935, 31). That is to say that the supervision of elected legislatures and chief executive has been no more successful in controlling public administration than religious kings could infuse religion into their retainers. Finer takes the most serious umbrage with this observation, calling it “truly startling” (1936, 581). He goes on to declare it wrong and wrong. Finer crystallizes the difference between them as the difference between “a sense of duty” (Friedrich) and “the fact of responsibility” Finer. The sense of duty as Finer sees it is directed to a profession, one’s own conscience, or the public interest. Each of these three is abstract and ethereal. In contrast he asserts the fact of responsibility is obedience to explicit direction. Finer implicitly upholds the prevailing orthodoxy that politics and administration were to be sharply distinguished, the former to direct, the latter to obey (Goodnow 1900, 22). 3 For his part Friedrich argued that policy and administration blended together. Making policy dependant on administrative knowledge of practical details and likewise administration involved political judgement about what can be done and what cannot be done in context. Friedrich argued this case at a time of the expansion of government services in the early days of the Roosevelt Administration with a consequent focus on administration to deliver those services. Many of these services had a technical element understood directly by the administrator but only in outline by the minister. It was a prescient argument given the enormous expansion of government that shortly followed in remainder of the Great Depression, World War II, and the welfare state of the post war world. Finer likewise realizes the all-pervasive nature of government (Finer 1940, 336), and speaks of it providing 25% of the happiness of the people because it consumes 25% of the Gross National Product (Finer 1936, 572). The orthodox distinction between politics and administration traces back to Max Weber in Economy and Society (Fry and Nigro 1996 and Van Riper 1984). According to this distinction, politicians decide policy – what shall be done and how it shall be done – and administrators do it. There is a sealed door between the two worlds which opens only when politicians deliver orders to administrators. As Friedrich made these arguments based, in the main, on his observations in the United States they drew a sharp rebuttal from Herman Finer in the England. Further exchanges occurred, creating the FriedrichFiner debate. Many arguments were made in the debate but the key points provide the kernel of three laws of burocratics. Friedrich’s argument is descriptive and normative. Ministers cannot supervise public administrators in detail as a matter of fact, and they should not do so for that would stifle creativity in context. Finer’s reply was likewise descriptive and normative: ministers can and must supervise administrators. He argues that responsibility is an arrangement of correction and punishment including dismal (1940, 345). Ministers must supervise administrators in the name of democracy, as the elected representatives of the people. “Politicians and employees [administrators] are working not for the good of the public in the sense of what the public needs, 4 but of the wants of the public as expressed by the public” (emphasis in the original, Finer 1940, 337). Elections express what the public wants. Ministers can supervise administrators by giving clear directives and specifying not only what is to be done (policy) but how (administration) it is to be done. Finer argued that the exact obedience to orders is necessary (1940, 337) to make public administrators subservient to the elected assembly (1940, 338). In reply Friedrich argued that the span of activities, the technical and scientific aspects of many of them and the complexity of interaction among activities combine to limit political supervision. Better he argued to educate and motivate officials to act responsibly by increasing their professionalism through education. He says “Pious myth-makers continue to suppose that parliamentary responsibility is enough” (1940, 3). The reality is, he argues, that “even under the best arrangements a considerable margin of irresponsible conduct of administrative activities is inevitable” (1940, 3). He argues that neither the electorate nor the legislative assemblies can effectively bring out responsible conduct by close supervision. While popular and legislative supervision may suffice to keep government from doing wrong, they do no suffice to make it responsible. Obedience is at best a negative instrument to prevent corruption in his view. Friedrich continues, many errors trace back to contradictory and illdefined policy embodied n faulty legislation (1940, 4). In more contemporary terms we might say that they trace back to policy decisions made in haste to placate vested interests without regard to the wide implications, decisions made to surmount a crisis, decisions made without careful legislative draughtsmanship to avoid contradiction and duplication. Happily, we can say today that none of these kinds of decisions are now made. “Public policy, to put it flatly, is a continuous process, the formation of which is inseparable from its execution,” says Friedrich (1940, 6). It “is being formed as it is being executed, and it is likewise being executed as it is being formed. Politics and administration play a continuous role in both the formation and execution” (1940, 6). Though he acknowledges, that “there is probably more politics in the formation of policy, [and] more administration in the 5 execution of it” (1940, 6). He goes on to explain that many policies are not ordained at the stroke of legislative pen, but evolve slowly over time and administrative officials participate continuously and significantly in this process of evolving policy (1940, 7). Against such a reality, Friedrich argues that “a higher official will hesitate to reverse the decision of a lower official, when that lower officials has a better knowledge of the facts and the details (1941, 49). On the other hand, Friedrich does severally stress that where a rule exists it should be followed (1940, 16 and 1941, 54). With this background, the difference between Friedrich and Finer might be best understood by making a distinction between responsibility and accountability. Friedrich argues for responsibility, which includes an inner motivation, and Finer argues for accountability, a direct external accounting to another for one’s actions. Friedrich characterizes the differences as between enforcing responsible conduct (Finer) and eliciting responsible conduct (Friedrich). Enforcing takes the forms of explicit instructions and schedules of punishment for failure to obey. Eliciting takes the form of professionalizing public administration through training, education, and conditions of employment that give independence of a semijudicial kind (this latter, Friedrich 1935, 34). Friedrich concludes that enforcing can be effective for preventing undesirable actions like corruption, but only eliciting can be effective for securing good effects (1935, 33). Friedrich contends that bureaucracy exists to deal with needs identified by government and the challenge is make those functions effective, not to take power away from them (1940, 10) for fear of wrong doing. He continuously emphasizes technical knowledge, as the following paraphrased example shows: Take agricultural policy. It exists to help farmer weather drought and pestilence and other unanticipated calamities beyond individual control. A variety of programs are called into creation to meet this goal, crop reduction, price-fixing, monopoly marketing, and the like. Crop reduction in turn leads to processing taxes. These taxes require reports, inspections, and work sheets. In this evolving this process where does politics end and administration begin, asks Friedrich (140, 6)? At the bottom is the 6 technical knowledge mastered by the public administrator for whom that special expertise may be a life’s work, and this technical knowledge is derived from nature’s laws which are always enforced (1940, 12-13) even if inconvenient politically. Friedrich concludes that we need both political responsibility (Finer) and technical responsibility (Friedrich) (1940, 14). But we can no longer maintain the fiction that administration is aloof from politics and conversely that politics is apart from administration (1940, 15). Finer, likewise arrives at a moderate conclusion. He says that if the political neutrality of public administrators “should fall under suspicion, we should be faced with the social tragedy that the unskilled political ministers would hesitate to accept the skilled aid of the permanent experts” (1936, 586), a passage Friedrich might well have written. Yet Finer has argued throughout that the unskilled minister commands the skilled public administrator. He continues, the public administrator is not a moveable piece of furniture (1936, 586) nor an automaton (1936, 587). More significantly, he says, “I am willing to admit an external agency could not attend to every administrative particular without” damage, “some latitude must be given – both owing the technical impossibility of complete political coverage” (1940, 340, emphasis added). The result is that administration may include rules, says Finer, which look like legislation but its essence is that the administrator uses but derived authority (1940, 342, emphasis added). Had the argument ended there it might seem that Finer and Friedrich were “furiously agreeing.” However, Finer goes on to assert that those who take Friedrich’s view are antidemocratic (1940, 346) by placing some modicum of public administration beyond the explicit control of ministers. It has been argued that Friedrich’s view prevailed in the post-war years (O’Leary 2005) as the size of government grew. The 1930s, when this debate opened, saw the rise of European fascism, of which Finer was a close observer from London. His response to Friedrich is partly colored by that knowledge. On occasion he interprets the core of Friedrich’s argument to be anti-democratic. Specifically, Finer says inward responsibility is the hallmark of dictatorial systems and he goes on to mention Nazi government (1940, 336). The essence of democracy, Finer adds, is the 7 “primacy of the people over officeholders” (1941, 337), where elected member of parliament are the vice of the people and office holders are public administrators. Those administrators know better than the elected representatives of the people what is best and must act on that (technical) knowledge. In contrast, Finer argues, with Thomas Hobbes, that administrators are but the bone and sinew of the sovereign, which is the government-of-the-day; they are instruments, not agents. Theirs is not to reason why but to do as they are told even if it does not make sense in the local context for it may make sense in the larger context seen by the minister. That implicit reference to the mistaken Charge of the Light Brigade in the Crimean War leads one to thinks of the British army officers in World War I who stuck to plans in battle that were visibly failing in deference to a higher logic. For his part, Friedrich saw ministers and administrators as partners. The minister and administrator together pooling their knowledge to develop policy through interaction based on the experiences unique to each perspective. Administrators are responsible both for the letter and spirit of the directives they receive and accept. Moreover, once a policy is developed its implementation may require judgment in context rather as a physician make judgment about when to tell patients what they have to know to manage reactions. Thinking again of the experience of World War I (which neither writer mentions) brings to mind Field Marshal Graf Helmuth von Moltke’s maxim that “No battle plan survives contact with the enemy” that influenced German thinking in the War. Planning and preparation, it follows, must allow for flexibility when tested by reality. Likewise, one might image Friedrich thinking that no policy, however carefully developed, survives intact contact with the diverse heterogeneous reality of a continental federal system like the United States. Finer, surveying a smaller scope in a unity government, prefers the tight rein of control. Over the years these poles evolved, but nevertheless remained poles. On the one side there is Finer with a command and control concept of bureaucracy and on the other there is Friedrich with an entrepreneurial and flexible idea of bureaucracy. The Finer command and control approach places a near absolute priority on 8 obedience to instruction, while the Friedrich entrepreneurial and flexible model speaks of the discretion of administrators to adapt instruction to the hard ground of reality guided by a higher concept of the public interest or the common good that transcend the government of the day. Friedrich’s argument partly rested on the concept of a public interest or common good that stood apart from the government of the day and superordinate to it. Accordingly part of the duty of a public servant was to consider that enduring and general interest of the nation that transcended the political interest of the government of the day. In multi-cultural societies intellectuals soon conclusively demonstrated that there was no such thing as a public interest or common good. Without faith in the belief that some wider, deeper, and common interest united a people than the government of the day Friedrich’s arguments were weakened. (Curiously many of these same intellectuals decried government policies, programs, and practices, but as their arguments showed there was no master narrative to legitimate their criticisms, which then fell on deaf ears.) This argument took many twists and turns and government grew until the 1980s when the size of government itself became a cause of concern. The result was considerable re-thinking about the nature of government and led to many changes to reduce the size of government by adopting private business practices (making corporation out of public entities like airlines and telephone companies), contracting out pubic service to businesses, scaling back some services and the like. This is a well known story of the times. The search from the 1980s on was to bring to government market discipline that made business so flexible, responsive, effective, and cheap. The examples of that inspired this trend include Adelphia, Arthur Andersen, At&T Canada, Barrings, Enron, Global Crossing, Halliburton, Hollinger, Maxwell, NatWest, Nortel, Parmalat, Qwest, Sunbeam, Tyco, Waste Management, and World.Com. Interestingly enough, Finer and Friedrich both cited private business as instructive examples for public administration. When each looked at private business saw the parts that supported their case. Finer admired the discipline and direction of business governed by the price mechanism (1936, 583), while Friedrich praised the 9 resourcefulness and flexibility of business needed to win and keep customers (1940, 20). In the end the size of government was altered if not exactly reduced, and those who remained public administrators - defined as working directly for a minister or under a public service act came to be regarded as burocrats, though no historian as yet has been able to identify either the first time the term “burocrat” replaced “bureaucrat” in official communication, though they have been able to pinpoint the date when the Microsoft Word spellchecker came to accept it, as the 1st of July 2017 curiously coincident with the two hundredth anniversary of the first British North America Act. In time the relationship of ministers to administrators was codified into the Three Laws of burocratics “in a Civil Service where smooth and sociable performance was more useful than individualistic competence (Asimov 1959, 76). These laws were inspired by the three laws of robotics created by Isaac Asimov. While the public officials Asimov presents struggle with inner qualms about some of the laws they must enforce (1959, 32), the robots do not. When a human says in anger to a robot “Don’t ever do that it again!” The positronically mind robot replies “Never again insist on the observation of the law” (1959, 38)? “The essence of the robot lies in a completely literal interpretation of the universe” (1959, 102). In contrast, “a human being can recognize the fact that, on the basis of an abstract moral code, some laws may be bad ones and their enforcement unjust” (1959, 104). The Three Laws of Burocrats were designed to secure literal obedience and to relieve burocrats of conscience by defining their role as obedience only. Initially, the laws were rendered as absolute. Thus the first law prevented an administrator from obeying any instruction from a minister that an administrator had reason to think might possibly result in harm to the minister no matter what the odds were. Complete risk aversion. Harm itself had to be defined as loss of political legitimacy or authority. Thus a burocrat could not cooperate with a minister, like Roger Quaife portrayed in C P Snow’s historical novel, Corridors of Power who devises a high risk plan for unilateral nuclear disarmament, on the ground that the plan might well lead to the end of the minister’s career as it did in that case. Of 10 course, judging political harm is no easy matter. Complete risk aversion meant doing nothing. While that was an attractive option in time a half-way point was developed. The present state of affairs is that administrators must make the minister aware of potential political risks, however slight, and thereafter accept the minister informed direction. The strict constructionists of the Three Laws maintain that an administrator should interpret the First Law absolutely, while the revisionists contend that interpretation effectively freezes any change in policy, program, or practise. Strict constructionists agree that it does so and so prevents any change. Equally, the Second Law has been tested many times. It has been narrowed in meaning to obeying any directive from one’s superordinate ministers that is consistent with the law, relevant to the administrator’s statement of duties, and concerns the public business of the minister. Thus the minister cannot require a public administrator to perform sexual congress unless that is stipulated in the duty statement of the public servant or is included in the duties of the minister’s portfolio. Finally, the Third Law has preserved an ever decreasing number of public administrators employed under the public service act. Yet these law remain imperfect, for as Asimov (1959) has shown repeatedly, a burocrat may act against a minister unknowingly. This mistake occurs when a burocrat is but one set of hands among many and participates in a chain of events that bring harm to a minister. The last remaining Friedrichites marginalized in universities, have formulated but dared not publish a law prior to the First Law that they call the Zeroth Law. This unpromulgated law states that 0. A public administrator may not injure humanity, or, through inaction, allow humanity to come to harm. One sees immediately that this law would limit ministerial authority by making the judgment of utility – the public good – prior to the obedience of the First Law. And so a burocrat, acting on this law, might say “Perhaps my action was to your harm. I am sorry if the general good requires that,” (Asimov 1959, 237), chilling words no minister wishes to hear from a burocrat. No longer does a burocratic say, “No 11 Minister, I do not work for you; I work for the public interest. Friedrich quoted this passage from John Gaus (1936, 39-40) often: “the responsibility of the civil servant [Is] to the standards of his profession, in so far as those standards make for the public interest.” This is a corollary of the Zeroth Law in that it makes a separate and independent judgment by the public servant necessary. Moreover, it takes the exclusive judgment of utility from the minister alone and makes the administrator responsible, at least in part for making a concurring judgment about the public good. This ridiculous idea is maintained only by a few irrelevant professors. References Asimov, Isaac (1959) Caves of Steel. New York, Doubleday. Asimov, Isaac (1956) The Naked Sun. New York, Doubleday. Finer, H. (1936). "Better Government Personnel." Political Science Quarterly 51(4): 569-599. Finer, H. (1940). "Administrative responsibility in democratic government." Public Administration Review 1(4): 335-350. Friedrich, C. J. (1935). Problems of the American public service. New York, McGraw-Hill. Friedrich, C. J. (1937). Constitutional government and politics; nature and development. New York, Harper. Friedrich, C. J. (1940). Public policy and the nature of administrative responsibility. Public Policy: a yearbook of the Graduate School of Public Administration. C. J. Friedrich and E. Mason. Boston, Harvard University Press. 1: 3-24. Fry, B. R. and Nigro L.G. (1996). Max Weber and US public administration: the administrator as neutral servant, Journal of management history, 2 (1), 37-46. Gaus, John (1936). The responsibility of public administration, The Frontiers of Public Administration. (Chicago: University of Chicago Press). Goodnow, Frank (1900) Politics and Administration. New York: Macmillan, 1900). O'Leary, R. (2005). The Ethics of Dissent. Washington, D.C. Congressional Quarterly. 12 Van Riper, P.P. (1984). The politicsadministration dichotomy: concept or reality? In Rabin, J., Bowman J.S. (eds), Politics and Administration: Woodrow Wilson and American Public Administration. New York: Marcel Dekker, 17-30.