SECTION: Theories of European Integration DO WE NEED THEORY? GOVERNANCE AND DEMOCRATIC THEORY AS THEORETICAL UNDERPINNINGS FOR THE UNDERSTANDING OF THE EUROPEAN UNION Working paper ECPR - Fifth Pan-European Conference on EU Politics Porto, 2010 Cláudia Toriz Ramos Universidade Fernando Pessoa (UFP) – Porto cramos@ufp.edu.pt Abstract: Increasingly, the ‘fate’ of the European Union (EU) has been debated in terms of a democratic polity in the making, although one that is a new political creature, rather than a polity designed according to extant political models. Far from being purely descriptive, this view is theoretically inscribed in non state-centric views of the EU, namely in the multi-level governance approach. Concomitantly, theorisation on a hypothetical political community underpinning EU’s democratic legitimacy has evolved and widely resorts to interpretations based on the theory and practice of democracy under the archetypes of representative as well as direct democracy. I argue that the crossing of both frameworks of analysis – i.e. governance and democratic theory – brings further contribution mutually to understanding the European Union and to normative uses at the level of EU building. Keywords: governance; multi-level governance; democracy; legitimacy INTRODUCTION ‘Democratic governance assumes distinct political norms and rules. Government becomes (at least in part) a trusteeship based on fiduciary arrangements and the democratic quality of a polity depends on properties of its citizens and officials. A spirit of citizenship and public office implies willingness to think and act as members of the political community and to follow rules of appropriate behaviour, as defined by the community, and not to act solely as self-interested individuals or members of particular interest groups.’ (Olsen, 2007: 8) Increasingly, the ‘fate’ of the European Union (EU) has been debated in terms of a democratic polity in the making, although one that is a new political creature, rather than a polity designed according to extant political models. Far from being purely descriptive, this view is theoretically inscribed in non state-centric views of the EU, namely in the multi-level governance approach. 1 Concomitantly, theorisation on a hypothetical political community underpinning EU’s democratic legitimacy has evolved and widely resorts to interpretations based on the theory and practice of democracy under the archetypes of representative as well as direct democracy. I argue that the crossing of both frameworks of analysis – i.e. governance and democratic theory – brings further contribution mutually to the understanding of the European Union and for normative uses at the level of EU building. The question underlying this topic of debate occurs to me every year in teaching European integration to students being introduced to the topic1, who therefore do not start from theory and who eventually ask the simplest of questions: ‘What is the European Union?’. Of course I can give them ‘facts’, about the history, the institutions and decision making procedures, EU law, or policies. However, even for the simplest presentation of facts, a conceptual underlying framework is necessary. For instance, If we take the history of European integration, conceptual tools such as interdependence, increased international cooperation, postnationalism, functional integration under the Jean Monnet method, federalism, intergovernmentalism are all quite useful for the task. Common questions coming from the students are: ‘Is Europe going to become a federation as... (the usual example being the USA)?’ Or, ‘Is the European Union an international organisation?’ Or ‘What is the democratic deficit about’? Can we, in teaching, answer these without conceptualising? And can we conceptualise without putting forward alternative interpretations of the on-going process? Grand theories, such as neo-functionalism, for example, provide several lines of argument that are worth being explored with students. However, they have to be presented as theoretical frameworks and, as such counter-arguments coming from other theories must also be presented as alternatives. Although this may seem a very basic level for the debate on theories, my point is that when in the EU debate, one of the recurrent topics of integration is addressed – the need to foster public debate on EU issues – what is actually at stake is this basic understanding of the European integration process. And that is what theories are for. Besides, and because the understanding of the process may have normative implications, it is important not to take 1 Under the Jean Monnet module ‘European Union Politics’, coord. by Prof. P. Vila Maior and running at UFP since 2007, on a previously existent course on EU Politics of the University’s own initiative. 2 matters of argument as if they were matters of fact. The alleged distance between the common citizen and EU as an institutional architecture may be more a result of lack of knowledge than of deliberate indifference or rejection (cf. Fossum and Trenz, 2006). As Olsen (2007: 132) puts it ‘Democracy and citizenship are concepts strongly linked to the framework of the nation-state’ and thus ‘changes in mentality’ are probably necessary for accomplishing the project of a European political community. In this text and for the sequence of my argument, two main topics will be addressed: governance and democracy, while theoretical fields for EU theorisation and strong conceptual tools for explaining some of its key aspects. Institutions, conventionally the place for meso theories, are at present in integration studies a substantial space for research and theorisation, either under the tradition of conventional international organisations analysis, or the frameworks of national comparative politics (cf. Jachtenfuchs, 2006). The word ‘governance’ became an ever increasing presence in this field, bringing innovative views on political institutions and society. Besides, democracy being the conventional ideological frame underpinning state - society relations, issues of democracy and democratic legitimacy are to be debated as well. I argue that there is inevitable interconnectedness between the two topics. And the (public) discussion of both is of utmost importance for fostering the debate with the citizens. 1. GOVERNANCE AND THE EU My departing point for this part of the paper is that we cannot address EU institutions without addressing the broader picture of institutional change and institutional building and this brings along issues of state - society relations, (or, perhaps better put for the EU context, issues of political institutions - society relations). Beate Kohler-Koch (2005) speaks of ‘systemic impacts’ and of ‘institutional change’ as part of the processes the literature addresses under the very broad idea of governance in the EU. According to the author, these entail ‘political structuring’ at the EU level, but may have ‘disintegrative effects’ at the national level. That the institutional system of the European Union is ‘new and open-ended’ (Olsen, 2007: 16) is a widely accepted assertion. Still, conventional theoretical fields may have a capacity to explain it. Jachtenfuchs (2006: 159) mentions the divide between ‘theories of international relations’ and ‘theories of domestic politics’ but further considers that ‘the dividing line 3 between the two subdisciplines of political science is eroding. Ideally, a more general approach to political science should be able to offer an integrated view’ (Jachtenhfuchs, 2006: 160). The idea that the two subdisciplines are converging is, I think, key to understanding the whole process. International relations sprang from the study of the structure of the international system as a system of states. But is it still so? State-centrism has been for long cornerstone for the interpretation of Western political systems and of international relations. Many theories on the EU still take this approach, namely those affiliated in the first subdiscipline mentioned above, that will present the EU as a ‘highly institutionalized negotiating system among states’ (Jachtenhfuchs, 2006: 159) as in current theories of intergovernmentalism (Moravcsik, 2003). From the first point of view the logics underlying the EU are very much the result of minimum common denominators between the member-states, negotiated at the level of intergovernmental fora. Decisional power remains fundamentally with the states that have entered these arrangements in order to maximize their negotiation capability and domestic and international spheres are discrete, rather than continuous (Hooghe and Marks, 2001: 2-3). If instead the interpretation of the European Union is one that sees it as a polity (though a new polity in the making) the core of the system has to be dislocated. Theories emphasising the supranational dimension of many of the EU institutions and procedures, i.e., their autonomy and the inherent transferences of sovereignty from the national to the supranational level thus undermine the role of the conventional nation-state. In presenting the EU as a polity, Hix states: ‘(...) with the global devolution of power to regions, localities and non-state organizations, and the delegation of authority to supranational bodies such as the European Union and the World Trade Organization, political power is now dispersed or ‘shared’. This does not mean that the ‘state’ does not exist. But, it does mean that politics and government now exist in many contexts either outside or beyond the classic state.’ (Hix; 2006: 141). This view is consistent with analyses of ‘world politics’ as put forward in theories of global governance and indeed it can be argued that there is continuity between the structural changes in political power at the global and the regional (European) levels (cf. Warleigh-Lack, 2006). Governance, and for the EU context ‘multi-level governance’ (MLG) (Hooghe and Marks, 2001; Jachtenfuchs and Kohler-Koch, 2004) are alternative views to state-centrism. However, 4 because the word governance is being increasingly used, its meaning may be slightly blurred, thus requiring some initial definitions. Definitions The concept does not belong solely with EU integration studies. Several definitions can be analysed and theoretical work has been done on this, notably for the EU context (Treib, Bahr and Falkner, 2005; Kohler-Koch, 2005). This text does not aim at producing a full overview of definitions but some guidelines are nevertheless necessary. As abovementioned there is some continuity between uses of the word ‘governance’ for global politics and for EU politics. For the former the concept made its way among others on Rosenau’s (1992) well known assertion of ‘governance without government’ which became a landmark for the debate: To presume the presence of governance without government is to conceive of functions that have to be performed in any viable human system irrespective of whether the system has evolved organizations and institutions explicitly charged with performing them. Among the many necessary functions, for example, are the needs wherein any system has to cope with external challenges, to prevent conflicts among its members or factions from tearing it irretrievably apart, to procure resources necessary to its preservation and well-being, and to frame goals and policies designed to achieve them (...) governance is not synonymous with government. Both refer to purposive behaviour, to goal-oriented activities, to systems of rule; but government suggests activities that are backed by formal authority, by police powers to insure the implementation of duly constituted policies, whereas governance refers to activities backed by shared goals that may or may not derive from legal and formally prescribed responsibilities and that do not necessarily rely on police powers to overcome defiance and attain compliance. Governance, in other words, is a more encompassing phenomenon than government (1992: 3-4). It seems very relevant that Rosenau stresses functional requisites as starting point for governance. However, it does not exclude governments from governance (cf. Treib, Bahr and Falkner, 2005) though it does affirm that there is governance beyond governments. For the world of state-centrism governance would be the exclusive product of governments, whereas for the world of globalisation, there is governance, as ‘systems of rule’ without the underlying formal, legal, hierarchical and exclusive state structure. Globalisation theorists will claim that power has ‘escaped’ the state upwards (the regional and global levels), downwards (the regional sub-national and the local levels) and sidewards (the trasnational civil society hypothesis) thus enlarging the number of agents in the process and blurring the conventional state - society divide, as well as the domestic - international divide (Held and McGrew, 2007; Karns and Mingst, 2004). For political action purposes and therefore from a normative point 5 of view, the United Nations (UN) have fully adopted the concept, namely through the work of the Commission on Global Governance (1995)2, though they tend to craft it with the modifier ‘good’ governance. In some cases, academic theorisation on global governance also carries a strong normative imprint (cf. Warleigh-Lack, 2006: 568). Despite the similarities and the aspects that are common to both political processes at both levels (the regional and the global) the concept, in the context of EU theorisation, addresses a much more structured political reality, not only because the states are still in place, but also because the range of differences to match for governing Europe is relatively small if compared with world politics. In other words, the European Union is more levelled internally. To put it simply: the EU is for governance purposes a terrain where strong and solidly rooted political institutions, the states, remain playing a fundamental political role. Yet, the debordering of conventional political territorialisation is happening as in the rest of the world: growing interdependences, transnationalisation of civil society, supranational political institutions. Yet, unlike for the rest of the world, the latter is already a quite developed institutional framework. Therefore an incremental but pervasive process of readjustment is in place in the EU (Hooghe and Marks, 2001: 39). Beate Kohler-Koch and Jachtenfuchs (2004: 99): define governance ‘as the continuous political process of setting explicit goals for society and intervening in it in order to achieve these goals’. Also, Peters and Pierre (2009: 93-94) consider that ‘at a very fundamental level, governance is a functional theory, assuming that societies must govern themselves and to do so must perform certain activities’. They further clarify that governance often involves ‘a variety of actors, many from outside the public sector itself, in order to achieve public purposes’. 2 Governance is the system of values, policies and institutions by which a society manages its economic, political and social affairs through interactions within and among the state, civil society and private sector. It is the way a society organizes itself to make and implement decisions — achieving mutual understanding, agreement and action. It comprises the mechanisms and processes for citizens and groups to articulate their interests, mediate their differences and exercise their legal rights and obligations. It is the rules, institutions and practices that set limits and provide incentives for individuals, organizations and firms. Governance, including its social, political and economic dimensions, operates at every level of human enterprise, be it the household, village, municipality, nation, region or globe. (UNDP (2000). Strategy Note on Governance for Human development. cit in UNDP, 2009: 7). 6 Treib, Bähr and Falkner (2005) analyse definitions of ‘governance’ according to their emphasis on politics, polity or policy. They also present Héritier’s distinction between an encompassing definition, which embraces both hierarchical ‘political steering’ and a restricted sense, which entails ‘political steering in which non-hierarchical modes of guidance, such as persuasion and negotiation are employed’ (Treib, Bähr and Falkner, 2005: 6). Three aspects are to be emphasised. First, and as in the global dimension, these definitions include the societal need for organisation as starting point for ‘governance’. Second they establish that there are several types of actors involved and some coming from outside the public sector, i.e., leaving behind conventional state - society divides. Still, Peters and Pierre (2009: 92) remind us that the word still encompasses conventional governments. Third, soft, non-hierarchical mechanisms as those highlighted by Héritier are a marker of ‘governance’, although it does not necessarily discard hierarchical mechanisms. The European Commission (2001) has adopted the word and has used it in its well known ‘EU Governance. A White Paper’. According to this: ‘Governance’ means rules, processes and behaviour that affect the way in which powers are exercised at European level, particularly as regards openness, participation, accountability, effectiveness and coherence.’ (2001: 8) Here the connotation is with ‘good’ governance, based on principles of democratic governance, which will be further addressed below. As a whole, the concept is now indisputable in EU studies. Its potential for addressing the process of European integration has been particularly developed under the multi-level governance framework (Hooghe and Marks, 2001; Jachtenfuchs and Kohler-Koch, 2004; Zimmer and Benz, 2010; Littoz-Monnet, 2010) the main characteristics of which are summarised below. As aforementioned, multi-level governance is a non-statecentric framework for interpetation of the political architecture of the EU. It further pressuposes that the polity is organised under a fairly complex system of political levels, or layers. Whether the metaphor of layers geometrically organised as concentric circles at the core of which is the citizen (according to the principle of subsidiarity) is adequate, can be a matter of some contention. A decentred and overllaping layout of the layers may well be more adjusted to the object being depicted. The 7 metaphor of the layer cake as oposed to the marble cake can also be used here, for visual illustration of the idea (cf. Risse, 2004, for the paralel issue of identities). Peters and Pierre (2009: 95) stress this complex characteristic. It can be further explained if we look at the distribution of competences (cf. Zimmer and Benz, 2010). Whereas exclusive competences draw a fairly clear, eventually hierarchical, dividing line between levels, shared competences rely on a case to case assessment of levels of political decision, which enforces the malleability of the system but may create some instability. This is also a consequence of the procedures involved: there are hierarchical procedures, but there is a lot of negotiation and bargaining between actors as relevant as governments, some of which at sheer intergovernmental level, and a series of soft instruments that are aimed at creating convergence in policies. These address articulations within the same level, though partners involved may be not equally strong (sovereign states, under the intergovernmental procedures all have a veto, but it is not so when it comes to softer negotiations procedures). A further difficulty arises from vertical relations (cf. Littoz-Monnet, 2010), notably the fact that the levels are not all equally consistent or capable of exerting political power: the regional level cannot be compared to the national level, not to mention the fact that there is a huge variation between what is being called region for the purposes of this level. Because this is the result of a polity in the making, dynamics of the construction still have a strong impact upon the structure: not only decisional processes keep being adjusted (eg. under treaty amendments) but also there is a tension between functional requirements and politically structured processes: Jachtenfuchs (2006) mentions the need for horizontal collaboration, understood as functional interdependencies across policy areas, so evident these days, along with the vertical articulation the system presupposes. The imprint of the model is therefore that of an ‘open ended process’, that meaning that much of it is incremental rather than constitutionalised. Hooghe and Marks (2001: 46) draw a comparative framework between ‘feudal order’, ‘state order’ and ‘post-state order’ which is worth some reflection. From the layout, similarities between the first and the third types of political order emerge, notably the overlapping characteristic, the multiplicity and the sharing of competencies. State order was created in the ‘West’ as an overcoming of feudalism: this meant the crafting of the notion of exclusive sovereignty as a prerogative of the central state and the clear and hierarchical definition of relations between vertical political levels (e.g. the 8 local/regional and the central); but it was in the long run also responsible for the introduction of the distinction between public and private affairs, based on a distinction of political power vis à vis other forms of private power, which liberalism then reified in the state - civil society dividing line, under representative democracies (Chambers and Kopstein, 2008). ‘Post-state’ order is blurring these distinctions: the drift of political power upwards and downwards questions the hierarchical dominance of the state, whereas sidewards drifting (i.e. market and civil society) reintroduces society as another locus for politics. Hooghe and Marks’ layout does not assess the types of political order from the point of view of efficiency or the quality of political solutions involved. Still the comparison opens several lines of reflection as to the evolution of Western political systems and indeed has to be read under what Beate KohlerKoch (2005) has designated as long term systemic impacts of political change. ‘Good’ governance id est democratic governance? At its minimum, governance means some kind of political order and the word does not necessarily carry a normative orientation (cf. Treib, Bahr and Falkner, 2005). Yet, and for the EU case, re-opening the Pandora box of Western politics, as addressed in the comparison above, may indeed mean unleashing hidden ‘devils’. By this I mean that the reformulation of the spheres of European politics expressed in the many and overlapping layers may entail loopholes providing opportunities for the privatisation of powers and ambiguities in the definition of ‘common interest’. Thus, in EU politics ‘good’ governance has often been identified with democratic governance. This is expressed in the Commission’s approach to governance, in 2001 (cf. above) where principles of good governance, understood as synonym of democratic governance3, within a multi-level framework are clearly expressed: 3 Also the EU glossary on-line states, for the entry ‘governance’: ‘The debate on European governance, launched by the Commission in its White Paper of July 2001, concerns all the rules, procedures and practices affecting how powers are exercised within the European Union. The aim is to adopt new forms of governance that bring the Union closer to European citizens, make it more effective, reinforce democracy in Europe and consolidate the legitimacy of the institutions. The Union must reform itself in order to fill the democratic deficit of its institutions. This governance should lie in the framing and implementation of better and more consistent policies associating civil society organisations and the European institutions. It also entails improving the quality of European legislation, making it clearer and more effective. Moreover, the European Union must contribute to the debate on world governance and play an important role in improving the operation of international institutions.’ http://europa.eu/legislation_summaries/glossary/governance_en.htm [accessed 15/06/2010] 9 ‘Each principle is important for establishing more democratic governance. They underpin democracy and the rule of law in the Member States, but they apply to all levels of government – global, European, national, regional and local.’ (European Commission, 2001: 10). The five principles are: i) ‘Openness’ of the institutions vis à vis the general public, with the explicit aim of fostering ‘confidence in complex institutions’; ii) ‘Participation throughout the policy chain – from conception to implementation’ a formula aiming both at the improvement of policies and the reinforcement of citizens’ confidence in the institutions; iii) ‘Accountability’ of the institutions at the various levels, understood as clarification of roles and responsibility; iv) ‘Effectiveness’ of policies presented in conjunction with the principles of proportionality and subsidiarity; v) finally, ‘Coherence’ understood as vertical and horizontal articulation of policy levels in a complex policy system. As a whole, these principles cover statutory requirements of democracy, namely participation and accountability, but they sound as a top down effort for reform of institutions that have themselves been repeatedly accused of weaknesses in democratic governance. Peters and Pierre (2009: 97) state that EU governance remains undemocratic. That the EU is very much a bureaucratic construction, the product of an ‘elite’ of politicians and decision makers is eventually a fairly indisputable interpretation of the European Union. Overcoming this imperfection is one of the major challenges for the European project today, especially if democracy is understood not as a procedural but as a substantial concept, as stated by KohlerKoch and Rittberger: ‘It is the principle of autonomy that stands at the center stage of the democratic project. (...) Autonomy is intimately linked to self-determination: Autonomy implies that people are free and equal in the determination of their own lives. Autonomy qua self-determination is thus set against any notions of paternalistic authority or domination which deny that people are the best judges of their own individual good or interest.’ (2007: 12) The threshold for democratic multi-level governance in the EU thus defined is quite demanding. 2. DEMOCRACY AND THE EU Democracy is statutory in the EU (TEU, article 2 and Title II). At the same time, democracy has proved to be a difficult requisite to fulfil, at every movement of EU governance. This part of the text, departing from the assumption that EU as a sui generis political system meets a very good explanatory framework in multi-level governance theory, addresses hindrances to 10 democracy that occur in the EU, in the framework of that model, and further tackles the possible ways to overcome them. The problem: the ‘democratic deficit’ ‘The democratic deficit – that is, the weakness of representative democracy in the EU – is rooted in the institutional genesis of the EU as an offspring of national institutions that claim sovereignty in their respective territories’ (Hooghe and Marks, 2001: 41) The expression ‘democratic deficit’ was coined late in the seventies to designate the distance between the citizens and the institutions in European governance (Marquand cit. by Mény, 2003: 399) and has, ever since, fuelled strong academic and political debates (cf. among many others, Dahl, 1998; Schmitter, Majone and Moravcsick, 2000; Follesdal and Hix, 2005)4. Let’s try to define the basic contours of the problem, within the purposes of the present text: If, under a state-centric approach to EU integration, a strictly procedural approach to the topic of ‘democratic legitimacy’ is adopted then there isn’t much to debate (cf. Ramos, 2009). The fact that the states involved in the process are democratic and that their governments are legitimate makes of their decisions for the supranational sphere, legitimate decisions, in the framework of national democracies. Furthermore, if centrality is attributed to the role of the states, the problem is mostly a problem of the domestic order, i.e., of the contract between the citizens and political institutions as established internally, in domestic elections under the conventional pattern of representative democracy. Whether political parties manage or not to meet the requirements of and expectations created in the citizens is very much a problem of domestic policy, if civil society in the EU is addressed as a series of discrete national civil societies and representation understood as a two step process: for internal and for external matters. But is this conventional layout traditionally designed for legitimating national governments acting in issues of foreign policy sufficient for the on-going process of European 4 The on-line glossary of the European Union states: ‘The democratic deficit is a concept invoked principally in the argument that the European Union and its various bodies suffer from a lack of democracy and seem inaccessible to the ordinary citizen because their method of operating is so complex. The view is that the Community institutional set-up is dominated by an institution combining legislative and government powers (the Council of the European Union) and an institution that lacks democratic legitimacy (the European Commission)./ At every stage of the European integration process, the question of democratic legitimacy has become increasingly sensitive. The Maastricht, Amsterdam and Nice Treaties have triggered the inclusion of the principle of democratic legitimacy within the institutional system by reinforcing the powers of Parliament with regard to the appointment and control of the Commission and successively extending the scope of the co-decision procedure. (...)’ [http://europa.eu/legislation_summaries/glossary/democratic_deficit_en.htm] [accessed 15/06/2010] 11 integration? National parliaments have repeatedly claimed that, unlike for domestic issues, they loose control upon governmental decisions taken at EU level, a recurrent argument within the democratic deficit debate (Auel and Benz, 2007; Follesdal and Hix, 2005). And even when the ‘output legitimacy’ (cf. Bekkers, 2007) argument is put forward, sustained by the alleged efficiency (good governance?) of EU policies (Majone, 1996), the counter argument that these policies should be the result of the scrutiny of the majority rather than that of spurious processes does arise (Bellamy, 2010). A significant step into supranationalism was taken in 1979 with the emergence of the European Parliament as a directly elected institution and thus introducing a new type of legitimacy, direct legitimacy (cf. Ramos, 2009), based on representation resulting directly from the votes of the citizens. This meant institutional innovation, at the European level, from the point of view of patterns of legitimacy; but from the point of view of patterns of democracy it relies entirely upon formal representative democracy. However, and ever since, there have been claims that the EP remains weak (although its powers were substantially reinforced as a result of the sequence of treaty amendments). Besides, the mediating political parties, electoral campaigns and electoral systems in place for EU elections remain national, rather than supranational. Neither did a European public sphere ‘automatically’ emerge as unified space for the debate of European politics. Nor can the analysis of the transnationalisation of civil societies in the EU put forward major evidence of the emergence of a united political community, the citizens remaining far from the EU (Follesdal and Hix, 2005; Mair, 2005). The shortcomings of explanations based on this dichotomy are the reason why the multi-level framework becomes functional for explaining patterns of political institutions – society relations in the EU, and eventually for operationalising research on democracy in the EU. The answer to the characterisation of the EU political system does no longer seem to be an either or statement based on the intergovernmental pattern as opposed to the supranational pattern, the latter understood as a state like polity, only in a larger scale (Follesdal and Hix, 2005; Mair, 2005). Under a multi-layered framework, the question of democratic participation has to be put both at each level within its specificities, and also for the whole architecture involved. The question becomes even more complex since MLG encompasses overlapping levels and also for the fact that multi-level arrangements are not based on such a stricter distinction 12 between society and political institutions as was conventional for domestic representative democracies. With such distinctions blurred, it may become difficult to overcome democratic deficits on the basis of representative democracy only. Thus democratic inputs have to be sought for also under other mechanisms of political participation. It can be hypothesised that MLG may portray a transitional period, given the systemic changes occurring and the pervasiveness of incrementalism over constitutionalism in the EU. The mechanism encountered for fostering the legitimacy of the European Commission (the election by the EP) may seem one such experiment, eventually leading to other solutions in the future. However, multiplicity and non exclusive attachments to political levels seem to be the rule, rather than hierarchy, and it may well be that these are permanent features of the new polity and thus, that a framework imbued of traditional shapes may be inadequate (Follesdal and Hix, 2005; Kohler-Koch, 2005; Schmidt, 2006; Olsen, 2007). Democratic participation and multi-level governance Within Schmidt’s (2006) analysis of state-societal structures in ‘simple’ and ‘compound’ polities5 she includes the EU in the second category and characterises it as a ‘highly compound regional polity’: ‘The EU has a high degree of diffusion of power and authority through quasi federal institutional structures, allows for a high level of interest access and influence through semipluralist policy formulation processes, ensures the uniform application of the rules trough regulatory implementation processes and emphasizes consensus-oriented politics through largely non partisan patterns of voting and exercising voice in a weak proportional representation system’ (2006: 230-231). Subsidiarity, as part of democratic theory, and ‘constitutional’ principle in the European Union emphasises the ascendant (subsidiary) characteristic of the levels in EU governance, from the citizen to the top. Eventually, this does not fully characterise reality but only empirical evidence will be able to say more (cf. Bekkers, 2007; Kohler-Koch and Rittberger, 2007). This text does not review concrete practices of democracy (either representative or of a more direct inspiration – participatory, deliberative, etcetera) at each and every level of multilevel EU governance, neither the transactions between the levels. It focuses mostly the 5 The author defines ‘compound’ polities as a combination of proportional representation systems, corporatist policy making processes and federal or regionalised states that disperse power through multiple authorities (2006: 227). 13 implications of different types of democracy in promoting EU democratic legitimacy at central EU level. Thus, in the framework of MLG analysis to EU governance, I would like to conduct this part of the text under two main questions: i) is representative democracy still a/the solution (and according to conventional formula or some other)? ii) what other solutions are there, in order to guarantee the principle of autonomy as basilar democratic principle (cf. Kohler-Koch and Rittberger above)? As to the first question: mechanisms of representative democracy in place account for formal legitimacy, notably for Council and EP decision-making. Yet, neither for the first nor for the second case has the process managed to overcome the alleged distance, and what is worse, resistance (as expressed in treaty ratification referenda or EP elections turnouts) of the citizens vis à vis the European Union. Lord and Pollak (2010) speak of ‘EU’s many representative modes’ as ‘compound representation’, addressing both conventional, formal mechanisms of representation (as above) and other informal ways of representation (such as through non-elected representatives of civil society organisations). They present both advantages and disadvantages of the model. Among the latter, I would stress the possibility that the representation of several interests in such compound system may ‘collide’ instead of ‘cohere’, and also the fact that, unlike under formal representation, informal representatives stand for segmented interests and thus, no general claims can be assumed. They conclude that ‘EU’s specific combination of representative practices hardly allows for ensuring public control with political equality’ (Lord and Pollak, 2010: 117). In fact, increased participation in the design and implementation of policies by those civil society members directly involved (as stated in the Commission’s White Paper) may increase the quality of policies, that way having a positive throughput and output impact. Yet, it does not guarantee general public control over bureaucratic and political agents of policy making (namely the Commission), neither are the informal representatives under clear ‘accountability’ rules. As Olsen puts it: ‘One basic principle of democratic citizenship is that those affected by decisions should be able to influence common affairs on equal terms’ (2007: 119). However, criticisms have also been put forward and some scepticism expressed as to the capacity of improving the EU as a polity, by copying the state pattern, and thus seeking to 14 implement competitive European party politics, as grounds for a fully representative exercise of legislative and executive powers in the EU. Mair (2005) emphasises the fact that also at the national level partisan politics are undergoing a crisis (‘depoliticization’) and therefore that this is time for seeking for other complementary processes of political participation, instead of imprisoning the EU in the old clothes of the states. Mair and Thomassenn (2010) even affirm that the lack of party government at the European level (i. e. government according to formal representation) may be more of a virtue than a flaw in the system, an assertion many would contest (cf. Kohler-Koch and Rittberger: 2007; Schmidt, 2009). As for my second question: Rather than enlarging the concept of representation, which at the level of informal representation is even arguable, it is perhaps better to put the question at the basilar level of political institutions and societies’ patterns of relation, because this is where apparently the issue of the democratic deficit started (cf. above). Rather than using representation as a key concept, it is perhaps better to replace it by ‘participation’ (cf. Kholer-Koch, 2010) and thus to look into other alternative types of democracy, entailing other types of participation (Catt, 1999; Held, 2006). The dividing line of representation versus direct democracy runs on the mediation of the will of the citizen by a delegate (Lord and Pollak, 2010) versus personal intervention in the process. The second, quite obviously collides with rigid political institutions - society divides based on the liberal representative pattern, but may fit well a more indistinct layout as that of MLG. Bekkers and Edwards’ (2007: 55) systematization of strengths and weaknesses of models of democracy in terms of input/throughput/output legitimacy grounds a good research hypothesis, which is that for MLG patterns and given their diversity, multiple forms of democracy may produce better combined results than a single form. What was addressed as informal representation above largely draws on the move towards governance and participatory democracy (Joerges, Meny and Weiler, 2001; Finke, 2007; Greven, 2007) as fuelled by the European Commission in the last decades. It is therefore a top-down and output oriented strategy, specifically designed for fostering the involvement of ‘civil society’ in policy making. It may indeed improve the quality of political outputs and 15 promote consensus among specific interest groups, but it hardly fits a notion of ‘common interest’. Other participatory practices have aimed at involving the citizen directly, for fostering the input side of democratic legitimacy (Finke, 2007; Kohler-Koch, 2010). However, they are difficult to implement in terms of scope and can only encompass the small number, or the small territorial dimension. Popular legislative initiative, recently introduced in the treaty of Lisbon, still has its way to make, in order to prove that it is more than just a principle. As for referenda, and although there is not the possibility of a general referendum at EU level, the track record for national referenda on EU issues is far from convergent with the decisions taken by the politicians, under the mechanisms of representative democracy. Deliberative experiments are theoretically grounded in the promotion of a European public sphere, which remains nevertheless quite unstructured (Vreese, 2007). CONCLUSION Reifying governance as ‘the structure’ of EU is a dangerous operation, since it is only a theory. Still, it is a theory that provides alternative explanations for aspects of EU integration that can hardly find better ones under intergovernmentalism, or supranationalism of the conventional type. Multiplicity and overlapping layers quite inevitably make of it a patchy terrain for regular political participation. Conventional representative democracy does not seem to be able to provide democratic legitimacy al all levels of EU integration, without alienating the citizens. Even if the problem is a problem of the domestic relation of the governments with their national citizens, in the end it amounts to the ‘central’ problem of EU’s democratic deficit, since the levels are subsidiary. Participation throughout different but complementary mechanisms may be a good tool for improving it, in the context of EU’s MLG structure. MLG is an alternative way of looking into European integration. It requires new conceptual tools and collapses with entrenched state-centric views of the polity. The European Commission uses the model in a prescriptive way and tries to reinforce communication with and participation of the citizens. The academic debate forcefully goes beyond that approach. For instance, Kholer-Koch (2010), in debating representation and participation as established 16 in the European Union, metaphorically turns grassroots (politics) into ‘astroturf’... because democracy is not (only) procedural. It is mostly a project of ‘autonomy’. REFERENCES Auel and Benz (2007). «Expanding National Parliamentary Control: Does it enhance European Democracy?» in KohlerKoch, Beate and Rittberger, Berthold (eds.). Debating the Democratic Legitimacy of the European Union (Governance in Europe). London: Rowman & Littlefield, pp. 57-74. Bekkers, V. and Edwards, A. (2007). “Legitimacy and Democracy: a Conceptual Framework for Assessing Governance Practices” in Bekkers, V. et. al. Governance and the Democratic Deficit. Aldershot: Ashgate. Bekkers, V. et al. (2007). Governance and the Democratic Deficit. Aldershot: Ashgate. Bellamy, Richard (2010). 'Democracy without democracy? Can the EU's democratic ‘outputs’ be separated from the democratic ‘inputs’ provided by competitive parties and majority rule?'Journal of European Public Policy, 17:1, 2 – 19 Catt, Helena (1999). Democracy in Practice. London: Routledge. Chambers, S. and Kopstein, J. ( 2006). “Civil Society and the State”. Dryzeck, J, Honig, B. and Phillips, A. The Oxford Handbook of Political Theory. Oxford: Oxford UP Dahl, R. (1998). On Democracy. New Haven: Yale UP. European Commission (2001). European Governance: A White Paper. COM(2001) 428 final (Brussels, 25/07/2001). Finke, Barbara. (2007). Civil society participation in EU governance. Living Reviews in European Governance, 2-2 http://www.livingreviews.org/lreg-2007-2 Follesdal, Andreas and Hix, Simon (2005). «Why there is a Democratic Deficit in the EU: a Response to Majone and Moravcsik» in European Governance Papers (EUROGOV). No C-05-02 [available at: http://www.connexnetwork.org/eurogov/pdf/egp-connex-C-05-02.pdf] Follesdal, Andreas, and Simon Hix (2005). Why There is a Democratic Deficit in the EU: A Response to Majone and Moravcsik. European Governance Papers (EUROGOV) No. C-05-02, http://www.connex-network.org/eurogov/pdf/egp-connex-C-05-02.pdf Fossum, John Erik, and Trenz, Hans-Jörg (2006). When the people come in: Constitu-tion-making and the belated politicisation of the European Union. European Governance Papers (EUROGOV) No. C-06-03, http://www.connex-network.org/eurogov/pdf/egp-connex-C-06-03.pdf Greven, Michael (2007). «Some considerations on Participation in Participatory Governance» in Kohler-Koch, Beate and Rittberger, Berthold (eds.). Debating the Democratic Legitimacy of the European Union (Governance in Europe). London: Rowman & Littlefield, pp. 233-248. Held, D. and Mcgrew, A. (eds) (2007). Globalization Theory: approaches and controversies. Cambridge: Polity Press. Held, David (2006). Models of democracy. 3rd ed. Stanford: Stanford UP. Hix, S. (2006). “The European Union as a Polity (I)” in Jorgensen, Knud, Pollack, Mark and Rosamond, Ben (eds.). Handbook of European Union Politics. London: Sage, pp. 141-158. Hooghe, Liesbeth and Marks, Gary (2001). Multi-Level Governance and European Integration. Lanham, Rowman & Littlefield. Jachtenfuchs, Markus (2006). «The European Union as a Polity (II)» in Jorgensen, Knud, Pollack, Mark and Rosamond, Ben (eds.). Handbook of European Union Politics. London: Sage, pp. 159-174. Jachtenfuchs, Markus and Kohler-Koch, Beate (2004). «Governance and Institutional Development» in Wiener, A. and Diez, T. (eds.). European Integration Theory. Oxford: Oxford UP, pp. 97-116. Joerges, C., Meny, Y. and Weiler J. (eds.) (2001). Mountain or Molehill? A Critical Appraisal of the Commission White Paper on Governance. In The Jean Monnet Working papers. Nº 6/01. Jorgensen, Knud, Pollack, Mark and Rosamond, Ben (2006). Handbook of European Union Politics. London: Sage. Karns, Margaret and Mingst, Karen (2004). International Organizations: The Politics and Processes of Global Governance. London: Lynne Rienner Publishers 17 Kohler-Koch, Beate (2005). European governance and system integration. European Governance Papers (EUROGOV) No. C-05-01, http://www.connex-network.org/eurogov/pdf/egp-connex-C-05-01.pdf Kohler-Koch, Beate (2007) in Kohler-Koch, Beate and Rittberger, Berthold (eds.). Debating the Democratic Legitimacy of the European Union (Governance in Europe). London: Rowman & Littlefield. Kohler-Koch, Beate (2010). Civil society and EU democracy: ‘astroturf’ representation? Journal of European Public Policy, 17: 1, 100 – 116 Kohler-Koch, Beate and Rittberger, Berthold (eds.) (2007). Debating the Democratic Legitimacy of the European Union (Governance in Europe). London: Rowman & Littlefield. Littoz-Monnet, Annabelle (2010). Dynamic Multi-Level Governance – Bringing the Study of Multi-level Interactions into the Theorising of European Integration, European Integration online Papers (EIoP), 14-1 http://eiop.or.at/eiop/texte/2010001a.htm. Lord, Christopher and Pollak, Johannes (2010). The EU's many representative modes: Colliding? Cohering? Journal of European Public Policy. 17: 1, 117 – 136 Mair, Peter (2005). Popular Democracy and the European Union Polity. European Governance Papers (EUROGOV) No. C05-03, http://www.connex-network.org/eurogov/pdf/egp-connex-C-05-03.pdf Mair, Peter and Thomassen, Jacques (2010). 'Political representation and government in the European Union'. Journal of European Public Policy, 17:1, 20 – 35 Majone, Giandomenico (ed.) (1996). Regulating Europe. London: Routledge. Mény, Yves (2003). «De la démocratie en Europe: Old Concepts and New Challenges» in Weiler, Joseph, Begg, Ian and Peterson, John (eds.). Integration in an Expanding European Union – Reassessing the Fundamentals. London: Blackwell, pp. 393-406. Moravcsik, Andrew (2002). «In Defence of the Democratic Deficit: Reassessing Legitimacy in the European Union» in Journal of Common Market Studies. (40: 4) pp. 603-624. O'Brien, R. and Williams, M. (2004). Global political Economy. Evolution and Dynamics. Houndmills: Palgrave, Macmillan. Olsen, Johan (2007). Europe in Search of Political Order. An institutional perspective on unity/diversity, citizens/their helpers, democratic design/historical drift and the co-existence of orders. Oxford: Oxford UP Peters, B. and Pierre, J. (2009). Governance Approaches in Wiener, Antje and Diez, Thomas (eds.) . European Integration Theory. 2nd ed. Oxford: Oxford UP. Ramos, C. (2009). On Democracy and Political Participation: Quagmires of Legitimacy in the European Union Context. Paper presented to the IPSA –21st World Congress of Political Science – Global Discontent: Dilemmas of Change. Santiago, 2009 http://paperroom.ipsa.org/papers/view/1508 Risse, Thomas (2004). «Social Constructivism and European Integration» in Wiener, A. e Diez, T. (eds.). European Integration Theory. Oxford: Oxford UP, pp. 159-175. Rosenau, J. (1992). Governance without Government: Governance, Order and Change in World Politics. Cambridge: Cambridge U.P. Schmidt, Vivian (2006). Democracy in Europe. The EU and national polities. Oxford: Oxford UP Schmidt, Vivien A. (2009). Re-Envisioning the European Union: Identity, Democracy, Economy. Journal of Common Market Studies, 47, 17-42 Schmitter, Philippe, Majone, Giandomenico and Moravcsick, Andrew (2000). «Democracy and Constitutionalism in the European Union» in ECSA Review. (13: 2) pp. 2-7. [available at: http://aei.pitt.edu/61/01/DemocracyForum.htm]. Treib, Oliver, Holger Bähr and Gerda Falkner (2005). Modes of Governance: A Note Towards Conceptual Clarification. European Governance Papers (EUROGOV) No. N-05-02, http://www.connex-network.org/eurogov/pdf/egp-newgov-N-05-02.pdf UNDP - United Nations Development Programme. Oslo Governance Centre. 2009. Governance Indicators. User’s Guide. 2nd ed. http://www.undp.org/oslocentre/flagship/democratic_governance_assessments.html Vreese (de), Claes H. (2007). The EU as a public sphere. Living Reviews in European Governance, 2-3 http://www.livingreviews.org/lreg-2007-3 18 Warleigh-Lack, Alex. (2006). “The European and the Universal Process? European Union Studies, New Regionalism and Global Governance” in Jorgensen, Knud, Pollack, Mark and Rosamond, Ben (eds.). Handbook of European Union Politics. London: Sage, pp 561-575 Wiener, Antje and Diez, Thomas (eds.) (2004). European Integration Theory. Oxford: Oxford UP. Wiener, Antje and Diez, Thomas (eds.) (2009). European Integration Theory. 2nd ed. Oxford: Oxford UP. Zimmer, Christina and Benz, Arthur. (2010). The EU's competences: The 'vertical' perspective on the multilevel system. Living Reviews in European Governance, 5-1 http://www.livingreviews.org/lreg-2010-1 19